1NC K The aff embraces a neoliberal ethic of unending consumption, false altruism, and medical apartheid—turns the case and causes global violence against the periphery Hughes 3 [Nancy Scheper-Hughes (Professor of Anthropology—Cal-Berkeley; Cofounder and Director—Organs Watch, a medical human rights organization that monitors international organ trafficking); “Rotten trade: millennial capitalism, human values and global justice in organs trafficking”; 2003; Journal of Human Rights, 2:2, 197-226] Amidst the neo-liberal readjustments of societies, North and South, we are experiencing today a rapid depletion, an ‘emptying out ’ even, of traditional modernist, humanist and pastoral ideologies, values and practices. New relations between capital and labor, bodies and the state, belonging and extra-territoriality, and between medical and biotechnological inclusions and exclusions are taking shape. But rather than a conventional story of the lamentable decline of humanistic social values and social relations, our discussion is tethered to a frank recognition that the material grounds on which those modernist values and practices were based have shifted today almost beyond recognition. What the Comaroffs (2001) refer to as millennial or ‘second coming’ capitalism has facilitated a rapid dissemination to virtually all corners of the world of advanced medical procedures and biotechnologies alongside strange markets and ‘occult economies’. Together, these have incited new tastes and desires for the skin, bone, blood, organs, tissue and reproductive and genetic material of others. Nowhere are these processes more transparent than in the field of organ transplant, which now takes place in a transnational space with both donors and recipients following new paths of capital and medical technology in the global economy. The spread of transplant capabilities created a global scarcity of transplantable organs at the same time that economic globalization released an exodus of displaced persons and a voracious appetite for foreign bodies to do the shadow work of production and to provide ‘fresh’ organs for medical consumption. The ideal conditions of an ‘open’ market economy have thereby put into circulation mortally sick bodies traveling in one direction and ‘healthy’ organs (encased in their human packages) in another direction, creating a bizarre ‘kula ring’ of international body trade. The emergence of strange markets, excess capital, renegade surgeons, local ‘kidney hunters’ with links to an international Mafia (Lobo and Maierovitch 2002) (and thereby to a parallel traffic in slave workers, babies, drugs and small arms) has produced a small but spectacularly lucrative practice of transplant tourism , much of it illegal and clandestine. This confluence in the flows of immigrant workers and itinerant kidney sellers who fall into the hands of ruthless brokers and unscrupulous, notorious, but simultaneously rewarded, protected and envied outlaw transplant surgeons is a troubling sub-text in the story of late twentieth and early twenty-first century globalization, one that combines and juxtaposes elements of pre- and postmodernity. These new transplant transactions are a strange blend of altruism and commerce; consent and coercion; gifts and theft; science and sorcery; care and human sacrifice. On the one hand, the phenomenal spread of transplant technologies, even in the murky context of black markets in medicine, has given the possibility of new, extended or improved quality of life to a select population of mobile kidney patients from the deserts of Oman to the rain forests of the Amazon Basin. On the other hand, new developments in ‘transplant tourism’ have exacerbated older divisions between North and South, core and periphery, haves and have-nots, spawning a new form of commodity fetishism in demands by medical consumers for a quality product: ‘fresh’ and ‘healthy’ kidneys purchased from living bodies. In these radical exchanges of body parts and somatic information, life-saving measures for the one demands a bodily sacrifice of self-mutilation by the other. And one man’s biosociality (Rabinow 1996) is another woman’s biopiracy, depending on whether one is speaking from a Silicon Valley biotech laboratory or from a sewage-infested banguay in Manila. Commercialized transplant, a practice that trades comfortably in the domain of postmodern biopolitics with its values of disposability, individuality, free and transparent circulation, exemplifies better than any other biomedical technology the reach and the limits of economic liberalism. In transplant gifts of life and death (Parsons et al . 1969) promise to surpass all previous ‘natural’ limits and restrictions. And the uninhibited circulation of purchased kidneys exemplifies the neo-liberal episteme, a political discourse based on juridical concepts of the autonomous individual subject, equality (at least equality of opportunity), radical freedom, accumulation and universality (the expansion of medical rights and medical citizenship 3 ). The commodified kidney is, to date, the primary currency in transplant tourism; it represents the gold standard of organ sales worldwide. In the past year, however, markets in part-livers and single corneas from living vendors are beginning to emerge in Southeast Asia. This paper continues my discussion (Scheper-Hughes 2000b, 2001a, 2001b, 2002) of the darker side of transplant practice. In all, three crucial points about the organs trade have emerged. The first is about invented scarcities and artificial needs within a new context of highly fetishized ‘fresh’ organs. The scarcity of cadaver organs has evolved into an active trade in ‘surplus’ organs from living ‘ suppliers’ as well as in new forms of ‘biopiracy’. The second point concerns the transplant rhetoric of altruism masking real demands for human sacrifice. The third point concerns surplus empathy and the relative visibility of two distinct populations – excluded and invisible organ givers and included and highly visible organ receivers. We have found almost everywhere a new form of globalized ‘apartheid medicine’ that privileges one class of patients, organ recipients, over another class of invisible and unrecognized ‘non-patients’, about whom almost nothing is known – an excellent place for a critical medical anthropologist (Scheper-Hughes 1990) to begin. The impact is multiple scenarios for extinction---it’s try or die for a radical reconceptualization of politics. Adrian Parr, Associate Professor of Philosophy and Environmental Studies at University of Cincinnati, The Wrath of Capital: Neoliberalism and Climate Change Politics, ‘13 A quick snapshot of the twenty-first century so far: an economic meltdown; a frantic sell-off of public land to the energy business as President George W Bush exited the White House; a prolonged, costly, and unjustified war in Iraq; the Greek economy in ruins; an escalation of global food prices; bee colonies in global extinction; 925 million hungry reported in 2010; as of 2005, the world's five hundred richest individuals with a combined income greater than that of the poorest 416 million people, the richest 10 percent accounting for 54 percent of global income; a planet on the verge of boiling point ; melting ice caps; increases in extreme weather conditions; and the list goes on and on and on.2 Sounds like a ticking time bomb, doesn't it? Well it is. It is shameful to think that massive die-outs of future generations will put to pale comparison the 6 million murdered during the Holocaust; the millions killed in two world wars; the genocides in the former Yugoslavia, Rwanda, and Darfur; the 1 million left homeless and the 316,000 killed by the 2010 earthquake in Haiti. The time has come to wake up to the warning signs.3 The real issue climate change poses is that we do not enjoy the luxury of incremental change anymore. We are in the last decade where we can do something about the situation. Paul Gilding, the former head of Greenpeace International and a core faculty member of Cambridge University's Programme for Sustainability, explains that "two degrees of warming is an inadequate goal and a plan for failure;' adding that "returning to below one degree of warming . . . is the solution to the problem:'4 Once we move higher than 2°C of warming, which is what is projected to occur by 2050, positive feedback mechanisms will begin to kick in, and then we will be at the point of no return. We therefore need to start thinking very differently right now. We do not see the crisis for what it is; we only see it as an isolated symptom that we need to make a few minor changes to deal with. This was the message that Venezuela's president Hugo Chavez delivered at the COP15 United Nations Climate Summit in Copenhagen on December 2009, when he declared: "Let's talk about the cause. We should not avoid responsibilities, we should not avoid the depth of this problem. And I'll bring it up again, the cause of this disastrous panorama is the metabolic, destructive system of the capital and its model: capitalism's The structural conditions in which we operate are advanced capitalism. Given this fact, a few adjustments here and there to that system are not enough to solve the problems that climate change and environmental degradation pose.6 Adaptability, modifications, and displacement, as I have consistently shown throughout this book, constitute the very essence of capitalism. Capitalism adapts without doing away with the threat. Under capitalism, one deals with threat not by challenging it, but by buying favors from it, as in voluntary carbonoffset schemes. In the process, one gives up on one's autonomy and reverts to being a child. Voluntarily offsetting a bit of carbon here and there, eating vegan, or recycling our waste, although well intended, are not solutions to the problem, but a symptom of the free market's ineffectiveness. By casting a scathing look at the neoliberal options on display, I have tried to show how all these options are ineffective. We are not buying indulgences because we have a choice; choices abound, and yet they all lead us down one path and through the golden gates of capitalist heaven. For these reasons, I have underscored everyone's implication in this structure-myself included. If anything, the book has been an act of outrageoutrage at the deceit and the double bind that the "choices" under capitalism present, for there is no choice when everything is expendable. There is nothing substantial about the future when all you can do is survive by facing the absence of your own future and by sharing strength, stamina, and courage with the people around you. All the rest is false hope. In many respects, writing this book has been an anxious exercise because I am fully aware that reducing the issues of environmental degradation and climate change to the domain of analysis can stave off the institution of useful solutions. But in my defense I would also like to propose that each and every one of us has certain skills that can contribute to making the solutions that we introduce in response to climate change and environmental degradation more effective and more realistic. In light of that view, I close with the following proposition, which I mean in the most optimistic sense possible: our politics must start from the point that after 2050 it may all be over. The alternative is to vote negative to endorse a radical break from neoliberal market society---we should use educational spaces to create networks of resistance to capital. Henry Giroux, currently holds the Global TV Network Chair Professorship at McMaster University in the English and Cultural Studies Department and a Distinguished Visiting Professorship at Ryerson University, “Beyond Savage Politics and Dystopian Nightmares” ‘13 Right-wing market fundamentalists want to root out those considered defective consumers and citizens, along with allegedly unpatriotic dissidents. They also want to punish the poor and remove their children from the possibility of a quality public education. Hence, they develop schools that are dead zones of the imagination for most children and highly creative classroom environments free of the frenzy of empiricism and test-taking for the children of the rich. It gets worse. In Pennsylvania, right-wing Gov. Tom Corbett and Philadelphia Mayor Michael Nutter are intent on destroying the public school system. Instead of funding public schools, Corbett and Nutter are intent on crushing the teachers union and supporting vouchers and charter schools. They also are fond of claiming that money can’t help struggling public schools as a pretext for closing more than 23 schools “while building a $400 million state prison.”[xv] As Aaron Kase reports, “Things have gotten so bad that at least one school has asked parents to chip in $613 per student just so they can open with adequate services, which, if it becomes the norm, effectively defeats the purpose of equitable public education, and is entirely unreasonable to expect from the city’s poorer neighborhoods.”[xvi] Vouchers and under-regulated charter schools have become the unapologetic face of a vicious form of casino capitalism waging war on the imagination while imposing a range of harsh and punitive disciplinary methods on teachers and students, particularly low-income and poor white minorities.[xvii] The vast stores of knowledge and human creativity needed by young people to face a range of social, economic and political problems in the future are not simply being deferred, they are being systematically destroyed. When the emancipatory potential of education does emerge, it is often couched in the deadening discourse of establishing comfort zones in classrooms as a way of eliminating any pedagogy that provokes, unsettles or educates students to think critically. Critical knowledge and pedagogy are now judged as viable only to the degree that they do not make a student uncomfortable. There is more at stake here than the death of the imagination; there is also the elimination of those modes of agency that make a democracy possible. In the face of such cruel injustices, neoliberalism remains mute, disdaining democratic politics by claiming there are no alternatives to casino capitalism. Power in the United States has been uprooted from any respect for public value, the common good and democratic politics. This is not only visible in the fact that 1 percent of the population now owns 40 percent of the nation’s wealth or took home “more than half of the nation’s income,” it is also evident in a culture that normalizes, legitimates and thrives in a politics of humiliation, cruelty, racism and class discrimination.[xviii] Political, moral and economic foundations float free of constraints. Moral and social responsibilities are unmoored, free from any sense of responsibility or accountability in a permanent war state. Repression is now the dominant mantra for all of society. As Zygmunt Bauman and David Lyons point out, the American public has been turned into “ security addicts,” ingesting mistrust, suspicion and fear as the new common sense for a security state that seems intent on causing the death of everything that matters in a democracy.[xix] The surveillance state works hard to not only monitor our phone conversations or track our Internet communication but to turn us into consumers, ratchet up the desire to be watched, and enforce new registers of social exclusion between those inside and outside the official temples of consumerism, social rights and captainship itself. Confining, excluding and vigilantism is one register of the new face of authoritarianism in the US. As America enters a historical era dominated by an authoritarian repressive state, the refugee camp as a symbol of exclusion and suffering is everywhere, visible in the material encampments for the homeless, urban ghettoes, jails, detention centers for young people, and in the tents propping up alongside highways that hold the new refugees from the suburbs who have lost their jobs, homes and dignity. The refugee camp also has become a metaphor for those who question authority, because they are increasingly rendered stateless, useless and undesirable. Critical thought is now considered dangerous, discomforting and subject to government prosecution, as is evident in the war being waged against whistleblowers in the name of national (in)security.[xx] The technologies of smart missiles hunt down those considered enemies of the United States, removing the ethical imagination from the horror of the violence it inflicts while solidifying the “victory of technology over ethics.”[xxi] Sorting out populations based on wealth, race, the ability to consume and immigration status is the new face of America. The pathologies of inequality have come home to roost in America.[xxii] Moreover, as suffering increases among vast swaths of the population, the corporate elite and rich use the proliferating crises to extract more wealth, profits and resources.[xxiii] Crises become the new rationale for destroying the ideologies, values and institutions that give power to the social contract. [xxiv] The ethos of rabid individualism , hyper-masculinity and a survival-of-thefittest ethic has created a society of throwaways of both goods and people. The savage ethic of economic Darwinism also drives the stories we now tell about ourselves. The state of collective unconsciousness that haunts America has its deepest roots not only in the writings of Friedrich Hyek, Ayn Rand, Milton Friedman and other neoliberal philosophers but also in the increasing merging power of private-sector corporations that, as John Ralston Saul has argued, has its roots in the “anti-democratic underpinnings of Fascist Italy in particular, but also of Nazi Germany.”[xxv] Today this “corporatism [is] so strong it that it has taken the guts out of much of daily democratic life.”[xxvi] Combined with the power of the national surveillance state, it is fair to say, again quoting Saul, that “corporatism, with all of the problems attached to it, is digging itself ever deeper into our society, undermining our society.”[xxvii] Clearly, those words echoed a few years ago were not only prescient but vastly underestimated the growing authoritarianism in the United States, in particular. We now live in a society in which leadership has been usurped by models of corporate management, self-interest has triumphed over the ethical imagination, and a respect for others is discarded for the crude instrumental goal of accumulating capital, regardless of the social costs . Intellectuals in too many public spheres have become either dysfunctional or they have sold out. Higher education is no longer the city on the hill. Instead it has become a corporate boardroom/factory in which Bill Gates wannabes govern the university as if it were an outpost of Wall Street. Outside of the boardrooms, intellectual violence prevails aimed largely at faculty and students, who are reduced to either grant writers or consumers. To make matters worse academic knowledge is drowning in firewalls of obtuseness, creating a world of dysfunctional intellectuals, at least those who have tenure. Those who don’t have such security are tied to the harsh rhythm and rituals of contingent subaltern labor and barely make enough money to be able to pay their rent or mounting debts - never mind engage in teaching critically and creatively while writing as a sustained act of dissent. At the same time, the wider culture is sinking under a flood of consumer and celebrity idiocy. There are some who suggest that such critiques of the growing authoritarianism and repression in American society are useless and in the long run do nothing more than reinforce a crippling dystopianism. I think this line of argument is not only wrong but complicitous with the very problems it refuses to acknowledge. From a left suffocating in cynicism, there is the argument that people are already aware of these problems, as if neoliberal hegemony does not exist and that its success in building a consensus around its ideology as a mode of common sense is passé. At the same time, liberals detest such criticism because it calls into question the totality of American politics rather than focus on one issue and gestures toward a radical restructuring of American society rather than piecemeal and useless reforms. The call for such a restructuring rather than piecemeal reforms sends liberals into fits of hysteria. Of course, the right in all of its varieties views criticism as a virus that destroys everything they admire about America - a society in which democracy has been eviscerated and largely benefits the top ten percent of the population. Most importantly, the banality of evil lies less in the humdrum cruelty of everyday relations but in its normalization, the depolicitizaton of culture, and, at the present moment, in the reproduction of a neoliberal society that eradicates any vestige of public values, the ethical imagination, social responsibility, civic education and democratic social relations. The enemy is not a market economy but a market society and the breakdown of all forms of social solidarity that inform democratic politics and the cultural, political and economic institutions that make it possible. The authoritarianism that now shapes American society is not a matter of fate but one rooted in organized struggle and a vision built on the recognition that there are always alternatives to the existing order that speak to the promise of a democracy to come. The contradictions of neoliberalism are unraveling, but the consensus that informs it is alive and well. And it is at that level of educational intervention that the war against market authoritarianism in all of its diverse forms has to be fought first . Commonsense has become the enemy of critical thought. Hope is no longer part of the discourse of the left, only a dreary sense of despair with no vision of how to imagine a radical democracy. Manufactured ignorance has become a virtue instead of a liability in a society ruled by the financial elite. And as such we have no serious crisis of ideas. Instead, we have a crisis of power relations and structures that needs a new political language if it is to be contested at the level of both a pedagogical and political struggle. The current neoliberal drive to ruthlessly extend the never-ending task of accumulating capital is matched only by its ruthless determination to produce a notion of common sense that reinforces the idea that there is no way to think beyond the present system. The American public needs to break the authoritarian dysimagination machine that affirms everyone as a consumer and reduces freedom to unchecked selfinterest while reproducing subjects who are willingly complicit with the plundering of the environment, resources and public goods by the financial elite. Class and racial warfare are alive and well in the United States. In fact, racism and the class warfare waged by right-wing politicians, bankers, hedge fund managers and the corporate rich are intensifying. Americans need to reject a politics in which public goods are demonized and eradicated, African-American youths become the fodder for wars abroad and the military-prison-industrial complex, the underclass disappears, public servants are disparaged, youths vanish into debt and despair, and the middle class passes into oblivion. While politics must be connected to its material moorings, it is not enough to imagine a different future than the one that now hangs over us like a suffocating sandstorm. Those intellectuals, workers, young people, artists and others committed to a radical democracy need to develop a new vocabulary about how to think about the meaning of politics, human agency and the building of a formative culture through which organized collective struggles can develop in the effort to imagine a new and more democratic future. 1NC CP The United States should - Implement a strict presumed-consent policy for organ donations, protected by a tort of strict liability - Substantially increase public education programs about organ donation - Establish financial incentives and governmental regulations for the for-profit private-sector procurement of organs, and consolidate and centralize OPOs as appropriate - Implement a priority allocation scheme under which registered donors are granted priority in the event that they need an organ donation. Strict presumed consent solves the Aff Glaser 5 (Glaser, Sheri R., J.D. candidate at the Washington College of Law, "Formula to Stop the Illegal Organ Trade: Presumed Consent Laws and Mandatory Reporting Requirements for Doctors." Human Rights Brief 12, no. 2 (2005): 20-22., http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1311&context=hrbrief, ZBurdette) APPROXIMATELY 15 TO 20 NATIONS have enacted presumed consent laws for organ donation. These laws are intended to produce a surplus of organs for transplant surgery, establish equity in the distribution of organs, and end any illicit trade in organs. They essentially create situations where people must opt-out of being an organ donor, rather than opt-in, as in the United States and other countries. These laws vary in terms of their strength. For example, many of the European laws are weaker, meaning they have easy opt-out provisions. In France the family is given an opportunity to stop the donation, even if the deceased expressed his or her desire to be an organ donor. Where the system of presumed consent is weak, it does not increase organ supply to the point of meeting demand. Instead, those systems operate like the opt-in system in the United States because people who would have chosen to remain a non-organ-donor in the United States may stop a family member’s donation and opt themselves out of being organ donors. Such systems do not effectively increase the supply of organs. In contrast , Brazil’s Presumed Organ Donor Law is an example of a strict presumed consent law, where it is more difficult to opt-out. The law defines all Brazilian adults as universal organ donors unless they officially declare themselves “non-donors of organs and tissues.” In order to opt-out, citizens must have “non-donor of organs and tissues” permanently stamped on their civil identity card or driver’s license. Citizens must pay for their documentation, which presents an economic hardship and thus a major hurdle for many in Brazil. Additionally, citizens must navigate various bureaucratic obstacles in order to opt-out. For example, authorities reportedly told Maria Celestina de Oliveira Pinto, adomestic worker in Sao Paulo, that she was not allowed to declare herself a non-donor when she went to get her new documents. She reportedly had to wait in line four times and argue before she received a “non” before the word “donor” on her card. Though strict presumed consent laws effectively increase supply, they may create unfair hardships on those individuals who wish to opt-out. States that pass strict presumed consent laws should make the process by which citizens opt-out free of charge and simpler than Brazil’s system. IMPACT OF PRESUMED CONSENT LAWS Presumed consent, when the state strictly follows it, is the best-practice method of legally obtaining organs. In countries with presumed consent laws, there is a higher procurement rate for organs than in countries without these laws. Many argue that if the demand for organs were met legally, then people would have less incentive to illegally obtain organs and the black market would eventually diminish. On a more basic level, if there were more organs available for transplant, then more people’s lives would be saved. In addition, presumed consent leads to improvements in tissue matching between donor organs and recipients, and it allows surgeons to be more particular about which organs are selected. Furthermore, these laws allow for more careful application of brain-death criteria because the increased supply of donor organs diminishes incentive to obtain organs through “inappropriate” means. For example, there have been cases in Russia and Argentina where organs were removed from comatose patients who were prematurely declared brain-dead. Presumed consent also ensures that organs are “fresher” because it eliminates the doctor’s need to contact the deceased’s next of kin, thus shortening the time between death and determination of consent. Lastly, the decision as to whether or not to donate organs is not made during the grieving period immediately following someone’s death. Financially, presumed consent lowers costs on the part of the government. For example, in the United States, with a federally funded dialysis program, the cost of a kidney transplant, taking into account the cost per year after the transplant for further medical care, is less than the yearly cost of dialysis. One could reasonably argue that, as kidney transplants become even more commonplace, the costs will continue to fall. If a nation has a system of presumed consent and has more organs available for transplants, then that nation will presumably be performing more transplants and will have fewer patients on dialysis, thus lowering government costs. And procurement reform is key Beard 13 [T. Randolph Beard (Professor of Economics—Auburn University), David L. Kaserman (Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University), Rigmar Osterkamp (Researcher—Munich University of Applied Sciences), “The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses”, p. 100-103, 2013] In the United States, as in other countries, the procurement of organs for¶ transplantation is a public function, entrusted to monopsonistic, nonprofit au-¶ thorities. Among the provisions contained in the 1984 National Organ Trans-¶ plantation Act (NOTA) in the United States, for example, is one that created¶ a set of regional organ procurement organizations ( OPOs) and established the¶ market structure under which they would operate. (The German equivalent,¶ the Deutsche Stiftung Organ transplantation, has a very similar structure, although¶ it is nationally unitary.) From the economic perspective, these structures ex-¶ hibit two important characteristics. First, each of the 58 U.S. regional OPOs is¶ assigned an exclusive geographic territory within which it could conduct its¶ activities. These territories vary considerably in size, both in geographic scope¶ and population served. For example, large OPOs serve parts of California (One¶ Legacy Transplant Donor Network in Los Angeles, 17.5 million persons) and¶ multiple states in New England (New England Organ Bank, 11.1 million per-¶ sons), while smaller, sparsely populated states are often serviced by much smaller¶ networks, as in New Mexico (New Mexico Donor Services, 1.8 million) or¶ Nebraska (Nebraska Organ Retrieval System, 1.6 million). These assignments¶ of exclusive territories provide each OPO a "monopsony " (monopoly on the buyer side of the market) over all organ procurement activities within its region. As a consequence, competition among procurement organizations in primary donor recruitment is limited. The NOTA also established the financial incentive system under which these monopsony OPOs must operate. In particular, these organizations are legally (private) nonprofit entities. This status has several practical implications under the laws of the United States and most other countries. First, the OPOs do not have ownership rights that are tradable, implying that there cannot be a conventional market for the residual rights to income of the organizations. Hence, OPOs are not subject to market-launched "takeovers," nor is it necessarily a simple matter for outsiders to judge the performance of an OPO management.' Additionally, the selection of managers is made by volunteer boards whose incentives and abilities to evaluate OPO performance may be weak. A detailed review of these features of the U.S. organ procurement apparatus can be found in Barnett and Kaserman (2002), so our treatment here is brief and generic. Nevertheless, these features are informative because, with few significant exceptions, they are duplicated in all the other countries. Consider first the geographic monopsony feature. Due to this structure, the pressure to improve performance (i.e., lower costs and/or increase output) that is normally found in the competitive setting is eliminated. While a few organs are transported between OPOs, there is no head-to-head competition among OPOs at the acquisition stage. In terms of Figure 5.1, this means that the factual quantity Q0 may be lower than some maximum feasible number that could be acquired—even at the zero price. That this is indeed the case is overwhelmingly supported by a variety of evidence from numerous sources. For example, the Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative (ODBC), discussed at greater length in Chapter 6, is itself predicated on the existence of such inefficiencies, which it seeks to eliminate. Plainly, OPO organ procurement rates (defined with respect to hospital deaths, for example) vary greatly in the United States, sometimes by a factor of ten. These differences are analyzed at length by Beard, Kaserman, and Saba (2005), who show that such variations are significantly related to variations in OPO efficiency. Thus, U.S. OPO performances vary dramatically, a result not inconsistent with the lack of any sort of ordinary competition among these organizations. Priority allocation solves the shortage – majority of the population is ambivelant towards donation AND the CP flips presumption towards donation Kolber 3 – law professor @ Brooklyn Law School Adam J., “A MATTER OF PRIORITY: TRANSPLANTING ORGANS PREFERENTIALLY TO REGISTERED DONORS” Rutgers Law Review Vol 55 No 3 Pgs 671-739 // The principal reason to institute a priority allocation scheme is purely instrumental-doing so will increase the organs available to all. The altruistic motivation to donate has proven itself woefully insufficient, and while many preach that it should be sufficient, people on organ waiting lists are dying at an average rate of sixteen per day in the United States.'27¶ Many people are ambivalent about donating and could be convinced to donate with just a small incentive to help them overcome the inertia which protects us from mulling over our own mortality. Though we need more empirical research, it is quite likely that if registered donors were granted priority to receive organs, we would sway many more people into the willing-donor category.128¶ The benefits of registering under a priority incentive program clearly exceed the costs. Even after registering, it is extremely unlikely that a registrant will donate organs because it is rare to die with organs medically eligible for transplantation. We have far more organ recipients than donors because each body used in transplantation provides organs to several individuals. 9 Under a priority scheme, potential donors can make the trade off between the very remote possibility of becoming an organ donor and the not-quiteso remote possibility of needing an organ. Understandably, neither the role of donor nor recipient is particularly appealing to think about. If you are in the latter category, your life is threatened, and if you are in the former category your life is over. But, under a priority system, you have an incentive to register because you are more likely to be rewarded by the system than made to contribute to it.¶ More importantly, the actual rewards of registering under a priority scheme (and thereby increasing one's life expectancy) far outstrip the costs, if any, of having some organs removed after death. Despite the discomfort one may have about registering to donate, an actual donation will only be made when one is dead and unaware, while the process of needing an organ occurs only while one is alive and usually very much aware. 1NC BIO PRINTING DA The aff’s compensation system reverses the direction of current jurisprudence and necessarily requires common law to recognize property rights for the body Laurel R. Siegel 2K, JD Candidate, Emory University School of Law, “Re-Engineering the Laws of Organ Transplantation,” Summer 2000, 49 Emory L.J. 917, Lexis 2. Compensation Systems Compensation systems would change the nature of altruistic organ donation. The theory states that people may be more willing to provide organs if they receive compensation . n283 Several types of compensation systems have been proposed, each attacking the organ shortage in a slightly different way, but with the same ultimate goal - to provide Compensation systems require development of common law to increase the property rights of individuals after death . Additionally, a compensation system could only go into effect if NOTA and the 1987 UAGA amendments are repealed or amended. n284 NOTA, however, allows all other remuneration. participants in the organ procurement and transplantation process, except the donor, to receive compensation. Arguably, the donor should receive compensation as well. Compensation systems have several advantages. First, they help to make up for the organs wasted under the donative system. n285 Second, if a person sells his organs, there may be less emotion and tension involved than if an altruistic donation was made out of love or guilt. n286 Primarily, dissatisfaction with the proposed compensation systems concerns the lack of the customary altruism. n287 Critics fear that the lack of altruism would upset society as well as reduce the organ supply. n288 Selling organs would take away from the traditional notion of providing a generous act in the face of tragedy. n289 Allowing sales of organs encroaches into a sacred area where such sales are controversial. The notion of profiting from the sales of body parts is repulsive to many. Critics of compensation systems have a serious concern with coercion of the poor. n290 Destitute people, who otherwise might not chose to donate organs, might feel compelled to sell their organs. n291 Another concern involves the allocation of organs. Under a compensation [*951] system, those who could afford organs would have a greater chance of receiving them. n292 Finally, allowing sales of organs could promote family strife due to pressure to sell organs. n293 a. Inter Vivos Market for Organs In an inter vivos organ market, organs would be considered an ordinary commodity to be sold for a profit. System regulators would have to decide where to draw the line - selling non-essential organs such as kidneys versus selling essential organs such as the heart. The theory for such a system is based on the notion that all parties in the organ donation process are compensated, thus the donor should be included as well. n294 Creating a market for organs may actually fail to increase the supply because otherwise altruistic donations may be curtailed. n295 It also risks offending many citizens and takes advantage of the poor who may not otherwise choose to donate or sell organs. b. Futures Market A less controversial version of a compensation system is a futures market. A futures market would allow healthy individuals during life to contract for the sale of their body tissue for delivery after their death. n296 Under this regime, if the donor's organs are successfully harvested and transplanted, the donor's estate would receive payment. n297 Like the current donation system, people would sign donor cards, but unlike the current system, the donor or vendor would receive compensation. n298 Proponents of this system claim it avoids ethical problems. First, by not using live donors, proponents claim it does not exploit the poor. n299 Second, the system does not deal with allocation so the [*952] rich will not have greater access to organs than the poor. n300 Third, people will be selling their own organs, so relatives will not have to participate. n301 This system requires creating and legally enforcing property rights in the decedent's body . This system is only hypothetical and has not yet been attempted in any jurisdiction. If implemented in the current system, it would clearly violate NOTA, because it involves sales of organs. In addition, it might exploit the poor because only the poor would have incentive to sell their organs, unless the price was high enough for moderately wealthy individuals to be interested. Even though the system does not deal with allocation, the poor will naturally be discriminated against because they may be unable to afford the organs if Medicaid or other government assistance does not cover them. c. Death Benefits A death benefits system, while not market-based, is a third type of compensation system. Such a system would merely provide incentives to relatives of the decedent in exchange for donating the decedent's organs. n302 Examples of incentives include estate tax deductions, funeral expense allow-ances, and college education benefits. n303 As illustrated above, Pennsylvania is experimenting with a death benefits system in its newly enacted legislation. n304 Proponents argue that a death benefits system does not conflict with the current altruistic system. n305 Proponents also assert that a death benefits system does not violate NOTA's prohibition of organ sales, because Congress did not intend to include this kind of compensation. n306 With respect to the Pen-nsylvania law, proponents claim funeral expenses could be a reasonable expense exempted from the NOTA prohibition. n307 They claim that because money does not go directly to donors or beneficiaries, the payment is not technically for organs. n308 Opponents claim that a death benefits system con-stitutes the sale of organs; indirect compensation is given in exchange for one's [*953] organs. This proposal, set up as a pilot program administered by individual states, is promising. B. Suggestions First, solutions must be found for the problems of the current system, in which an outright market is inappropriate, but in which incentive programs and public health education could serve as successful boosts to the organ supply. For the second stage, after technology alters the status and supply of organs, society can plan a solution for the future. Only at that point could a full-fledged market be an acceptable, ethical medium to exchange organs. 1. The Current System As illustrated above, problems are inherent in the current organ transplantation system. Society must cope with the problems as they exist today, using currently available technology and resources. The best way to address the immediate organ shortage is to administer pilot programs providing incentives for organ donations, following the lead of Pennsylvania. Congress should propose an Amendment to NOTA that would allow the Department of Health and Human Services to oversee pilot programs. Compensation would rise incrementally, beginning with small payments, such as funeral expenses or hospital bills. The prohibition of sales of organs should remain in place for live organs because allowing sales of live organs jeopardizes existing life and brings into play many ethical issues. Thus, the amendment would only apply to organs of decedents. In addition to avoiding the ethical problems inherent in a market for organs, allowing an incentive system would probably increase awareness of donation, increase actual donation, and fairly and tactfully compensate the donor. The approach is an important bridge to the future when engineered organs will make compensation systems viable. Most importantly, more patients, who would otherwise die, will benefit from receiving life-saving organs. Organ donation does not have to be perceived as a grim, avoidable topic; donating organs transforms death into a positive experience - essentially bestowing the gift of life. In addition to the pilot programs, governmental efforts should focus on public health education. If the public is made more aware of the plight, the decision to donate organs would be made prior to death. This tactic would avoid difficult, uncomfortable situations for families and doctors, which often prevent donation. Many states already have [*954] implemented organ donor awareness funds, funded through donations when renewing driver's licenses or filing taxes. n309 Similar programs must be established. Public health officials should talk to high school students about organ donation. Special task forces could explain the organ transplant system to people, in the form of television commercials or advertisements in magazines. The erection of billboards with organ donation messages would implant the seed in people's minds. 2. The Future System The current solution only affects organs from decedents. In the foreseeable future, technology will create live organs from existing cells and biodegradable scaffolds. When that occurs, the organ shortage will no longer be a problem. But in order to have potentially unlimited organs, cell donation must occur. This may eventually be done individually at birth, but phased in by adults contributing to a generic pool. Will these donors be compensated for their pre-organ donation? The donation of cells differs from a functioning organ and probably lies outside of organ transplantation laws. Most likely, providing compensation for this stage would be allowable and beneficial. An individual donating his cells would face no risk to his health by donating. Fewer ethical issues are involved. Therefore, for the organ system of the future, allowing incentives to donors is a sound idea. This can only become a reality if the common law develops, allowing a property right in live tissue and organs . This will be established in the marketplace as long as common law and statutory law do not prohibit sales. That wrecks biotech research Spinello 4 – Clinical Associate Professor @ Carroll School of Management at Boston College Richard A., “Property rights in genetic information” Ethics and Information Technology 6:29–42 // It is axiomatic, therefore, that a property right will efficiently protect the interests of patients and donors. But, despite the laudable intentions embodied in this property rights approach to genetic source material, there are notable disadvantages and externalities. The major problem with the adoption of a property rights regime for genetic information is economic ineffi- ciency. Fragmented property rights in the genetic data coming from multiple sources would require a substantial integration effort if that data were needed for a particular research project. The higher trans- action costs imposed by a property regime would almost certainly constitute an obstacle for biomedical research. A market which recognizes these ‘‘up- stream’’ property rights, such as monopolistic patents for genes or proprietary rights in genetic data, would function by licensing this ‘‘property’’ to downstream researchers and biotech firms which are working to develop treatments of genetically based diseases and diagnostic tools. Consider the impediments to that downstream research such as the negotiations with multiple owners required by this property regime, the payment of licensing fees to these owners, the likeli- hood that some of the owners will act opportunisti- cally and hold up the project. All of this will greatly inhibit research and increase the cost of important end products . Thus, the adverse social and economic effects of recognizing these rights seems beyond dis- pute. But what does the law have to say about the property rights of sources? ¶ In the most pertinent legal case of Moore v. Re- gents of California 22 the California Supreme Court rejected Moore’s claim that his property right had been violated when doctors did not share the com- mercial gains they had obtained through the use of his surgically excised spleen cells. A key issue in this case was whether or not Moore owned his human tissue source along with the genetic information co- ded into his cells, but the court concluded that he did not have a valid ownership claim. The court’s ratio- nale was that the bestowal of such a property right would hinder scientific research: ‘‘this exchange of scientific materials, which is still relatively free and efficient, will surely be compromised if each cell sample becomes the potential subject matter of a lawsuit’’ ( Moore v. Regents of California , 1990). The court was worried that the nascent biotechnology industry would be irreparably harmed if researchers were forced to ‘‘investigate the consensual pedigree of each human cell sample used in research’’ ( Moore v. Regents of California , 1990). In making its decision the Moore court at least implicitly rejected the claim that researchers were bound to share the sometimes ample rewards of that research with those who con- tribute human tissue (or other samples) like Mr. Moore.¶ The problem, underscored in the Moore decision, is that society has a critical interest in stimulating biomedical research. And this includes the kind of research that is being conducted by deCODE Genetics. As Harrison 23 observes, progress in bio- technology research will become ‘‘unduly burdened by the existence of too many intellectual property rights in basic research tools.’’ Property held in common is subject to a ‘‘tragedy of the commons,’’ since individual incentives are often at variance with the collective good. Each individual’s marginal exploitation of some common property (such as a fertile track of land) ultimately destroys that property. But if we effectively remove valuable scientific data from the intellectual commons through the assignment of proprietary rights we get the opposite of a tragedy of the commons, that is, a tragedy of the anti-commons. 24 In this case too few resources are held in common and researchers are blocked from using source material (such as genes or genetic data) that have become privatized unless they negotiate with a multiplicity of owners. The rights of usage become so fragmented that it is virtually impossible to conduct productive research. The end result is an unfortunate suboptimal underconsumption of human genetic material, and that material is obviously criti- cal for the development of downstream products such as diagnostic tests and gene therapies.¶ There is considerable risk, therefore, that excessive ownership of information inputs, such as genetic data, and other source material will impose high costs and formidable burdens on the flow of critical scientific information. Biomedical research depends upon the open availability of genetic data resources so long as privacy is ensured. High transaction costs and perverse anti-commons effects, however, will undermine that availability if property rights are granted. Also, while ownership might result in some compensation for those individuals who license their genetic sequences or sell their genetic information, that compensation will be trivial in most cases, and it will be far offset by the social good of better health- care that will be realized by research efforts unen- cumbered by these transaction costs.¶ One of the ironies of the Moore case, however, is that the court seemed to contradict itself. It refused to recognize a property right for Moore in the name of research but it concluded that the collectors of genetic data would need such a property right (in the form of a patent) as an incentive. Otherwise, the Court rea- soned, ‘‘the theory of liability that Moore urges us to endorse threatens to destroy the economic incentive to conduct important medical research’’ ( Moore v. Re- gents of California , 1990). As Boyle 25 points out, the notion that ‘‘property rights must be given to those who do the mining [of genetic material]’’ is indicative of the ‘‘doctrinal chaos’’ of intellectual property law.¶ DNA material including genes, gene fragments (called expressed sequence tags or ESTs), and related products, are considered to be patentable subject matter. The Patent Act does not cover ‘‘the gene as it occurs in nature’’ (Utility Examination Guidelines), 26 but when a gene has been isolated and purified it is considered to have been modified. This makes it a ‘‘new composition of matter’’ eligible for patent protection. This conclusion seems consistent with the U.S. Congress’s apparent intention that the patent statute cover ‘‘anything under the sun that is made by man’’. 27 Three types of patents are possible: structure patents, covering the isolated and purified gene; function patents, covering a new use for the DNA in question (such as a diagnostic test or gene therapy); and process patents which cover a new method of isolating, purifying, or synthesizing this DNA mate- rial. 28¶ The patentability of genetic material such as DNA sequences is an intricate and complex issue. Sup- porters of those patents argue that without the incentive of patents the genome will not be ade- quately exploited by researchers. Opponents such as Hettinger 29 argue against patents out of respect for life, which should not be the subject of patents. The source or raw material for the gene patents is human tissue, and some ethicists claim that patents should not be given for human material.¶ The validity and scope of patent protection in the human genome is a question we cannot settle here. But the issue of gene patentability is analogous to the question of ownership of an individual’s genetic information and deserves some treatment. What is particularly significant in the Moore decision is the claim that ‘‘private ownership of genetic materials could dull the pace of medical innovation’’. 30 We have argued that this principle should apply to the ultimate sources, that is, patients and donors sup- plying genetic information and raw material (such as human tissue). But it should also apply to a limited extent to third party researchers and their claims for human gene patents.¶ As we have observed, the problem is that sub- stances which are upstream in the research cycle must be made easily accessible for downstream research. According to Horn, 31 ‘‘This kind of information is considered basic research and provides the data that is necessary for making end products such as drugs, diagnostic tests, and other treatments based on genes and their products.’’ The gene is a basic tool of re- search, and according to some critics, seeking an exclusive right to a gene by means of a patent is like ‘‘trying to gain ownership of the alphabet’’. 32 When DNA is abstracted from human tissue or blood the goal is to produce a gene that functions exactly as it would in the human body. The lab that does this work can get a patent for this gene or DNA sequence even though the utility of this ‘‘invention’’ is sometimes vague or trivial and the gene in question may be critical for future research projects conducted by other scientists. We now know, for example, that there are many diseases caused by defects in multiple genes. According to Pinto (2002), research has shifted from Mendelian diseases (involving a single gene) to ‘‘polygenic disorders’’ involving several genes. But under the current system researchers will need to lo- cate the patentees of these genes and pay royalty fees for doing research. As Horn (2002) points out, ‘‘if the licensing and transaction costs are too high, these valuable downstream innovations [such as therapeutic and diagnostic products] will never take place.’’¶ It is a mistake, therefore, to award proprietary rights too far upstream in the research and develop- ment value chain for biotech products. This includes patents for genes and gene fragments and it also in- cludes providing property rights in the ultimate source material: human tissue and the genetic information that it contains. As we have seen, the upshot of granting such rights is a tragedy of the anti-commons: resources will be under utilized and downstream research and commercialization efforts will be hampered.¶ In addition, loosely awarding proprietary rights too far upstream in the value chain will most likely raise the cost of downstream innovations. According to Pollack (2002), about 14 % of the cost of gene therapies is attributable to the royalties that must be paid to gene patent holders. Those costs will surely increase even further if donors of DNA samples or participants in genetic studies also demand royalties for therapeutic products based on their genetic information.¶ It is also worth considering whether or not gene patents can be justified on a normative basis. For example, are they justifiable when viewed from the perspective of Locke’s labor-desert theory? Stripped of its subtleties, that theory claims that labor engen- ders a property right. According to Locke, people engage in labor not for its own sake but to reap its benefits; as a result, it would be unjust not to let people have these benefits they take such pains to procure. In short, property rights are required as a return for the laborers’ painful and strenuous work. As Locke 33 maintains, one who takes the laborer’s property ‘‘desire[s] the benefit of another’s pains, which he has no right to.’’ In the case of gene frag- ments the labor desert view provides no support since little labor is involved in sequencing these frag- ments. 34 On the other hand, sequencing the entire gene is more labor intensive so a patent for a full length gene appears to be on firmer ground. ¶ But Locke calls for limits on the acquisition of property even when a property right seems to be commensurate with the labor performed. According to Locke, the bestowal of a property right should be denied unless there is ‘‘enough, and as good left for others’’ (Locke, 1952). This proviso, when applied to intellectual property, implies that the granting of a property right should not harm the intellectual com- mons. In this context, awarding an exclusive entitle- ment will interfere with the research activities of other scientists who will find it difficult to pursue related or similar research trajectories. As Shaw 35 indicates, there is compelling evidence that gene patents are having ill-effects on research: ‘‘With genetic patents staking private claims to huge chunks of [genetic] code, researchers and clinicians are finding their ge- netic research and diagnostic efforts thwarted by various restrictions imposed by commercial, and in some instances, academic, patent holders.’’ Given that the commons is impaired by the removal of a gene that has been patentented, a Lockean justification for genetic patents seems dubious. Arguably, a modified property right that requires access at a reasonable cost (for example, some form of compulsory licensing) will resolve this problem and be more consistent with Locke’s liberal philosophy of property rights.¶ Given the high social costs of strong and broad patent rights, they are also hard to justify from a utilitarian perspective. There is a case to be made, however, on utilitarian grounds for some types of gene patents as a basis for stimulating genetic re- search. The American Medical Association advocates patents on processes used to isolate and purify gene sequences, substance patents on purified proteins, and gene patents ‘‘only if the inventor has demon- strated a practical, real world, specific and substantial use (credible utility) for the [gene] sequence’’. 36 Thus, according to this policy a gene patent would not be awarded as a tool for scientific research but only in cases where a practical use has been demonstrated. The AMA policy also calls for access to gene patents by all ‘‘certified laboratories at a reasonable cost’’ so that other researchers will be able to build upon these innovations (Horn, 2002). These limited genetic pat- ents would preserve incentives but minimize inter- ference with downstream research initiatives.¶ But what about the protection of privacy and autonomy rights? Are we sacrificing these basic hu- man goods for the sake of biomedical research? Absolutely not. We have made a tenable case on utilitarian grounds that property rights in genetic material are unsound since the social costs are dis- proportionate to the benefits received. Those costs include the inhibition of research and higher prices for therapeutic products and genetic screenings. Society benefits tremendously from the enhancement of human health through biomedical research and when that research is constrained the social welfare loss (such as undeveloped treatments or genetic screening products) is quite substantial. It may be that privacy and autonomy are marginally safer with a property right, but, as we will demonstrate in the next section, sound privacy legislation based on in- formed consent can also be an effective means of ensuring genetic privacy and autonomy. Critical to avoid extinction Noble 13 RONALD K. NOBLE is Secretary General of Interpol, Foreign Affairs, November/December 2013, "Keeping Science in the Right Hands", http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/140157/ronald-knoble/keeping-science-in-the-right-hands But science still must proceed unhindered. If biological research and the development of new scientific techniques are not allowed to progress, the very fabric of human existence could be affected . Diseases will continue to mutate, and without robust scientific research to produce better vaccines, human health could be endangered. Therefore, all nations should safeguard their sciences and ensure that future scientific developments generate significant advances for the good of all. [end of article] 1NC POLITICS Keystone supporters are courting moderate dems for a veto-proof majority Colman 12/15 Zack, “Keystone XL: So will it finally get built?” [http://www.washingtonexaminer.com/keystone-so-will-itfinally-get-built/article/2557281?custom_click=rss] // REPUBLICANS PUSH AHEAD Republicans say passing legislation to build the pipeline will be a top legislative priority when the GOP takes control of both chambers in January. They see it as a way to present a contrasting agenda to Obama, whose administration has been reviewing and stalling on Keystone XL since 2008.¶ "It shows the fundamental difference. You've got the Obama administration that's held up the project for six years. That is about a $7.9 billion investment, not one penny of federal government spending. But it creates energy, it creates jobs, it created hundreds of millions in tax revenue," Sen. John Hoeven said.¶ "It shows the difference in approach," the North Dakota Republican said.¶ Hoeven is leading the charge to put legislation approving the remaining 1,200 miles of pipeline on Obama's desk early next year.¶ A bill to approve the pipeline failed by one vote in November, one of the last orders of business for the Democratic-held Senate. GOP lawmakers think that, with support from centrist Democrats, they could get the 67 Senate votes needed to override a veto from Obama.¶ Republicans and Democrats who support the pipeline say it will create a gusher of construction jobs. The State Department said it would support 42,100 direct and indirect jobs during the two-year construction phase and would boost property tax revenue for communities along the route. It also would strengthen energy security by getting crude from Canada, an ally, rather than less friendly nations such as Venezuela.¶ Still, even with Republicans in the majority, Hoeven is cautious.¶ "I know that we're over 60, but I don't know that we can get to 67," he said. "If he vetoes it, then we can try to attach it to other legislation."¶ Obama likely would reject any bill that forces his hand on the pipeline, as he has consistently threatened to veto bills that circumvent the State Department's review. That review is on hold until the Nebraska Supreme Court rules on whether a new pipeline route the state legislature approved was constitutional. That decision is expected any day.¶ Congress might have the legal authority to authorize pipeline construction as the State Department dallies. A 2012 report by the Congressional Research Service found that doing so "appears likely to be a legitimate exercise of Congress’s constitutional authority to regulate foreign commerce."¶ The pipeline has become a political albatross around Obama's neck.¶ It has kept centrist Democrats at odds with the president. A clutch of Democratic senators who pleaded with Obama to approve the project lost their seats in last month's midterm elections, as Republicans tied their opponents to the president and his policies. ¶ Many labor unions, too, have broken ranks with the president over the pipeline because they want the jobs it would provide.¶ Even environmental groups have largely moved on, at least in the political sense. Several senators who publicly supported Keystone XL netted official endorsements and funding from the same green organizations that are trying to kill the project.¶ That has some Keystone XL boosters thinking that Obama might want to end the whole episode.¶ "I don't expect it's going to have to be a veto override. I think we can find a way to resolve it with a strong bipartisan vote because there's a lot of Democrats who would tell the president, 'You know, enough's enough. Let's move on with this issue.' So I suspect that is what's going to happen," Gerard said.¶ ¶ OBAMA KICKS THE CAN¶ Perhaps that's wishful thinking, considering the political capital Obama has spent continually punting the project.¶ In August 2011, the State Department released its first final environmental review of the pipeline, saying it wouldn't significantly alter the Earth's climate. The announcement came during two weeks of Washington demonstrations against the pipeline that led to more than 1,200 arrests and elevated Keystone XL into the national conscience. ¶ Three months later, when he was running for re-election, the president said the State Department needed to conduct another environmental review to analyze the new pipeline route that Nebraska's legislature had just approved.¶ The review process hasn't been transparent, and it has faced several delays. When the review finally came out in January, which largely backed the August 2011 findings, many hoped for a quick 90-day inter agency review to determine whether the project was in the national interest. But then the Obama administration said it would wait for the Nebraska Supreme Court decision before resuming the process.¶ Meanwhile, Obama has made repeated public comments that appear to side with environmental groups. He has made light of the 35 permanent jobs Keystone XL is expected to create. He has said he would kill the pipeline if it "exacerbates the problem of carbon pollution."¶ "It's good for Canada, it could create a couple thousand jobs in the initial construction of the pipeline. But we've got to measure that against whether or not it is going to contribute to an overall warming of the planet that could be disastrous," Obama said last week on "The Colbert Report."¶ A recent remark Obama made during a November speech in Burma caught the attention of Charles Ebinger, a senior fellow with the Brookings Institution's Energy Security Initiative.¶ The president contended oil sands piped from Alberta would be exported to other nations, echoing attacks from environmental groups such as NextGen Climate Action, the super PAC backed by Tom Steyer, a billionaire former hedge fund manager. But Ebinger said refineries would be the ideal destination for the oil sands. Drillers sending oil to refineries in the upper Midwest had to reduce their crude prices last year because of transportation bottlenecks. And Gulf Coast refineries are equipped to process the heavier crude from the oil sands. ¶ Petroleum products such as gasoline might be exported, Ebinger said, but much of the oil would remain in the country.¶ "The fact that he made that statement, to me, is that he believes Keystone isn't important to the U.S.," Ebinger said.¶ That comment also caught the attention of Deborah Gordon, director of the Energy and Climate Program with the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. ¶ "I just don't know that he's going to put his guns down on this," she said.¶ At this point, it's not clear how Obama would benefit politically from approving Keystone XL after years of waiting. Congressional Republicans are unlikely to cut a deal to approve one of the administration's priorities, such as raising the federal minimum wage, just to get the pipeline through.¶ The same goes for the increasingly liberal Democratic Party. Keystone XL backers in Alaska, Louisiana, North Carolina and Arkansas all pushed Obama to approve the project. All of them lost their elections. A Democrat winning a Senate race in any of those states appears unlikely for some time.¶ "I'm not sure what the president gains from it at this point, or what the Democratic Party gains in the long term," Ebinger said. "I think the president would like to punt this indefinitely."¶ Delays are starting to annoy even Democrats who have opposed the project. Some are starting to speak out against what they consider disingenuous climate change concerns posed by environmental groups.¶ Sen. Tom Carper, D-Del., said more progress on climate change is occurring in other arenas. He pointed to a nonbinding agreement between Obama and Chinese President Xi Jinping on reducing greenhouse gas emissions beyond 2020, a move that would get the world's top two emitters on the same page for the first time.¶ "That dwarfs the concerns that we've heard now for a number of years on Keystone," Carper said recently. "I think the other factor that's working here is we have waited for not months, but years, to get a decision on Keystone." ¶ Hoeven said he thinks the legislative style that incoming Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell, R-Ky., hopes to install would smooth passage for a bipartisan Keystone XL bill that includes energy items important to some Democrats.¶ McConnell has hinted he would operate with an open amendment process, unlike current Majority Leader Harry Reid, D-Nev., who has blocked amendments.¶ "I fully expect that we will bring the bill to the floor, and there will be an open amendment process," Hoeven said. "Maybe there will be some amendments offered that have some broad support to get over the 67-vote threshold."¶ That could lure other Democrats. Sen. Chris Coons, D-Del., for example, voted against the Keystone XL bill in November. But given the chance to advance one of his top priorities — for years he has advocated extending a tax structure known as "master limited partnerships" to renewable energy — he might vote for building the pipeline. Obama PC key to sustainable veto – he’s successfully corralling democrats now Eilperin 12/3 Juliet, “Obama, looking to mend fences with Congress, is reaching out. To Democrats.” [http://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/obama-looking-to-mend-fences-with-congress-is-reaching-out-todemocrats/2014/12/03/3fdf9078-7a40-11e4-9a27-6fdbc612bff8_story.html] // President Obama and his closest aides have determined that their best chance of success in the next two years will depend on improved relationships on Capitol Hill, but their behind-thescenes efforts are more focused on Obama’s own party rather than the Republicans who are about to take full charge of Congress in January.¶ Obama’s attention on congressional Democrats, allies whom he once regarded as needing little attention, marks a shift in his view on how to deal with Congress. The president now sees his path to success as running through Hill Democrats, a group that has been disenchanted by the treatment it has received from the White House over the years.¶ The remedial work has included frequent calls to Democratic leaders since the midterm elections and comes as Republicans prepare to take control of both chambers for the first time since Obama took office. While the president and GOP leaders have pledged to seek common ground, Obama’s use of executive action to alter immigration enforcement procedures and other steps have already angered Republicans, making significant legislative accomplishments more difficult. ¶ And White House officials are looking to Hill Democrats as a defense against Republican efforts to undo key elements of Obama’s legislative legacy, including the Affordable Care Act, his immigration action and climate policy.¶ The president’s ability to sustain the vetoes he is likely to issue will depend on whether he is able to mend relations with congressional Democrats — many of whom blame the president for the party’s large midterm losses — and persuade Republican legislators to work with him in a way that has eluded the two parties for the past six years.¶ On Wednesday, the outreach effort began publicly as Obama hosted Sen. Mitch McConnell (R-Ky.) — who will lead the Senate starting in January — in the Oval Office. It was the first time the two have met one on one for an extended period in more than four years. The most recent small gathering they had was with Vice President Biden, nearly 3 1/2 years ago. ¶ McConnell spokesman Don Stewart called the session “a good meeting” but did not release additional details. ¶ By contrast, House Minority Whip Steny H. Hoyer (D-Md.) has been in near-constant communication with the White House since the midterm elections. He received back-to-back calls from Obama on Nov. 24 and 25, the first to discuss the administration’s handling of sanctions against Iran amid ongoing negotiations over that nation’s nuclear program, and the second to confer on the two men’s shared opposition to a pending proposal extending a series of federal tax breaks.¶ “In the past couple of months, I’ve seen heightened outreach,” Hoyer said in an interview Tuesday. “To some degree, we become even more relevant than we were before. Now he needs to rely on both houses to sustain a veto.”¶ Those are not the only calls Hoyer has received from the White House recently. Obama’s chief of staff, Denis McDonough — who paid a visit to House Minority Leader Nancy Pelosi (DCalif.) on Tuesday — called Hoyer on Nov. 13 to discuss an effort by lawmakers to force federal approval of the Keystone XL oil pipeline and on Nov. 25 to talk about tax policy. The White House legislative-affairs staff also called him Nov. 6 to discuss immigration policy, a day after Obama called him at home in the evening to discuss immigration and ongoing efforts to counter the Islamic State.¶ Hoyer, who was also part of a group of Democratic leaders who had dinner with the president last month in advance of his immigration announcement, said those discussions have allowed him to have an impact on issues such as how the administration is working to fund its military strategy in Iraq and Syria.¶ “I do believe I was part of the conversation that has hopefully focused us all on accomplishing the president’s objectives,” he said.¶ Outreach efforts¶ Sen. Robert P. Casey Jr. (D-Pa.), another White House ally, said there have been “substantial improvements” in the president’s legislative outreach, in large part because Obama’s director of legislative affairs, Katie Beirne Fallon, has revived an operation that had been moribund for an extended period. ¶ “Just speaking as a Democratic senator, that was not a problem-free area,” Casey said, adding that he had this advice for the White House a few months ago: “My main suggestion is they needed to have more ‘What do you think?’ meetings instead of ‘Here’s what we’re doing’ meetings.” ¶ Rep. Joseph Crowley (D-N.Y.), who co-chairs the Congressional Caucus on India and Indian-Americans, got McDonough to meet with about a dozen members of the bipartisan group in late May. Crowley said the group pushed for more of a focus on India. “Obviously, there has been a tremendous enhancement in that relationship,” he said.¶ The White House has dramatically stepped up its use of perks for lawmakers in the past year. At the president’s request, his staff is making more room for members on Air Force One (eight lawmakers flew with him to Las Vegas for his immigration event there last month), and he now gives a shout-out to nearly all lawmakers who attend his public speeches. This year his staff issued more than 4,270 invitations to come to the White House, travel with the president or attend his events, almost double the number handed out in 2012, and it is letting lawmakers use the President’s Box at the Kennedy Center more often. ¶ The plan is political suicide Calandrillo 4 [Steve Calandrillo (Law Prof—U of Washington); George Mason Law Review, Vol. 13, pp. 69-133, 2004; “Cash for Kidneys? Utilizing Incentives to End America's Organ Shortage”] REAL REFORMS: UTILIZING INCENTIVES TO END THE NATION’S ORGAN SHORTAGE Despite the above analysis, any form of legalized human organ market would be far from a utopian solution: it would be political suicide to propose, entail significant administrative costs to establish and monitor, and remain morally distasteful to many Americans. While such markets havebeen debated without much progress in the past, far less attention has been paid to dozens of other monetary and nonmonetary incentives that could be employed. Taking an incentive-based approach would avoid imposing risk on living donors, dramatically expand the pool of available organs, and shock the conscience far less than allowing living-seller markets.190 Keystone approval causes fast, catastrophic climate change Joe Romm, Think Progress, 6/5/11, James Hansen slams Keystone XL Canada-U.S. Pipeline: “Exploitation of tar sands would make it implausible to stabilize climate and avoid disastrous global climate impacts”, thinkprogress.org/climate/2011/06/05/236978/james-hansen-keystone-pipeline-tarsands-climate/ The Canadian tar sands are substantially dirtier than conventional oil as the chart above shows (longer analysis here). They may contain enough carbon-intensive fuel to make stabilizing atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide at non-catastrophic levels all but impossible. And that is the point of Dr. James Hansen in a must-read essay on the proposed Keystone XL Pipeline to bring that dirty fuel into this country, “Silence Is Deadly: I’m Speaking Out Against Canada-U.S. Tar Sands Pipeline.” Hansen, director of NASA’s Goddard Institute for Space Studies, has been right longer about the climate than just about anyone else (see “Right for 27 years: 1981 Hansen study finds warming trend that could raise sea levels“). So he deserves to be heard. Here is his essay, to which I’ve added some commentary with links: The U.S. Department of State seems likely to approve a huge pipeline, known as Keystone XL to carry tar sands oil (about 830,000 barrels per day) to Texas refineries unless sufficient objections are raised. The scientific community needs to get involved in this fray now. If this project gains approval, it will become exceedingly difficult to control the tar sands monster. The environmental impacts of tar sands development include: irreversible effects on biodiversity and the natural environment, reduced water quality, destruction of fragile pristine Boreal Forest and associated wetlands, aquatic and watershed mismanagement, habitat fragmentation, habitat loss, disruption to life cycles of endemic wildlife particularly bird and Caribou migration, fish deformities and negative impacts on the human health in downstream communities. Although there are multiple objections to tar sands development and the pipeline, including destruction of the environment in Canada, and the likelihood of spills along the pipeline’s pathway, such objections, by themselves, are very unlikely to stop the project. For more on the pipeline controversy, see “WikiLeaks reveals State Department discord over U.S. support for Canadian tar sands oil pipeline.” An overwhelming objection is that exploitation of tar sands would make it implausible to stabilize climate and avoid disastrous global climate impacts. The tar sands are estimated (e.g., see IPCC Fourth Assessment Report) to contain at least 400 GtC (equivalent to about 200 ppm CO2). Easily available reserves of conventional oil and gas are enough to take atmospheric CO2 well above 400 ppm, which is unsafe for life on earth. However, if emissions from coal are phased out over the next few decades and if unconventional fossil fuels including tar sands are left in the ground, it is conceivable to stabilize earth’s climate. Extinction Flournoy 12 (Citing Dr. Feng Hsu, a NASA scientist at the Goddard Space Flight Center, in 2012, Don Flournoy, PhD and MA from the University of Texas, Former Dean of the University College @ Ohio University, Former Associate Dean @ State University of New York and Case Institute of Technology, Project Manager for University/Industry Experiments for the NASA ACTS Satellite, Currently Professor of Telecommunications @ Scripps College of Communications @ Ohio University, Citing Dr. "Solar Power Satellites," Chapter 2: What Are the Principal Sunsat Services and Markets?, January, Springer Briefs in Space Development, Book) In the Online Journal of Space Communication, Dr. Feng Hsu, a NASA scientist at Goddard Space Flight Center, a research center in the forefront of science of space and Earth, writes, “The evidence of global warming is alarming,” noting the potential for a catastrophic planetary climate change is real and troubling (Hsu 2010). Hsu and his NASA colleagues were engaged in monitoring and analyzing cli- mate changes on a global scale, through which they received first-hand scientific information and data relating to global warming issues, including the dynamics of polar ice cap melting. After discussing this research with colleagues who were world experts on the subject, he wrote: I now have no doubt global temperatures are rising, and that global warming is a serious problem confronting all of humanity. No matter whether these trends are due to human interference or to the cosmic cycling of our solar system, there are two basic facts that are crystal clear: (a) there is overwhelming scientific evidence showing positive correlations between the level of CO2 concentrations in Earth’s atmosphere with respect to the historical fluctuations of global temperature changes; and (b) the overwhelming majority of the world’s scientific community is in agreement about the risks of a potential catastrophic global climate change. That is, if we humans continue to ignore this problem and do noth- ing, if we continue dumping huge quantities of greenhouse gases into Earth’s biosphere, humanity will be at dire risk (Hsu 2010). As a technology risk assessment expert, Hsu says he can show with some confi- dence that the planet will face more risk doing nothing to curb its fossil-based energy addictions than it will in making a fundamental shift in its energy supply. “This,” he writes, “is because the risks of a catastrophic anthropogenic climate change can be potentially the extinction of human species, a risk that is simply too high for us to take any chances” (Hsu 2010). It was this NASA scientist’s conclusion that humankind must now embark on the next era of “sustainable energy consumption and re-supply, the most obvious source of which is the mighty energy resource of our Sun” (Hsu 2010) (Fig. 2.1). 1NC SHORTAGES Cadaveric organs can’t meet demand Hughes 3 [Nancy Scheper-Hughes (Professor of Anthropology—Cal-Berkeley; Cofounder and Director—Organs Watch, a medical human rights organization that monitors international organ trafficking); “Rotten trade: millennial capitalism, human values and global justice in organs trafficking”; 2003; Journal of Human Rights, 2:2, 197-226] The present scenario began over two decades ago with the realization by transplant professionals in the USA and elsewhere that cadaver organs , for many complex social reasons (Lock 2002) would never supply the growing demand for a steady supply of transplantable organs. Meanwhile, advances in immunology and the development of powerful new anti-rejection drugs such as cyclosporin made close tissue matching between donor and recipient unnecessary. The positive outcomes for kidney transplant patients who have purchased kidneys from impoverished vendors in various parts of the world where basic blood- but not tissue-matching procedures are followed, in clandestine commercialized transactions, lead to a growing realization that an excellent HLA tissue match is no longer required to achieve a successful transplant outcome. Today almost any person willing to be an organ donor, ideally medically suited or not , can do so. And living donor organs – one kidney, half a liver and lobe of one lung – are becoming the organs of choice to supply the growing demands for transplant from ever expanding waiting lists. Meanwhile, living donor organs are also preferred by surgeons and their patients to increase the longevity and viability of transplants. In 2001, for the first time, in the United States live donor kidney transplant accounted for 50% of all transplants, and living donor liver transplants rose to 10% (Delmonico 2002). The consumers: the body and commodity fetishism Transplant procedures are astronomically expensive (in the United States a heart transplant costs more than $300 000) and are frequently hindered by so-called shortages in organs. The media, prompted by organs procurement organizations, produce frequent references to the numbers of people who will die each year waiting for an organ. (There is no system to track or record the health, medical problems, or deaths of those who have donated organs.) In the United States over 70 000 people appear on organs waiting lists. Every year the demand for organs increases as transplant organizations, transplant professionals and patients’ rights groups demand that new (and marginal) categories of p eople become eligible for organ transplants. For example, at their annual meetings in Leiden, The Netherlands, in September 2000, members of Eurotransplant actively and enthusiastically supported new experiments that expanded transplant waiting lists to include the medical margins – those over 70 years, infants, those with hepatitis C and HIV seropositivity, and those proven to be immunologically prone to organ rejection. There was no consciousness or recognition that these experiments would inflate the dem and for organs and promote desperate means, including the black market, to obtain them. Instead, these programs were defended as democratic in their inclusiveness and as a service to medical consumers demanding the right to any and all advanced medical procedures now available. Similarly, kidney and transplant patient advocacy groups in many parts of the world – from Brazil to Israel to Iran to the United States – have articulated a new medical consumers bill of rights, one that includes a patient’s right to transplant and even to unobstructed access to the life-saving and healthy spare organs of ‘the other’, for which patients are willing to travel great distances and to pay a negotiable, market-based price. In continuing to articulate the current dilemma of transplant, under these new social conditions, in terms of sc arcity, supply and demand – when the precious ‘commodities’ in question are increasingly attached to living bodies – serious ethical dilemmas are created for the patients and for their doctors who find themselves in the position of passively and inadvertently or actively creating a medically protected space for the kidney commerce. ‘Who am I to second guess, let alone to judge, my patients?’, asked Michael Friedlaender, 14 kidney transplant specialist at Hadassah Hospital, with reference to the growing numbers of patients in his hospital-based practice who have returned from overseas having purchased a kidney. Later, he was to write (2002: 971–972): ‘Here began my conversion from fierce objection to kidney marketing to passive acquiescence in this trade. We could not prevent our patients travelling to Iraq [later to Turkey, Romania, and the USA]. We gave patients who asked our advice all the information I have presented here, and warned them that we could not help them outside our national boundaries, but assured them that we would immediately assist them on their return.’ Part of the information that is given to his dialysis patients is the differential survival rates for living donor kidneys vs. cadaveric kidneys, based on research by Wolfe and his colleagues (1999) – a median (50%) graft survival of 21.6 years (living donor kidney) compared with 13.8 years for a cadaver kidney. ‘If my own kidneys failed I would opt for a transplant from a living donor’, Dr Friedlaender has said on more than one public occasion. The data on differential survival rates are circulated widely among kidney transplant surgeons around the world, and are frequently cited by their patients and directly contribute to the decision to abandon conventional cadaver organ waiting lists in pursuit of ‘fresh’ kidneys from living people. Another consumer-based stimulus behind the occult economy in living donor kidneys (and part livers) is the growing rejection of hemo-dialysis by increasingly sophisticated kidney patients. Dialysis treatment for any period of time, even as a bridge while waiting for transplant, is increasingly viewed by kidney activists as unacceptable suffering , as time on the cross. In September 2000 a young man I will call Amatai, a 23-year-old university student from Jerusalem, flew to New York City for a kidney transplant with an organ purchased from a local ‘donor’ arranged through a broker in Brooklyn. Most of the cost of the surgery ($200 000) was paid for by his Israeli ‘sick funds’ (medical insurance that is guaranteed to all Israeli citizens). Particularly noteworthy in his narrative was the almost seamless naturalization of living donation and the rejection of the artificiality of the dialysis machine: Kidney transplant from a living person is the most natural solution because you are free of the [dialysis] machine. With transplant you don’t have to go to the hospital three times a week to waste your time for three or four hours. And after each dialysis you don’t feel very well, and you sleep a lot, and on weekends you feel too tired to go out with your friends. There are still a lot of poisons left in the body and when you can’t remove them, you feel tired. Look, dialysis isn’t a normal life. And also you are limited to certain foods. You are not allowed to eat a lot of meat, salt, fruits, vegetables. Every month you do tests to see that the calcium level is OK, and even if so your skin becomes yellow. Aesthetically, dialysis isn’t very nice. A kidney transplant from a living donor is the very best, and the most natural solution. At the same time many kidney patients resist the idea of conventional ‘waiting lists’ for cadaver organs as archaic vestiges or residues of wartime triage and rationing or worse as reminiscent of socialist bread lines and petrol ‘queues’. In the present climate of biotechnological optimism and biomedical triumphalism, the very idea of a shortage, even an organs shortage, suggests a basic management, market or policy failure. The ideology of the global economy is one of unlimited and freely circulating goods. And those new commodities are evaluated, like any other, in terms of their quality, durability and market value. The cadaver kidney has been consigned to the dustbins of surgical history by those with the ability to get a living donor, like 71-year-old Avirham, a retired lawyer with end-stage kidney disease for whom time was running out and for whom neither a spectral waiting list nor a dead man’s kidney seemed like reasonable options. So, in 1999 Avraham took the decisive step to fly with Dr Zaki Shapira and several other Israeli and Italian kidney patients to an undisclosed location in Eastern Europe where they were all transplanted with kidneys purchased from displaced rural workers. The entire venture was, Avriham admits, an enormous risk. ‘You have no idea how poor where we went to was!’ he said. ‘The hospital was like something you would expect maybe in a third world country.’ But it was a risk he was willing to take to avoid the queue at home for a cadaveric kidney transplant: Why should I have to wait months and years for a kidney from someone who was in a traffic accident, pinned under the car for many hours, then in miserable condition in the ICU [intensive care unit] for weeks and only after all that trauma, have that same organ put inside me? It’s really a disgusting idea to think about putting that dead man’s organ inside you. That organ is not going to be any good! His kidney is practically dead. After it was kept on ice for several hours, how can you expect it to go right back to work for me? Or worse, I could get the kidney of an elderly person, or an alcoholic, or a person who died of a stroke. That kidney is all used up. No, it is far better to get a kidney from a healthy man or woman who can also benefit from the money I can afford to pay. Where I went for my transplant the people were so poor they did not even have bread to eat. Do you have any idea what one thousand, let alone five thousand dollars means to a peasant? The money I paid was a gift equal to the gift that I received. Obviously, free-market medicine requires a divisible body with detachable and demystified organs seen as ordinary and ‘plain things’, simple material for medical consumption. But these same ‘plain’ objects have a way of reappearing and returning like the repressed, when least expected, almost like medieval messengers and gargoyles from the past in the form of highly spiritualized and fetishized objects of desire . As Veena Das once wryly observed: ‘An organ is never just an organ’. And the fetishized or ‘designer’ kidney purchased from a living donor conjures up primitive beliefs in human immortality, transcendence and magical energy. As Averham explained his frantic and dangerous search for a living kidney donor: ‘I chose the better way. I was able to see my donor [in a small town in Eastern Europe]. My doctor pointed him out to me. He was young, strong, healthy – everything that I was hoping for!’ Here, the symbolic equations between kidney market, slave market and brothel come to the surface. Meanwhile, international Internet brokers prey on consumer prejudices and on the anxieties of transplant candidates. For example, ‘Livers-4-You’, until a few weeks ago when it was forced off cyberspace, advertised the following via kidneysurgery@s-s-net.com: ‘Want a healthy living donor next week, or a morgue organ in five years? We are a new organization with a New York City phone number and unique experience in locating the overseas pathway for those waiting too long for a transplant.’ Bioprinting solves the organ shortage – less than a decade away *momentum/new tech answers solvency deficits DAEF 14 An online platform launched by the Directorate General for Communications Networks, Content and Technology of the European Commission to facilitate a broad reflection on future European policies, “Advances in bio-artificial and 3D-printed organs” [http://ec.europa.eu/digitalagenda/futurium/en/content/advances-bio-artificial-and-3d-printed-organs] Accessed September 2, 2014 // Organs such as kidneys, livers and lungs have always been in high demand by patients with severe illnesses. In 2008, 56 000 people were waiting for a suitable organ within the European Union. The demand exceeds the number of available organs in Member States and is increasing faster than organ donation rates. Bio-artificial and 3D-printed organs are critical for overcoming this challenge.¶ Advances in bio-artificial organs¶ Bio-artificial organs are the products of tissue engineering. Scientists explain that tissue engineering uses the concepts and tools of biotechnology, molecular and cell biology, material science and engineering to understand the structure-function relationships in mammalian tissues and to develop biological substitutes for the repair or replacement of tissue or organ functions (Bioartificial Organs as Outcomes of Tissue Engineering).¶ The generation of bioartificial organs takes part in 3 steps:¶ Obtaining the patient’s autologous cells with the help of biopsy procedure, isolating the cells from the tissue biopsy and increasing their number in the cell culture (outside the human).¶ Transferring the cells onto a carrier structure (matrix) which is usually generated from animal tissue or from synthetic components. In the lab cells sprout on the matrix, dissolve it and replace it by private proteins.¶ After reaching a level of maturation in the laboratory, the bio-artificial tissue is transplanted as replacement tissue into the patient.¶ Dr Anthony Atala, director of the Institute for Regenerative Medicine at the Wake Forest Baptist Medical Center in North Carolina (US) breaks tissue engineering into four levels of complexity:¶ Flat structures that are made up of just one type of cells are the simplest to engineer. Skin is an example.¶ Tubes like blood vessels and urethras which have two types of cells and act as a conduit.¶ Hollow non-tubular organs like the bladder and the stomach. These have more complex structures and functions.¶ Solid organs like the kidney, hearth and liver are the most complex to engineer because they have many different cell types and also require blood supply.¶ German researchers are already mass producing swatches of real human skin. As of 2009, the price per unit was 34 Euros. The skin produced by Fraunhofer-Gesellschaft is exactly like the skin on human bodies – made up of different cell types whereas skin manufactured previously used to be one thin layer made up of only one type of cell.¶ Between March 2004 and July 2007, the research team at Wake Forest University led by Dr Atala built artificial urethras for five boys using the patients' own cells. Tests measuring urine flow and tube diameter confirmed that the engineered tissue remained functional throughout the six-year follow-up period. Scientists say that bio-artificial urethras can be used successfully in patients and could be an alternative to the current treatment, which has a high failure rate.¶ Anthony Atala also reported the successful transplantation of laboratorygrown urinary bladders into beagles in 1999. Less than 10 years later the same procedure was repeated in humans suffering from end-stage bladder disease - functional bioartificial bladders were successfully implanted into patients.¶ Growing solid organs in the lab is however is much more complex. Organs like kidneys, lungs or hearts requires putting a number of different cell types into the right positions and simultaneously growing complete networks of blood vessels to keep them alive. Although the task is indeed challenging, scientists continue to make advances – Doris Taylor created a beating rat hearth at the Texas Heart Institute in Houston. At the University of Michigan David Humes created a cell-phone-size artificial kidney that has passed tests on sheep. ¶ Some scientists believe that implanting bio-artificial solid organs into humans is achievable, other remain more sceptical.¶ Advances in 3D-printed organs¶ The bioprinting trend is being driven by three factors - more sophisticated printers, refined CAD software and advances in regenerative medicine. Scientists are becoming increasingly interested in the field – from 2008 to 2011, the number of scientific papers referencing bioprinting almost tripled.¶ Bio 3D printers function in the same way as traditional 3D printers – tissue is printed layer by layer. Once a layer of cells is laid down by the printer, a layer of hydrogel that operates as a scaffold material follows and the process repeats. When the cells fuse, the hydrogel is removed to create material made entirely of human cells. The material is then moved to a bioreactor where the tissue continues to grow into its final form.¶ 3D printing has already been used to create personalised prosthetics, human bones and human tissue. For example, LayerWise, a Belgian metal parts manufacturer successfully printed a jaw bone in 2012. The artificial jaw was implanted into a 83-year old patient. San Diego-based company Organovo successfully prints small pieces of blood vessel or liver tissue. Although the mini-livers are half a millimetre deep and 4 millimetres across, they can perform most functions of the real organ. The ultimate goal of Organovo is to create human-sized structures suitable for transplantation.¶ Currently, the biggest challenge in 3D bioprinting is producing larger branched networks of blood vessels to nourish complex organs. Stuart William, executive and scientific director of the Cardiovascular Innovation Institute (US), suggests that scientists will be able to print fully functional hearts from a patient’s own cells within 10 years. First steps have already been made – in the first half of 2013 researchers printed and implanted a portion of a heart and blood vessels in mice.¶ Given the progress to date, further advances in bioprinting might even enable bionic organs – body parts that restore and extend human ability. Scientists at Princeton University have conducted experiments aiming to integrate electronics into bioprinting. Earlier in 2013 they created an ear that receives a wide range of frequencies using a coiled antenna printed with silver nanoparticles. The artificial ear can pick up frequencies beyond the range of normal human hearing. ¶ Bio-artificial and 3D-printed organs can not only alleviate the shortage of donor organs. Artificially created organs can also be used to test the impact of new drugs, thus eliminating the need to test new drugs on humans. 3D models of organs could also be used for educational and research purposes. 1NC EXPLOITATION It’s not a true choice – the people most likely to sell their organs face material constraints that dictate the decision Hughes 9 [Paul M. Hughes, PhD, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan-Dearborn, Med Philos (2009) 34 (6), “Constraint, Consent, and Well-Being in Human Kidney Sales,” http://jmp.oxfordjournals.org/content/34/6/606.full, accessed 8/22/14] I have argued in this article that recent advocates of markets in human bodily organs have sought to defend a conception of autonomy that makes it possible for a person to autonomously choose to sell a body organ irrespective of the fact that he does so involuntarily, is coerced, is compelled to do so by unjust poverty, or is exploited. I have also shown how the hierarchical conception of autonomy typically employed to articulate the nature and value of personal autonomy in these arguments actually implies that conditions of constraint sometimes generate volitional ambivalence, a state in which an agent cannot wholly identify with her higher order desires and, thus, cannot choose or act autonomously. If the circumstances of those most likely to sell a body organ in commercial organ markets constrain potential vendors in this sort of volitionally ambivalent way, then potential vendors are not autonomous . This is an important corrective to those who claim that on the preferred conception of autonomy, an agent may act autonomously even when she acts involuntarily, from coercion, or by being exploited.¶ I have also offered an analysis of how the wellbeing of potential organ vendors is marginalized in pro-market perspectives. It is disregarded in its full sense because these perspectives tend to conflate people's choices to sell organs with their consent to the contexts of constraint within which those choices are made possible and desirable. Even if people may autonomously choose within contexts of constraint that are economically unjust, those constraints define a comparatively impoverished level of well-being that can only be temporarily allayed by selling an organ.¶ Moreover, the idea that exploited persons may make autonomous choices misses the deeper reality that what makes the option of selling an organ attractive to economically disadvantaged people are the economic constraints within which they make their choices. And these, in turn, are the result of broader social, political, and economic structures over which they have no control, no meaningful voice in establishing or revising, and from which there is no exit. This is the deeper concern about exploitation that advocates of markets in human bodily organs fail to appreciate. Legalized markets remove the choice for those in poverty – creates social and legal pressure to sell their organs Rippon 12 – assistant professor in philosophy @ Central European University Simon, “Imposing options on people in poverty: the harm of a live donor organ market” J Med Ethics 2014;40:145-150 // Why an organ market would harm people in poverty ¶ Let us begin with the observation that the introduction of a legal market in bodily organs would allow many of us an additional option to get cash that we would not otherwise realistically have. We should then also recognise that the introduction of this option would fundamentally change the norms of the relationships of each of us to our bodily organs and to each other. As things stand currently, organs do not generally have a monetary value for their owners. But if organs can be easily exchanged for cash they will then become commodified, and naturally subject to the kinds of social and legal demands and responsibilities that govern our other transactions in the marketplace. For example, faced with a rent demand and inadequate cash to pay for it under the status quo, a couple of the choices you could make currently would be to sell some of your possessions, or to find (additional) employment and sell some of your labour. One choice that most of us do not realistically have as things stand (and therefore do not have to consider) is to sell an organ to raise the funds. This means that even if you have no possessions to sell and cannot find a job, nobody can reasonably criticise you for, say, failing to sell a kidney to pay your rent. If a free market in organs was permitted and became widespread, then it is reasonable to assume that your organs would soon enough become economic resources like any other, in the context of the market. Selling your organs would become something that is simply expected of you as and when financial need arises. Our new ‘option’ can thus easily be transformed into a social or legal demand, and it can drastically change the attitudes that others adopt towards you. In another context, Dworkin puts the point nicely: "Once I am aware that I have a choice, my failure to choose now counts against me. I now can be responsible, and be held responsible, for events that prior to the possibility of choosing were not attributable to me. And with the fact of responsibility comes the pressure (social and legal) to make “responsible” choices.5"¶ My contention, then, is that because people in poverty often find themselves either indebted or in need of cash to meet their own basic needs and those of their families, they would predictably find themselves faced with social or legal pressure to pay the bills by selling their organs, if selling organs were permitted. So we would harm people in poverty by introducing a legal market that would subject them to such pressures.¶ Are the harms at stake significant enough to prohibit a market in live donor organs? Oddly, when Dworkin himself writes about organ selling about a decade after having done much to elucidate the ways in which options can be bad for you, he only gives cursory consideration to the question of what harms would arise from these new options and how significant they might be. He admits that once a market price for organs is established, ‘individuals may choose not to sell [organs] in the knowledge that they have made a choice which leaves their family worse off economically than they might have been,’ and says that this may have a ‘psychic cost’.3 But this cost, he thinks, pales in comparison with the ‘psychic costs that are incurred by individuals and their families who face … death as a result of an inadequate supply of organs.’ Dworkin also identifies a second psychic cost, where if we assume that organs from family members are preferable because of tissue matches, then ‘introducing markets is likely to strain family relations’ because ‘[f]amily members are likely to be resentful of being asked to contribute without compensation when a stranger would receive substantial payment.’ But he speculates that developing immunosuppressant technology will overcome this problem.¶ But we should not limit our consideration of the potential harms imposed by the market to Dworkin's psychic costs alone. Once we have come to conceptualise our ‘excess’ organs and organ parts as pieces of unnecessary property by commodifying them, there would naturally follow genuine social and legal costs to pay for failing to sell them when economically necessary, just as there are social and legal costs to pay for failing to take employment when you are able to do so. We should ask questions such as the following: Would those in poverty be eligible for bankruptcy protection, or for public assistance, if they have an organ that they choose not to sell? Could they be legally forced to sell an organ to pay taxes, paternity bills or rent? How would society view someone who asks for charitable assistance to meet her basic needs, if she could easily sell a healthy ‘excess’ organ to meet them?¶ Such social and legal pressures do not merely impose psychic costs, and markets that introduce them can make large numbers of people considerably worse off. It is in view of the harms imposed by pressures like these that we think it necessary to enact restrictive laws for labour markets that stipulate, for example, minimum wages, minimum vacation days, parental and sick leave, and workplace safety standards, which cannot be contracted out of. These potential harms also provide us with grounds for enacting laws aimed at preventing commodification of other things, for example, laws against prostitution or against selling our children (even into the most loving homes). Wherever there is great value in not being put under social or legal pressure to sell something as a result of economic forces, we should think carefully about whether it is right to permit a market and to thereby impose the option on everyone to sell it. ¶ The prevalence of exploitation and the enormous impact of economic, social and legal pressure in real-world organ markets are supported empirically by research conducted by Goyal et al.14 They surveyed about 300 people in Chennai, India, who had sold a kidney, on average 6 years prior to the survey. They found that 96% of participants had sold their kidneys to pay off debts, and received an average of only about $1000 in return. Moreover, they found little evidence of any long-term benefit to the participants: their participants' average family incomes had declined by a third after nephrectomy, and three-fourths of them were still in debt at the time of the survey. Seventy-nine per cent of the participants would not recommend that others sell a kidney. Iran proves a legal market doesn’t solve Corwin 6 Julie, “World: The Risks, Benefits Of A Free Market In Organs” [http://www.rferl.org/content/article/1068445.html] May 16 // But Scheper-Hughes says there are no guarantees that legalizing kidney sales would end all the abuses now associated with the black market. She says that in Iran legal sales have not corrected a problem of the black market: the exploitation of poor people as organ suppliers for middle- and upper-class recipients.¶ "We know from research, including research conducted by a postdoctoral fellow of mine who was working in Iran, that the donors are often recruited from marginal populations that include, in addition to very poor people and people in debt, also include populations of young people who are disaffected from their families -- some of whom are spending a great deal of their time in the street and some of whom are drug-using people and so forth," Scheper-Hughes says. Laundry list of other countries for organ brokers to shift too Sack 14 [Kevin Sack, New York Times, 8/17/14, “Transplant Brokers in Israel Lure Desperate Kidney Patients to Costa Rica,” http://www.nytimes.com/2014/08/17/world/middleeast/transplant-brokers-in-israel-luredesperate-kidney-patients-to-costa-rica.html?_r=0, accessed 8/21/14] Experts list China, Egypt, India, Pakistan, Sri Lanka, Turkey, Eastern Europe and the former Soviet republics as hot spots for organ trafficking. But illicit transplants usually go undetected unless there is a surgical mistake or a payment dispute. Prosecutions are thwarted by false affidavits, toothless laws and lack of international cooperation, particularly regarding extradition.¶ Over the last decade, the authorities have pursued only a handful of cases worldwide. Few have sidelined the brokers, who seem bolder than ever. Some, like Mr. Volfman, who leases office space atop a mirrored skyscraper in Ramat Gan, have moved out of the shadows. They brazenly ply their trade even while under police scrutiny, posting Facebook photos of the luxury cars and five-star hotel rooms they rent on the road. Economic incentives outweigh regulatory safeguards – brokers will continue operating sales in the illicit market b/c it’s more profitable Mendoza 11 [Roger Lee Mendoza, Professor, Wilmington University/University of Pennsylvania, J Public Health (2011) 33 (1), “Price deflation and the underground organ economy in the Philippines,” http://jpubhealth.oxfordjournals.org/content/33/1/101.full#ref-10, accessed 8/22/14] The dividing line between the underground and legal transplant systems becomes razor-thin when several participants (matching agencies, foundations, hospitals, doctors and law-enforcers) in one system consciously or unconsciously perform the same roles or functions in the other with relative ease. Kidney patients pay huge sums for new kidneys, but most of them go to brokers, including some doctors/medical facilities, for locating and transporting poor donors. Without brokers operating in a relatively unrestrained market, it is doubtful if many poor vendors will find kidney buyers. Without incentives (e.g. cash rewards) to report these brokers and their vast networks, and swift government action, the underground kidney trade will continue to flourish , entrench market inequalities based on asymmetric information and dent government reform efforts. ¶ The Philippine experience thus yields valuable public health policy insights that are transferable to other countries, particularly in the developing world: (i) grassroots-based educational and health promotion strategies are vital considering vendors' socio-demographic profile and limited awareness of legal prohibitions and health risks; (ii) a carefully designed mix of supply-side and demand-side incentives complements law-enforcement (e.g. cash incentives to report buy-and-sell transactions and swift government action with on-the-spot media coverage); (iii) criminal deterrence is insufficient and costly in the absence of creative policing and prosecution strategies to cope with ever-changing trading environments (e.g. online, sham marriages between foreign patients and Filipino vendors) and rules (e.g. sub-contracting); (iv) donor post-operative care and long-term health deserve equal attention (e.g. making organ recipients partly responsible for donors' health care promotes a more equitable transplantation model); and (v) policy debate should not be confined to legitimacy issues (e.g. prohibition and punishment of compensated donations), but should address other relevant aspects of transplantation, including better renal care programs, promotion of cadaveric (brain-death and cardiac-death) organ donations, the health hazards of illicit organ-selling and sources of information asymmetries.¶ Collectively, these policy implications underscore the need to evaluate government action in terms of its net effect on participants in the underground organ commerce. A carefully designed mix of effective regulation and lawenforcement and public education should raise the costs and lower the benefits of brokered organ trading. It should also encourage the exchange of useful and symmetric information concerning organ donation and transplantation. Otherwise, organ traders will likely find it economically inefficient to distinguish between what is legal and prohibited in organ donation and transplantation. Illegal brokers circumvent the plan – they’ll just move to a new country Sack 14 [Kevin Sack, New York Times, 8/17/14, “Transplant Brokers in Israel Lure Desperate Kidney Patients to Costa Rica,” http://www.nytimes.com/2014/08/17/world/middleeast/transplant-brokers-in-israel-luredesperate-kidney-patients-to-costa-rica.html?_r=0, accessed 8/21/14] A broker who trades in human organs might seem a difficult thing to find. But Ms. Dorin’s mother began making inquiries around the hospital where she worked, and in short order the family came up with three names: Avigad Sandler, a former insurance agent long suspected of trafficking; Boris Volfman, a young Ukrainian émigré and Sandler protégé; and Yaacov Dayan, a wily businessman with interests in real estate and marketing.¶ The men were, The New York Times learned during an investigation of the global organ trade, among the central operators in Israel’s irrepressible underground kidney market. For years, they have pocketed enormous sums for arranging overseas transplants for patients who are paired with foreign donors, court filings and government documents show.¶ The brokers maintain they operate legally and do not directly help clients buy organs. Dodging international condemnation and tightening enforcement, they have nimbly shifted operations across the globe when any one destination closes its doors. ¶ The supply of transplantable organs is estimated by the World Health Organization to meet no more than a tenth of the need. Although there is no reliable data, experts say thousands of patients most likely receive illicit transplants abroad each year. Almost always, the sellers are poor and ill-informed about the medical risks.¶ The vast marketplace includes the United States, where federal prosecutors in New Jersey won the first conviction for illegal brokering in 2011. ¶ But a Times analysis of major trafficking cases since 2000 suggests that Israelis have played a disproportionate role. That is in part because of religious strictures regarding death and desecration that have kept deceased donation rates so low that some patients feel they must turn elsewhere. ¶ “When someone needs an organ transplant, they’ll do everything in their power,” said Meir Broder, a top legal adviser to Israel’s Ministry of Health. Legalization doesn’t increase the quality of organs – creates an incentive for donors to lie about preexisting conditions *DDOC = deceased donor organ commercialism Epstein et al 11 – senior Lecturer in Medical Ethics and Law @ Barts and The London School of Medicine and Dentistry, Miran, Dominique Martin, and Gabriel Danovitch, “Caution: deceased donor organ commercialism!” Transplant International Volume 24, Issue 9, pages 958–964, September 2011 // DDOC also risks impairing the safety of organ transplantation. Commercial organ donation, both from the living and deceased, is accompanied by an increased risk of infection [67]. Although such complications may be related to the quality of transplantation services, in particular the screening of organ vendors and the hazards of maintaining continuity of patient care in the setting of transplant tourism, DDOC may nevertheless contribute to increased risks. For example, prospective organ providers or their relatives may be reluctant to reveal information about the provider’s health that might jeopardize the chance of sale, such as the presence of risk factors for infection or disease. Medical staff may also conceal such information to profit from organ recovery or transplantation. In this regard it is worth noting that in the U.S., paid blood donation was discontinued precisely because of the increased infection risk. The larger the amount of money at stake the greater may be the propensity to conceal critical information [68]. Antibiotic use doesn’t spike resistance THOMAS, M.E., et al., 08 ("Risk factors for the introduction of high pathogenicity Avian Influenza virus into poultry farms during the epidemic in the Netherlands in 2003." Preventive veterinary medicine 69, (10 June 2005): 1-11. Agricola. EBSCO. [1 Aug. 2008, http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=agr&AN=IND43716042&site=ehost-live] With the exception of ciprofloxacin resistance, there is a paucity of scientific evidence to document the association of antimicrobial agents used in veterinary medicine with increases in antimicrobial-resistant pathogens (Phillips et al., 2004). For example, it has been suggested that the increased prevalenc e of extended-spectrum cephalosporin-resistant strains is in part related to the use in food animals of ceftiofur, which is an extended-spectrum cephalosporin approved for use in veterinary medicine (White et al., 2001); however, scientific evidence is lacking. Antimicrobial agents used for intensive calf rearing in the 1970–1980s have also been speculated to contribute to the emergence of multiple-antibiotic resistant Salmonella Typhimurium DT104 strains. Genes included in the antibiotic resistance gene cluster of Salmonella Typhimurium DT104 confer resistance to four of the five antimicrobials used during that time to treat veal calves, therefore co-selection of the entire cluster could have arisen from the use of any one of those drugs (Velge, Cloeckaert, & Barrow, 2005). While there is no definitive evidence for this scenario, several reviews have been published presenting contrasting views regarding the role of veterinary usage of antimicrobials in the emergence of antibiotic-resistant foodborne pathogens. In support of a causal relationship are reviews by Angulo et al., 2004 and Mølbak, 2004, whereas reviews by Phillips et al., 2004 and Wassenaar, 2005 advocate that veterinary usage of antimicrobial agents are inaccurately incriminated as being a major contributor to antibiotic-resistant pathogens in humans. Debate on this topic will continue but should consider the additional routes which lead to resistant bacterial populations, that antimicrobial usage in animals is required for animal health and well-being, and that not every antimicrobial-resistant pathogen has human health consequences. On this latter point, clearly not all infections caused by resistant pathogens fail to respond to treatment. For example, in a study of 23 diarrhea cases in Thailand, nearly all were infected with ciprofloxacin-resistant Campylobacter, yet 58% of patients receiving ciprofloxaxin treatment were cured. This response implies that treatment with ciprofloxacin could still be effective in many cases (Sanders et al., 2002). Another consideration is that acquisition of drug resistance could entail a biological cost to the pathogen resulting in reduced fitness and competitiveness in the absence of antibiotic selection pressure. For example, most data on E. coli suggest that increased antibiotic resistance results in decreased fitness (Wassenaar, 2005). Alternatively, for some foodborne pathogens such as fluoroquinoloneresistant C. jejuni, resistance can be neutral or even beneficial in terms of fitness (Luo et al., 2005). When coinoculated into chickens, fluoroquinolone-resistant Campylobacter isolates either outcompeted or were outcompeted by most of the fluoroquinolone-susceptible strains, with the outcome being dependent on the genetic background of the recipient strain. These variable results highlight the complex nature of antibiotic resistance and the large data gaps that exist in making informed scientific decisions on use of antimicrobials in animals used for food. 1NC SOLVENCY Most people don’t donate cadaveric organs because they’re averse for reasons that financial incentives can’t overcome Newton 11 – Research Fellow in the Department of Marketing @ Monash University Joshua D., “How does the general public view posthumous organ donation? A meta-synthesis of the qualitative literature” BMC Public Health 2011, 11:791 // Background¶ Many individuals are unwilling to become posthumous organ donors, resulting in a disparity between the supply and demand for organ transplants. A meta-synthesis of the qualitative literature was therefore conducted to determine how the general public views posthumous organ donation.¶ Methods¶ Three online databases (PubMed, PsycINFO, Scopus) were searched for articles published between January 1990 and May 2008 using the following search terms: organ donation, qualitative, interview. Eligibility criteria were: examination of beliefs about posthumous organ donation; utilization of a qualitative research design; and publication in an English peerreviewed journal. Exclusion criteria were examining how health professionals or family members of organ donors viewed posthumous organ donation. Grounded theory was used to identify the beliefs emerging from this literature. Thematically-related beliefs were then grouped to form themes.¶ Results¶ 27 articles from 24 studies met the inclusion criteria and were reviewed. The major themes identified were: religion, death, altruism, personal relevance, the body, the family, medical professionals, and transplant recipients. An altruistic motivation to help others emerged as the most commonly identified motivator for becoming an organ donor, although feeling a sense of solidarity with the broader community and believing that donated organs are put to good use may be important preconditions for the emergence of this motivation. The two most commonly identified barriers were the need to maintain bodily integrity to safeguard progression into the afterlife and the unethical recovery of organs by medical professionals. The influence of stakeholder groups on willingness to become an organ donor was also found to vary by the level of control that each stakeholder group exerted over the donation recovery process and their perceived conflict of interest in wanting organ donation to proceed.¶ Conclusions¶ These findings afford insights into how individuals perceive posthumous organ donation.¶ Background¶ Demand for transplantable organs currently exceeds supply [1], and one of the principle reasons for this disparity is that many next of kin are reluctant to allow organ donation to proceed. In the United States of America, for example, next of kin withhold consent for organ donation in 47% of eligible cases [2], and similar rates of refusal have been reported in both Australia [3] and the United Kingdom [4]. However, next of kin are more likely to grant permission for organ recovery if the deceased had indicated during their lifetime a willingness to become an organ donor [5,6]. Understanding the beliefs that encourage or dissuade individuals from becoming willing organ donors is therefore of particular importance.¶ Early efforts to examine the factors that influence donation willingness made use of quantitative research designs [7-10]. While such designs are well suited to enumerating the beliefs that influence behavior, they are less amenable to understanding how individuals perceive, conceptualize, and give meaning to issues such as organ donation [11]. To redress this limitation, qualitative methods have more recently been used to complement the results obtained by quantitative studies. One of the strengths of qualitative designs is that they allow researchers to explore the multifaceted, inter-related, private, and often conflicting beliefs held by individuals [11]. Qualitative designs also allow researchers to clarify what individuals actually mean when they describe particular beliefs or experiences [11]. Qualitative research can therefore provide unique insights into how individuals perceive organ donation. Unfortunately, much of the qualitative research on organ donation has been conducted with small samples or among populations with unique characteristics (see Table 1). As a result, findings from qualitative studies are often of limited generalizability.¶ Table 1. Characteristics of the Studies Reviewed in the Meta-synthesis¶ One way of addressing the limited generalizability of qualitative research is to conduct a metasynthesis of the available research [12]. In a meta-synthesis, findings from multiple qualitative studies are aggregated so that the factors that shape social phenomena across multiple populations can be identified [12]. In the context of organ donation, such an analysis would provide clinicians, policy makers, and researchers with a deeper understanding of the beliefs that encourage or dissuade individuals from becoming willing organ donors. A meta-synthesis of the qualitative research on organ donation has not, however, been previously conducted. The current study was therefore designed to address this gap.¶ Methods¶ Study selection¶ Three electronic bibliographic databases (PubMed, PsycINFO, Scopus) were searched using the following terms: "organ donation AND interview" and "organ donation AND qualitative". These search terms were applied to articles published between January 1st 1990 and May 31st 2008. Articles were also found by hand-searching the reference lists of relevant articles. Articles identified through this process were selected for analysis if they: (i) utilized a qualitative study design; (ii) were published in an English-language, peer-reviewed journal; and (iii) investigated the beliefs that individuals hold about posthumous organ donation. Studies were excluded if their primary aim was to examine: (i) how individuals arrive at a decision about donating the organs of a deceased family member; or (ii) the reactions of health professionals to posthumous organ donation. Multiple papers from a single study were included for analysis if each paper presented unique data. A summary of the search strategy and selection criteria utilized in the current study is presented in Figure 1. Twenty-seven articles from 24 studies [13-39] satisfied the selection criteria and were included in the review (see Table 1). These studies represented the views of 1,213 participants towards organ donation. ¶ thumbnailFigure 1. Literature search strategy. Figure 1 illustrates the number of articles that were identified through database searches and a hand search of article reference lists. The inclusion criteria used to select the final 27 articles for review are also presented.¶ Analysis¶ Qualitative data extracted from the results section of each reviewed study were analyzed using a grounded theory framework [40], a method of analysis that has also been used in other meta-syntheses [41,42]. Following a grounded theory methodology, data about individuals' perceptions of organ donation were inductively coded to create a series of belief-based concepts. Constant comparisons between and within belief concepts were undertaken throughout this process to ensure that each concept provided an accurate representation of the original qualitative data. Similar concepts were then grouped to form thematic categories. To enhance methodological rigor, a second coder independently analyzed the data using the belief-based concepts generated by the first coder. Feedback from the second coder also led to several minor changes being made to the belief-based concepts. The coding schemes from the first and second coders were then compared, and any coding inconsistencies were resolved through discussion.¶ Results¶ Seven key thematic categories that impacted on individuals' willingness to become an organ donor were identified. Each theme encapsulated a series of positive or negative beliefs about organ donation (see Table 2). ¶ Table 2. Beliefs Identified in the Reviewed Studies Theme 1: Religion¶ Religious beliefs about organ donation existed along a continuum that ranged from outright rejection of organ donation to unequivocal support. The religious belief most commonly used to reject organ donation was the notion that bodily integrity should be maintained to safeguard progression into the afterlife.¶ "The organs will be witness to your actions on Judgement Day." UK, Indo-Asian, Muslim, male, 37 years old [14]¶ This belief was by no means universal among those who shared the same faith, however, suggesting that many religious beliefs are personalized interpretations of more general religious precepts. ¶ "When we die it's not our body that goes, it's our soul that goes." UK, Pakistani, Muslim, female [24]¶ A second religious belief perceived as being in opposition to organ donation was concern that organ retrieval could prevent the observance of specific funeral or burial rituals.¶ "With us, only close relatives, no more than four, should touch the body (to wash it) and place it in the grave." UK, South Asian, Muslim [35]¶ Fatalism, or the notion that all events are predestined, also shaped views about organ donation. Fatalistic individuals typically spoke about organ transplantation as being either unnecessary or against the will of a divine being. As a consequence, they opposed the need for both organ donation and transplantation.¶ "You die when the Creator thinks it's time for you to die, not to extend a person's life simply because of their age, or, you know, because there is a chance to do so." Canada, Coast Salish [28]¶ At the other end of the continuum were religious beliefs that were seen as providing support for organ donation. While many of the religious barriers to organ donation were very specific in nature, religious support for becoming an organ donor was derived from more general precepts about the importance of helping others.¶ "It's better to give than to receive." Canada, Indian, Christian [30]¶ "If you save the one life, then you save the whole world." Canada, Indian, Muslim [30]¶ Although many individuals believed their religion either supported or opposed organ donation, some expressed uncertainty about their religion's stance towards organ donation. One of the reasons for this uncertainty was the perception that religious texts provide little instruction concerning the appropriateness of organ donation. These individuals therefore wished to clarify their religion's position before they made a decision about organ donation.¶ "I do not know anything myself, but I would ask the scholars... If they tell us it is alright, then it is alright ... If they say no, that is no." UK, Indo-Asian, Muslim, male, 38 years old [14] Theme 2: Death¶ Concerns about death intersected with beliefs about organ donation. Those who feared thinking or talking about death, for instance, were often reluctant to consider the issue of organ donation. Declaring one's donation wishes was also seen to be tempting fate.¶ "Buying a lot in the cemetery, they [would] rather not talk about it. So if you raise the question about donating your parts after you die, they probably don't want to hear about it." Canada, Chinese [29] ¶ "Talking about bad things sometime gives them the power to happen." USA, African-American, female [39]¶ Others, in contrast, saw organ donation as a way to transcend the finality of death and achieve symbolic immortality by allowing the donor to 'live on' in the transplant recipient. ¶ "You often hear people say, well my child, my brother gave something to another person, so therefore they live on." Australia, male [27]¶ Theme 3: Altruism ¶ Willingness to become an organ donor was often expressed in terms of an altruistic, non-religiously-motivated desire to help individuals in need.¶ "When you give an organ, you're doing it to help somebody." USA, African-American [15]¶ Alternative altruistic motivations for becoming an organ donor also emerged. Some respondents, for instance, situated their desire to become an organ donor within the broader context of helping the general community.¶ "I am also in favour [of organ donation] because it is a service to humanity and it is giving life ... because you are, of course, dying so it is better off that you save someone else's life, like a gift for society." Australia, male [27]¶ Others justified their support for organ donation by making reference to indirect reciprocity. Indirect reciprocity refers to the notion that an individual is duty bound to help others as they themselves would want to be helped. ¶ "I'm sure if you needed an organ you would want someone to donate if it was going to save your life. You would want somebody to donate." USA, African-American [15]¶ Identifying with the broader community may, however, be an important precondition for the expression of these altruistic ideals. Specifically, some respondents who felt socially or culturally isolated indicated an unwillingness to donate their organs.¶ "It's like, you're black first, a man second. That stops you feeling part of it." UK, Caribbean, male [31] Theme 4: Personal relevance¶ Personal relevance appeared to play an important role in how respondents interacted with the notion of organ donation. For many, consideration of organ donation did not take place until it became contextualized within the lived experience of an acquaintance or family member.¶ "It didn't dawn on us to discuss it [organ donation] unless, of course, there's a situation - when it's close to home. But if you are comfortable right now, it seldom happens." USA, Filipino [13]¶ Personal relevance also appeared to act as a catalyst for broader attitude change. One respondent, for instance, described the experience of watching a close friend's daughter receive dialysis while waiting for an organ transplant. ¶ "I had an aversion to donation, but with the sort of awareness I have now, it is important that everyone, everyone carries a donor card." UK, African, male, 31-44 years old [19] Theme 5: The body¶ The body was an integral component of many individuals' self-identity. As such, actions that could dehumanize or threaten the dignity or individuality of the body were viewed with suspicion and distress. Examples of such beliefs included the notion that organ donation could lead to the body being treated as a collection of 'spare parts' or as cuts of meat in a butchers shop.¶ "Thinking of them as a hunk of meat, like a piece of sheep or something. That is how doctors think." Australia, male [27]¶ "The human body is not a machine. Organ transplantation is abusing the body's dignity. Our organs are not mere spare parts. They are a gift from Allah." UK, IndoAsian, male, 24 years old [14]¶ As a result, the prospect of organ donation often fuelled a desire to retain control over the body, even after death.¶ "It (the body) is your possession. The more you use it, the more you value it, the more prize possession it becomes, the less you want it harmed, or taken apart, or damaged or illness to come to you." UK, female, 21 years old [26]¶ Nevertheless, there was some evidence to suggest that such concerns may be resolved by reassuring individuals that organ recovery is carried out respectfully and in a manner that preserves the outward appearance of the body.¶ "I can donate everything just as long I look OK in my coffin." USA, Filipino [13]¶ While some individuals rejected organ donation out of a desire to preserve the dignity of the whole body, others felt that organ recovery could take place so long as certain parts of the body were left untouched. The eyes and heart, for instance, were sometimes thought to hold particular significance because of the perceived centrality of these parts of the body to an individual's sense of self.¶ "I don't want to give my heart and my eyes because I feel like you think things with your heart." UK, white, female [24]¶ An associated belief was the notion that aspects of an individual's personality are situated within specific body parts. Individuals who held this belief therefore feared that organ transplantation could result in personality contamination.¶ "I don't like the idea of my organs living in another body, it may affect their personality and make them more like me." UK, Pakistani, female [35]¶ Other individuals held more utilitarian views of the body, believing that the body gave physical form to the self but was not an integral component of their self-identity. For these individuals, the body held little intrinsic importance after death.¶ "Who cares what happens to my body ... after I die. I don't care one way or the other. If there's someone who needs my organs, sure, why not, my soul will be gone anyway." USA, Oglala Lakota Sioux [22]¶ As a result, refusing to become an organ donor was deemed to be a waste of healthy and potentially life-saving organs.¶ "I'd rather not go to waste if someone could use it." USA [32]¶ One way that individuals explained this utilitarian view to others was by equating organ transplantation with the replacement of faulty parts in a machine. As outlined earlier, this view was seen by others as dehumanizing the body.¶ "Cynically speaking, it's machine parts, in principle nothing strange." Sweden [37] Theme 6: The family¶ Individuals appeared desirous of maintaining family cohesion and stability and were consequently influenced by the donation attitudes held by their family members.¶ "I personally have no objection but my father does, so I am not sure." UK, Indo-Asian, female, 20 years old [14]¶ Further indicative of this desire to maintain family stability was an inclination to minimize stress among surviving family members. For some, this meant making their donation wishes known to family members in order to take:¶ "The emotive onus away from your relatives." UK, white, female [24]¶ For others, it meant refusing to become an organ donor so that their families would not have to see their body following organ recovery.¶ "I don't like the idea of my relatives having to see my body having been carved up." UK, Gujarati, male [35] Theme 7: The medical profession¶ Mistrust of the medical profession was a common cause of anxiety across the reviewed papers. The most common variant of this concern was that organs would be recovered unethically. Some, for instance, feared that doctors would deliberately remove a patient's organs before the patient had died, while others believed that life-saving medical care would be withheld so that patients could become eligible for organ donation. There was also a belief that medical staff go beyond an individual's terms of consent to obtain additional organs. ¶ "If I sign up to donate a kidney, they may take out everything else as well." UK, Caribbean, male, 31-44 years old [19]¶ While some believed that organs may be unethically procured, others thought that organs could be taken prematurely as a result of mistakes made during organ recovery. The concept of brain death was particularly singled out as a potential barrier to becoming a willing donor, with questions being raised about doctors' ability to determine if a patient met the criteria for brain death or whether the medical profession more generally was mistaken for using brain death as the basis for allowing donation to proceed.¶ "Brain death may not be definitive so if you do donate your organs you've given away your (or someone else's) last chance at life." Australia [27] ¶ Fears about more routine medical errors were also identified.¶ "The medical team, although they admitted making the mistake, made that mistake ... that's really going to, uh, cause some thinking now before anyone wants to donate or receive an organ." USA, African-American [15]¶ Juxtaposed with the notion that organs are removed prematurely was the belief that doctors prolong life unnecessarily to obtain organs. There was also concern that the medical profession was too eager to push the boundaries of nature.¶ "The desire to play that many doctors have is really dangerous. In the end they will breach the borders that nature has determined." Sweden [37] ¶ Other medicalrelated beliefs about organ donation also emerged. One concern was that the process of allocating organs was biased, particularly against ethnic minorities or the poor.¶ "I still think it's a racial thing too because most Black people feel that they're never going to get an organ anyway because the organs are going to go to those people with money, or those people who know someone, or White people." USA, African-American [16]¶ There was also a fear that organs could be used for unintended purposes, violating the altruistic reasons for which these organs had been donated. These unintended purposes included the illicit trading of organs, especially for monetary gain, and the use of donated organs in unauthorized medical experiments.¶ Perceived knowledge gaps, either about organ recovery or the method for recording donation wishes, were also identified as barriers to becoming an organ donor. Likewise, health system constraints were seen as reducing the impetus to record donation wishes. An individual living on a reservation in the United States of America, for instance, questioned whether health professionals at the local hospital examined drivers' licenses to identify the donation wishes of the deceased. Plan doesn’t solve demand EVEN IF everyone agreed to sell their organs – not enough eligible cadavers die every year – also assumes a legal market Becker and Elias 7 – professor of economics @ University of Chicago and assistant professor of economics @ State University of New York at Buffalo Gary S. and Julio Jorge, “Introducing Incentives in the Market for Live and Cadaveric Organ Donations” Journal of Economic Perspectives Vol. 21, No. 3 (Summer) pp. 3-24 // Perhaps most crucially, the present gap between demand and supply of kidneys could not be fully met from cadavers, even with full payments for cadaver organs. For their organs to be usable, cadaver donors must have had healthy, well-functioning organs and been free of infections at the time of their death. The majority of cadaveric organs come from accident or stroke victims who have been declared brain dead. In 2000, stroke victims accounted for over 40 percent of all cadaveric donors.¶ Table 4 presents various estimates from different studies of the maximum potential supply of cadaveric organs. The geographical area and the year consid- ered in the studies are reported in the second and third column respectively. The fourth column of the table reports the estimates of the potential cadaveric donors rates in per million of population. In the last column, we estimate the maximum potential supply of cadaveric donors for the United States by taking the rates of potential donors reported in column four and scaling up to the 2006 U.S. population.¶ Taking into account the need to have healthy organs, these estimates suggest that between 10,000 and 16,000 of those dying annually are considered medically suitable for organ donation. Since all organs are not always useable from any single cadaver, the number of organs available for transplantation per cadaveric organ donor is limited even further. In 2000, the average number of kidneys and livers recovered per cadaveric organ donor was 1.82 and 0.83, respectively. The average number of kidneys and livers recovered and actually transplanted per cadaveric organ donor are much lower. In 2000 it was 1.57 for kidneys and 0.76 for livers.¶ These numbers and the number of useable cadavers indicate that the most reasonable estimates of the supply of cadaveric kidneys-in row 6 of Table 4 (the Evans et al. study)-imply a maximum number of cadaveric kidneys harvested between 15,500 and 24,000 (8,510 times 1.82 and 13,048 times 1.82). This overlaps the actual demand for kidneys transplants in 2005 at 21,500. Yet only a fraction of all these potentially useable cadaveric kidneys are likely to be offered for sale, or to be useable even if offered since they may not be matched with any of the potential recipients.¶ Moreover, once a market for organs is in place, the actual demand would surpass present demand, since currently kidney transplants are only offered to people who have irreversible kidney failure. Other medical or surgical treatments for kidney problems are usually tried before consideration of a kidney transplant. Thus, it is highly unlikely that the full demand for kidney transplants could be met with organs of deceased persons. Legalizing cadaveric organ sales decreases the organ pool – crowds out altruistic donations Caplan 8 – director of the Center for Bioethics @ the University of Pennsylvania Arthur, “Cash for kidneys? Sales won’t widen donor pool” [http://www.nbcnews.com/id/25370851/ns/health-health_care/#.VA9AoEj85Xw] June 25 // If this country were to allow financial incentives for organs, the money would presumably go to the family or the deceased’s designee. But if these people have their hand on the life-support plug and know they stand to make good money as soon as the owner of the valuable body parts is dead, how hard are they going to try to keep that owner alive? While offering money for organs might persuade a few more to donate, it is more likely to turn off those now willing to consider giving out of fear or knowing there’s a reward for their death. Net result: A loss in the overall number of organs available. 1NC RISK Their 1AC card is backwards – Yudkowsky is saying we should be more worried about extinction-level impacts and less worried about high-probability systemic impacts Yudkowsky 06 [Eliezer, 8/31/2006. Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence Palo Alto, CA. “Cognitive biases potentially affecting judgment of global risks, Forthcoming in Global Catastrophic Risks, eds. Nick Bostrom and Milan Cirkovic, singinst.org/upload/cognitive-biases.pdf. The conjunction fallacy similarly applies to futurological forecasts. Two independent sets of professional analysts at the Second International Congress on Forecasting were asked to rate, respectively, the probability of "A complete suspension of diplomatic relations between the USA and the Soviet Union, sometime in 1983" or "A Russian invasion of Poland, and a complete suspension of diplomatic relations between the USA and the Soviet Union, sometime in 1983". The second set of analysts responded with significantly higher probabilities. (Tversky and Kahneman 1983.) In Johnson et. al. (1993), MBA students at Wharton were scheduled to travel to Bangkok as part of their degree program. Several groups of students were asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance. One group of subjects was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance covering the flight from Thailand to the US. A second group of subjects was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance covering the round-trip flight. A third group was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance that covered the complete trip to Thailand. These three groups responded with average willingness to pay of $17.19, $13.90, and $7.44 respectively. According to probability theory, adding additional detail onto a story must render the story less probable. It is less probable that Linda is a feminist bank teller than that she is a bank teller, since all feminist bank tellers are necessarily bank tellers. Yet human psychology seems to follow the rule that adding an additional detail can make the story more plausible. People might pay more for international diplomacy intended to prevent nanotechnological warfare by China, than for an engineering project to defend against nanotechnological attack from any source. The second threat scenario is less vivid and alarming, but the defense is more useful because it is more vague. More valuable still would be strategies which make humanity harder to extinguish without being specific to nanotechnologic threats - such as colonizing space, or see Yudkowsky (this volume) on AI. Security expert Bruce Schneier observed (both before and after the 2005 hurricane in New Orleans) that the U.S. government was guarding specific domestic targets against "movie-plot scenarios" of terrorism, at the cost of taking away resources from emergency-response capabilities that could respond to any disaster. (Schneier 2005.) Overly detailed reassurances can also create false perceptions of safety: "X is not an existential risk and you don't need to worry about it, because A, B, C, D, and E"; where the failure of any one of propositions A, B, C, D, or E potentially extinguishes the human species. "We don't need to worry about nanotechnologic war, because a UN commission will initially develop the technology and prevent its proliferation until such time as an active shield is developed, capable of defending against all accidental and malicious outbreaks that contemporary nanotechnology is capable of producing, and this condition will persist indefinitely." Vivid, specific scenarios can inflate our probability estimates of security, as well as misdirecting defensive investments into needlessly narrow or implausibly detailed risk scenarios. More generally, people tend to overestimate conjunctive probabilities and underestimate disjunctive probabilities. (Tversky and Kahneman 1974.) That is, people tend to overestimate the probability that, e.g., seven events of 90% probability will all occur. Conversely, people tend to underestimate the probability that at least one of seven events of 10% probability will occur. Someone judging whether to, e.g., incorporate a new startup, must evaluate the probability that many individual events will all go right (there will be sufficient funding, competent employees, customers will want the product) while also considering the likelihood that at least one critical failure will occur (the bank refuses a loan, the biggest project fails, the lead scientist dies). This may help explain why only 44% of entrepreneurial ventures survive after 4 years. (Knaup 2005.) Dawes (1988, p. 133) observes: 'In their summations lawyers avoid arguing from disjunctions ("either this or that or the other could have occurred, all of which would lead to the same conclusion") in favor of conjunctions. Rationally, of course, disjunctions are much more probable than are conjunctions.' The scenario of humanity going extinct in the next century is a disjunctive event. It could happen as a result of any of the existential risks discussed in this book - or some other cause which none of us foresaw. Yet for a futurist, disjunctions make for an awkward and unpoetic-sounding prophecy. Multiplying probability by magnitude is the only moral option – Yudkowsky, Research Fellow at the Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence, 1/22/2008 (“Circular Altruism,” http://www.overcomingbias.com/2008/01/circular-altrui.html) Suppose that a disease, or a monster, or a war, or something, is killing people. And suppose you only have enough resources to implement one of the following two options: 1. Save 400 lives, with certainty. 2. Save 500 lives, with 90% probability; save no lives, 10% probability. Most people choose option 1. Which, I think, is foolish; because if you multiply 500 lives by 90% probability, you get an expected value of 450 lives, which exceeds the 400-life value of option 1. (Lives saved don't diminish in marginal utility, so this is an appropriate calculation.) "What!" you cry, incensed. "How can you gamble with human lives? How can you think about numbers when so much is at stake? What if that 10% probability strikes, and everyone dies? So much for your damned logic! You're following your rationality off a cliff!" Ah, but here's the interesting thing. If you present the options this way: 1. 100 people die, with certainty. 2. 90% chance no one dies; 10% chance 500 people die. Then a majority choose option 2. Even though it's the same gamble. You see, just as a certainty of saving 400 lives seems to feel so much more comfortable than an unsure gain, so too, a certain loss feels worse than an uncertain one. You can grandstand on the second description too: "How can you condemn 100 people to certain death when there's such a good chance you can save them? We'll all share the risk! Even if it was only a 75% chance of saving everyone, it would still be worth it - so long as there's a chance - everyone makes it, or no one does!" You know what? This isn't about your feelings. A human life, with all its joys and all its pains, adding up over the course of decades, is worth far more than your brain's feelings of comfort or discomfort with a plan. Does computing the expected utility feel too cold-blooded for your taste? Well, that feeling isn't even a feather in the scales, when a life is at stake. Just shut up and multiply. Previously on Overcoming Bias, I asked what was the least bad, bad thing that could happen, and suggested that it was getting a dust speck in your eye that irritated you for a fraction of a second, barely long enough to notice, before it got blinked away. And conversely, a very bad thing to happen, if not the worst thing, would be getting tortured for 50 years. Now, would you rather that a googolplex people got dust specks in their eyes, or that one person was tortured for 50 years? I originally asked this question with a vastly larger number - an incomprehensible mathematical magnitude - but a googolplex works fine for this illustration. Most people chose the dust specks over the torture. Many were proud of this choice, and indignant that anyone should choose otherwise: "How dare you condone torture!" This matches research showing that there are "sacred values", like human lives, and "unsacred values", like money. When you try to trade off a sacred value against an unsacred value, subjects express great indignation (sometimes they want to punish the person who made the suggestion). My favorite anecdote along these lines - though my books are packed at the moment, so no citation for now - comes from a team of researchers who evaluated the effectiveness of a certain project, calculating the cost per life saved, and recommended to the government that the project be implemented because it was cost-effective. The governmental agency rejected the report because, they said, you couldn't put a dollar value on human life. After rejecting the report, the agency decided not to implement the measure. Trading off a sacred value (like refraining from torture) against an unsacred value (like dust specks) feels really awful. To merely multiply utilities would be too cold-blooded - it would be following rationality off a cliff... But let me ask you this. Suppose you had to choose between one person being tortured for 50 years, and a googol people being tortured for 49 years, 364 days, 23 hours, 59 minutes and 59 seconds. You would choose one person being tortured for 50 years, I do presume; otherwise I give up on you. And similarly, if you had to choose between a googol people tortured for 49.9999999 years, and a googol-squared people being tortured for 49.9999998 years, you would pick the former. A googolplex is ten to the googolth power. That's a googol/100 factors of a googol. So we can keep doing this, gradually - very gradually - diminishing the degree of discomfort, and multiplying by a factor of a googol each time, until we choose between a googolplex people getting a dust speck in their eye, and a googolplex/googol people getting two dust specks in their eye. If you find your preferences are circular here, that makes rather a mockery of moral grandstanding. If you drive from San Jose to San Francisco to Oakland to San Jose, over and over again, you may have fun driving, but you aren't going anywhere. Maybe you think it a great display of virtue to choose for a googolplex people to get dust specks rather than one person being tortured. But if you would also trade a googolplex people getting one dust speck for a googolplex/googol people getting two dust specks et cetera, you sure aren't helping anyone. Circular preferences may work for feeling noble, but not for feeding the hungry or healing the sick. Altruism isn't the warm fuzzy feeling you get from being altruistic. If you're doing it for the spiritual benefit, that is nothing but selfishness. The primary thing is to help others, whatever the means. So shut up and multiply! And if it seems to you that there is a fierceness to this maximization, like the bare sword of the law, or the burning of the sun - if it seems to you that at the center of this rationality there is a small cold flame - Well, the other way might feel better inside you. But it wouldn't work. And I say also this to you: That if you set aside your regret for all the spiritual satisfaction you could be having - if you wholeheartedly pursue the Way, without thinking that you are being cheated - if you give yourself over to rationality without holding back, you will find that rationality gives to you in return. But that part only works if you don't go around saying to yourself, "It would feel better inside me if only I could be less rational." Chimpanzees feel, but they don't multiply. Should you be sad that you have the opportunity to do better? You cannot attain your full potential if you regard your gift as a burden. Throwing out scenarios is a terrible corrective—they replace probability neglect with consequence neglect—the best middle ground is to balance magnitude with probability Friedman, PhD candidate in public policy, and Zeckhauser, professor of political economy – Kennedy School @ Harvard, ‘12 (Jeffrey A. and Richard, “Assessing Uncertainty in Intelligence,” HKS Faculty Research Working Paper Series RWP12-027) To provide empirical support for its discussion, this article examines a broad range of National Intelligence Estimates (NIEs). Though NIEs comprise only a small fraction of overall estimative intelligence, their production is so highly scrutinized that it is reasonable to assume that their flaws would characterize lower-profile estimates as well.8 In addition to examining more than a dozen specific estimates, the following sections describe general patterns across a database of 379 declassified NIEs that were written between 1964 and 1994 and that were released through the Central Intelligence Agency’s Historical Review Program.9 Throughout the following sections, this combination of deductive and inductive analysis helps to draw out the tensions between eliminating uncertainty and assessing uncertainty in estimative intelligence. Analyzing Alternatives Intelligence analysts often wrestle with alternatives. To return to the example of an analyst studying Syria in 2012, this analyst would have had to consider a wide range of possibilities. If al-Assad were to survive the year, his domestic and international standing could presumably change in any number of ways. If alAssad left power, the transition might be stable but it might also descend into widespread violence, while al-Assad’s eventual successors could be relatively friendly or hostile to the United States. There are many relevant scenarios here. An intelligence analyst who seeks to eliminate uncertainty would argue that one of them constitutes the ‘correct answer’, and that her ideal goal should be to identify what that answer is. Intelligence tradecraft often encourages this kind of thinking when it comes to analyzing alternative possibilities. When estimates focus on a single possibility, it is called ‘single-outcome forecasting’. This practice has been criticized for some time, because analysts often have insufficient information for making definitive predictions, and because policymakers should be aware of a range of potential contingencies.10 Yet even when analysts do consider multiple possibilities, several elements of standard practice reveal a tendency to assume that one of those scenarios should be considered the most important or the most correct. For instance, most NIEs highlight a ‘Best Estimate’ or ‘Key Judgments’. In principle, calling some estimates ‘Best’ does not exclude the idea that there are other possibilities. Meanwhile, the Key Judgments section of an NIE is generally intended to serve the function of an executive summary, so it does not inherently privilege one alternative over another. In practice, however, these sections often highlight a subset of relevant possibilities and encourage consumers to give these possibilities special attention. NIEs typically present their judgments in sequence, often with one or two possibilities receiving the bulk of explanation and support. Many NIEs contain a distinct section enumerating ‘Alternatives’ that often receive relatively limited discussion. This treatment can suggest that certain alternative views are relatively insignificant , and the 2002 NIE on Iraq’s Continuing Programs for W eapons of M ass Destruction serves as a prominent example. The Key Judgments section of this NIE begins with 42 paragraphs supporting the assessment that Iraq ‘has continued its weapons of mass destruction (WMD) programs’ and that ‘if left unchecked, it probably will have a nuclear weapon during this decade’. That conclusion, as is now widely known, was based on controversial information. Doubts about the NIE’s main judgment were raised in a two-paragraph text box at the end of the opening section, arguing that the evidence does not ‘add up to a compelling case that Iraq is currently pursuing… an integrated and comprehensive approach to acquire nuclear weapons’. It is almost impossible to miss this objection – but it is equally difficult to miss the disparity in emphasis between these very different points of view about Iraq’s nuclear program. The tendency to privilege particular judgments goes beyond the structure of intelligence estimates. Ironically, it permeates many of the conceptual frameworks that are intended to encourage analysts to consider multiple possibilities in the first place. For instance, one prominent text on analytic tradecraft recommends that analysts approach complex questions by generating multiple hypotheses, evaluating the ‘credibility’ of each hypothesis, sorting hypotheses ‘from most credible to least credible’, and then ‘select[ing] from the top of the list those hypotheses most deserving of attention’.11 Though its authors intend for this method of ‘multiple hypothesis generation’ to ensure that important alternatives do not get overlooked, the instruction to focus on the ‘most credible’ predictions indicates an assumption that unlikely possibilities are less ‘deserving of attention’. Yet that is often untrue. The most consequential events (such as major terrorist attacks, the outbreak of conventional wars, and the collapse of state governments ) are often perceived as unlikely before they occur, yet they can have such enormous impact that they deserve serious consideration. The overall significance of any event is a product of its probability and its consequences, and so both of these factors must be considered when comparing alternative scenarios. To give another example, many intelligence analysts are trained in a practice called Analysis of Competing Hypotheses (ACH). ACH seems to embrace the goal of assessing uncertainty. It instructs analysts to form a matrix of potential hypotheses and available information that helps to show how much evidence supports (or contradicts) each possibility. This practice combats first impressions and promotes alternative thinking.12 Yet the word ‘Competing’ is important here. Competing for what? The original description of ACH explains its goal as being to determine ‘Which of several possible explanations is the correct one? Which of several possible outcomes is the most likely one?’13 A recent manual introduces ACH as a tool for ‘selecting the hypothesis that best fits the evidence’.14 To this end, ACH instructs analysts to ‘focus on disproving hypotheses’.15 This does not mean that ACH always generates singleoutcome estimates, and the method is designed to indicate places where the evidence sustains multiple interpretations. When this occurs, ACH tells analysts to rank remaining possibilities from ‘weakest’ to ‘strongest’. An analyst seeking to assess uncertainty would approach the issue differently. She would not see the relevant possibilities as rival or competing. She would say that no possibility merits attention for being ‘correct’ and that focusing on disproving hypotheses places unnecessary emphasis on eliminating relevant scenarios from consideration. Moreover, she would argue that it makes little sense to say that any possibility is ‘weak’ or ‘strong’ so long as analysts accurately assess its likelihood. 16 This is not to claim that all scenarios have equal significance. But to repeat, the significance of any possibility is the product of its likelihood and its potential consequences. For that reason, ACH’s method of ranking hypotheses based on probability exposes analysts to consequence neglect. 2NC CP All of their evidence says it doesn’t reduce the shortage 100% - other planks and neither does the aff And the surplus would be huge in the US—the gap between the number willing to donate and those that state a preference is massive Zümrüt 9 (Murat Civaner1, Zümrüt Alpinar2, Yaman Örs3 1Uludag University School of Medicine, Department of Medical Ethics, Gorukle Campus, TR–16059 Bursa 2Middle East Technical University, Department of Philosophy, İnönü Bulvarı, TR–06351 Ankara 3Akdeniz University Faculty of Medicine, Department of Medical Ethics, “Why Would Opt-Out System for Organ Procurement be Fairer?*”, PDF, ZBurdette) Furthermore, we argue that the opt-out system respects one’s autonomy more than opt-in. Because it is well-known that most of the people are willing to donate their organs but only few of them do actually donate. Many researchers have found that 70–95% of people are willing to donate while only 20–24% of them actually register their wish to do so.37,38,39,40,41 So, as English correctly emphasises, unless opinion polls are wrong, presuming that an individual wishes to donate would likely reinforce the autonomy of that individual rather than presuming an individual does not wish to donate.42 The best stats go neg Zümrüt 9 (Murat Civaner1, Zümrüt Alpinar2, Yaman Örs3 1Uludag University School of Medicine, Department of Medical Ethics, Gorukle Campus, TR–16059 Bursa 2Middle East Technical University, Department of Philosophy, İnönü Bulvarı, TR–06351 Ankara 3Akdeniz University Faculty of Medicine, Department of Medical Ethics, “Why Would Opt-Out System for Organ Procurement be Fairer?*”, PDF, ZBurdette) Now we would like to evaluate two systems by comparing their features, and determine their fairness by taking into consideration the degree of serving the right to healthcare. First of all, one can easily claim that opt-out would obviously provide more organs, and would expectedly save more lives than the opt-in system. The main aim of any kind of procurement system is to increase the resources, and the optout system is more appropriate to that aim. As Hamm compiled, a growing body of evidence supports this claim.15 A study in 2006 compared 22 countries over 10 years, and it took account of the determinants that might affect donation rates, such as gross domestic product per capita, health expenditure, religious beliefs, legislative system, and the number of deaths from traffic accidents and cerebrovascular diseases. Authors concluded that when other determinants of donation rates are ac-counted for, presumed consent countries have roughly 25– 30% higher dona-tion rates than informed consent countries.16 A study in 2003 found similar results.17 The successful results observed in Spain did not necessarily result from presumed consent, as the infrastructure and educational system in Spain showed great improvements during the same period of time. However, presumed consent may have played a role. Donation rates increased in Belgium, Singapore, and Austria after presumed consent was initiated.18,19,20 These findings suggest that the adoption of opt-out would increase donation rates, and, consequently, would fulfil the requirements of the right to healthcare more appropriately. Presumed consent solves the illicit market – it’s only a question of supply Glaser 5 – J.D. candidate at the Washington College of Law Sheri R., “Formula to Stop the Illegal Organ Trade: Presumed Consent Laws and Mandatory Reporting Requirements for Doctors” [http://www.wcl.american.edu/hrbrief/12/2glaser.pdf] // Presumed consent, when the state strictly follows it, is the best- practice method of legally obtaining organs. In countries with pre- sumed consent laws, there is a higher procurement rate for organs than in countries without these laws. Many argue that if the demand for organs were met legally, then people would have less incentive to illegally obtain organs and the black market would eventually dimin- ish. On a more basic level, if there were more organs available for transplant, then more people’s lives would be saved. 2NC DA The aff necessarily creates a property right to the body---it’s the only way to regulate and legitimize sale---that’s Siegel The aff flips common jurisprudence towards a property right for the body---now’s the brink Heather Hausleben 13, J.D., Seton Hall University School of Law, “Property Rights in Organs – An Argument for Commodification of the Body,” 1 May 2013, http://scholarship.shu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1350&context=student_scholarship At common law, the ability to donate through a gift doctrine requires that the donor has “the necessary disposing power,”31 which must intrinsically be linked to the power of property because one cannot give something that one does not have.32 Despite the fact that courts have not openly recognized a property interest in bodily tissue, the finding that a donation or gift can legally be made necessarily implies a property interest of some sort in the body . Courts are also beginning to recognize a property interest in deceased relative’s body parts .33 Although the outcome of these types of litigation often rest on the practical difficulties of medical examiners sharing all concerns with next of kin, the acceptance by courts of the idea of constitutionally protected34 property rights in the body of a deceased relative displays the change of attitude recognizing that the body is the property of an individual, or the in event of death, of the individual’s family. The aff guarantees legislation to overturn the UAGA---these necessarily include support of property rights for the body Gregory S. Crespi 94, Assistant Professor, Southern Methodist University School of Law, J.D., Yale University, 1985, Ph.D., University of Iowa, “Overcoming the Legal Obstacles to the Creation of a Futures Market in Bodily Organs,” Winter 1994, 55 Ohio St. L.J. 1, Lexis Let me set forth my reasoning in more detail. As previously discussed, the 1968 version of the UAGA -- still the basis for current state law in most jurisdictions -- does not expressly address the matter of organ sales. This gives the courts some room to exercise their discretion. Given the underlying policy of facilitating organ transplantation that was central to the drafting and widespread adoption of the UAGA, n220 the forceful arguments that can be made that a futures market could better achieve that objective than does the existing system, n221 and the lack of clear evidence concerning the intent of the adopting legislatures , n222 it may be possible to convince judges to construe those statutes that are based upon the 1968 UAGA to not preclude commercial organ [*56] transactions. Such a construction could be accompanied by judicial endorsement of the concept of property rights in body parts -- a concept now supported by a significant body of legal authority n223 -which in conjunction would remove at least the state law obstacles to the operation of a futures market in the significant number of states that have statutory frameworks based upon the 1968 UAGA and that have not adopted express prohibitions against commercial organ transactions. n224 2NC RISK Throwing out scenarios is a terrible corrective—they replace probability neglect with consequence neglect—the best middle ground is to balance magnitude with probability Friedman, PhD candidate in public policy, and Zeckhauser, professor of political economy – Kennedy School @ Harvard, ‘12 (Jeffrey A. and Richard, “Assessing Uncertainty in Intelligence,” HKS Faculty Research Working Paper Series RWP12-027) To provide empirical support for its discussion, this article examines a broad range of National Intelligence Estimates (NIEs). Though NIEs comprise only a small fraction of overall estimative intelligence, their production is so highly scrutinized that it is reasonable to assume that their flaws would characterize lower-profile estimates as well.8 In addition to examining more than a dozen specific estimates, the following sections describe general patterns across a database of 379 declassified NIEs that were written between 1964 and 1994 and that were released through the Central Intelligence Agency’s Historical Review Program.9 Throughout the following sections, this combination of deductive and inductive analysis helps to draw out the tensions between eliminating uncertainty and assessing uncertainty in estimative intelligence. Analyzing Alternatives Intelligence analysts often wrestle with alternatives. To return to the example of an analyst studying Syria in 2012, this analyst would have had to consider a wide range of possibilities. If al-Assad were to survive the year, his domestic and international standing could presumably change in any number of ways. If alAssad left power, the transition might be stable but it might also descend into widespread violence, while al-Assad’s eventual successors could be relatively friendly or hostile to the United States. There are many relevant scenarios here. An intelligence analyst who seeks to eliminate uncertainty would argue that one of them constitutes the ‘correct answer’, and that her ideal goal should be to identify what that answer is. Intelligence tradecraft often encourages this kind of thinking when it comes to analyzing alternative possibilities. When estimates focus on a single possibility, it is called ‘single-outcome forecasting’. This practice has been criticized for some time, because analysts often have insufficient information for making definitive predictions, and because policymakers should be aware of a range of potential contingencies.10 Yet even when analysts do consider multiple possibilities, several elements of standard practice reveal a tendency to assume that one of those scenarios should be considered the most important or the most correct. For instance, most NIEs highlight a ‘Best Estimate’ or ‘Key Judgments’. In principle, calling some estimates ‘Best’ does not exclude the idea that there are other possibilities. Meanwhile, the Key Judgments section of an NIE is generally intended to serve the function of an executive summary, so it does not inherently privilege one alternative over another. In practice, however, these sections often highlight a subset of relevant possibilities and encourage consumers to give these possibilities special attention. NIEs typically present their judgments in sequence, often with one or two possibilities receiving the bulk of explanation and support. Many NIEs contain a distinct section enumerating ‘Alternatives’ that often receive relatively limited discussion. This treatment can suggest that certain alternative views are relatively insignificant , and the 2002 NIE on Iraq’s Continuing Programs for W eapons of M ass Destruction serves as a prominent example. The Key Judgments section of this NIE begins with 42 paragraphs supporting the assessment that Iraq ‘has continued its weapons of mass destruction (WMD) programs’ and that ‘if left unchecked, it probably will have a nuclear weapon during this decade’. That conclusion, as is now widely known, was based on controversial information. Doubts about the NIE’s main judgment were raised in a two-paragraph text box at the end of the opening section, arguing that the evidence does not ‘add up to a compelling case that Iraq is currently pursuing… an integrated and comprehensive approach to acquire nuclear weapons’. It is almost impossible to miss this objection – but it is equally difficult to miss the disparity in emphasis between these very different points of view about Iraq’s nuclear program. The tendency to privilege particular judgments goes beyond the structure of intelligence estimates. Ironically, it permeates many of the conceptual frameworks that are intended to encourage analysts to consider multiple possibilities in the first place. For instance, one prominent text on analytic tradecraft recommends that analysts approach complex questions by generating multiple hypotheses, evaluating the ‘credibility’ of each hypothesis, sorting hypotheses ‘from most credible to least credible’, and then ‘select[ing] from the top of the list those hypotheses most deserving of attention’.11 Though its authors intend for this method of ‘multiple hypothesis generation’ to ensure that important alternatives do not get overlooked, the instruction to focus on the ‘most credible’ predictions indicates an assumption that unlikely possibilities are less ‘deserving of attention’. Yet that is often untrue. The most consequential events (such as major terrorist attacks, the outbreak of conventional wars, and the collapse of state governments ) are often perceived as unlikely before they occur, yet they can have such enormous impact that they deserve serious consideration. The overall significance of any event is a product of its probability and its consequences, and so both of these factors must be considered when comparing alternative scenarios. To give another example, many intelligence analysts are trained in a practice called Analysis of Competing Hypotheses (ACH). ACH seems to embrace the goal of assessing uncertainty. It instructs analysts to form a matrix of potential hypotheses and available information that helps to show how much evidence supports (or contradicts) each possibility. This practice combats first impressions and promotes alternative thinking.12 Yet the word ‘Competing’ is important here. Competing for what? The original description of ACH explains its goal as being to determine ‘Which of several possible explanations is the correct one? Which of several possible outcomes is the most likely one?’13 A recent manual introduces ACH as a tool for ‘selecting the hypothesis that best fits the evidence’.14 To this end, ACH instructs analysts to ‘focus on disproving hypotheses’.15 This does not mean that ACH always generates singleoutcome estimates, and the method is designed to indicate places where the evidence sustains multiple interpretations. When this occurs, ACH tells analysts to rank remaining possibilities from ‘weakest’ to ‘strongest’. An analyst seeking to assess uncertainty would approach the issue differently. She would not see the relevant possibilities as rival or competing. She would say that no possibility merits attention for being ‘correct’ and that focusing on disproving hypotheses places unnecessary emphasis on eliminating relevant scenarios from consideration. Moreover, she would argue that it makes little sense to say that any possibility is ‘weak’ or ‘strong’ so long as analysts accurately assess its likelihood. 16 This is not to claim that all scenarios have equal significance. But to repeat, the significance of any possibility is the product of its likelihood and its potential consequences. For that reason, ACH’s method of ranking hypotheses based on probability exposes analysts to consequence neglect. 2NC SOLVENCY Markets don’t solve Caplan 13 – director of the Center for Bioethics @ the University of Pennsylvania Arthur, “Opinion: Why selling kidneys still won't work” [http://www.nbcnews.com/health/healthnews/opinion-why-selling-kidneys-still-wont-work-f8C11459943] October 24 // Nor is it clear that $10,000 would really be enough to prompt many people to have a kidney removed. Kidney surgery is still major surgery, living with one kidney is a bit risky and there is a very real danger of various complications. While they won’t kill you, the problems could keep you in the hospital for days or weeks.¶ There is also the problem that markets only work for kidneys. We have two kidneys, which is one more than most people need. But markets won’t help obtain more hearts or livers or lungs. That means running one part of the transplant system with payments and the other based on altruism. Those involved with kidney transplants want to give markets a try. Those doing heart transplants don’t — they worry that a market will dry up the altruism they must rely on to get those organs.¶ Lastly, putting $10,000 on the table to get people to sell a kidney should not happen unless and until there are national standards for who can safely decide to sell one. The sicker you are or the more mentally unstable you are, the harder it should be to let you sell your kidney. But there are no agreed-upon criteria about either minimal health or mental competency to sort out those moved only by money to sell.¶ The idea of trying markets to increase the supply of kidneys is the whack-a-mole of transplant policy. Every other year someone does a study, tosses out a model or just proclaims that a market will solve the kidney shortage problem. But there is more than money involved when it comes to body parts, and until proponents of payment can engage those concerns, it is not likely that we will see a shift from academic talk to political action. Not enough people will sell Varjavand 13 [Reza Varjavand, Saint Xavier University associate professor of economics and finance at the Graham School of management, 2013, Journal of Management Policy and Practice vol. 14(4), “Legalized Market for Human Kidneys: A Wrong Solution to a Right Problem,” http://www.nabusinesspress.com/JMPP/VarjavandR_Web14_4_.pdf, accessed 8/1/14] Shortage, in the U.S. is not caused by economic factors like lack of price; there is no concrete evidence to prove that. People do not wish to donate a kidney in expectation of pecuniary gains especially in affluent countries like the United States. Unlike the peasants living in the rural areas of a less developed country who are the major source of kidneys that are for sale, I believe the poor in the U.S. are not so depredate they would sell their body parts for money, even if it were legal. And, if a few of them do, it is not going to change the prospect of the persistent shortage. In addition, because people are well- informed about the possible health risks and the harm they may suffer because of the possible side effects, they cannot be lured into selling a kidney against their wishes. So I think an attempt to boost supply through monetary incentives may not be as effective as it sounds. Likewise, people do not seek a kidney because it is cheap or expensive; they need it because they suffer from an unfortunate medical condition and they hope that there is a matching donor somewhere out there who can help save their life. Again, shortage is not a pricing problem and should not be dealt with by finding a monetary solution. Err neg – aff studies are flawed – too vague, support for legalization isn’t the same as willingness to sell, and examples of other countries don’t apply to the US Rid et al 9 – Senior Lecturer in Bioethics in the Department of Social Science, Health & Medicine @ King’s College London A., L. M. Bachmann, V. Wettstein, and N. Biller-Adorno, “Would you sell a kidney in a regulated kidney market? Results of an exploratory study” Journal of Medical Ethics 35:558-564 // This paper focuses on the first, empirical claim about a regulated kidney market—namely, that such a market would increase the supply of kidneys. Market proponents claim that ‘‘surveys suggest that the public favours compensation and that compensation would increase donation’’. 6 However, the data they cite to support this claim are insufficient . Studies investigating the impact of financial incentives in the deceased donation context have limited significance for the context of live donation. 8–11 Moreover, surveys that do not detail the conditions of a regulated kidney mar- ket 10 12 13 are too vague to assess how the population would respond to such a market, and the distinction between removing financial disincen- tives and providing financial incentives is often unclear. 12 Attitudes about legalising live kidney sales 10 may not reflect one’s willingness to sell an organ. Finally, data from Iran 14 —the only country that has implemented a regulated kidney market today—are difficult to extrapolate, because the Iranian market allows for co-payments among transplant recipients and living conditions in Iran are strikingly different from those in industrialised countries. 2NC SHORTAGE Bio-printing solves the shortage---multiple research rends, complex developments, momentum mean the shortage will be resolved in the next 10 years---that’s DAEF---that’s faster than the aff---establishment of regulations, and availability will be gradual due to shifting cultural norms. Advances in bioprinting will solve organ shortages Griggs 14 Brandon, “The next frontier in 3-D printing: Human organs” [http://www.cnn.com/2014/04/03/tech/innovation/3-d-printing-human-organs/] April 3 // Soon, however, 3-D printers may be spitting out something far more complex, and controversial: human organs.¶ For years now, medical researchers have been reproducing human cells in laboratories by hand to create blood vessels, urine tubes, skin tissue and other living body parts. But engineering full organs, with their complicated cell structures, is much more difficult. ¶ Enter 3-D printers, which because of their precise process can reproduce the vascular systems required to make organs viable. Scientists are already using the machines to print tiny strips of organ tissue. And while printing whole human organs for surgical transplants is still years away, the technology is rapidly developing.¶ "The mechanical process isn't all that complicated. The tricky part is the materials, which are biological in nature," said Mike Titsch, editor-in-chief of 3D Printer World, which covers the industry. "It isn't like 3-D printing plastic or metal. Plastic doesn't die if you leave it sitting on an openair shelf at room temperature for too long."¶ The idea of printing a human kidney or liver in a lab may seem incomprehensible, even creepy. But to many scientists in the field, bioprinting holds great promise. Authentic printed organs could be used for drug or vaccine testing, freeing researchers from less accurate methods such as tests on animals or on synthetic models.¶ Then there's the hope that 3D printers could someday produce much-needed organs for transplants. Americans are living longer, and as we get deeper into old age our organs are failing more. Some 18 people die in the United States each day waiting in vain for transplants because of a shortage of donated organs -- a problem that Anthony Atala, director of the Wake Forest Institute for Regenerative Medicine and a pioneer in bioprinting, calls "a major health crisis."¶ An 'exciting new area of medicine'¶ Bioprinting works like this: Scientists harvest human cells from biopsies or stem cells, then allow them to multiply in a petri dish. The resulting mixture, a sort of biological ink, is fed into a 3-D printer, which is programmed to arrange different cell types, along with other materials, into a precise three-dimensional shape. Doctors hope that when placed in the body, these 3-D-printed cells will integrate with existing tissues.¶ The process already is seeing some success. Last year a 2-year-old girl in Illinois, born without a trachea, received a windpipe built with her own stem cells. The U.S. government has funded a university-led "body on a chip" project that prints tissue samples that mimic the functions of the heart, liver, lungs and other organs. The samples are placed on a microchip and connected with a blood substitute to keep the cells alive, allowing doctors to test specific treatments and monitor their effectiveness.¶ "This is an exciting new area of medicine. It has the potential for being a very important breakthrough," said Dr. Jorge Rakela, a gastroenterologist at the Mayo Clinic in Phoenix and a member of the American Liver Foundation's medical advisory committee.¶ "Three-D printing allows you to be closer to what is happening in real life, where you have multiple layers of cells," he said. With current 2-D models, "if you grow more than one or two layers, the cells at the bottom suffocate from lack of oxygen."¶ To accelerate the development of bioprinted organs, a Virginia foundation that supports regenerative medicine research announced in December it will award a $1 million prize for the first organization to print a fully functioning liver.¶ One early contender for the prize is Organovo, a California start-up that has been a leader in bioprinting human body parts for commercial purposes. Using cells from donated tissue or stem cells, Organovo is developing what it hopes will be authentic models of human organs, primarily livers, for drug testing.¶ The company has printed strips of human liver tissue in its labs, although they are still very small: four by four by one millimeter, or about one-fourth the size of a dime. Each strip takes about 45 minutes to print, and it takes another two days for the cells to grow and mature, said Organovo CEO Keith Murphy. The models can then survive for about 40 days. ¶ Organovo has also built models of human kidneys, bone, cartilage, muscle, blood vessels and lung tissue, he said. Momentum is building---accelerates the process. Phillips 14 – senior contributor and editor at Inside3DP.com Shanie, “Latest Development Brings Us One Step Closer to Bioprinting Organs” [http://www.inside3dp.com/latest-development-brings-us-one-step-closer-bioprinting-organs/] August 6 // Printing organs is certainly one of the coolest and most talked about capabilities of 3D printing. Even though fully functional, implantation-safe organs have yet to be artificially created, many developments have been made that lead in that direction. This past week, another revelation in bioprinting was made that brings us one step closer to 3D printed organs.¶ A team of researchers from universities across the US and China tested biological ‘inks’ with different concentrations of mouse fibroblasts and hydrogel solutions, and found that adding more cells in the bioinks reduces both droplet size and the rate at which the ink gets dispensed. This is a significant breakthrough in bioprinting, as no studies have been done yet that really reveal how bioinks behave when dispensed through printer nozzles. ¶ “There are a few different biofabricating methods, but inkjet printing has emerged as a frontrunner. It has been used to print live cells, from hamster ovary cells to human fibroblasts, which are a common type of cell in the body,” the researchers reported in the American Chemical Society journal Langmuir, which published the results.¶ Organ shortage is a serious issue. Currently over 120,000 people are on waiting lists for donated organs, yet less than 10,000 received the transplants they needed between January and April of this year. In addition to the shortage itself, available organs also run the risk of being rejected by the patient’s body. With the new bioink information discovered this week, researchers can now better conduct and tailor bioprinting studies, which could lead to quicker development of functional 3D printed ‘self-made’ organs that can’t be rejected.¶ “The new results will help scientists move forward with this promising technology,” said Yong Huang, one of the researchers from the University of Florida in Gainesville. Other researchers in the team were from Clemson University in South Carolina, Zheijiang University in China and the Medical University of South Carolina. We’re on the brink of being able to bioprint organs Ungar 13 Laura, “Researchers closing in on printing 3-D hearts” [http://www.usatoday.com/story/tech/2013/05/29/health-3d-printing-organ-transplant/2370079/] May 29 // LOUISVILLE, Ky. — Researcher Stuart Williams is not talking about a far-off, science-fiction effort when he describes how scientists here will create new, functioning human hearts — using cells and a 3-D printer.¶ The project is among the most ambitious in the growing field of three-dimensional printing that some say could revolutionize medicine.¶ STORY: Doctors design custom implant for baby¶ STORY: 3-D printing revolutionizes development¶ "We think we can do it in 10 years — that we can build, from a patient's own cells, a total 'bioficial' heart," said Williams, executive and scientific director of the Cardiovascular Innovation Institute. The institute is a collaboration between the University of Louisville and the Jewish Heritage Fund for Excellence.¶ Known for creating products as diverse as car parts and action figures, 3-D printing also is being used to create models of human bones and organs, medical devices, personalized prosthetics and now, human tissues. Williams describes the process as taking a three-dimensional structure "and essentially cloning it, using a printer."¶ "Bioprinting is pretty much done everywhere," said Dr. Anthony Atala, director of the Wake Forest Institute for Regenerative Medicine in North Carolina where scientists recently won an award for innovations in bioprinting. "Our ultimate goal is increasing the number of patients who get organs."¶ Earlier this month, officials announced that a baby's life had been saved when a 3-D printed device from the University of Michigan — a specially designed splint — restored his breathing. The case was recently featured in the New England Journal of Medicine.¶ Here, Williams and his colleagues recently created and implanted parts of hearts in mice as part of their heart-printing research. And University of Kentucky scientists have used the technology to grow new ulna bones in rabbits and make numerous models of human parts for teaching and surgery planning.¶ Eventually, scientists across the globe hope printing tissues and organs from patients' cells can eliminate the danger of rejection and the persistent shortage of transplant organs. Atala said that may be years away, and scientists face a number of challenges, such as replicating the complexity of blood vessels. ¶ But Bill Gregory of the UK Center for Visualization and Virtual Environments expressed the optimism of many scientists, saying that, in the future, "You'll be able to custom-make parts and get them when you need them."¶ Work began in 1990s¶ While interest in 3-D printing has "all of a sudden exploded," Williams said that he and other scientists have been studying medical applications of the technology since the 1990s. ¶ It involves taking a three-dimensional digital image of a structure, then replicating the structure by depositing material in layers. Materials can be plastic, liquid or cells in a biologically safe glue. Different researchers use different custom-made glues and printers.¶ Williams, who worked at the University of Arizona before coming to UofL in 2007, said his team there received money from the U.S. Department of Defense to use 3-D printing to create a lymph node — with the idea it could be implanted in the event of bioterrorism.¶ To create the node — which they did in 2001 — they built a 3-D printer called the BioAssembly Tool, or BAT, for about $400,000. They started with a direct-write printer, adding parts from the hardware store and from custom shops.¶ In 2003, Williams won an R&D 100 Award for his work on the custom printer, which has resulted in $30 million worth of bioprinting work. ¶ Williams has brought the BioAssembly Tool here, where his main interest is creating blood vessels, cardiac structures and ultimately hearts to fight cardiovascular disease, which accounts for about 3 in 10 deaths in Kentucky.¶ "This was what killed my dad," he said. "My dad was in congestive heart failure." ¶ In 2007, the Cardiovascular Innovation Institute received a $2 million grant from the National Institutes of Health to develop the printing technology, which researchers used at the time to organize tissue grown in the lab to build networks of small blood vessels using mice and rats. Their work has continued since.¶ Tissues are created using cells derived from an individual's fat and extracted with a machine. They go into the BioAssembly Tool, and the living cells are mixed with a glue that eventually dissolves inside the body like surgical sutures.¶ STORY: 3-D printing shows promise in prosthetics¶ VIDEO: 3-D printer could make live body parts¶ The printer rebuilds the structure, which then can be implanted. Williams said they are still working on whether the fat-derived cells will be coaxed into becoming cardiovascular cells in the lab or inside the body.¶ He said building a heart involves creating five parts — valves, coronary vessels, microcirculation, contractile cells and the organ's electrical system. Six months ago, researchers created and implanted a portion of a heart and blood vessels in mice.¶ The ultimate goal is to extract a patient's fat through liposuction, isolate cells with a machine, mix them with the glue and "print" a heart — all within an hour.¶ Williams said the total bioficial heart could cost about $100,000 in today's dollars, not counting $150,000 or so in hospital and surgery costs. That's less than the typical heart transplant and doesn't require ongoing costs for anti-rejection drugs.¶ If the bioficial heart were proven and federally approved, insurance most likely would cover it if it were considered medically necessary for the patient, he said.¶ Williams said some of his peers laugh at his 10-year timetable, but he's not discouraged.¶ "I love it when they laugh," he said. "It provides me with a challenge."¶ Beyond Louisville¶ Scientists in Lexington also are tapping into the possibilities of 3D printing.¶ Gregory said his UK center printed ulnas for rabbits around 2005, using "bone-seeding" material that coaxed new bone to grow within rabbits.¶ A more common application of 3-D printing at UK is to create surgical models from CT or MRI images, using liquid, small beads or powder, Gregory said.¶ Models allow surgeons to practice on a person's precise anatomy before an operation — or teach medical students or residents — using printed replicas of structures such as jaws, eye sockets or cheekbones. Gregory said doctors also develop custom implants for reconstruction. ¶ Dr. Larry Cunningham, chief of oral maxillofacial surgery at the University of Kentucky, said models give doctors "something you can hold in your hand," instead of trying to visualize a structure from a twodimensional image.¶ "The advantage to the patient is I'm better prepared," Cunningham said. "I can be faster with less down time, which is important because OR time can cost $100 a minute."¶ The cost of 3-D printers has come down. Gregory said people can buy decent "hobby printers" for a couple thousand dollars, and sophisticated lab versions cost around $20,000 with custom-made printers costing much more.¶ The increasingly accessible technology has spawned new companies and products.¶ San Francisco-based Bespoke Innovations creates custom prosthetics, saying on its website: "The advent of 3-D printing has allowed us to build something based on the unique shape of a particular user, modify it with our designs, and turn it into something physical that can be worn." ¶ Human parts¶ Meanwhile, scientists across the world are working on the next step, creating an array of real human parts.¶ In February, doctors at Weill Cornell Medical College and biomedical engineers at Cornell University in New York announced they had used 3-D printing and injectable gels made of cells to build a facsimile of a human ear that looks and acts like a real one.¶ And in the case of the baby in Michigan, university officials said the splint was created from a CT scan of the patient's trachea and bronchus, integrating a computer model with 3-D printing. The baby, who stopped breathing every day when his collapsed bronchus blocked the flow of air, was off a ventilator three weeks after the surgery, and officials say he hasn't had breathing trouble since. ¶ Wake Forest scientists, like their peers in Louisville, are working on organs. Officials at Wake Forest say their scientists were the first in the world to engineer a lab-grown organ, and they hope to scale up the process by printing organs with a custom printer. Institute scientists there have also designed a bioprinter to print skin cells onto burn wounds. 2NC MARKET Geographic containment is impossible – domestic donor pool will inevitably dry up and market forces means donors from underprivileged countries will travel to the US to sell their organs Jha and Chugh 6 – professors of nephrology @ Nephrology at the Postgraduate Institute of Medical Education and Research, Chandigarh, India. Vivekanand and Kirpal S., “The case against a regulated system of living kidney sales” [http://abcnews.go.com/images/WNT/The%20case%20against%20a%20regulated%20system.pdf] // Schemes for setting up government-funded and regulated paid kidney donation programs that give equal opportunity to rich and poor people, and guarantee health care to the donors, have been proposed. Getting such programs to work, however, would be a major challenge. Even the proponents of regulated sales concede that such models can apply only to Western countries that have well-established systems of implementation and monitoring to ensure fair and equitable distribution through existing domestic networks. Inherent in such schemes is the assumption that strict geographical containment is possible.¶ Once the initial rush of domestic donors is exhausted, the globalization of organ trade, whereby donors would come in large numbers from the developing world to supply organs to the industrialized world, is inevitable. The accep- tance of even a limited domestic organ market in the advanced nations will act as the proverbial thin end of the wedge and encourage adoption of commercial donation in the developing world. This view was endorsed by the National Kidney Foundation in a testimony to the US Congress where Dr Francis Delmonico argued that “...a US congressional endorsement for payment would propel other countries to sanction unethical and unjust standards...”.¶ Paid transplantations negatively affect living related and cadaveric transplantation in devel- oping countries. 13 When cheap organs are avail- able, people often opt to buy one rather than subject a loved one to the risk of donation. There are other strategies apart from organ sales that can increase donation rates, such as public awareness campaigns, a ‘presumed consent’ law, use of marginal donors and performing ABO- incompatible or paired-exchange transplanta- tions. An element of reciprocity could also be injected into the system, so that—for example— people can choose to donate organs only to those who have in turn indicated their willingness for the same.¶ The arguments supporting a regulated organ market are extremely simplistic, and ignore the ground realities. Allowing such an activity in any corner of the world would open the doors for rampant exploitation of the underprivileged in areas that are already plagued by vast economic inequalities. It is important that the transplant community approaches this issue with a sense of responsibility towards society that is equal to the compassion it shows towards its patients. Iran proves a legal market doesn’t solve Corwin 6 Julie, “World: The Risks, Benefits Of A Free Market In Organs” [http://www.rferl.org/content/article/1068445.html] May 16 // But Scheper-Hughes says there are no guarantees that legalizing kidney sales would end all the abuses now associated with the black market. She says that in Iran legal sales have not corrected a problem of the black market: the exploitation of poor people as organ suppliers for middle- and upper-class recipients.¶ "We know from research, including research conducted by a postdoctoral fellow of mine who was working in Iran, that the donors are often recruited from marginal populations that include, in addition to very poor people and people in debt, also include populations of young people who are disaffected from their families -- some of whom are spending a great deal of their time in the street and some of whom are drug-using people and so forth," Scheper-Hughes says. Laundry list of other countries for organ brokers to shift too Sack 14 [Kevin Sack, New York Times, 8/17/14, “Transplant Brokers in Israel Lure Desperate Kidney Patients to Costa Rica,” http://www.nytimes.com/2014/08/17/world/middleeast/transplant-brokers-in-israel-luredesperate-kidney-patients-to-costa-rica.html?_r=0, accessed 8/21/14] Experts list China, Egypt, India, Pakistan, Sri Lanka, Turkey, Eastern Europe and the former Soviet republics as hot spots for organ trafficking. But illicit transplants usually go undetected unless there is a surgical mistake or a payment dispute. Prosecutions are thwarted by false affidavits, toothless laws and lack of international cooperation, particularly regarding extradition.¶ Over the last decade, the authorities have pursued only a handful of cases worldwide. Few have sidelined the brokers, who seem bolder than ever. Some, like Mr. Volfman, who leases office space atop a mirrored skyscraper in Ramat Gan, have moved out of the shadows. They brazenly ply their trade even while under police scrutiny, posting Facebook photos of the luxury cars and five-star hotel rooms they rent on the road. Economic incentives outweigh regulatory safeguards – brokers will continue operating sales in the illicit market b/c it’s more profitable Mendoza 11 [Roger Lee Mendoza, Professor, Wilmington University/University of Pennsylvania, J Public Health (2011) 33 (1), “Price deflation and the underground organ economy in the Philippines,” http://jpubhealth.oxfordjournals.org/content/33/1/101.full#ref-10, accessed 8/22/14] The dividing line between the underground and legal transplant systems becomes razor-thin when several participants (matching agencies, foundations, hospitals, doctors and law-enforcers) in one system consciously or unconsciously perform the same roles or functions in the other with relative ease. Kidney patients pay huge sums for new kidneys, but most of them go to brokers, including some doctors/medical facilities, for locating and transporting poor donors. Without brokers operating in a relatively unrestrained market, it is doubtful if many poor vendors will find kidney buyers. Without incentives (e.g. cash rewards) to report these brokers and their vast networks, and swift government action, the underground kidney trade will continue to flourish , entrench market inequalities based on asymmetric information and dent government reform efforts. ¶ The Philippine experience thus yields valuable public health policy insights that are transferable to other countries, particularly in the developing world: (i) grassroots-based educational and health promotion strategies are vital considering vendors' socio-demographic profile and limited awareness of legal prohibitions and health risks; (ii) a carefully designed mix of supply-side and demand-side incentives complements law-enforcement (e.g. cash incentives to report buy-and-sell transactions and swift government action with on-the-spot media coverage); (iii) criminal deterrence is insufficient and costly in the absence of creative policing and prosecution strategies to cope with ever-changing trading environments (e.g. online, sham marriages between foreign patients and Filipino vendors) and rules (e.g. sub-contracting); (iv) donor post-operative care and long-term health deserve equal attention (e.g. making organ recipients partly responsible for donors' health care promotes a more equitable transplantation model); and (v) policy debate should not be confined to legitimacy issues (e.g. prohibition and punishment of compensated donations), but should address other relevant aspects of transplantation, including better renal care programs, promotion of cadaveric (brain-death and cardiac-death) organ donations, the health hazards of illicit organ-selling and sources of information asymmetries.¶ Collectively, these policy implications underscore the need to evaluate government action in terms of its net effect on participants in the underground organ commerce. A carefully designed mix of effective regulation and lawenforcement and public education should raise the costs and lower the benefits of brokered organ trading. It should also encourage the exchange of useful and symmetric information concerning organ donation and transplantation. Otherwise, organ traders will likely find it economically inefficient to distinguish between what is legal and prohibited in organ donation and transplantation. Illegal brokers circumvent the plan – they’ll just move to a new country Sack 14 [Kevin Sack, New York Times, 8/17/14, “Transplant Brokers in Israel Lure Desperate Kidney Patients to Costa Rica,” http://www.nytimes.com/2014/08/17/world/middleeast/transplant-brokers-in-israel-luredesperate-kidney-patients-to-costa-rica.html?_r=0, accessed 8/21/14] A broker who trades in human organs might seem a difficult thing to find. But Ms. Dorin’s mother began making inquiries around the hospital where she worked, and in short order the family came up with three names: Avigad Sandler, a former insurance agent long suspected of trafficking; Boris Volfman, a young Ukrainian émigré and Sandler protégé; and Yaacov Dayan, a wily businessman with interests in real estate and marketing.¶ The men were, The New York Times learned during an investigation of the global organ trade, among the central operators in Israel’s irrepressible underground kidney market. For years, they have pocketed enormous sums for arranging overseas transplants for patients who are paired with foreign donors, court filings and government documents show.¶ The brokers maintain they operate legally and do not directly help clients buy organs. Dodging international condemnation and tightening enforcement, they have nimbly shifted operations across the globe when any one destination closes its doors. ¶ The supply of transplantable organs is estimated by the World Health Organization to meet no more than a tenth of the need. Although there is no reliable data, experts say thousands of patients most likely receive illicit transplants abroad each year. Almost always, the sellers are poor and ill-informed about the medical risks.¶ The vast marketplace includes the United States, where federal prosecutors in New Jersey won the first conviction for illegal brokering in 2011. ¶ But a Times analysis of major trafficking cases since 2000 suggests that Israelis have played a disproportionate role. That is in part because of religious strictures regarding death and desecration that have kept deceased donation rates so low that some patients feel they must turn elsewhere. ¶ “When someone needs an organ transplant, they’ll do everything in their power,” said Meir Broder, a top legal adviser to Israel’s Ministry of Health. Legalization doesn’t increase the quality of organs – creates an incentive for donors to lie about preexisting conditions *DDOC = deceased donor organ commercialism Epstein et al 11 – senior Lecturer in Medical Ethics and Law @ Barts and The London School of Medicine and Dentistry, Miran, Dominique Martin, and Gabriel Danovitch, “Caution: deceased donor organ commercialism!” Transplant International Volume 24, Issue 9, pages 958–964, September 2011 // DDOC also risks impairing the safety of organ transplantation. Commercial organ donation, both from the living and deceased, is accompanied by an increased risk of infection [67]. Although such complications may be related to the quality of transplantation services, in particular the screening of organ vendors and the hazards of maintaining continuity of patient care in the setting of transplant tourism, DDOC may nevertheless contribute to increased risks. For example, prospective organ providers or their relatives may be reluctant to reveal information about the provider’s health that might jeopardize the chance of sale, such as the presence of risk factors for infection or disease. Medical staff may also conceal such information to profit from organ recovery or transplantation. In this regard it is worth noting that in the U.S., paid blood donation was discontinued precisely because of the increased infection risk. The larger the amount of money at stake the greater may be the propensity to conceal critical information [68]. Antibiotic use doesn’t spike resistance THOMAS, M.E., et al., 08 virus into poultry farms during the ("Risk factors for the introduction of high pathogenicity Avian Influenza epidemic in the Netherlands in 2003." Preventive veterinary medicine 69, (10 June 2005): 1-11. Agricola. EBSCO. [1 Aug. 2008, http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=agr&AN=IND43716042&site=ehost-live] With the exception of ciprofloxacin resistance, there is a paucity of scientific evidence to document the association of antimicrobial agents used in veterinary medicine with increases in antimicrobial-resistant pathogens (Phillips et al., 2004). For example, it has been suggested that the increased prevalenc e of extended-spectrum cephalosporin-resistant strains is in part related to the use in food animals of ceftiofur, which is an extended-spectrum cephalosporin approved for use in veterinary medicine (White et al., 2001); however, scientific evidence is lacking. Antimicrobial agents used for intensive calf rearing in the 1970–1980s have also been speculated to contribute to the emergence of multiple-antibiotic resistant Salmonella Typhimurium DT104 strains. Genes included in the antibiotic resistance gene cluster of Salmonella Typhimurium DT104 confer resistance to four of the five antimicrobials used during that time to treat veal calves, therefore co-selection of the entire cluster could have arisen from the use of any one of those drugs (Velge, Cloeckaert, & Barrow, 2005). While there is no definitive evidence for this scenario, several reviews have been published presenting contrasting views regarding the role of veterinary usage of antimicrobials in the emergence of antibiotic-resistant foodborne pathogens. In support of a causal relationship are reviews by Angulo et al., 2004 and Mølbak, 2004, whereas reviews by Phillips et al., 2004 and Wassenaar, 2005 advocate that veterinary usage of antimicrobial agents are inaccurately incriminated as being a major contributor to antibiotic-resistant pathogens in humans. Debate on this topic will continue but should consider the additional routes which lead to resistant bacterial populations, that antimicrobial usage in animals is required for animal health and well-being, and that not every antimicrobial-resistant pathogen has human health consequences. On this latter point, clearly not all infections caused by resistant pathogens fail to respond to treatment. For example, in a study of 23 diarrhea cases in Thailand, nearly all were infected with ciprofloxacin-resistant Campylobacter, yet 58% of patients receiving ciprofloxaxin treatment were cured. This response implies that treatment with ciprofloxacin could still be effective in many cases (Sanders et al., 2002). Another consideration is that acquisition of drug resistance could entail a biological cost to the pathogen resulting in reduced fitness and competitiveness in the absence of antibiotic selection pressure. For example, most data on E. coli suggest that increased antibiotic resistance results in decreased fitness (Wassenaar, 2005). Alternatively, for some foodborne pathogens such as fluoroquinoloneresistant C. jejuni, resistance can be neutral or even beneficial in terms of fitness (Luo et al., 2005). When coinoculated into chickens, fluoroquinolone-resistant Campylobacter isolates either outcompeted or were outcompeted by most of the fluoroquinolone-susceptible strains, with the outcome being dependent on the genetic background of the recipient strain. These variable results highlight the complex nature of antibiotic resistance and the large data gaps that exist in making informed scientific decisions on use of antimicrobials in animals used for food. 1NR KEYSTONE Runaway warming leads to extinction – precautionary principle means you should vote neg if there’s any risk they don’t lead to extinction Roberts 13—citing the World Bank Review’s compilation of climate studies - 4 degree projected warming, can’t adapt - heat wave related deaths, forest fires, crop production, water wars, ocean acidity, sea level rise, climate migrants, biodiversity loss David, “If you aren’t alarmed about climate, you aren’t paying attention” [http://grist.org/climateenergy/climate-alarmism-the-idea-is-surreal/] January 10 We know we’ve raised global average temperatures around 0.8 degrees C so far. We know that 2 degrees C is where most scientists predict catastrophic and irreversible impacts. And we know that we are currently on a trajectory that will push temperatures up 4 degrees or more by the end of the century. What would 4 degrees look like? A recent World Bank review of the science reminds us. First, it’ll get hot: Projections for a 4°C world show a dramatic increase in the intensity and frequency of high-temperature extremes. Recent extreme heat waves such as in Russia in 2010 are likely to become the new normal summer in a 4°C world. Tropical South America, central Africa, and all tropical islands in the Pacific are likely to regularly experience heat waves of unprecedented magnitude and duration. In this new hightemperature climate regime, the coolest months are likely to be substantially warmer than the warmest months at the end of the 20th century. In regions such as the Mediterranean, North Africa, the Middle East, and the Tibetan plateau, almost all summer months are likely to be warmer than the most extreme heat waves presently experienced. For example, the warmest July in the Mediterranean region could be 9°C warmer than today’s warmest July. Extreme heat waves in recent years have had severe impacts, causing heat-related deaths, forest fires, and harvest losses. The impacts of the extreme heat waves projected for a 4°C world have not been evaluated, but they could be expected to vastly exceed the consequences experienced to date and potentially exceed the adaptive capacities of many societies and natural systems. [my emphasis] Warming to 4 degrees would also lead to “an increase of about 150 percent in acidity of the ocean,” leading to levels of acidity “unparalleled in Earth’s history.” That’s bad news for, say, coral reefs: The combination of thermally induced bleaching events, ocean acidification, and sea-level rise threatens large fractions of coral reefs even at 1.5°C global warming. The regional extinction of entire coral reef ecosystems, which could occur well before 4°C is reached, would have profound consequences for their dependent species and for the people who depend on them for food, income, tourism, and shoreline protection. It will also “likely lead to a sea-level rise of 0.5 to 1 meter, and possibly more, by 2100, with several meters more to be realized in the coming centuries.” That rise won’t be spread evenly, even within regions and countries — regions close to the equator will see even higher seas. There are also indications that it would “significantly exacerbate existing water scarcity in many regions, particularly northern and eastern Africa, the Middle East, and South Asia, while additional countries in Africa would be newly confronted with water scarcity on a national scale due to population growth.” Also, more extreme weather events: Ecosystems will be affected by more frequent extreme weather events, such as forest loss due to droughts and wildfire exacerbated by land use and agricultural expansion. In Amazonia, forest fires could as much as double by 2050 with warming of approximately 1.5°C to 2°C above preindustrial levels. Changes would be expected to be even more severe in a 4°C world. Also loss of biodiversity and ecosystem services: In a 4°C world, climate change seems likely to become the dominant driver of ecosystem shifts, surpassing habitat destruction as the greatest threat to biodiversity. Recent research suggests that large-scale loss of biodiversity is likely to occur in a 4°C world, with climate change and high CO2 concentration driving a transition of the Earth’s ecosystems into a state unknown in human experience. Ecosystem damage would be expected to dramatically reduce the provision of ecosystem services on which society depends (for example, fisheries and protection of coastline afforded by coral reefs and mangroves.) New research also indicates a “rapidly rising risk of crop yield reductions as the world warms.” So food will be tough. All this will add up to “large-scale displacement of populations and have adverse consequences for human security and economic and trade systems.” Given the uncertainties and long-tail risks involved, “ there is no certainty that adaptation to a 4°C world is possible.” There’s a small but non-trivial chance of advanced civilization breaking down entirely. Now ponder the fact that some scenarios show us going up to 6 degrees by the end of the century, a level of devastation we have not studied and barely know how to conceive. Ponder the fact that somewhere along the line, though we don’t know exactly where, enough self-reinforcing feedback loops will be running to make climate change unstoppable and irreversible for centuries to come. That would mean handing our grandchildren and their grandchildren not only a burned, chaotic, denuded world, but a world that is inexorably more inhospitable with every passing decade. The plan destroys Obama’s political standing Martin Gunnarson, PhD student in Ethnology at the Centre for Studies in Practical Knowledge, Södertörn University, and at the Department of Arts and Cultural Sciences, Lund University, 2012, The body as gift, resource, and commodity, http://sh.divaportal.org/smash/get/diva2:510121/FULLTEXT01.pdf But is a gift that is presumed really a gift? And if one’s dead body is such a valuable resource for helping others in grave need, should it still be considered an object that one is entitled to control the ways of even when one is dead? Perhaps the right thing to do would be to once and for all let go of the gift metaphor and officially start referring to the brain-dead body as a resource. In the wake of such a rhetorical shift, a political space might open up allowing the implementation of policies aimed at increasing the number of organs available for transplantation. But as we all know, leaders who propose changes of such nature would almost certainly risk committing political suicide. The problems of implementing strategies aimed at increasing the number of organs for transplantation are many and hard to solve, everybody involved knows this. In this context, not only politicians risk losing the trust of people, health care practitioners do, too. Whether we are talking about making consent as a necessary requirement for do- nation weaker, or about making the donor pool larger by moving from total brain death to a criteria based on that the parts of the brain necessary for being conscious and feeling pain are forever gone, mistrust may easily arise and spread if patients in some situations move from being a subject of concern in their own right to being a resource for the concern of others. Emergency care to keep organs fresh for transplantation, rather than trying to save the life of the person that the organs presently belong to, are hard to handle, for health care personnel, as well as for relatives. Every prognosis in medicine has a certain percentage of uncertainty to it, and if we move from total brain death to less strict criteria (either directly or by the way of DCD) the chances (even if still very close to zero) will rise that somebody diagnosed as dead will come back to life (meaning coming back to consciousness). And even if this does not happen in a case which has been strictly controlled, it might happen, or, at least, be said to have happened, in other cases which involve coma not being sufficiently diagnosed to determine if it is irreversible or not. Political death sentence Hippen 8 [Benjamin E. Hippen (Associate editor of the American Journal of Transplantation, transplant nephrologist in private practice with Metrolina Nephrology Associates and the Carolinas Medical Center, at-large member of the United Network for Organ Sharing/Organ Procurement and Transplant Network Ethics Committee); March 20, 2008; “Organ Sales and Moral Travails: Lessons from the Living Kidney Vendor Program in Iran”; Policy Analysis, No. 614] A straightforward repeal of Section 301 of the National Organ Transplant Act, 71 which proscribes the exchange of “valuable consideration” for organs, would be the most effective first step toward establishing a comprehensive system of organ vending in the United States. A more feasible but politically difficult first step would be for Congress to allow exemptions from Section 301 of NOTA to permit pilot programs in organ vending. However, whether or not such programs proved successful could depend on many variables. For example, a pilot program might increase the number of organs without fulfilling other obligations to organ vendors, invit ing unflattering comparisons to underground organ trafficking. Or a program might be successful in one community but ineffective (or inappropriate) in other communities. An incentive program that works in Chicago might not be nearly as effective in Poughkeepsie. By extension, a single program which fails to increase the number of organs should not lead to the conclusion that all incentive proposals are certain to fail. For these reasons, a straightforward repeal of Section 301 would be preferable. Empirics prove the link Laura Meckler, WSJ, 2007, Kidney Shortage Inspires A Radical Idea: Organ Sales, online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB119490273908090431?mg=reno64wsj&url=http%3A%2F%2Fonline.wsj.com%2Farticle%2FSB119490273908090431.html Despite their differences over organ sales, Drs. Matas and Delmonico have much in common. Both have been kidney-transplant surgeons since the late-1970s, when the field was young and all the leading surgeons knew one another. Dr. Matas's wife sent gifts when Dr. Delmonico's grandchildren were born. Dr. Delmonico was quick with recommendations for the best Italian food in Boston's North End when Dr. Matas came to town to visit. Dr. Delmonico has used his influence to help kill efforts on the kidney-selling front. In 2003, several medical groups, including the American Medical Association and the United Network for Organ Sharing, endorsed legislation to allow pilot studies of payments to families that donate a loved one's organs after death. Dissent was strong, including from Dr. Delmonico, who testified before Congress on behalf of the National Kidney Foundation. "The sale of bodies or body parts would undermine the fundamental values of our society," he told the House Energy and Commerce Committee. The bill went nowhere. PC key to holding dems in line Simendinger 12/29 Alexis, “Obama's 2014: Buffeted Yet Buoyed by Late-Year Uptick” [http://www.realclearpolitics.com/articles/2014/12/29/obamas_2014_buffeted_yet_buoyed_by_lateyear_uptick_125061.html] // Obama, as was true of his predecessors, will need to hold his party to protect his vetoes from being overridden by required two-thirds majorities in each chamber. Overriding vetoes is not easy, as history has shown.¶ Vetoes are a powerful constitutional shield to block legislation during divided government, and can be used as weapons to force legislative compromises. Having wielded his veto powers just twice to date, Obama is poised to get more practice. During President Clinton’s final two years in office, Chuck Brain was the White House legislative director during a contentious period with Republicans in Congress. Brain envisions a series of Obama vetoes that he believes should be strategically worked out with members of the president’s party, and yet be unpredictable enough to keep Republicans guessing.¶ “We’re going to see in the last two years of this presidency, in this next Congress, the high art of veto politics,” Brain told RCP during a Dec. 11 panel discussion held at American University.¶ Obama says he’ll make strides using his unilateral powers in the next two years. That means he has new calculations to make after losing the Senate four years after losing Democratic control of the House.¶ “The numbers that matter to the president are 34 and 146,” Schiliro added. “If the president focuses on that, then he has the ability to have a disproportionate influence on the process. Those are the numbers he needs to sustain a veto.” PC key to sustain vetos Douglas Bloomfield, 12/31/14, Washington Watch: Democrats in disarray , www.jpost.com/Opinion/Washington-Watch-Democrats-in-disarray-386301 In recognition of the rising influence of the liberal wing and Warren’s own national stature, Reid created a leadership post for her as a strategic advisor. Obama expects to be using his veto pen quite a bit over the next two years, and he will need Democrats to help sustain those decisions. Some, however, may be reluctant to go to the barricades for a lame-duck president who many feel has taken them for granted and could drag them down. Pelosi’s and Warren’s opposition to the year-end spending compromise between the White House and Republicans told the president not to try to bypass them to cut deals with the opposition because he will need them in the showdowns . Obama’s working to maintain veto support—that’s key Charles Babington, AP, 12/7/14, Obama, Congress Brace For Veto Showdowns, www.huffingtonpost.com/2014/12/07/obama-congress-veto_n_6283688.html Veto brinkmanship between congressional Republicans and President Barack Obama was virtually absent in his first six years in office, but it's about to unleash itself on Washington. Until now, controversial Republican-backed legislation rarely reached the president's desk because Senate Democrats blocked it. Starting in January, however, Republicans will control both the House and Senate, and Obama may have to decide more often whether to sign or veto GOP-crafted bills. Obama gave lawmakers an early taste of veto politics recently when he forced congressional leaders to drop a proposed package of tax breaks that were popular with many Republican constituents. Some Democrats did support the plan, but liberals and the White House said it tilted too heavily toward corporations, not lower-income workers. The White House also has promised to veto any bills restricting the president's major changes to immigration policies, setting up likely showdowns early next year. Obama's threats present the type of bind that Republicans may face repeatedly in the next two years. They can agree to many or all of the changes he demands in legislation, or they can let him use his veto and hope Americans will blame him more than them. It's a gamble, especially with critical spending bills Congress soon must address. Some Republicans want to amend these must-pass bills to thwart Obama's bid to protect millions of immigrants, now in the country illegally, from deportation. Assuming Obama keeps his veto promise, Republican lawmakers would have to decide whether to drop their demands or let parts of the federal government close for lack of money. GOP leaders say there will be no shutdowns, but they have yet to explain how they can force Obama to back off on immigration. The 2013 partial government shutdown occurred under similar partisan circumstances. Polls show the public blamed congressional Republicans more than the Democratic president. It's unclear how often Obama will face a veto decision. Even in the minority, Democratic senators can use the filibuster, the name for unlimited debate, to block many measures that break strictly along party lines. But some proposals, such as building the Keystone XL pipeline, enjoy significant bipartisan support. They might attract enough Democratic backing to reach 60 Senate votes, overcoming a filibuster and sending the measure to Obama. White House senior adviser Dan Pfeiffer said if Congress assembles legislation that Obama opposes, the White House will threaten vetoes and "if Congress decides to pass them anyway, then we'll veto them." "We're not going to go out looking for them, but we're not going to run from them either," he said. Should Obama veto a proposal such as the Keystone project, the question would be whether two-thirds of the Senate and two-thirds of the House would vote to defy him. That's the constitutional threshold for overriding a veto. It will be critical for Republicans to put together veto-proof majorities in the House and Senate. Because any bill would require 60 Senate votes to overcome filibusters, the Senate vote would always be bipartisan and closer to the two-thirds majority needed to override a veto. Defense under-estimates—Keystone key Susan Casey-Lefkowitz, NRDC Switchboard, 1/17/13, New Analysis Shows Simple Math: Keystone XL Pipeline = Tar Sands Expansion = Accelerated Climate Change, thinkprogress.org/tag/keystone-xl/ New research confirms what we have heard time and again from the industry itself: the proposed Keystone XL tar sands pipeline will be a direct cause of an increase in tar sands oil development. More tar sands oil taken out of the ground means more dangerous pollution that hurts our climate and health. And, this new research also shows that tar sands will cause even more climate pollution than we previously thought due to the impacts of the high carbon byproduct petroleum coke. This is especially important in a time where our communities are feeling the damage of climate change in violent storms, wildfires, droughts and floods. Just recently a federal advisory panel—established by Congress in 1990 to analyze climate research—released the draft of its third National Climatic Assessment. The report confirmed there is “unambiguous evidence” that the earth is warming. The Pembina Institute’s analysis, “The climate implications of the proposed Keystone XL pipeline”, shows that pipelines are a key determinant of tar sands expansion, and argues that the increase in greenhouse gas emissions associated with supplying the Keystone XL pipeline with tar sands bitumen represents a significant barrier to Canada meeting its domestic and international climate commitments. Oil Change International’s new report “Petroleum Coke: The Coal Hiding in the Tar Sands” reveals that current analyses of the impacts of tar sands fail to account for a high-carbon byproduct of the refining process: petroleum coke. Because it is considered a refinery byproduct, petcoke emissions are not included in most assessments of the climate impact of tar sands. Thus, the climate impact of oil production is being consistently undercounted. This analysis is making headway in Washington. Energy and Commerce Committee Ranking Member Henry A. Waxman noted: “The new reports show that TransCanada’s Keystone XL pipeline is the key that will unlock the tar sands. If the pipeline is approved, the world will face millions more tons of carbon pollution each year for decades to come. After Hurricane Sandy, devastating drought, unprecedented wildfires, and the warmest year on record in the United States, we know that climate change is happening now, we have to fight it now, and we must say no to this pollution pipeline now.” Tar sands have no viable alternatives to keystone Sarah Laskow , TNR, 2/19/14, Keystone Opponents Have Nothing to Apologize For: Stopping the Pipeline Will Slow Climate Change , www.newrepublic.com/article/116644/blocking-keystone-xl-reallywould-help-slow-climate-change On one side of this debate are leaders of major environmental groups and prominent activists who want President Obama to block the pipeline’s development. Their argument, which you may know by now, goes like this: Without that crucial piece of infrastructure to carry oil from the tar sands to coastal refineries and the supertankers that ferry it across the world, companies won’t have an easy time moving the oil they extract. The industry will have to slow down extraction efforts dramatically—or, better still, give up on them altogether. On the other side are energy policy wonks who wonder whether fighting this one, seemingly obscure project is worthwhile—and whether blocking it would really do much to reduce emissions. For a while, the dissent was pretty quiet. You’d only hear murmurs, usually from people working on the drier side of climate policy—like advocates for improving public transit infrastructure or energy efficiency. But then, in October, Jonathan Chait came right out and said it in New York magazine: “Picking a fight over Keystone XL,” he wrote, “was a bad idea.” Late last month, the State Department finally weighed in on Keystone XL's climate impacts, by issuing a report that more or less sides with the skeptics. According to the report, the tar sands industry has other options for transporting, refining and (eventually) burning the oil it's pulling from the ground. As a result, the report said, blocking the pipeline was “not likely” to affect the amount of oil companies took from the tar sands. Here in the pages of the New Republic, Ted Nordhaus and Michael Shellenberger—who, like Chait, have seen Keystone XL as a distraction for environmentalists—summarized the logic behind the State Department’s conclusion: “If new pipelines aren’t available, rail cars or supertankers can be easily substituted with little technological or economic difficulty.” But is that really so clear? There is a reason that Keystone XL is the oil industry's first choice for transporting tar sands oil. Generally speaking, pipelines are the cheapest, safest way to transport oil. That’s a big reason why the vast majority—more than 94 percent—of oil into U.S. refineries goes that way. Not so long ago, the discussion of Keystone XL alternatives focused on the possibility of alternative pipelines heading east or west through Canada and to the coasts. But those pipeline projects have run into the same kind of political opposition (from the same sorts of groups and people) as Keystone XL has generated. As for trucks or barges, the State Department concluded that they are not a viable alternative to the pipeline. Transporting that much oil would take too many trucks, the State Department report said, and there's not an inland waterway big enough to accommodate such heavy barge traffic. That leaves rail. This is where the ambiguity comes in. It's technologically possible to transport large volumes of oil by rail, and TransCanada, the company that wants to build Keystone XL, has considered the possibility. But it would take extra investment both to add tank cars, spur lines, and oil storage facilities to the existing infrastructure and to comply with safety regulations. Shipping oil by rail already costs more than shipping by pipeline: estimates about the difference range from as low as five dollars extra to closer to $25, or more. And the price of increasing a single terminal's oil-loading capacity comes in at a magnitude of hundreds of millions; the system-wide improvements it will take to replace Keystone XL's carry capacity will cost billions. With rail, the industry also increases its chance of spilling a lot of oil, which means losing some of the supply and dealing with the consequences—legal, financial, and political. And it may not even be much of a chance: as train traffic from the U.S.'s Bakken oil fields has increased, so have spills. (If you're interested in the details of tank car safety regulations, and the implications for the Keystone debate, Elena Schor has a good write-up.) The bottom line? Companies like TransCanada will probably keep developing the tar sands even if they don’t get Keystone XL. But they probably won’t be able to do it as quickly—or successfully. Approving the pipeline, in other words, is likely to ease the flow of oil to Gulf Coast refineries. Whether that makes the Keystone XL fight worthwhile, obviously, is another matter entirely. Tar sands not inevitable David Roberts, Grist, 2/6/13, Debunking Nature’s arguments for Keystone, grist.org/politics/debunkingnatures-arguments-for-keystone/ This is the most familiar argument on behalf of Keystone, though “we can’t prevent this horrible thing so let’s embrace it” is a peculiar form of endorsement. I don’t get it. The world is not a spreadsheet. It contains friction, physical and temporal limitations, politics and competing interests. Nothing is inevitable. If activists can block Keystone, yeah, there are other possible routes to get the tar-sands oil out. So … activists will fight those, too. Tar-sands producers want to ship the stuff west? Well, there’s the small matter of a wall of First Nations opposition (and in Canada, unlike the U.S., indigenous tribes have real political power). They want to ship the tar sands east? Well, there’s a coalition of enviro groups fighting that too, pulling together some impressively large rallies. They want to ship the tar sands by train, to avoid all these pipeline protests? Well, that’s more expensive and more dangerous and there isn’t nearly enough rail capacity right now to handle it. “Without Keystone XL, oil sands face choke point,” says the Globe & Mail. In this collection of quotes [PDF] pulled together by 350.org, oil industry analysts and executives acknowledge that without Keystone, tar-sands oil could be stranded, or at least severely constrained. Evidence bad- its not conclusive Even if Nebraska rules against Keystone, it only delays construction at worst Colman 12/19 Zack, “No Keystone XL decision out of Nebraska” [http://www.washingtonexaminer.com/no-keystone-xldecision-out-of-nebraska/article/2557636] // If the court decides the law is constitutional, the Obama administration will continue an inter-agency review of the pipeline that will be used to determine whether building it is in the national interest. If the court rejects the law, TransCanada would need to get the Nebraska Public Service Commission to green light the route, which could take up to one year. Warming causes a methane burp – means extinction Lynas ‘7 [Mark, writer for The Guardian and author of Six degrees: our future on a hotter planet, “Six steps to hell,” http://books.guardian.co.uk/departments/scienceandnature/story/0,,2063401,00.html, April 23] The Eocene greenhouse event fascinates scientists not just because of its effects, which also saw a major mass extinction in the seas, but also because of its likely cause: methane hydrates. This unlikely substance, a sort of ice-like combination of methane and water that is only stable at low temperatures and high pressure, may have burst into the atmosphere from the seabed in an immense "ocean burp", sparking a surge in global temperatures (methane is even more powerful as a greenhouse gas than carbon dioxide). Today vast amounts of these same methane hydrates still sit on subsea continental shelves. As the oceans warm, they could be released once more in a terrifying echo of that methane belch of 55 million years ago. In the process, moreover, the seafloor could slump as the gas is released, sparking massive tsunamis that would further devastate the coasts. Again, no one knows how likely this apocalyptic scenario is to unfold in today's world. The good news is that it could take centuries for warmer water to penetrate down to the bottom of the oceans and release the stored methane. The bad news is that it could happen much sooner in shallower seas that see a stronger heating effect (and contain lots of methane hydrate) such as in the Arctic. It is also important to realise that the early Eocene greenhouse took at least 10,000 years to come about. Today we could accomplish the same feat in less than a century. If there is one episode in the Earth's history that we should try above all not to repeat, it is surely the catastrophe that befell the planet at the end of the Permian period, 251 million years ago. By the end of this calamity, up to 95% of species were extinct. The end-Permian wipeout is the nearest this planet has ever come to becoming just another lifeless rock drifting through space. The precise cause remains unclear, but what is undeniable is that the end-Permian mass extinction was associated with a supergreenhouse event. Oxygen isotopes in rocks dating from the time suggest that temperatures rose by six degrees, perhaps because of an even bigger methane belch than happened 200 million years later in the Eocene. Sedimentary layers show that most of the world's plant cover was removed in a catastrophic bout of soil erosion. Rocks also show a "fungal spike" as plants and animals rotted in situ. Still more corpses were washed into the oceans, helping to turn them stagnant and anoxic. Deserts invaded central Europe, and may even have reached close to the Arctic Circle. One scientific paper investigating "kill mechanisms" during the end-Permian suggests that methane hydrate explosions "could destroy terrestrial life almost entirely". Acting much like today's fuel-air explosives (or "vacuum bombs"), major oceanic methane eruptions could release energy equivalent to 10,000 times the world's stockpile of nuclear weapons. Whatever happened back then to wipe out 95% of life on Earth must have been pretty serious. And while it would be wrong to imagine that history will ever straightforwardly repeat itself, we should certainly try and learn the lessons of the distant past. If they tell us one thing above all, it is this: that we mess with the climatic thermostat of this planet at our extreme - and growing - peril.