PRISONS: REFORM OR ABOLITION? Roderick T. Long Auburn University | Molinari Institute | Center for a Stateless Society A Brief Visual History Prisons in a Free Society? How would prisons change in a libertarian society? Most obvious difference: nobody imprisoned for noninvasive “crimes” (e.g., use or sale of guns or drugs, etc.) But what else? Moral Limits on Forcible Response The Non-Aggression Principle (NAP) forbids initiatory force against person or property What does it imply for reactive force? One might think: anything goes Torturing someone to death for stealing a paper clip might seem consistent with the NAP Moral Limits on Forcible Response But suppose we think of aggression as a violation of a person’s boundary and of defense as expelling someone from one’s boundary Moral Limits on Forcible Response That would suggest that any use of force against person or property greater than what is needed to end a boundary-violation is itself aggression and so forbidden Call this the First Limit Moral Limits on Forcible Response Is the First Limit entailed by the letter of NAP? Perhaps not But it’s entailed by the spirit of NAP: If force is justified only as a response to aggression, then force beyond what’s needed to end aggression is excessive Moral Limits on Forcible Response Is the First Limit the only restriction on reactive force? Arguably not If the only way I can stop a toddler from stealing a paper clip is to shoot her, this is consistent with the letter but not with the spirit of the First Limit Limits on Forcible Response The point of the First Limit is to rule out disproportionate forcible responses This renders the Second Limit a reasonable extension of the first Moral Limits on Forcible Response First Limit: forcible response to aggression is justified only if it is necessary to end the aggression Second Limit: forcible response to aggression, even when necessary to end the aggression, is justified only if the response is also not disproportionate to the moral seriousness of the aggression Implications for Restorative Justice If I take your property against your will, I remain inside your boundary until I return it If I destroy or damage your property against your will, I likewise remain inside your boundary until I restore it Implications for Restorative Justice Hence forcing aggressors to return stolen property, or to restore damaged or destroyed property, is consistent with the First Limit Implications for Restorative Justice What if the damage caused cannot be “made whole” (as in killing, maiming, etc.)? Given “ought implies can,” one cannot have an obligation to perform an impossible restitution Implications for Restorative Justice Hence the obligation shifts from “make whole” to “make as nearly whole as possible” If it didn’t, the First Limit would arguably prohibit compelling restitution, since X cannot be defended as necessary for Y if Y is impossible Implications for Restorative Justice Also, even restitution to make as nearly whole as possible cannot be compelled beyond the point allowed by the Second Limit (Thus, e.g., no enslavement for debt) Implications for Punishment This analysis presents obstacles to punishment – or at least to forcible punishment (as opposed to non-forcible sanctions like ostracism) – and thus to imprisonment, to the extent that the latter is punishment Theories of Punishment Retributive punishment: Inflicting suffering because the criminal deserves it Theories of Punishment Forbidden because although responsive force may incidentally make an aggressor unhappy, using force beyond what’s needed for defense just in order to make the aggressor unhappy violates the First Limit Theories of Punishment Deterrent punishment: Inflicting suffering to motivate others to refrain from wrongdoing Theories of Punishment Forbidden because force against A to ward off aggression from B, C, and D does not count as defensive; must be against A Theories of Punishment Moreover, force against A to ward off aggression from A is not justified either, if the response is purely preemptive Theories of Punishment Rehabilitative punishment: Inflicting suffering as a way to make the wrongdoer a better person Theories of Punishment Forbidden because, again, force that goes beyond ending the aggression is not legitimately defensive Further Considerations Aggression need not be intentional to license responsive force If a sleepwalker attacks me, I can defend myself If you take my umbrella by mistake, I can still demand it back Further Considerations But of course it wouldn’t be legitimate to punish an unintentional aggressor by inflicting more force than necessary for defense/restitution Yet an intentional aggressor differs from an unintentional one only by the thoughts in her head Further Considerations We have no legitimate jurisdiction over the thoughts in other people’s heads We can’t (forcibly) punish people for bad thoughts Further Considerations So if we can’t punish an unintentional aggressor and intentional aggressors differ from unintentional ones only by thoughts that are beyond the reach of legitimate compulsion then we can’t punish intentional aggressors either Further Considerations Moreover: given human error, any system of punishment will inadvertently punish some innocent people and given human moral weakness, any system of punishment will also be liable to deliberate abuse of power Further Considerations So even on pragmatic grounds, we should be very cautious about endorsing systems of punishment What About Restraint? What if a person represents an ongoing threat of aggression? Is incarceration justified as defense against that person’s aggression? What About Restraint? Not if it’s purely preemptive; force must be responsive, not anticipatory But if the person has already aggressed and seems likely to continue to do so, can he or she be treated as engaging in ongoing aggression and so be restrained? What About Restraint? YES What About Restraint? YES BUT What About Restraint? YES BUT the restraint approach is fairly limited in what it can justify Terminological Reminder First Limit: forcible response to aggression is justified only if it is necessary to end the aggression Second Limit: forcible response to aggression, even when necessary to end the aggression, is justified only if the response is also not disproportionate to the moral seriousness of the aggression Limits of Restraint If a crime is unlikely to be repeated (say, a revenge killing), then even if it is illegitimate there will be no grounds for restraining the offender (though forcible restitution may be appropriate) Limits of Restraint After all, as per the First Limit, responsive force is permissible only when it is necessary in order to end aggression If there’s little likelihood of a repeat offense, the aggression is already ended Limits of Restraint Even when a crime is likely to be repeated, many crimes (such as property crimes) will be mild enough that locking the offender in a cage would be morally disproportionate and so would run afoul of the Second Limit Limits of Restraint A person who poses an ongoing threat of sufficiently serious aggression (e.g. murder or assault) may in principle be incarcerated consistently with the First and Second Limits Limits of Restraint But can such persons be incarcerated in prisons as we now know them? If prisons are places where prisoners are likely to kill or assault each other, then placing them there does not prevent their ongoing aggression and so cannot be justified as necessary to prevent it (First Limit) Limits of Restraint Likewise, if prisons are places where prisoners are likely to be assaulted or mistreated by guards (given human incentives to abuse power), imprisonment is again forbidden, since such further abuse violates the First Limit Limits of Restraint Note that making prisons private rather than public would not by itself do anything to address these libertarian concerns about imprisonment Limits of Restraint A sufficiently reformed prison system – one with deep changes in incentive structure (such as Bob Murphy’s proposal that inmates should be allowed to choose among competing systems) – could be justified for severely dangerous inmates Limits of Restraint BUT Limits of Restraint BUT even then, incarceration will be justified only when there are no less invasive ways of securing protection against serious aggressors And keep in mind that the elasticity of demand for aggression varies among aggressors Limits of Restraint For some serious aggressors (though doubtless not all), their demand for further aggression would be significantly reduced by systems helping them reintegrate into the community Limits of Restraint The Prison Abolition Movement works to explore and build such systems Since that movement is dominated by anti-market anarchists, pro-market anarchists are less familiar with it than they should be Limits of Restraint The availability of (private, non-violent) rehabilitation systems will in many cases be a defeater (thanks to the First and Second Limits) to imprisoning serious aggressors Limits of Restraint As for deterrence: recall that revenge killings, if unlikely to be repeated, call only for restitution, not incarceration Hence serious aggressors will have reason to worry about revenge by victims or their families Limits of Restraint To quote the Marquis de Sade’s suggested legal pronouncement to murderers: “I pardon you – but I also pardon whoever will kill you.” The Question Suppose there were a button that, if pushed, would release all prisoners everywhere from their prisons. And if it’s not pushed, all prisoners remain where they are. (There’s no intermediate button that releases most prisoners but sends the worst to a supernice facility.) The Question Should we push it? The Question Yes: because freeing that many unjustly imprisoned people is worth the risk THE END