A Defense of Traditional Marriage by Tim Hsiao The Argument Marriage is an institution grounded in human nature that is primarily centered around responsible procreation and child-rearing. It is for this reason that the state confers legal and economic benefits upon married couples, for it recognizes that both procreation and childrearing are difficult tasks that require considerable amounts of time and labor. Since responsible procreation and child-rearing are essential to the advancement of society, the state has a vested interest in protecting a stable relationship under which this can take place. The state therefore ought to give special recognition to heterosexual unions, for they function as a precondition to society. Indeed, had there only been one gender, it seems unlikely that the institution of marriage would have ever arisen to begin with. Relationships which do not have procreation as their core do not deserve such recognition, for they are not foundational to society. The recognition of homosexual unions as marriages would therefore be unjustly denying the special social value of heterosexual unions. Moreover, since a healthy marriage culture is necessary for the flourishing of a just society, the legal recognition of the natural institution of marriage is a proper function of government. This counts against the libertarian idea that marriage should be privatized. Perhaps the most common argument against the traditional understanding of marriage is that it would violate the rights of homosexual couples via some legal or moral principle, such as the 14th Amendment, due to the fact that it discriminates against such relationships. This is mistaken. Mere discrimination is morally neutral – it is not immoral for a prospective employer to discriminate against a lazy job candidate on the basis that he lacks the skills that are required of him. Discrimination is only unjust when someone is denied something they have a right to on the basis of criteria that are irrelevant to what is being denied. And in order to know what is irrelevant, we must first know what is relevant. The same is true of rights. We must first know what we are talking about before we can determine who has a right to it. The main issue in the same-sex marriage debate is thus over the nature of marriage. Rights derive their very content from the thing that they are grounded in, such that it is necessary to first determine what the latter is before we talk about the former. It is question-begging to argue for a revisionist conception of marriage on the basis that it recognizes the right of same-sex couples to marry, for this presupposes that they have such a right to begin with. This, however, is precisely what opponents of same-sex marriage deny. So before we can claim that the traditional conception of marriage would discriminate against homosexual couples, we must first settle the issue of what marriage is. If the nature of marriage excludes same-sex couples to begin with, then no discrimination would be taking place, for they are not being unjustly denied something they deserve because they do not deserve it to begin with. It’s up to advocates of same-sex marriage to argue for their account of marriage instead of just assuming it. What About Sterile and Interracial Couples? It may be objected that the traditional conception of marriage prevents sterile heterosexual couples from marrying due to the fact that they are unable to procreate. But this objection fails to understand the argument. The traditional conception of marriage is based on human nature as being a type of relationship under which procreation is intrinsically possible, and this remains true even if the possibility is never realized due to some defect.. A heterosexual union is always oriented toward procreation, even if it doesn’t happen due to some defect. Indeed, we refer to such couples as sterile precisely because they lack the ability to realize a capacity that is grounded in the nature of their relationship. We recognize that there exists a privation of what should be there. By contrast, homosexual relationships are such that procreation is impossible in principle. Their inability to procreate is not merely accidental to the type of their relationship, but essential. Thus, this objection confuses acts that are reproductive in type with acts that are reproductive in effect. Neither will comparing same-sex marriage to interracial marriage work, for the analogy falsely assumes that there is no relevant difference between race and gender. While race is irrelevant to procreative ability, gender certainly isn’t. A heterosexual interracial marriage is still a procreative type union and thus falls under the traditional conception of marriage. This is precisely why bans on interracial marriage were unjust. Gender, however, is a different story. A homosexual union is intrinsically incapable of procreation and thus would be excluded from counting as a marriage. Therefore, the state has a principled reason to exclude couples from entering into marital relationships on the basis of their gender, but not race. Love Is Not All You Need It’s sometimes said that same-sex couples should be allowed to marry because marriage is about love. But this is all too vague. The million-dollar question that needs to be asked is “What is love?” Unless one defines what love is, there is a risk of begging the question. By love do we mean merely an intense emotional feeling, or do we mean the state of satisfaction that flows from living properly? While the latter is how love was traditionally viewed, its grounding in human nature excludes same-sex marriage and thus cannot be an option for its proponents. Hence one will have to opt with something like the former. But viewing love as an intense emotional feeling is too broad, for the state would have no reason to exclude any types of relationships as long as those involved “love” each other in this regard. Friendships, business partnerships, incest, polygamy, self-marriage, group marriage, and virtually any sort of arrangement (One can be creative!) would not be excluded under this view. But obviously this is mistaken. Indeed, if one’s view logically implies the conclusion that the state is obligated to legally recognize incest and polygamy, then that implication alone is a sufficient reason to reject it. Such a conception of marriage renders inexplicable why the institution exists in the first place and why the state is so interested in it.