Back to Realism Applied to Home Page Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 History_Rat79.doc A HISTORY OF RAT PREFERENCE FOR SIGNALLED SHOCK: FROM PARADOX TO PARADIGM GERLAD B. BIEDERMAN and JOHN J. FUREDY University of Toronto The evidential and logical status of preference-for-signal in the inescapable unmodifiable shock context in rats was examined over a period that has seen the notion of a preference for signalled shock develop from an apparent paradox in the existing conceptual framework of the 1950s to a readily acceptable, established paradigm in the 1970s. The transformation of the phenomenon from paradox to paradigm was found to be unwarranted from an assessment of the merits of symmetrical and asymmetrical preference procedures upon which it was based. The belief that there is a preference in humans and animal subjects for signalled over unsignalled inescapable and physically unmodifiable noxious events, articulates so well with most currently important theories of behaviour (e.g., Berlyne, i960; Perkins, 1968; Seligman, 1975), that it might appear foolish to question the methodological and empirical basis for this belief. In humans the preference for signalling has recently been questioned in a review of studies involving more than 570 subjects (Furedy, 1975), but it can be argued that the issue is more critically resolved with animal subjects, for whom the noxious event can ethically be made genuinely aversive. In this paper we direct our attention to a body of literature with rats as subjects and shock as the noxious, genuinely aversive event, where it is clear that the general acceptance of preference-for-signalling notion is extremely The research by the authors was supported by grants from the National Research Council of Canada, Canada Council, The Atkinson Charitable Foundation, Medical Research Council of Canada, and the Health Sciences Committee of the University of Toronto. We are grateful to Professor W. O’Neill, Université de Moncton, Moncton, New Brunswick, Canada, whose research on the avoidance conditioning literature influenced some of the historical analyses in this paper, and to J. M. Arabian for comments on an earlier draft. Requests for reprints should be sent to G. B. Biederman, Scarborough College, University of Toronto, West Hill, Ontario MIC IA4, Canada. widespread. Reviewers such as Seligman (1975) while qualifying conclusions about a preference-forsignalled shock (PSS) phenomenon in humans by citing Averill and Rosenn (1972) and Furedy and Doob (1971, 1972) “for contrary results”, make no hint of the necessity of any such qualification in rats (Seligman, 1975,p. 199). D’Amato (1974) in another review of the literature speaks of “a large number of studies... which clearly show that animals ... very generally prefer signaled to unsignaled reinforcement”, and that the “experiments, particularly those dealing with aversive stimulation, seem to offer striking support for the information hypothesis” (p. 93). Experimenters also accept the existence of PSS as the natural starting point for research. For example, Cantor and LoLordo (1972) state that “When an organism is permitted to choose between a Pavlovian reinforcer preceded by a warning signal and the same rein-forcer unsignaled, he chooses the signaled reinforcer... with electric shock as the reinforcer” (p. 259). MacDonald and Baron (1973) claim that “the present results, together with previous findings that animals choose signaled shock in preference to unsignaled shock support the hypothesis that signaling shock reduces its aversiveness” (p. 37). In yet another experimental report Arabian and Desiderato (1975) state that 102 ”Data from both human [and] animal ... subjects have shown that, given the choice, organisms will act to produce stimuli that signal the imminence of a painful event” (p. 191). Finally, Miller, Daniel, and Berk (1974) reaffirm that “rats ... are commonly believed to prefer signaled shock to unsignaled shock even when the shock is not modifiable” (p. 271). Nevertheless, we shall suggest here that the rat-PSS phenomenon is, in fact, a notion for which the evidential support is equivocal. We shall trace the history of PSS in rats as it has been transformed from a paradox — from the standpoint of a 1947 paper by Mowrer — carefully investigated and cautiously interpreted, into a paradigm, taken for granted, and apparently needing no usual rigorous validating checks, but only demonstrations. In what follows we shall outline the evidential development of experiments after 1959 which have had a bearing on rat-PSS. We are aware that any interpretation of historical development in science may be subject to reinterpretation; however, we wish to emphasize that the methodological analysis which forms a part of the historical account is not subject to interpretational ambiguity as a function of historical perspective. This review will consider only literature which used signal-contingent behaviour as the dependent variable. Such other dependent variables as conditioned emotional response (CER) (e.g., MacDonald & Baron, 1973) and ulceration (e.g., Weiss, 1970) have been cited as relevant for PSS. However, even if one assumes that these indices are valid measures of “aversiveness” (MacDonald & Baron, 1973), it is still the case that the concepts of aversiveness and preference, though related, are different (cf. Furedy & Doob, 1971). Thus, the present analysis will be limited to studies which purport to be direct measures of preference for signalled shock.1 All measures of preference for signal must use signalcontingent behaviour but, as we hope to show by analysis of a specific example, all signalcontingent behaviour-based measures are not valid measures of preference. In particular, we will propose that the only valid studies of PSS are those which employ equivalent or “symmetrical” behaviours to index both PSS and preference for unsignalled shock (PUS). THE CAUTIOUS, INVESTIGATORY ‘FIFTIES Knapp, Kause, and Perkins (1959) employed a symmetrical choice paradigm to look specifically at preference in the T-maze. These workers were quite open to both the negative (conditioned-fear) and positive (informational), or, in their terms, “preparatory-response” aspects of the signal. Their awareness of the negative aspects of signalling is illustrated by their conclusion that the “results of Exp. I could be interpreted as supporting the hypothesis that S will make a response followed by shock if this response also eliminates a danger signal (a stimulus that has regularly been followed by shock) and the accompanying anxiety” (Knapp et al., 1959, p. 361). On the other hand, they note the positive aspects of signalling when they say that the “results of Exp. II are not in line with such an interpretation, as in this experiment & acquired the response which was followed by a danger signal (lights and buzzer) rather than one which was not” (p. 361). 1 It may well happen that the ulceration and CER data form the corpus of the only clear evidence for the beneficial effects of signalling (e.g., Desiderato & Newman, 1971; Hymowitz, 1976; Macdonald & Baron, 1973; Seligman, 1975; Weiss, 1970, 1971a, 1971b). PSS as discussed in this paper is, as will be apparent, so controversial, complex and perhaps inconsistent, that to attempt to fully describe and analyse CER and ulceration evidence in addition, is to wander too far from our path and to attempt too long a trip. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 103 Kamin (1956, 1957a, 1957b) which elegantly investigated the prediction that WS termination, despite the absence of US termination, should lead to the learning of an avoidance response (i.e., an escape-from-WSresponse). Kamin (1956) found that either WS escape or US avoidance could equally well serve as the reinforcing event for shuttling behaviour. Other studies have also supported the analysis of the importance of WStermination in the acquisition of avoidance learning (Brush, Brush, & Solomon, 1955; Church & Solomon, 1956; Verhave, 1959). Other workers who have not accepted Mowrer’s fear-conditioning analysis have nevertheless used WS as a conditioned aversive reinforcer whose contingent termination may increase some responses. Dinsmoor (1954), Schoenfeld (1950), and Sidman (1953) did not accept the notion of an underlying fear-state, but still treated WS termination as a reinforcing event. By 1959, therefore, most psychologists, if asked, would probably have not predicted PSS. Indeed, on the basis of the conditioned fear properties attaching to the WS, or on the basis of the signal possibly causing one to “tense up” (in layman terms), both the psychologists of the ‘fifties and the man in the street would have had a reasonable framework for predicting a preference for unsignalled shock (PUS). The signal in the inescapable shock context was therefore seen as having predominantly aversive consequences. THE ENTHUSIASTIC DEMONSTRATIONAL SIXTIES One paper which seems to have had a significant role in converting caution regarding PSS, as found in Knapp et al. (1959), to enthusiasm is the often-cited report by Lockard (1963). However, the report itself was neutral with respect to predictions of PSS; the purpose was to “test whether a warning signal followed by unavoidable shock becomes aversive” (Lockard, 1963, p. 526). The preference for the signalled side in this shuttle-box symmetrical-choice experiment was clear, reaching 90% in an orderly, negatively accelerated acquisition function over 12 days (Lockard, 1963, Figs 1 and 2), so that it is perhaps not surprising that reviewers became enthusiastic over the informational, rewarding properties of signals, and started to regard PSS as a phenomenon to be demonstrated, rather than one whose existence, because of the possibility of signals becoming “aversive” (Lockard, 1963, p. 526), was still an open question. The demonstrational approach was probably strengthened by the report of a check for the scrambling factor where unauthorized avoidances were monitored and found to be both of low frequency of occurrence and uncorrelated with PSS (Lockard, 1963, p. 529). This way of checking on the scrambling factor seems, in general, less effective in comparison to the methods of Badia (Note 1), and later, of Biederman and Furedy (1973), who all manipulated scrambling and found that PSS emerged only with unscrambled shocks. Moreover, the Lockard method measured unauthorized modifications on a two-point scale (present or absent); later studies by Biederman and Furedy (1973) and Furedy and Biederman (1976) confirmed Lockard’s low complete-modificationpercentage finding, but found that when partial modification was measured by recording amount of shock received on each unscrambled shock trial, there was a significant relationship between amount of unauthorized modification and amount of PSS in the unscrambled-shock conditions. Logically, of course, this scrambling confound is not affected by the strength and clarity of the PSS with unscrambled shock reported by Lockard. However, there is a less cited paper by the same author (Lockard, 1965) which repre- Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 104 sented a more extensive set of groups than those in the earlier paper. The main finding of the Lockard (1965) experiment is a weaker PSS effect.2 In addition to Lockard’s (1963) paper the other main evidential basis of the ‘sixties is the paper by Perkins et al. (1966). In discussing their five reported experiments designed to investigate various factors behind the PSS, Perkins et al. indicate their confidence in the generality of PSS when they note that there “does not appear to be a single report of results indicating that unexpected shock is less aversive than shock preceded by a signal” (Perkins et al., 1966, p. 195), and cite, the several previous studies which have found PSS, (e.g., Perkins, Levis, & Seymann, 1963). This ready acceptance of PSS is based on studies that all used unscrambled shock, and- it will be recalled that the importance of this factor had been empirically demonstrated by Badia’s (Note 1) early study (Note 2). The Perkins et al. (1966) study is noteworthy also because it is often cited as having overcome the modification problem by using fixed electrodes in its last (fifth) experiment presumably to overcome the “postural” strategies mentioned by the more cautious Knapp et al. (1959) paper, and the more specific grid-shock-delivery problem arising out of the failure to scramble the grids. However, as Perkins et al. (1966, p. 194) themselves indicate, so large a proportion of subjects seemed to be able to detach the electrodes during the course of the experiment that the adjective “fixed” cannot be justified in this procedure. Nevertheless, this era in history of animal PSS may be clearly charac2 It is interesting to note that a preference for unsignalled shock (about 76%) emerges in Lockard’s (1965, Fig. 1) paper, but signalled shock was correlated with higher intensity shock (about 7%) making the PUS finding not unequivocal. terized as being “enthusiastic” in its general acceptance of the phenomenon. As late as 1972, there is an empirical report (humansubject), stating that a “number of studies show that... rats (e.g., Perkins et al., 1966) ... consistently selected signaled over unsignaled shock in a choice situation” (Suboski, Brace, Jarrold, Teller, & Dieter, 1972, p. 407). However, at least for such symmetrical choice situations (generally based on the shuttle-box apparatus), evidence of various forms began to create considerable difficulties for the PSS paradigm after 1966, as detailed in the next section. EVIDENTIAL PROBLEMS FOR THE PSS PARADIGM IN SYMMETRICAL CHOICE DESIGNS The period of 1966 to the present can be characterized as one which offers no unequivocal support for strong animal PSS based on statistically evaluatable criteria in an unmodifiable-shock context. Moreover, there are a number of published and publicallyreported instances where either no PSS or a reliable PUS has been found. In other words, the data-base is most consistent with Badia’s (Note 1) early findings reported in a period where animal PSS was more of a paradox than a paradigm. This characterization of the post-1966 evidence will now be documented briefly. The first class of evidence is that of journalpublished null findings, as represented by the groups run with scrambled shock in the experiments of Biederman and Furedy (1973) and Furedy and Biederman (1976). The second class of evidence is that of unpublished or non-journal-published null outcomes. For obvious reasons the extent of this class is impossible to state with precision, but there is at least one series of thorough and carefully conducted experiments reported by Cotsonas (Note 3) in which external shock (scrambled) as well as (negatively reinforcing) brain stimulation was used, Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 105 and where no preference emerged. A conference paper by Douglass (Note 4) also reports failure to find PSS in shuttle-box situations, and perhaps most importantly, following the Perkins et al. (1966) “factorsbehind-the-PSS” paper, the published literature is substantially silent with respect to positive and statistically assessable instances of PSS with unmodifiable shock.3 Indeed, Arabian and Desiderato (1975) reported what has, to date, been the most convincing evidence for PUS, or for the aversive properties of the signal. The relevant group in this study chose (in a shuttle-box) between a situation where each (scrambled) shock was preceded by a 5-sec tone (i.e., signalled state) and one where the tone was uncorrelated (i.e., unsignalled state). This group developed over a 90% preference for the latter condition (Arabian & Desiderato, 1975). However, the results from this procedure, taken as a whole, do not support an overall PUS interpretation for at least two reasons. First, the group choosing not to have the 5-sec tone signal was still in a signalled state with respect to 10-min light signal that indicated whether or not (but not precisely when) shocks would occur, and with respect to this latter “nontemporal” (Furedy & Biederman, 1976) signal another group showed a clear PSS when given the choice between having the nontemporal light signal and not having it. Secondly, Collier (1977) employing the same preparation though with slightly different parameters (e.g., 10-rather than 5-sec tone temporal signals) obtained PSS outcomes even for the group given the choice between the having and not having the tone signal the precise time of shock onset. So the Arabian-Desiderato (1975) PUS outcome appears to be restricted to a rather 3 As recently as 1972, a published report uncritically using unscrambled shock and finding moderate PSS could still be found (French, Palestino, & Leeb). narrow set of conditions, but this, of course, is not to deny that the aversive properties of the signal can be important in determining whether there is PSS, PUS, or no preference. There has, on the other hand, been one equally strong apparent PSS effect reported by Miller et al. (1974) with shocks delivered through tail electrodes in order to rule out modifiability factors. According to these investigators the secret of their successful “demonstration” (p. 273) of PSS was the great number of training days given to their subjects, in contrast to the relatively short training sessions employed by such investigators as Biederman and Furedy (1973). However, Miller et al. (1974) obtained their effect in only three animals inasmuch as four others were eliminated for removing the shock electrodes (Miller et al., 1974, p. 274, n.l). It is therefore difficult to evaluate the statistical reliability of the result. Moreover, in a related investigation of the amount-of-training factor with an adequate (n= 14) sample of subjects, Biederman and Furedy (1976a) trained rats for 50 days in the shuttle-box with scrambled shock, and failed to obtain any significant preference.4 Taken together, then, the results 4 Miller and associates have very recently published a series of experiments wherein control of PSS appears to have been gained in a symmetrical design (Miller, Marlin, & Berk, 1977) in addition to having replicated Biederman and Furedy*s (1976a) parameters, and findings of no preference. The Miller et al. (1977) evidence would seem to indicate that experimental parameters strongly affect PSS or PUS outcomes. While this new evidence is not consistent with the view that PSS is a robust, readily obtainable phenomenon (they report considerable intragroup variation), their study may clearly become a major weight in the scale balancing between PSS and PUS. The attempt to balance PSS findings against PUS or no-preference outcomes is, of course, hampered by the uncertain number of no-preference or “negative** (i.e., PUS) results which may remain unpublished because of the general status of anti-paradigmatic results or results which are merely neutral with respect to a prevailing paradigm. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 106 from those post-1966 studies of symmetrical choice which did not permit unauthorized modification through use of unscrambled grids provided little if any evidential support for the notion of PSS. During the same period, two studies were reported (Biederman & Furedy, 1973; Furedy & Biederman, 1976) which directly examined the role of scrambling in symmetrical choice experiments, and which showed both in terms of preference behaviour itself, and in terms of continuously measured amount of unauthorized (unscrambled) shock modification, that: (a) PSS emerged only when the shock was unscrambled, and (b) there was a clear-cut connection between modification and the PSS, although both effects were weak, i.e., only partial modification and PSS of the order of only 70%. The relative weakness of these modification effects is important both because it is consistent with Lockard’s (1963) failure to find modification when it was measured only on an all-or-none basis (cf. Furedy & Biederman, 1976, Exp. HI), and because it explains why previous investigators (with the exception of Badia, Note 1) did not immediately remedy this confound. Nevertheless, as shown in the BiedermanFuredy studies, the scrambling confound appears completely to account for the PSS effect that can be obtained in the symmetrical-choice (usually shuttle-box apparatus) situation. Accordingly, these studies of the effect of scrambling the grid provided additional evidential problems for the PSS paradigm in symmetrical choice designs. From the paradigmatic view of PSS, however, the greatest empirical shortcoming of the symmetrical choice designs was that they simply did not “work” very well as tools to demonstrate PSS or the signal control of behaviour. Some form of the symmetrical choice design (e.g., the shuttle-box) is logically ideal as a procedure to investigate the relative strengths of the ”positive1” (i.e., informational) and “negative” (i.e., conditioned-fear) properties of signalling. However, if one is concerned to demonstrate the PSS phenomenon, clearly these procedures are inadequate, since, as we have seen, even when unauthorized modification is permitted, the preference levels reached are typically of the order of 70%; moreover, the effect cannot be produced in every individual subject but is found only at the level of large sample averages. Even Lockard’s (1963) more widely cited study (in contrast to her less strong 1965 results) indicated that PSS assessed in this way showed great “individual differences” which is one feature of behaviour that is intolerable for the demonstrational-paradigmatic approach. The PSS, having attained full paradigmatic status for most experimenters, and lacking a truly powerful demonstrational method, was dramatically bolstered by the asymmetricalchangeover procedure of Badia and his coworkers, a procedure which, despite its methodological shortcomings (to be discussed below), but because of its (seeming) usefulness as a demonstrational tool, has apparently displaced symmetrical-choice preparations as the preferred measure of preference. THE ASYMMETRICAL-CHANGEOVER PROCEDURE OF THE SEVENTIES: A METHODOLOGICAL ANALYSIS The method we will call asymmetrical changeover procedure (ACP) as introduced by Badia and co-workers (Badia, Coker, & Harsh, 1973; Badia & Culbertson, 1972; Badia, Culbertson, & Harsh, 1973) can be said to have provided the new evidential basis for current belief in animal PSS. Thus both D’Amato (1974) and Seligman (1975) rely heavily on this work to support the generality and power of animal PSS, and the earlier Lockard (1963) and Perkins et al. (1966) papers are not mentioned. The reason for this Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 107 preference for ACP on the part of reviewers accepting the PSS paradigm is not hard to find. As D’Amato states, in reference to one of the later ACP papers (Badia, Culbertson, & Harsh, 1973), “the magnitude of the difference in aversiveness of the two types of shock is indicated by the fact that in one study rats chose signaled shock ... 2 to 3 times more intense than unsignaled shock” (D’Amato, 1974, p. 93). The degree of “behavioural control” manifested by the ACP seems indeed impressive, especially when one recalls that Lockard (1963), who seemed to be able to get a 90% PSS (albeit with unscrambled shocks), obtained a PUS when the signalled shock was as little as 7% stronger than the unsignalled shock (Lockard, 1965); (see our footnote 1). Not only because of its apparent power, but because of its relative complexity, the ACP is worth diagramming in order to make clear the procedures involved. In Fig. 1 we have chosen to illustrate the first inescapable shock experiment in the ACP series, i.e., Experiment II of Badia and Culbertson (1972). As the bottom channel of Fig. 1 shows, shocks were delivered on a variable-interval response independent schedule. The second channel shows the operant (CO), which is the “changeover” (bar-press) response, and, contingent on this response (contingencies indicated by arrows) is a “correlated stimulus” (top channel) which, in that study, was a 3-min change in illumination (light on for some animals, and off for others). The arrangement is that if the changeover response occurs (except for the 3-min period following the last CO response), it is followed immediately by the onset of the correlated stimulus (as is illustrated in Fig. 1 by the first and fourth responses). The effect of the correlated stimulus is that while it is on, all shocks are signalled, as shown in the “warning signal” channel. Thus, in the examples shown in Fig. 1, while the correlated stimulus is on, following the first changeover response, the first two responseindependent shocks which appear are signalled (with a tone as the signal), but the next two shocks are not signalled because the correlated stimulus has terminated. Of course, the absence of the correlated stimulus is ended by the occurrence of the next changeover response (#5 in Fig. 1) which, in turn, insures that the next response-independent shock is once again signalled. The “2-sec delay” FIG. 1. Badia and Culbertson (1972, Exp. II) arrangements. For explanation see text. Note that following onset of unsignalled shocks a 2-sec delay was in effect during which responses were ineffective in producing the correlated stimulus and the warning signal. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 108 refers to the arrangement where following shock offset bar presses do not produce correlated stimulus. This 2-sec delay is intended to obviate the learning of spurious bar press-shock termination contingencies. At an intuitive level, this arrangement looks relatively complicated compared with the symmetrical choice shuttle-box (e.g., Lockard, 1963) procedures. However, given the strong “signal control” over behaviour that has impressed some reviewers, it appears that there is an implicit attitude that the intuitive complexities associated with ACP should not be allowed to prevent its use as a dominant index of rat PSS.5 We, however, do not agree with this attitude, and have raised methodological questions concerning ACP in preliminary (Biederman & Furedy, 1973, p. 385) and conference (Furedy & Biederman, Note 5) formats. More recently, in a technicalapparatus (instrumentation) and experimentaldesign critique of the ACP, we have detailed six problems with the 5 We have elsewhere reported evidence to indicate that the preparation does not meet scientific standards of replicability (Biederman & Furedy, 1976b; 1977). However, since this issue is experimentally soluble, we shall not pursue it here, but shall, for the purpose of this paper, assume that, contrary to our findings, operational duplications of the ACP procedure would produce behavioural replications of the changeover phenomenon reported by Badia and Culbertson (1972). The present problem has to do with difficulties in interpreting such changeover phenomena (assuming them to be replicable), difficulties which as indicated below arise from methodological problems inherent in the procedure. On the other hand, the replicability problem is of relevance for evaluating the relative empirical gravity of the seven logical or methodological problems presented in the text. A precise evaluation is possible only with a replicable procedure where one can obtain the basic (logically confounded) phenomenon and then evaluate the empirical importance of each of the confounds by removing each to see if that removal affects the outcome. With an unreliable procedure like the ACP such an empirical or experimental evaluation of the empirical importance of the confounds is not possible. procedure (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c). Accordingly, in what follows we shall, in the interests of space, refer to this 1976 article in all cases where our arguments are the same. Our purpose here is to present a final version of the methodological case against the ACP procedure. In addition, we shall comment briefly both on more recent empirical ACP papers (e.g., Badia, Harsh, Coker, & Abbott, 1976) as well as on some methodological arguments which have been offered (Badia & Harsh, 1977a, 1977b) in support of the ACP procedure as a measure of preference. The methodological case against ACP as a measure of preference is that there now seem to be at least seven conceptual difficulties associated with this procedure which invalidate it as an index of PSS, or, for that matter, as an index of preference between any two stimulus classes (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, p. 502). The earlier symmetricalchoice methods are free from all of these difficulties, simply because an arrangement like the shuttle-box (e.g., Lockard, 1963), whatever other problems it may have, at least provides the organism with a symmetrical choice between the two states (signalled and unsignalled) in a way that the ACP does not. The first and most fundamental of ACP’s problems is that of choice response asymmetry. To summarize what we have detailed elsewhere (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c), the problem is that radically different responses (bar-press and withholding-of-barpress) lead to the two states (signalled and unsignalled, respectively) for which unbiased preference is intended to be measured (see also Fig. 1). An empirical outcome which conveniently illustrates this problem is one where, in the arrangements depicted in Fig. 1, most subjects show near zero percent changeover. If the ACP were a valid index of preference, such a result Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 109 would be interpretable as very strong preference for unsignalled shock (PUS). However, as we noted in connection with data which did yield such low changeover results, the “more appropriate interpretation of these data is, of course, that the CO response simply had a low operant rate and that asymmetrical changeover is not a valid measure of choice” (Biederman & Furedy, 1976b, p. 422). A second and related problem in ACP arises from an asymmetry of responsestimulus contingencies between the behaviour (bar press) producing the signalled state and the behaviours (summarized by the term “nobar-press”, but consisting of an indefinite number of heterogeneous behaviours such as scratching, grooming, freezing, etc.) producing the unsignalled state. Although we have described a brief version of this problem previously (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, p. 508), that account requires clarification in some respects. Specifically, the problem is that the behaviour taken to index signalled preference (in Fig. 1 see changeover responses #1 and #5) is sometimes immediately followed by a clear consequence — the change from unsignalled to signalled state — so that in this case there is a relatively clear contingency between a homogeneous response (bar-press) and a consequent stimulus (see correlated stimulus channel in Fig. 1). On the other hand, the no-bar-pressfor-three-minutes behaviours taken to index unsignalled preference do not have a parallel contingency between a single type of response and an immediately consequent stimulus. Thus, in Fig. 1, the behaviour occurring at the end of the no-bar-press-forthree-minutes criterion that caused the first change back to the unsignalled state (correlated stimulus off) could be quite different from that which immediately preceded the second change back to the unsignalled state. A response-stimulus contingency can be specified in Fig. 1 for the purported index of signalled preference (see top two channels, changeover responses #1 and #5) but no similar specification can possibly be made for any index of unsignalled preference in ACP. The third problem, termed indicatorstimulus ambiguity, again arises from the asymmetrical nature of ACP, but our previous account (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, pp. 508-510) of both the logical nature of and empirical evidence for this confound is sufficiently detailed as to require only a very brief summary here. The nature of the confound can be gleaned from the correlated stimulus channel in Fig. 1. This 3-min consequence of the changeover response (second channel in Fig. 1) is intended by the experimenter to serve as an indictor that shocks will be signalled by the “warning signal” (third channel in Fig. 1). However, the correlated stimulus may produce bar pressing simply because of its properties qua stimulus, i.e., the stimulus change itself may be reinforcing. Empirical evidence for the confound is available by analysis of the results themselves of the Badia and Culbertson (1972, cf. their Fig. 3, p. 469, and Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, pp. 508-509), as well as a study by Biederman and Furedy (1973; cf. Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, pp. 509-510). The evidence from the former source is particularly worth noting because in all subsequent studies, except for one by Lewis and Gardner (1977), Badia and his associates have omitted the control groups (correlated stimulus alone with no signal consequent upon lever press, which produced a higher level of changeover performance; no correlated stimulus but signals still consequent upon lever press, which produced little or no changeover performance, cf. Badia and Culbertson, 1972, Fig. 3) that make it possible to obtain this type of evidence. However, of course, the methodological problem Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 110 that is due to indicator-stimulus ambiguity exists independently of the amount of illustrative empirical evidence that may be available. The fourth and fifth problems, labelled respectively dependent-variable measure and asymmetry of interpretation have been sufficiently described (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, pp. 510-511). The former refers to the fact that the dependent variable — percent time spent on signalled side — is confounded by the operant rate of bar pressing in a way that is not the case in any symmetrical-choice preparations (e.g., Lockard, 1963). The latter states the difficulty that the ACP design, unlike a symmetrical-choice preparation (SCP) is less unequivocal when un-signalled or no preference occurs than when signalled preference occurs. The sixth problem with ACP as a measure of preference arises from the very long-term changeover or “preference” training that animals are subjected to, and may be termed for reasons to be given, the filet mignon to hamburger or satiation confound. Specifically, unlike the symmetrical-choice designs where, in periods of no preference the animal is exposed to an equal extent to the signalled and unsignalled states, the ACP is so designed that at low rates of changeover or “preference”, the animal is exposed for a longer time to the unsignalled than the signalled state. One relevant analogy is a test of preference in humans between (wellprepared) filet mignon and cheap, ill-prepared hamburger, designed as follows: the filet is provided at regular response-independent intervals (i.e., analogous to no-signal), whereas the hamburger (analogous to signal) is contingent on some operant. After 50 days of filet mignon, the operant response producing (“changing over for”) hamburger might well appear, because of selective satiation with steak. It is even possible that humans might “prefer” a ham- burger diet for the next few days at levels close to 90%. To conclude on such grounds that hamburger was preferred to filet mignon would be clearly unwarranted, and would be acceptable only to hamburger enthusiasts who wanted to demonstrate the preference-forhamburger phenomenon, rather than investigate whether steak or hamburger was preferred. A valid investigation of that meaty problem, of course, would require a symmetrical-choice preparation rather than some analogue of the animal ACP. The seventh and last problem with ACP relates to the later and more spectacular reports (Badia, Coker, & Harsh, 1973; Badia, Culbertson, & Harsh, 1973) in which the ACP apparently showed that rats prefer much stronger, denser, and longer shocks if these were signalled. The methodological problem with these ACP studies is one of response fixation, and we have previously both described and cited evidence for the existence of this difficulty with the ACP design (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, pp. 511-512). In that paper we also suggested that although the various problems are linked to the asymmetricality of the procedure, they are also independent in the sense that all seven must be rejected for the ACP to be shown to be a valid index of preference. The present seven problems that we raise probably vary somewhat in their perceived gravity but we think that rejection of all assertions is unlikely even for those for whom PSS has, indeed, become a paradigm.6 6 Nevertheless, for those workers who would want to reject all seven of the above methodological difficulties as inconsequential, and who would also not wish to accept the replicability problems with the ACP procedure (footnote 5), there is also a set of technical problems which need to be considered with ACP as it has been used in the Bowling Green Laboratory. These problems, which are essentially apparatus difficulties associated with the modified Foringer chamber used in Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 111 Forms of the ACP have continued to be reported by Badia and his associates (Badia & Harsh, 1977a, 1977b; Badia, Harsh, & Coker, 1975; Badia et al., 1976; Culbertson & Badia, 1977; Harsh & Badia, 1974, 1975, 1976; Lewis & Gardner, 1977). These later studies, indeed, seem generally to be less enthusiastic about the strength of PSS. For example, Harsh and Badia (1976) report that what they take to be PSS occurs with a 150-sec period during which shocks are signalled but not with a 45-sec period. A similar class of finding with respect to shock intensity had already been reported with low shock intensity not yielding PSS (Harsh & Badia, 1975). Also, and perhaps more importantly, there has been no repetition of the apparently spectacularly strong PSS reports of changeover for much longer, stronger, and denser shocks (Badia, Coker, & Harsh, 1973; Badia, Culbertson, & Harsh, 1973). All this might be seen by some as indicating that the parameters of PSS are being established by these later ACP experiments. However, the methodological difficulties we have raised in connection with the original ACP studies apply with equal force to the later ACP examples because the difficulties are in the form of logical objections. As we have previously pointed out, it seems obvious that designs that are intended to measure preference validly should do so (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c), and there are now at least seven methodological reasons why the ACP does not. We take the fact that ACP continues to be used and reported to illustrate only the strength of the PSS as a paradigm, rather than any validation of ACP as an adequate test of footnote 6 continued the Bowling Green Laboratory, raise the question of modifiability, and suggest that the shocks used in the ACP experiment which were characterized as “inescapable” were, in fact, not so (Biederman & Furedy, 1976c, pp. 502-507; cf. especially photograph in Fig. 3 and recordings in Fig. 4). preference. That strength of belief in the PSS paradigm has been nicely, if perhaps unintentionally, illustrated recently by Lewis and Gardner (1977) who report a replication of the Badia and Culbertson (1972) ACP results, and, consistent with our footnote 5 in this paper, we shall for now assume that replicability of this particular ACP experiment can, despite our contrary findings (Biederman & Furedy, 1976b), be achieved. However, Lewis and Gardner also used a symmetrical changeover condition (where the same lever press produced both the signalled and the unsignalled shock on an alternating basis), and found PSS only in the two animals who were previously exposed to the (methodologically confounded) ACP arrangement. The verdict of these authors on the results from three animals only subjected to an (un-confounded) symmetrical changeover is that because those three rats “failed to develop a preference for signaled shock ... this particular symmetrical procedure appears inferior to the ACP changeover procedure” (Lewis & Gardner, 1977, p. 138, emphasis ours). When results inconsistent with the notion of PSS are categorized as “failures”, and the relative merits of designs are apparently judged in terms of how well they “succeed” in producing results that can be interpreted as PSS, it is clear that a paradox has indeed been transformed into a paradigm. Most recently Badia and Harsh (1977a, 1977b) have offered some arguments against our earlier suggestions that there are difficulties with ACP as a measure of PSS or, for that matter, of anything else. In this connection it is important to focus discussion on the PSS phenomenon itself as it was intended to be investigated in the original inescapable shock study of Badia and Culbertson (1972, Exp. II), rather than cloud what is already a sufficiently complex and controversial issue by analysing in detail numerous other papers Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 112 listed by Badia and Harsh (1977a, p. 14). Of these cited papers some do not contrast only signalled with unsignalled shock, but involve contrasting fixedand variable-time schedules (e.g., Badia et al., 1975), others do not involve ACP at all, but a symmetricalchoice procedure (e.g., Safarjan & D’Amato, Note 6), and yet others varied such parameters as the intershock interval and reported differential changeover as a function of that variation (e.g., Badia et al., 1976). We agree that probably “none of the factors described by Furedy and Biederman can account for these data” (Badia & Harsh, 1977a, p. 14), but that seems hardly the point. As we have indicated above, the methodological validity of the ACP as a measure of preference has to be rejected if only one of the seven arguments against it is granted. The arguments do not depend on their validity for their ability to fully account for even the original Badia and Culbertson (1972, Exp. II) study which was analysed; their validity certainly is not contingent on being able to be consistent with or account for the various other later claims made on the basis of later ACP papers, because, if at least one of our seven arguments are granted, these papers, like the one originally analysed, do not measure PSS. CONCLUSIONS We have tried to show that an analysis of the data base and The fate of Mowrer’s (1947) version of two-factor theory is another story (see Hernstein, 1969) and the current unpopularity of WS-termination as an explanation of avoidance learning clearly strengthens the present readiness to uncritically accept PSS as paradigmatic. The avoidance literature, which is quite distinct from the PSS evidence, has had a solid empirical basis relatively free from the gravitational influences of major theoretical masses. For example, Bolles, Stokes, and Younger (1966) found that while WS termination has a role in avoidance, it is not the critical variable; D’Amato, Fazzaro, and Etkin (1968) suggested that WS “termination (on avoidance trials) facilitates avoidance conditioning not because it results in fear reduction but 7 methodological status of PSS from 1959 to 1976 fails to support the notion that PSS is a robust phenomenon in rats.7 Moreover, it seems even more clear that any paradigmatic treatment of PSS, as if the converse phenomenon (PUS) was in some sense paradoxical, is an inadvisable way to study the effects of signalling unmodifiable noxious events. In particular, it appears that the ACP which has been used recently to support the paradigmatic status of rat PSS is itself a paradigm that is open to methodological (as well as replicational and technical) problems which render ACP-based results questionable for determining the preference issue. That issue, more generally, needs to be considered in a sceptical manner rather than in a “demonstrational” (Furedy, 1975) manner wherein not only the positive but also the negative aspects of signalling are recognized. As an experimental procedure signalling shock is of considerable interest because it allows the study, under relatively precisely controlled laboratory conditions, of how organisms cope with noxious unmodifiable events. It is important to recall that the value of this procedure is not dependent on being able to “achieve” robust PSS results. Even if PSS turns out to be an unstable effect (because of the aversive properties of the signal), it will still be of interest to study the functions of the various because it serves as an excellent discriminative cue for US avoidance** (p. 41). Thus, termination of WS might enhance avoidance by providing feedback (information) to the rat that US will not occur. Bolles and Grossen (1969) suggest that the WS in avoidance may function in a way similar to the SD of appetitive discrimination problems (cf. O’Neill & Biederman, 1974). Thus, informational properties now attributed to the WS in avoidance experiments are readily transferred to the inescapable, unavoidable PSS situation, despite the great functional (and psychological) differences in roles of the WS in avoidance learning and of the WS associated with inescapable, unmodifiable, unavoidable shock. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 113 physiological anticipatory responses elicited by the signal from the point of view of determining which of these lessen and which, perhaps, heighten the impact of the signalled noxious event. One hopes, of course, that these “under-the-skin” events will show patterns that can be related to the behavioural results represented by preference outcomes. What is clear, however, is that neither type of phenomena should be approached from a paradigmatic-demonstrational point of view. REFERENCE NOTES 1. BADIA, P. Intermittent immediate punishment preceded by a warning signal as determiners of choice. Un published MA thesis, Kent State University, 1959. 2. PERKINS, C. C, JR. Personal communication, 1969. 3. COTSONAS, P. M. Preference for signaled over unsignaled aversive stimulation. Unpublished MA thesis, University of North Carolina, 1972. 4. DOUGLASS, W. K. Some determinants of the preference for signaled shock. Paper presented to Eastern Psychological Association meetings, April 1969. 5. FUREDY, J. J., & BIEDERMAN, G. B. Methodological problems in evaluating rat preference for signaled or un-signaled shock. Paper presented to meeting of Psychonomic Society, November 1974. 6. SAFARJAN, W. R., & D’AMATO, M. R. Discriminated shock-free periods as the controlling variable in preference for signaled shock. Paper presented to Eastern Psychological Association meeting, New York 1975. REFERENCES ARABIAN, J. M., & DESIDERATO, O. Preference for signaled shock: A test of two hypotheses. Animal Learning and Behavior, 1975, 3, 191195. AVERILL, J. R., & ROSENN, M. Vigilant and nonvigilant coping strategies and psychophysiological stress reactions during the anticipation of electric shock. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1972, 23, 128-141. BADIA, P., COKER, C. C, & HARSH, J. Choice of higher density signaled shock over lower density unsignaled shock. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1973, 20, 47-55. BADIA, P., & CULBERTSON, S. The relative aversiveness of signaled vs. unsignaled escapable and inescapable shock. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1972, 17, 463-471. BADIA, P., CULBERTSON, S., & HARSH, J. Choice of longer or stronger signaled shock over shorter or weaker unsignaled shock. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1973, 79, 25-32. BADIA, P. & HARSH, J. Preference for signaled over unsignaled shock schedules: A reply to Furedy and Biederman. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 1977, 10, 13-16. (a) BADIA, P., & HARSH, J. Further comments concerning preference for signaled shock conditions. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 1977, 10, 17-20. (b) BADIA, P., HARSH, J., & COKER, C. C. Choosing between fixed time and variable time shock. Learning and Motivation, 1975, 6, 264-278. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 114 BADIA, P., HARSH, J., COKER, C. C, & A3BOTT, B. Choice and the dependability of stimuli that predict shock and safety. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1976, 26, 95-111. BERLYNE, D. E. Conflict, arousal, and curiosity. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1960. BIEDERMAN, G. B., & FUREDY, J. J. The preference-for-signalled-shock phenomenon: Signalling shock is reinforcing only if shock is modifiable. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1970, 22, 681-685. BIEDERMAN, G. B., & FUREDY, J. J. Preference-forsignalled-shock phenomenon: Effects of shock modiliability and light reinforcement. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1973, 100, 380386. BIEDERMAN, G. B., & FUREDY, J. J. The preference-for-signalled-shock phenomenon: Fifty days with scrambled shock in the shuttlebox. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 1976, 7, 129-132. (a) BIEDERMAN, G. B., & FUREDY, J. J. Operational duplication without behavioral replication of changeover for signaled inescapable shock. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 1976, 7, 421-424. (b) BIEDERMAN, G. B., & FUREDY, J. J. Preference for signaled shock in rats? Instrumentation and methodological errors in the archival literature. Psychological Record, 1976, 26, 501-514. (c) BIEDERMAN, G. B., & FUREDY, J. J. The preference-for-signalled-shock phenomenon: Reliability and sensitivity of asymmetrical and symmetrical changeover procedures in the Skinner box. Australian Journal of Psychology, 1977, 29, 111-124. BOLLES, R. C, & GROSSEN, N. E. Effects of an informational stimulus on the acquisition of avoidance behavior in rats. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1969, 68, 90-99. BOLLES, R. C, STOKES, L. W., & YOUNGER, M. S. Does CS termination reinforce avoidance behavior? Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1966, 62, 201-207. BRADY, J. V., & HUNT, H. F. An experimental approach to the analysis of emotional behavior. Journal of Psychology, 1955, 54, 345-352. BROWN, J. W., & JACOBS, A. Role of fear in motivation and acquisition of responses. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1949, 34, 747-749. BRUSH, F. R., BRUSH, E. S., & SOLOMON, R. L. Traumatic avoidance learning: The effect of CS-UCS interval with a delayed conditioning procedure. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1955, 48, 285-293. CANTOR, M. B., & LOLORDO, V. M. Reward value of brain stimulation is inversely related to uncertainty about its onset Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1972, 79, 259-270. CHURCH, R. M, & SOLOMON, R. L. Traumatic avoidance learning: The effects of delay of shock termination. Psychological Reports, 1956, 2, 357-368. COLLIER, A. C. Preference for shock signals as a function of the temporal accuracy of the signals. Learning and Motivation, 1977, 8, 159-170. CULBERTSON, S., & BADIA, P. Changeover from unsignaled to signaled avoidance as a function of the changeover period duration. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 1977, 9, 159-162. D’AMATO, M. R. Derived motives. Annual Review of Psychology, 1974,25, 83-106. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 115 D’AMATO, M. R., FAZZARO, J., & ETKIN, M. Anticipatory responding and avoidance discrimination as factors in avoidance conditioning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1968, 77, 41-47. DESIDERATO, O., & NEWMAN, A. Conditioned suppression produced in rats by tones paired with escapable or inescapable shock. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 1971, 77,427-435. DINSMOOR, J. A. Punishment: I. The avoidance hypothesis. Psychological Review, 1954, 61, 34-46. ESTES, W. K., & SKINNER, B. F. Some quantitative properties of anxiety. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1941, 29, 390-400. FRENCH, D., PALESTINO, D., & LEEB, C. Preference for warning in an unavoidable shock situation: Replication and extension. Psychological Reports, 1972, 30, 12-1 A. FUREDY, J. J. An integrative progress report on informational control in humans: Some laboratory findings and methodological claims. Australian Journal of Psychology, 1975, 27, 61-83. FUREDY, J. J., & BIEDERMAN, G. B. Preferencefor-signaled-shock phenomenon: Direct and indirect evidence for modifiability factors in the shuttle-bos. Animal Learning and Behavior, 1976, 4, 1-5. FUREDY, J. J., & DOOB, A. N. Autonomic responses and verbal reports in further tests of the preparatory-adaptive-response interpretation of reinforcement. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1971, 89, 258-264. FUREDY, J. J., & DOOB, A. N. Signaling unmodifiable shocks: Limits on human informational cognitive control. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1972, 21, 111-115. HARSH, J., & BADIA P. A concurrent assessment of the positive and negative properties of a signaled shock schedule. Animal Learning and Behavior, 1974, 2, 168-172. HARSH, J., & BADIA, P. Choice of signalled and unsignalled shock as a function of shock intensity. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1975, 23, 349-355. HARSH, J., & BADIA, P. A temporal parameter influencing choice between signalled and unsignalled shock schedules. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1976, 25, 327-333. HERRNSTEIN, R. J. Method and theory in the study of avoidance. Psychological Review, 1969, 76, 49-69. HYMOWITZ, N. Effects on responding of mixed and multiple schedules of signaled and unsignaled response-dependent electric-shock deliveries. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1976, 25, 321-326. KAMIN, L. J. The effects of termination of the CS and avoidance of the US in avoidance learning. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1956, 49, 420-424. KAMIN, L. J. The gradient of delay of secondary reward in avoidance learning. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1957, 50, 445449. (a) KAMIN, L. J. The gradient of delay of secondary reward in avoidance learning tested on avoidance trials only. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1957, 50, 450456. (b) KNAPP, R. K., KAUSE, R. H., & PERKINS, C. C., JR. Immediate vs. delayed shock in T-maze performance. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1959, 55, 357-362. LEWIS, P., & GARDNER, E. T. The reliability of preference for signaled Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 116 shock. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 1977, 9, 135-138. LOCKARD, J. S. Choice of a warning signal or no warning signal in an unavoidable shock situation. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1963, 3, 526-530. LOCKARD, J. S. Choice of a warning signal or none in several unavoidable-shock situations. Psychonomic Science, 1965, 3, 5-6. MACDONALD L., & BARON, A. A rate measure of the relative aversiveness of signaled vs. unsignaled shock. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1973, 19, 33-38. MILLER, N. E. An experimental investigation of acquired drives. Psychological Bulletin, 1941, 38, 534-535. MILLER, N. E. Studies in fear as an acquirable drive: I. Fear as motivation and fear-reduction as reinforcement in the learning of a new response. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1948, 38, 89-101. MILLER, R. R., DANIEL, D., & BERK, A. M. Successive reversals of a discriminated preference for signaled tailshock. Animal Learning and Behavior, 1974, 2, 271-274. MILLER, R. R., MARLIN, N. A., & BERK, A. M. Reliability and sources of control of preferences for signaled shock. Animal Learning and Behavior, 1977, 5, 303-308. MOWRER, O. H. On the dual nature of learning: A reinterpretation of “conditioning” and “problem solving”. Harvard Educational Review, 1947, 17, 102-148. MOWRER, O. H., & AIKEN, E. G. Continuity vs. drive-reduction in conditioned fear: Temporal variation in conditional and unconditional stimulus. American Journal of Psychology, 1954, 67, 26-38. MOWRER, O. R, & SOLOMON, L. N. Contiguity versus drive reduction in conditioned fear: The proximity and abruptness of drive-reduction. American Journal of Psychology, 1954, 67, 15-25. O’NEILL, W., & BIEDERMAN, G. B. Avoidance conditioning as a function of appetitive stimulus pretraining: Response and stimulus transfer effects. Learning and Motivation, 1974, 5, 195-208. PERKINS, C. C, JR. An analysis of the concept of reinforcement. Psychological Review, 1968, 75, 155-172. PERKINS, C. C, JR., LEVIS, D. J., & SEYMANN, R. Preference for signal-shock vs. shock-signal. Psychological Reports, 1963, 13, 735-738. PERKINS, C. C, JR., SEYMANN, R. G., LEVIS, D. J., & SPENCER, H. R., JR. Factors affecting preference for signal-shock over shock-signal. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1966, 72, 190-196. SCHOENFELD, W. N. An experimental approach to anxiety, escape, and avoidance behavior. In P. H. Hoch & J. Zubin (Eds.), Anxiety. New York: Grune and Stratton, 1950. SELIGMAN, M. E. P. Helplessness. San Francisco: Freeman, 1975. SIDMAN, M. Avoidance conditioning with brief shock and no exteroceptive warning signal. Science, 1953, 118, 157-158. SOLOMON, R. L., & BRUSH, E. S. Experimentally derived conceptions of anxiety and aversion. In M. R. Jones (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1956. SUBOSKI, M. D., BRACE, T. G., JARROLD, L. A., TELLER, K. J., & DIETER, R. Interstimulus interval and time estimation in ratings of signaled shock aversiveness. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1972, 2, 407-415. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118 117 VERHAVE, T. Technique for the differential reinforcement of rate of avoidance responding. Science, 1959, 129, 959-960. WEISS, J. M. Somatic effects of predictable and unpredictable shock. Psychosomatic Medicine, 1970, 32, 397408. WEISS, J. M. Effects of coping behavior in different warning signal conditions on stress pathology in rats. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1971, 77, 1-13. (a) WEISS, J. M. Effects of punishing the coping response (conflict) on stress pathology in rats. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 1971, 77, 14-21. (b) Received 7 June 1978. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol 31, No. 2. 1979, pp.101-118