Back to Realism Applied to Home Page The Behavioural and Brain Sciences (1986) 9, pp.365-370. Rational_vsEmp83.doc Commentary on James A. Dinsmoor (1983) Observing and conditioned reinforcement. BBS 6: 693-28. Abstract of the original article: When experimenters require their subjects to perform some readily recorded response to gain access to discriminative stimuli but do not permit this behavior to alter the schedule of reinforcement, the response is classified, by analogy, as an “observing” response. Observing responses have been used not only to analyze discrimination learning but also to substantiate the concept of conditioned reinforcement and to measure the reinforcing effect of stimuli serving other behavioral functions. A controversy however, centers around the puzzling question of how observing can be sustained when the resulting stimuli are not associated with any increase in the frequency of primary reinforcement. Two possible answers have been advanced: (a) that differential preparatory responses to these stimuli as conditional stimuli make both the receipt and the nonreceipt of unconditional stimuli more reinforcing; and (b) that information concerning biologically significant events is inherently reinforcing. It appears, however, that the stimulus associated with the less desirable outcome is not reinforcing. The maintenance of observing can be reconciled with the traditional theory that the acquisition of reinforcing properties proceeds according to the same rules as those for Pavlovian conditioning if it is recognized that the subject is selective in what it observes and procures a greater than proportionate exposure to the stimulus associated with the more desirable outcome. As a result of this selection, the overall frequency of primary reinforcement increases in the presence of the observed stimuli and declines in the presence of the nondifferential stimuli that prevail when the subject is not observing. Rationalist versus empirical approaches to observing and conditioned reinforcement: The (so-called) preference-for-signaled-shock J. J. Furedy and G. B. Biederman Department of Psychology, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, MSS 1A1 Canada Experimental psychologists in general, and operant psychologists in particular, consider themselves as primarily empirical in orientation. However, a rationalist strain sometimes may introduce itself in the form of the uncritical acceptance of certain generalizations that are assigned the status of a phenomenon. Once the elevation to this status occurs, critical analysis is suspended and the so-called phenomenon becomes entrenched in the manner of a rationalist first principle. From then on, further intellectual efforts are devoted solely to seeking to explain the mechanism through which the unquestioned and universally accepted phenomenon operates. An example of this type of approach is seen in Dinsmoor’s (1983) remarks and in the commentaries of most of his critics with respect to the so-called preference-for-signaled shock (PSS) phenomenon. The existence of the PSS phenomenon is accepted by all, and the only concern appears to be to determine whether the operative mechanism of the phenomenon is safety signal (as Dinsmoor, 1983, asserts), preparatory response (as Davis, 1983, and Perkins, 1983, claim), or information seeking (as, for example, Berlyne, 1960, had suggested). So in his reply to the commentators, Dinsmoor (1983) remarks that the "only mystery in this area . . . is why the animal will perform responses that produce a stimulus that is accompanied by an aversive stimulus" (p. 720). Thus, the implication is that only the mechanism of PSS needs further consideration. Dinsmoor states that he “lost interest” in the area "when the solution became apparent" that subjects were seeking safety signals (Dinsmoor 1983, p. 720). The implication of this remark appears to be that identifying the mechanism of a supposed phenomenon shuts down further critical Continuing commentary/Dinsmoor: Observing and conditioned reinforcement evaluation. To those commentators who disagree with Dinsmoor's account of the mechanism of the PSS phenomenon, his "solution" will be less than “apparent.” We may expect that argument to continue with the net effect of reinforcing the status of PSS as a first principle without further elucidating the status of the mechanism. At the empirical level we wish to question the unstated rationalist principle of the PSS as a universal effect despite its heuristic potential for theory, and its currently paradigmatic status (Biederman & Furedy 1979). Neither the logic of Dinsmoor's analysis and that of the commentators nor the evidence justifies the treatment of PSS as a first principle. Logically, two other effects are possible: There may be no preference for signaled shock, or there may even be a preference for unsignaled shock (PUS). Indeed, the PUS possibility is derivable both from some human subject accounts (e.g. "the shock hurts more when I tense up to prepare myself," cf., Furedy 1975), and some less current but not refuted psychological theory (e.g. the Hullian notion that the signal produces conditioned fear which potentiates the impact of signaled relative to unsignaled shock through the resultant increase in drive level). More important from an empirical standpoint is the fact that the empirical literature in support of the universality of PSS is by no means unequivocal. Much of it suffers from methodological problems (confounded experimental design), technical difficulties (unauthorized shock modification), and perhaps most serious, lack &f independent replication (see, e.g., Biederman & Furedy 1979). Moreover, even in procedures that do not suffer from these difficulties, the universality of PSS was not apparent even to a commentator such as Miller, who, together with some associates, concluded that they were "impressed with" and "disturbed by" the fact that "the effect is not universal across subjects under essentially identical conditions" (Miller, Marlin & Berk 1977, p. 308). Finally, although we are admittedly in a minority, others besides ourselves have reported no preference in studies that have had no obvious methodological shortcomings except the rationalist one of not succeeding in demonstrating the effect, e.g. Badia (1959), Cotsonas (1972), and Douglass (1969). The unclear status of PSS is best illustrated by our own recent experience. Having once found PSS (Biederman, Furedy & Beatty 1981) we were unable to replicate that result. Then, using a new procedure, we have recently found PUS in each of 10 subjects (Biederman, Furedy & Heighington 1984). In short, although there is little doubt that the weight of current scientific opinion is that PSS is a basic and universal effect whose existence should not be subject to serious question, the weight of sound scientific evidence does not support this conclusion, and scientific knowledge of the conditions producing PSS, no preference, or PUS is almost totally lacking. Such knowledge would in our view constitute a genuine “sign that we may be making progress toward becoming an objective science, in which theories converge because they are constrained by the data” (Dinsmoor 1983, p. 718). Author's Response On preferences for unsignaled shocks and for unpredictable rewards James A. Dinsmoor Department of Psychology, Indiana University. Bloomington, Ind. 47405 Furedy & Biederman complain that in taking an interest only in the mechanism responsible for the phenomenon of preference for signaled shock, not in an evaluation of the validity or the universality of the phenomenon, I and other writers on the topic have abandoned the empirical approach to behavior. I cannot agree. I do not equate lack of interest in further efforts to evaluate the phenomenon with uncritical acceptance of the data currently available. The reason the preference for signaled shock originally attracted a certain amount of scientific attention was that on first acquaintance it seemed to contravene established principles of behavior. Signals positively correlated with the receipt of shock should have been aversive to the subject (e.g. Dinsmoor 1962; for additional references, see McAllister, McAllister, Hampton & Scoles 1980) rather than reinforcing. However, experimental analyses of the situation (e.g. Badia & Culbertson 1972; Badia, Culbertson & Lewis THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2 Continuing commentary/Dinsmoor: Observing and conditioned reinforcement 1971; Dinsmoor, Flint, Smith & Viemeister 1969) indicated that it was the stimulus negatively correlated with the shock (safety signal) that was doing the job. If this is the case, the phenomenon per se recedes in interest, as it is not clear, whether amply or poorly verified, what implications a preference for signaled shock has for a systematic science of behavior. To repeat the familiar adage, we do not count the pebbles on the beach. References Badia, P. (1959) Intermittent immediate punishment preceded by a warning signal as determiners of choice. Unpublished MA thesis. Kent State University. [JJF] Badia, P. & Culbertson, S. (1972) The relative aversiveness of signalled vs unsignalled escapable and inescapable shock. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 17:463-71. [JAD] Badia, P., Culbertson, S. & Lewis, P. (1971) The relative aversiveness of signalled vs unsignalled avoidance. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 16:113-21. [JAD] Berlyne, D. E. (1960) Conflict, arousal, and curiosity. McGraw-Hill. [JJF] Biederman, G. B. & Furedy, J. J. (1979) A history of rat preference for signaled shock: From paradox to paradigm. Australian Journal of Psychology 31:101-18. [JJF] Biederman, G. B., Furedy, J. J. & Beatty, J. C. (1981) The preference for signaled shock phenomenon: Classical conditioning paradigms. The Psychological Record 31:357-69. [JJF] Biederman, G. B., Furedy, J. J. & Heighington, G. A. (1984) The double-alternative, double-start experimental apparatus: A new procedure for measuring preference. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 42:137-41. [JJF] Cotsonas, P. M. (1972) Preference for signaled over unsignaled aversive stimulation. Unpublished MA thesis, University of North Carolina. [JJF] Davis, H. (1983) Observing responses and the limits of animal learning theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6:706-7. [JJF] Dinsmoor, J. A. (1962) Variable-interval escape from stimuli accompanied by shocks. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 5:41-7. [JAD] Dinsmoor, J. A. (1983) Observing and conditioned reinforcement. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6:693-728. [HBD, JAD, JJF] Dinsmoor, J. A., Flint, G. A., Smith, R. F. & Viemeister, N. F. (1969) Differential reinforcing effects of stimuli associated with the presence or absence of a schedule of punishment. In: Conditioned reinforcement, ed. D. P. Hendry. Dorsey Press. [JAD] Douglass, W. K. (1969) Some determinants of the preference for signaled shock. Paper presented at the meeting of the Eastern Psychological Association, New York. [JJF] Furedy, J. J. (1975) An integrative progress report on informational control in humans: Some laboratory findings and methodological claims. Australian Journal of Psychology 27:61-83. [JJF] McAllister, D. E., McAllister, W. R., Hampton, S. R. & Scoles, M. T. (1980) Escape-from-fear performance as affected by handling method and an additional CS-shock treatment. Animal Learning and Behavior 8:417-23. [JAD] Miller, R. R., Marlin, N. A. & Berk, A. M. (1977) Reliability and sources of control of preferences for signaled shock. Animal Learning Behavior 5:303-8. [JJF] Perkins, C. C. (1983) Ways of observing conditioned reinforcement. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6:712-13. [JJF] THE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1986) 9:2