LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Table of Contents National Security Good National Security Bad Deontology Good Deontology Bad Social Contracts Support Individualism and Individual Rights The Social Contract Sustains Political and Economic Growth/stability The Social Contract is a Rational Choice The Social Contract is Totalitarian and Oppressive The Social Contract is Harmful Governmental Legitimacy Good Governmental Legitimacy Bad Utilitarianism Good Utilitarianism Bad Utilitarianism vs. Deontology Utilitarianism Doesn’t Respect Human Rights Economic Growth Good Economic Growth Bad Impacts: Economic Growth Morality Bad Morality Good Freedom of Expression Good Freedom of Expression Bad Justice Good MPX Justice is Sound Value Premise Justice is Bad for Society Justice is Not a Good Value for Debate Quality of Life Should Be Prioritized Quality of Life Not a Priority Cost Benefit Analysis and Deontology Answers to Cost Benefit Analysis Cost Benefit Analysis and Morality Cost Benefit Analysis is a Versatile Weighing Mechanism 2 3 5 6 8 9 10 12 13 14 15 16 18 19 20 22 23 24 25 27 31 33 34 36 37 39 40 41 42 44 46 48 LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES NATIONAL SECURITY GOOD NATIONAL SECURITY ONLY LIMITS INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS IN FAVOR OF THE NATION Hurst Hannum *, Executive Director, Procedural Aspects of International Law Institute, American Journal of International Law, 1981 CURRENT DEVELOPMENT: THE THIRTY-THIRD SESSION OF THE UN SUBCOMMISSION ON PREVENTION OF DISCRIMINATION AND PROTECTION OF MINORITIES, accessed 8-12-2010, http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ While some members had expressed reservations about the value of the Daes study on grounds that it was not appropriate or necessary to focus on limitations on rights or on individual duties instead of restraints on state action, the extensive final study does offer several useful observations and conclusions with respect to restrictions on the state's power to limit individual rights on the grounds, inter alia, of national security or ordre public. For example, the study makes clear that the mere procedural lawfulness of a statute restricting individual rights is not sufficient to justify that restriction, since the statute must also conform to the requirements set forth in the relevant international instruments. The study calls for the direct application of international human rights law in national tribunals and also recognizes the individual's status in international law. NATIONAL SECURITY ENABLES THE HARM PRINCIPLE Song Sang-ho, The Korea Herald 2010 CHILD PICKET BAN A VIOLATION OF RIGHTS’ Accessed 8-12-2010 http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ "Children's right to freely express their views can be restricted only when the restriction is necessary not to compromise national security, public safety, public order, public health or the protection of others' rights and freedoms." TELEOLOGY MUST BE USED TO DETERMINE JUSTIFICATION OF NATIONAL SECURITY Fleur Johns and Jacqueline Mowbray, Sydney Centre for International Law at the University of Sydney, 2010 ISLAM IS NOT ON TRIAL IN JUDGE’S BURQA RULING; COMMENT AND DEBATE, accessed 8-12-2010, http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ An analysis of whether the policy balanced national security considerations and individual rights must include discussion regarding its effectiveness. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES NATIONAL SECURITY BAD NATIONALISM DECREASES SAFETY OF MINORITIES, RESULTING IN MASS MURDER Nenad Miscevic, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2010 MATIONALISM, Accessed 8-12-2010 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nationalism/ Nationalism has long been ignored as a topic in political philosophy, written off as a relic from bygone times. It came into the focus of philosophical debate two decades ago, in the nineties, partly in consequence of rather spectacular and troubling nationalist clashes, such as those in Rwanda, the former Yugoslavia and the former Soviet republics. The surge of nationalism usually presents a morally ambivalent, and for this reason often fascinating, picture. “National awakening” and struggles for political independence are often both heroic and inhumanly cruel; the formation of a recognizably national state often responds to deep popular sentiment, but can and does sometimes bring in its wake inhuman consequences, including violent expulsion and “cleansing” of non-nationals, all the way to organized mass murder. The moral debate on nationalism reflects a deep moral tension between solidarity with oppressed national groups on the one hand and the repulsion people feel in the face of crimes perpetrated in the name of nationalism on the other. Moreover, the issue of nationalism points to the wider domain of problems, having to do with the treatment of ethnic and cultural differences within democratic polity, which are arguably among the most pressing problems of contemporary political theory. NATIONAL SECURITY CAN UNDERMINE JUSTICE Fleur Johns and Jacqueline Mowbray, Sydney Centre for International Law at the University of Sydney, 2010 ISLAM IS NOT ON TRIAL IN JUDGE’S BURQA RULING; COMMENT AND DEBATE Yet the ability of judges and jurors to see witnesses' faces, and otherwise assess witness credibility, is regularly compromised in Australian courts. The identity of undercover police and other informers may be concealed while they are giving evidence, so as not to jeopardise ongoing law-enforcement operations. Vulnerable witnesses, such as children or those suffering from an intellectual disability, are able to give evidence by live video link, or even through a prior video recording. Special arrangements are also made for witnesses who are physically disabled or who, for a range of reasons including their relationship to the accused, are likely to suffer emotional trauma or distress if required to appear in court. Such measures affect the ability of defendants to test the credibility of the evidence against them, and the ability of judge and jury to assess the veracity of that evidence. But they are considered necessary to protect other interests, including national security, public safety and the integrity of our legal processes. The courts balance the accused's right to a fair trial and other public interests. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES NATIONALISM UNDERMINES INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS UNCONSTITUTIONALLY Amos N. Guiora, Temple International and Comparative Law Journal, 2006 TRANSNATIONAL COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS OF BALANCING COMPETING INTERESTS IN COUNTER-TERRORISM Effective counter-terrorism strategy must be based on sophisticated risk assessment; an equal risk approach is operationally unfeasible and ineffective. The Bush administration's postSeptember 11 immigration detention policy, is demonstrated at the nation's airports. At U.S. airports, all travelers are subjected to the same check with little if any differentiation, just as all immigrants are treated with little differentiation. Just as that policy does not better protect the United States, detention predicated on belonging to a particular group rather than on an individualized basis does not better serve the public. In the context of the question that this article addresses, the alien policy adopted by the administration in the aftermath of September 11 reflects an improper balance between national security and individual rights. Furthermore, as clearly articulated by the Supreme Court in previous cases, the policy is unconstitutional. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES DEONTOLOGY GOOD ECONOMICS CANNOT FUNCTION WITHOUT DEONTOLOGY Irene Van Staveren, Professor of Pluralist Development Economics, 2007 Beyond Utilitarianism and Deontology: Ethics in Economics, p. 22-23 As is widely acknowledged among economists, an economy can function only when certain normative requirements are fulfilled. Partly, these requirements can be understood as rights, such as property rights and contractual rights. Another requirement concerns norms. These can be formal or informal norms – expressed in formal institutions, such as the welfare state, or informal institutions, such as culturally-shaped styles of human resource management in firms. Beyond Utilitarianism and Deontology Rights and norms have been widely understood to influence the economic behaviour of individual agents, firms, and the state. They have been taken up in a wide variety of economic traditions, including the mainstream through new institutional economics, public choice theory, and the field of law and economics. Deontological notions such as ‘rights’, ‘dignity’, ‘equality’, ‘obligations’, and ‘norms’ appear more prominently in heterodox traditions such as political economy, (old) institutional economics, Post Keynesianism, and socio-economics, as well as in cross-cutting areas such as feminist economics and ecological economics. The common ground is a recognition that rights and norms affect economicbehaviour as constraints on choice. DEONTOLOGY DOES NOT RELY ON UNPREDICTABLE OUTCOMES; CONSEQUENTIALISM FAILS IN REAL LIFE SCENARIOS Charles D. Kay, professor of philosophy, 1997 Notes on DEONTOLOGY, Kant's theory is an example of a deontological or duty-based ethics : it judges morality by examining the nature of actions and the will of agents rather than goals achieved. (Roughly, a deontological theory looks at inputs rather than outcomes.) One reason for the shift away from consequences to duties is that, in spite of our best efforts, we cannot control the future. We are praised or blamed for actions within our control, and that includes our willing, not our achieving. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES DEONTOLOGY BAD DEONTOLOGY CANNOT RECONCILE MORALITY WITH OTHER CONCERNS Irene Van Staveren, Professor of Pluralist Development Economics, 2007 Beyond Utilitarianism and Deontology: Ethics in Economics, p. 22-23 Deontology and economics do not seem to be compatible. Whereas economics is concerned with behaviour characterised by choices and ends, deontology is concerned with behaviour characterised by duties and limitations. While economics is about markets and allocation problems, deontology implies a rulesetting authority and distribution problems. It appears that economic behavior and moral rules are in opposition, and that little room exists for deontology in economics. DEONTOLOGY TOO SIMPLE TO APPLY TO THE COMPLEXITIES OF HUMAN LIFE; DOES NOT HAVE ANY REAL WORLD IMPACTS Irene Van Staveren, Professor of Pluralist Development Economics, 2007 Beyond Utilitarianism and Deontology: Ethics in Economics, p. 22-23 However attractive this moral theory may seem, it has several shortcomings. First, not all moral problems can be solved by rules. Human life is too complex to be reduced to a set of rights and duties (Anscombe, 1997). Indeed, as Walsh (2003, p. 285) has concluded, deontology is limited to issues of the will. It excludes vulnerabilities of human life that are outside the reach of the human will, such as scarcity of means and various contingencies to which social and economic life is so vulnerable. So morality needs to involve more than universalist reasoning and a steadfast will.2 As Putnam (2003, p. 405) has argued, it requires more than moral rules, since there are other ways values are expressed besides rules telling us what people must do. DEONTOLOGY TOO UNIVERSAL AND BROAD, DOES NOT ALLOW FOR DECISIONS BETWEEN TWO VALUES Irene Van Staveren, Professor of Pluralist Development Economics, 2007 Beyond Utilitarianism and Deontology: Ethics in Economics, p. 22-23 A further limitation is that deontological ethics has no criterion for dealing with conflicting rules. There is no higher-level rule that enables a unique rank ordering of moral rules according to their relative importance; nor does the theory allow for exceptions (Crisp & Slote, 1997). If killing is wrong and we find ourselves in a situation in which killing one person would help to save the lives of a hundred others, would we not, perhaps, reconsider the rule and look at its consequences in this particular context? What about a situation in which one needs to choose between two evils, for example lying in court and betraying a friend? LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVES CANNOT BE EFFECTIVELY APPLIED Ethics: An Introduction to Moral Philosophy October 8, 2009 Martin Cohen BOOKS; Pg. 48 No. 1917 "It's like being in a restaurant, and the waiter asks me what I'd like. I tell him, 'The tomato soup looks good,' and he, interpreting this purely as a psychological comment about my personal taste in soup, goes back into the kitchen and gets me nothing ... The whole thing ends with me soup less and him well informed; yet this is what your theory reduces morality to. "One small example: Noel Stewart suggests that giving £ 100 to charity is better than giving 10p, in the same sense that a straight line is better for being truly straight rather than wobbly, whereas the moral worth of a gift need not have anything to do with its cash value. Or take another unusual example, this time of urinating on graves. This, we are assured, illustrates the weakness of both utilitarianism and Immanuel Kant's kind of deontology, which, by allowing such a disgraceful act, become "ridiculous". "Both theories go badly astray here because they ignore the man's character," adds Stewart, who is, after all, a schoolteacher, and expected to be concerned about such things. Elsewhere, the line between the author's own views (indeed feelings) on a matter and the philosophical arguments becomes blurred. In a discussion of the limits of Kant's categorical imperative in application to abortion, Stewart roundly condemns Kant for ignoring "the intimate and raw feelings of love and the instincts of protective care mothers have for their babies", concluding the discussion tendentiously: "This is her baby we're talking about, not just some abstract source of future categorical imperatives. "It is a book in which the reader is invited to disagree, and there is much to disagree with here. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES SOCIAL CONTRACTS SUPPORT INDIVIDUALISM AND INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS SOCIAL CONTRACT ALLOWS FOR INDIVIDUALS TO ACHIEVE THEIR HIGHEST POTENTIAL David M. Shapiro, 2002 SELECTED PHILOSOPHY TOPICS THAT ARISE FREQUENTLY IN LINCOLN-DOUGLAS DEBATE, Accessed 8-12-2010, http://debate.uvm.edu/NFL/rostrumlib/ The Social Contract is a theory which seeks to explain this system of benefits and obligations in a society. The theory assumes that, long ago, individuals existed in an asocial context (they did not live in a society). Exponents of the Social Contract called this presocial condition the State of Nature. Because individuals did not belong to societies in the state of nature, they did not have obligations to societies and could more or less do whatever they wanted. But living without a society also meant that individuals received no benefits from a society. These individuals, as rational beings, gradually came to realize that the state of nature did not allow them to live up to their full potential because they remained divided and incapable of working together. SOCIAL CONTRACTS ENABLE INDIVIDUAL FULFILLMENT David M. Shapiro, 2002 SELECTED PHILOSOPHY TOPICS THAT ARISE FREQUENTLY IN LINCOLN-DOUGLAS DEBATE, Accessed 8-12-2010, http://debate.uvm.edu/NFL/rostrumlib/ People were fundamentally good, and therefore that state of nature was relatively peaceful. Nonetheless, the disorder of the state of nature meant that individuals could not unite and channel their energies toward common goals, hence the need for a society. Because Locke had more faith in human nature than did Hobbes, he saw no need to control people absolutely. Locke's Social Contract granted people more freedom than Hobbes's, and sought to strike a balance between order and liberty. THE SOCIAL CONTRACT SUPPORTS EQUAL AUTONOMY FOR ALL Rosenfeld, Michel. Professor of Law, New York Law School. THE RELATION BETWEEN CLASSIC CONTRACT LAW AND SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY. Iowa Law review. For those who share the liberal ideal of achieving the greatest possible autonomy for each individual compatible with both equal autonomy for all and the degree of social cooperation necessary to insure the survival of society, the conjunction of the social contract with freedom of contract seems highly desirable. Indeed, this conjunction not only permits neutrality with respect to individual visions of the good, but also strictly limits the realm of individual obligations. These results are achieved by dividing the universe of social relationships into the two separate and distinct spheres of the public and the private. The terms of the social contract govern the relationships in the public sphere and impose a limited number of obligations owed by each party to the social contract to all the other parties ot it. Freedom of contract, on the other hand, operates in an extensive private sphere in which individual obligations are limited to those arising out of particular legal contracts and extend only to the other party or parties to such contract. n4 Thus, in the private sphere, no obligation is owed to anyone unless it has been freely chosen, and, even then, it is only owed to the limited number of individuals to whom the obligor has freely chosen to make a commitment. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES THE SOCIAL CONTRACT SUSTAINS POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC GROWTH/STABILITY THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS AT THE BASIS OF THE MODERN POLITICAL STATE AND ECONOMY Amurad Merican. 2010. BAGAN DATOH AND 'THE SOCIAL CONTRACT' The Social Contract set the trend for modern political thought and philosophy of the state. It propounds a doctrine, set against the view of the divine right of kings, namely, that the government gets its authority by willing consent on our part, not by God's authorisation. While Rousseau's opening lines stated that "Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains", he thought that a good government can be justified in terms of the compromise to which each of us submits so as to gain civil liberty and proprietorship -- common themes in the European Enlightenment. The social contract doctrine was indeed central to the social, historical and geographical location of the Enlightenment in the Occident. Certainly Socrates and Plato had expressed similar arguments pertaining to our relationship with order and punishment, and the propensity for self-interests in Man. THE SOCIAL CONTRACT SUPPORTS ECNOMIC RECOVERY Dr. Gono, The Herald. 2007. SOCIAL CONTRACT THE WAY TO GO' Dr Gono says experiences in other countries show that the social contract has immense benefits in stabilising inflation and eventually achieving economic recovery. The social contract has been used with varying degrees of success in other countries such as Malaysia, Barbados and Australia. "A social contract can be a very useful tool to allow the Government, business and labour to map the way forward knowing what other social partners expect of them as opposed to the current situation where prices, bank rates and exchange rates go up overnight without warning. "Social contracts are more relevant to us in the Third World because we rely on foreign investment and aid. Even developed countries have some form of social partnership," THE SOCIAL CONTRACT CHECKS HYPERINFLATION Zimbabwe Independent. 2007. SOCIAL CONTRACT LONG-OVERDUE He therefore drew upon the lessons of history for, almost without exception, every successful recovery of economies from hyperinflation has been founded upon one common platform, that platform being known as a social contract. Germany anchored its recovery, from annualised inflation of 814 000 000% in 1923 to 4% in 1924, upon a social contract. Hungary used a social contract as the foundation for inflation containment from 19 800% per month to under 8%, while Bolivia similarly brought down inflation, in little more than one year, from 23 447% to less than 5%. Similar successes have, at different times, been achieved in the USA, Israel, Peru, Venezuela, Italy and many other countries, in every instance a social contract being the base upon which all the actions to contain inflation were founded LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS A RATIONAL CHOICE MEN HAVE EVERY REASON TO ENTER INTO SOCIAL CONTRACT Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (1651) THE STATE OF NATURE AND THE BASIS OF OBLIGATION In the following excerpts from Leviathan, Hobbes invited his readers to imagine a world without laws, police, courts, and prisons-a world of "perfect" liberty and equality-and then went on to show "scientifically" that such a world would be nothing less than a "war of every man against every man." Thus, he concluded, rational, self-interested people would have every reason to enter into a '"social contract" in which they put themselves under the unlimited authority of a sovereign ruler. SOCIAL CONTRACT PROTECTS PEOPLE – e.g. COPYRIGHT LAWS Fordham Intelectual Property, Media & Entertainment Law Journal, 2010 Accessed 8-11-2010 http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ THE SOCIAL CONTRACT AND AUTHORSHIP: ALLOCATING ENTITLEMENTS IN THE COPYRIGHT SYSTEM The social contract theories offer a fundamental theory about individual, societal and governmental or state relations that provides an important tool to deepen our understanding of the copyright system and what the law aims to achieve through the grant of statutory rights that create a temporary monopoly over literary and artistic works for which society bears the cost. n228 This [*472] Article argues that copyright law ought to be about the encouragement of authentic authorship by encouraging authors to be creative in their production of literary and artistic works for the public to benefit from. The law is much less about the publication, dissemination or commercialization of creative works and more about setting the optimum conditions in which authors and creators are encouraged to produce these works that will appeal to and benefit the public. The fundamental tenet of the social contract theory - that individuals within society arrive at a mutually beneficial agreement to be governed by a state authority, moral norms or a theory of justice as fairness n229 - is a particularly important philosophical idea to help us understand the historical trajectory of copyright law that has led us to this point and to provide us with a road map as to where we should head for the future with copyright policies and law. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS BASED ON UNANIMOUS CONSENT Carey, George. Professor, Georgetown University. NATURAL RIGHTS, EQUALITY, AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE. Ave Maria Law Review. In its most rudimentary form, the social contract theory postulated that individuals first lived without government in a state of nature, where they enjoyed equal liberty and natural rights (discrete portions of the natural, equal liberty), the exercise of which conformed with natural law (usually God-given and/or derived from reason). Because not all individuals obeyed the natural law and also because there was no acknowledged common superior to settle disputes that arose between individuals, governments were formed through contract by unanimous consent. As will be apparent later in this discussion, however, not all contract theories were exactly alike: differences existed over the context and source of the natural law, as well as over the character of rights. Nevertheless, this theory provided the rough framework within which issues such as the limits of obedience to government, the obligations of the citizens to authority, the legitimate powers of government, and the need for virtue and restraint were discussed before and during the founding period. SOCIAL CONTRACTS ARE AT THE HEART OF LAW AND JUSTICE IN THE UNITED STATES Allen, Anita. Professor, University of Pennsylvania. SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY IN AMERICAN CASE LAW. Florida Law Review. Social contractarian thought figures in American case law in at least three explicit ways, the first one less interesting than the others. First, courts invoke the names and views of noted contractarian philosophers-Locke, Hobbes, Rousseau, and Rawls-as corroborating scholarly authority. Locke's theory of government stressed individual rights against civil authority. Accordingly, judges cite Locke as scholarly authority for decisions that would limit the power of government in the interest of individual liberty or private property. Judges have cited both Locke and Hobbes as venerated support for the Fifth Amendment privilege against self- incrimination. Notwithstanding the civil libertarian understanding of the right against self-incrimination defended in his Leviathan, Hobbes argued for a near absolute form of sovereign government over the individual. From time to time judges cite Hobbes with plain disapproval as a paradigm of illiberal political extremism. Judges seeking warrant for extending government power or granting governmental immunities have cited Hobbes with approval. Rousseau's views about the role of the public in rearing and educating children were contrasted with the contemporary U.S. view favoring private child rearing in Franz v. United States. In another court of appeals case, the judge again mentioned Rousseau in relation to the dilemma of introducing public law into the private sector. The name of John Rawls, the leading contractarian political theorist of our times, appears more than a dozen times. Rawls is cited, for example, in a dissenting opinion in a torts case in which the judge adopted Rawls's methodology of reasoning about justice from the original position. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS TOTALITARIAN AND OPPRESSIVE THE SOCIAL CONTRACT DEPRIVES CITIZENS OF AUTONOMY AND MORALITY Guyora Binder, Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 2002 DEMOCRACY AND PUNISHMENT: PUNISHMENT THEORY: MORAL OR POLITICAL? In order to protect the autonomy of its members, society must coerce its members to behave according to the dictates of morality, but thereby appears to deprive them of their autonomy and so of any opportunity to act morally. THE SOCIAL CONTRACT CANNOT BE CHALLENGED United States Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit, 1998 Accessed 8-11-2010, http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ The plaintiffs submit that they are being forced into a contract with BTMUA involuntarily. The plaintiffs briefly claim that the ordinance violates the federal and New Jersey state constitutional provisions prohibiting laws impairing the obligation of contracts. The argument is plainly lacking in merit, because he ordinance does not impair any contracts. The plaintiffs then argue that general principles of contract law prohibit the township from charging fees for unwanted water service. Their claim is mistaken, because government is not required to deal with citizens on a purely contractual basis, as the mandatory connection cases discussed above demonstrate. The plaintiffs may be required to obtain their water service from BTMUA and to pay for that service just as they may be required to adhere to other laws that, one way or another, cost money. The only forced contract is the broader social contract, which is part of the nation's polity and as such is unchallengable here. RIGHTS EXIST PRIOR TO THE SOCIAL CONTRACT Luna, Erik. Professor, University of Utah. THE OVERCRIMINALIZATION PHENOMENON. American University Law review. But regardless of whether the inviolability of the individual stems from moral obligation or beneficial outcomes, this libertarian imperative necessitates certain rights and guiding principles for the interaction among individuals and between individuals and government. As usually described in the literature, a right is held by the individual and serves as a constraint on the action of all others, whether they are private citizens or representatives of the state. Rights establish absolute limits on how an individual may be treated, and as such, they must be respected at all times by other members of society. For deontological libertarians, rights exist prior to the state rather than being established by fictive social contract, and just as importantly, they limit the shape and authority that government can assume under this contract, with individuals and collectives having an affirmative moral duty not to violate the rights of others through their actions. And because human dignity is inherent and draws no exception among beings, all individuals must be bearers of equal rights. In the words of David Boaz, "The progressive extension of dignity to more people - to women, to people of different religions and different races - is one of the great libertarian triumphs of the Western world," and "the kind of equality suitable for a free society is equal rights." LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS HARMFUL THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS EXCLUSIVE Afua Hirsch. 2010. THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS BEING RENEGOTIATED Last week the Foundation for Law, Justice and Society gathered experts in law and social science at London's Gray's Inn to question the impact of the austerity measures on the terms of the "social contract". There is good reason to talk about the social contract now. The theory - drawn from the traditions of Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Kant and John Rawls among others - tends to go out of fashion during times of prosperity when improvements in personal security, heath and general stability encourage the affluent to "opt-out" of any sense of collective agreement. Historically it has been during times of recession that new terms have been negotiated Roosevelt's New Deal in Great Depression America, or the welfare state in post-war Britain. The problem with the theory has always been how to account for the consent of those too poor, ignorant or ill-equipped to take part in reasoning about the legitimacy of social arrangements. Many argue that the inability of most people to take part in the social contract confers even more responsibility on the state to provide facilities that will enable them to take part in the future. SOCIAL CONTRACTS LEAD TO CUTS IN VITAL SOCIAL PROGRAMS Editorial. 2007. NEW 'RAE DAYS' WILL NOT SAVE CITY. Short-sighted Toronto city councillors, objecting to both a tax increase and the inevitable service cuts that must result from a $575-million budget shortfall, are looking to the past for inspiration. Their model is the money-saving "social contract" imposed on public sector workers in 1993 by then-premier Bob Rae. Unfortunately, this is a badly flawed model that has only limited practical use in Toronto today. That has not stopped councillor Denzil Minnan-Wong from asking city staff to study and report on across-the-board wage freezes for all of Toronto's municipal employees and the imposition of unpaid days off as an alternative to transit cuts and other service reductions. "Cutting programs that directly affect residents and families should be the last thing we consider," Minnan-Wong says. ROUSSEAU: SOCIAL CONTRACT SACRIFICES INDIVIDUALISM AND CHOICE David M. Shapiro, 2002 SELECTED PHILOSOPHY TOPICS THAT ARISE FREQUENTLY IN LINCOLN-DOUGLAS DEBATE, Accessed 8-12-2010, http://debate.uvm.edu/NFL/rostrumlib/ Freedom meant making the General Will your will, so that in following the General Will you followed your will. For example, if your society decided to burn you as a witch, you would have to say "Yes, I'm a witch! Please burn me!" in order to be free. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY GOOD GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY IS NECESSARY FOR POLITICAL STRENGHT Margaret Levi, Harvard government professor, Achieving Government Legitimacy—and Good Government, 2006, A legitimate ruler or government elicits willing deference and obedience by justifying its exercise of authority with arguments the populace believes are normatively appropriate.i Legitimacy is a concept meant to capture the beliefs that bolster that willingness. The appeal of legitimacy as a feature of government has two aspects. First, the existence of legitimacy reduces the transaction costs of governing by reducing reliance on coercion and monitoring. Second, its existence denotes popular approval of government and governors or, at least, acceptance of their right to rule. GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY FULFILLS MORAL OBLIGATION TO HELP YOUR FELLOW MAN Christopher H. Wellman, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Guilford College, Liberalism, Samaritanism, and Political Legitimacy, 2008, What is striking, however, is that the moral dynamics of political legitimacy are echoic of those between Antonio and Bathsheba.8 I will argue that, just as Antonio has no right to drive off in solitude and leave Bathsheba vulnerable in Pleasantville, citizens have no right to be free from politi-cal coercion and leave others in a condition of political instability. Just as Antonio's car is the only vehicle in which Bathsheba can flee Pleas-antville, political society is the only vehicle with which people can es-cape the perils of the state of nature GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY BENEFITS ALL CITIZENS Christopher H. Wellman, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Guilford College, Liberalism, Samaritanism, and Political Legitimacy, 2008, Indeed, along the spectrum with Antonio and Professor Murphy's lounger on one side and the slave on another, a citizen's bur-den would apparently place her far closer to the latter than the former. But this objector errs by forgetting that, while the costs of citizenship are frequently plentiful and far-reaching, so are the benefits. Once one sub-tracts the benefits from the costs of citizenship, one understands the plausibility of invoking samaritanism to justify political coercion. This is why I specifically explained above that "a state may permissibly limit a person's liberty because this restriction is necessary to provide the crucial goods of political stability to that person and others" (p. 174, em-phasis added). At the time, my insistence that 'that person' receive the goods of political stability might have seemed paternalistic and out of place. But we now see that allotting benefits to all citizens is essential for political legitimacy not because of paternalism, but because these benefits are necessary to ensure that the burden of citizenship is not unreasonably costly LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY BAD GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY PROMOTES NEGATIVE GOVERNMENTAL CONTROL Margaret Levi, Harvard government professor, Achieving Government Legitimacy—and Good Government, 2006, For Weber, the three ideal types of legitimate domination are legal, traditional, and charismatic. But by his own accounting, traditional and charismatic authority rest on beliefs that may be inconsistent with democracy, protection of human rights, or other factors that promote general economic well-being and relative equity. History reveals numerous instances of rulers, deemed legitimate by their subjects, exercising their authority to eliminate enemies, internal and external. Legitimacy does not signify that power will be used to promote the good of the nation or of humanity. It implies only that the populace acquiesces in the exercise of governmental power. GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY IS A RUSE Thomas Franck, Professor of Law, 1992 THE EMERGING RIGHT TO DEMOCRATIC GOVERNANCE, American Journal of International Law In many nations, unfortunately, no such bargain was struck. Those who claim to govern cannot demonstrate that they have fulfilled the requirements of the democratic entitlement, even if they purport to recognize that entitlement. Senegal, for example, is a multiparty state with universal franchise and a secret ballot, but the results of the 1988 national elections were rejected as fraudulent both by opposition parties and by other social institutions. The other parties subsequently boycotted the 1990 local elections and refused to accept the Government's legitimacy. n10 Increasingly, as will be demonstrated later in this essay, governments whose legitimacy is questioned are turning to the international system for that [*51] validation which their national polis is as yet unable to give. They do so to avoid the alternative -- persistent challenge to authority by coups, countercoups, instability and stasis -and to enable themselves to govern with essential societal acquiescence. What they seek is legitimation by a global standard monitored by processes of the international system. GOVERNMENTAL LEGITIMACY IS TOO VAGUE AND IMEASURABLE TO PROMOTE ANY SOCIAL BENEFITS Margaret Levi, Harvard government professor, Achieving Government Legitimacy—and Good Government, 2006, Even if we leave these moral objections to the side, the concept itself is too imprecise for good positive research. It is more a catch phrase than a concept. Deference, trust, duty, adulation, and other attributes may interact with each other, but are any of them (all of them, some of them) necessary conditions for legitimacy? And, presuming we can achieve conceptual clarity, how does one measure such factors outside the laboratory? The major reason for unease, however, is that legitimacy is generally discussed in terms of only one of its dimensions: the beliefs people hold about the normative appropriateness of government structure, officials, and processes. Yet, equally important—at least for those of us concerned about improving the quality of government—are how individuals come to develop and accept current standards for normative appropriateness and how they are able to assess the extent to which a government meets those standards. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Utilitarianism Good Utilitarianism Creates Happiness Lewis J. Walker. President of Walker Capital Management Corp. 2004. THE MORALITY OF ECONOMICS HOW DO YOU DEFINE AND CONTRIBUTE TO A "JUST" SOCIETY? A CLASSIC PHILOSOPHY TEXT OFFERS SOME GUIDANCE. Rawls, who died in 2002, came from the deontological school of thought, incorporating duty and moral obligation into his ethical views of a just society. Deontology-from the Greek word "deon," meaning "obligation"-was championed by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant. It is often contrasted with utilitarianism, which consists of theories associated with classical economists like John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham and ancient Greek philosophers like Epicurus. Bentham's "rule of utility" proclaimed that good was whatever brings the greatest happiness to the greatest number of people. John Stuart Mill saw that the rightness of an action depended on the value of its consequences, and that the utility of that action could be rationally estimated. Utilitarian ethics holds that rightness can be defined free of external regulation, religious dogma, or social acceptability. Such thinking troubled ethicists from the JudeoChristian mold who felt that no man can be entirely free, and that God has imposed certain obligations and duties on each individual relative to his or her fellow man. Classical liberalism was a political philosophy grounded in individual freedom and limited government, which is seen today as conservatism. Today's liberalism, which emerged primarily in the aftermath of the Great Depression, is a neo-liberal Rawlsian notion of distributive justice. Utilitarianism Brings Order David M. Shapiro. Attorney. 1998. SELECTED PHILOSOPHY TOPICS THAT ARISE FREQUENTLY IN LINCOLNDOUGLAS DEBATE. There is a strong correlation between Utilitarian philosophy and an approach to the Social Contract, which emphasizes order over liberty. Often times, sacrificing some liberty for order up holds the greatest good for the greatest number. For example, we are searched for narcotics and firearms at the airport, which arguably is a limitation of our Fourth Amendment right to be free from unreasonable search and seizure, because a well-ordered society has an interest in controlling drugs and terrorism. In short, emphasizing order over liberty often serves Utilitarian principles. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Utilitarianism provides for happiness and security Binder, Guyora. Professor, State University of New York. 2000. UTILITARIASM AND THE PUNISHMENT OF THE INNOCENT. Rutgers Law Journal. Our argument, in brief, is that the charge of framing the innocent rests on a misunderstanding of utilitarian penology as an application of an "act-utilitarian" ethic governing individual behavior. We contend that utilitarianism began as a normative theory of law and legal process aiming not just at happiness in general, but also at security in particular, and that this theory was methodologically committed to publicity, regularity and representativeness of legal decision making. We argue further that utilitarian penology was the original and paradigmatic application of this theory of law and legal process, and should be so understood. When understood in this way, utilitarian penology cannot endorse punishment of the innocent, which violates either the security aim, or the publicity condition, or both. Indeed, utilitarian penology cannot endorse any program of official manipulation of the public that restricts information to a putatively utilitarian elite. It is simply not true that eschewing unnecessary punishment of the guilty logically entails willingness to punish the innocent. Utility aims to achieve happiness Mill, John Stuart. Philosopher. ON THE CONNECTION BETWEEN JUSTICE AND UTILITY. 1863. The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure. To give a clear view of the moral standard set up by the theory, much more requires to be said; in particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure; and to what extent this is left an open question. But these supplementary explanations do not affect the theory of life on which this theory of morality is grounded- namely, that pleasure, and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable things (which are as numerous in the utilitarian as in any other scheme) are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in themselves, or as means to the promotion of pleasure and the prevention of pain. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Utilitarianism Bad Utilitarianism is Destructive Gertrude Himmelfarb. Professor Emeritus at CUNY Graduate Center. 2004. ROMANTIC AT HEART; THE EMOTIONAL LIFE OF AN EMINENTLY RATIONAL THINKER. "I was born in London," Mill's Autobiography opens (after a paragraph justifying the writing of an autobiography), "on the 20th of May, 1806, and was the eldest son of James Mill, the author of the History of British India." This introduction was entirely fitting for an autobiography in which the father plays a major part and the mother appears not at all. (The few sentences about her in the original draft, expurgated by his wife, are dismissive, almost contemptuous.) It was his father who was responsible for the young Mill's awesome education: Greek at the age of 3, Plato (in Greek, of course) at 7, Latin (belatedly) at 8 and so on; the list of the books he read as a youth constitutes something like a bibliography of Western civilization. He was also initiated in the methodology and ideology of utilitarianism, and it was this that provoked the "crisis in my mental history," as Mill put it -- the discovery that the rigorously analytic, rationalistic, utilitarian philosophy was destructive of feeling, sentiment and imagination, and that life as he was meant to live it, as a thinker and reformer in the Benthamite mode, was meaningless and heartless. Utilitarianism is Morbid Jonathan Imbody. VP Government Relations at Christian Medical Association. The Washington Times. 2002. UTILITARIANISM IS NOT 'THE AMERICAN WAY' Echoing 19th century utilitarian philosopher Jeremy Bentham, paralyzed actor Christopher Reeve insisted at Tuesday's Senate hearing on human cloning, "Our government is supposed to do the greatest good for the greatest number of people" ("Reeve touts cloning to Senate," March 6). He encouraged hesitant senators to allow, in the name of utility, the cloning and killing of living human embryos to harvest their stem cells. Sadly, Mr. Reeve did not seem to grasp the grim irony that severely disabled individuals like himself would hardly fare well in the utilitarian calculus of anticipated benefit for the most people. If public policy truly were reduced to "the greatest good for the greatest number," racism and exploitation would flourish, eugenics would rule, and the fittest and favored would be released once and for all from the burden of those perceived as useless. Only in a compassionate society, rooted in the doctrines of divinely given human worth and justice for all, do vulnerable individuals have a hope and a future. That's because such a society asks not, "What is expedient," but instead, "What is right?" Rather than invoking utilitarianism to justify destructive human cloning research, patients seeking cures are far better served by advancing research on adult stem cells, which offer them proven promise, tested therapies, and a clear conscience. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES UTILITARIANISM VS. DEONTOLOGY Utilitarianism is preferable to deontology Larry Alexander, University of Chicago Law Review, 1999 ROOT OF FORMALISM: "WITH ME, IT'S ALL ER NUTHIN'": FORMALISM IN LAW AND MORALITY, accessed 8-11-2010 http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ If, however, those punished are acting in accordance with their own or others' deontological rights, then punishing them, though net beneficial, represents a utilitarianism of rights that is inconsistent with rights as side constraints. For example, it is possible that there is a strong deontological right to commit suicide under certain conditions, and that this right entails the right to assist others and to be assisted in committing suicide. It is also possible that permitting assisted suicide creates such dangers to other moral rights and values--such as the right not to be killed involuntarily--that a rule forbidding assisted suicide minimizes rights violations overall. Those who are punished under this rule and who are in fact exercising their moral right to assist and are not violating others' moral rights are thus being punished not for their violation of rights, but to minimize others' violations of rights. In such a domain of strong deontological rights--if such a domain exists--formal legal rules appear morally problematic. UTILITARIANIAM CAN COEXIST WITH DEONTOLOGY James E. Macdonald, Caryn L. Beck-Dudley, American Business Law Journal, 2001 A NATURAL LAW DEFENSE TO THE EMPLOYMENT LAW QUESTION: A RESPONSE TO RICHARD EPSTEIN, Accessed 8-11-2010 http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ These days Richard Epstein has come to think of himself as a "limited government utilitarian," having transformed himself from an earlier stage during which he was a "natural rights libertarian." n87 At first blush, it would seem that utilitarianism and natural rights libertarianism are inconsistent moral philosophies that would not permit an easy blending. Classical utilitarianism, after all, is notorious for smothering and dissolving the separate interests of individuals in its single-minded preoccupation with "the greatest happiness of the greatest number." Libertarianism, on the contrary, would seem to occupy the very opposite extreme from utilitarianism in the spectrum of possible moral philosophies, with its elevation and glorification of liberty and property interests of individuals to the status of nearly absolute and inalienable rights. In sum, libertarianism is a deontological theory, while utilitarianism is a consequentialist one, and, it would seem, ne'er the twain shall meet. n88 Yet Epstein is convinced that his new utilitarianism yields about the same old harvest of his favorite libertarian results as his earlier natural rights starting point did. So how can he convert from a natural rights libertarian to a social welfare utilitarian without much effort? . . . Epstein borrows his notion of social welfare from the literature of welfare economics, and it is not so easily brushed aside as are the classical utilitarian understandings of the greatest happiness principle. He eschews the old utilitarian approaches that assumed value is objective, and interpersonal comparisons of utility could be counted on in aggregating individual utilities. Rather, Epstein's position is subjective utilitarianism: one state A of the world is better than state B if someone, by his own subjective light, prefers A over B, while nobody, by their own subjective lights, prefers B over A. n94 LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Utilitarianism Doesn’t Respect Human Rights Utilitarianism will punish the innocent if necessary Binder, Guyora. Professor, State University of New York. 2000. UTILITARIASM AND THE PUNISHMENT OF THE INNOCENT. Rutgers Law Journal. Many philosophers have asserted that utilitarianism requires framing and punishing an innocent person when doing so will advance utility. Dozens of legal scholars have repeated some version of this charge, generally citing it as the principal objection to utilitarian penology. Carritt and H.J. McCloskey leveled the best known versions of this attack. Carritt reasoned that: if some kind of very cruel crime becomes common, and none of the criminals can be caught, it might be highly expedient, as an example, to hang an innocent man, if a charge against him could be so framed that he were universally thought guilty; indeed this would only fail to be an ideal instance of utilitarian 'punishment' because the victim himself would not have been so likely as a real felon to commit such a crime in the future; in all other respects it would be perfectly deterrent and therefore felicific. Utilitarianism is harmed be the people’s sense of Justice Mill, John Stuart. Philosopher. ON THE CONNECTION BETWEEN JUSTICE AND UTILITY. 1863. IN ALL ages of speculation, one of the strongest obstacles to the reception of the doctrine that Utility or Happiness is the criterion of right and wrong, has been drawn from the idea of justice. The powerful sentiment, and apparently clear perception, which that word recalls with a rapidity and certainty resembling an instinct, have seemed to the majority of thinkers to point to an inherent quality in things; to show that the just must have an existence in Nature as something absolute, generically distinct from every variety of the Expedient, and, in idea, opposed to it, though (as is commonly acknowledged) never, in the long run, disjoined from it in fact. UTILITARIANISM MORALLY INCORRECT Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell, Harvard Law Review, 2001 FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE, Accessed 8-11-2010 http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ Drawing an analogy to the obligation to tell the truth, Atiyah notes that many people's reluctance to tell even "white lies" "does not prove that it is wrong to tell such a lie; it may merely demonstrate how hard it is to act in unaccustomed ways." Id. He does not, however, use this analysis in the way that we do. (His primary purpose is to refute the criticism of utilitarianism by moral philosophers who argue that, because we all know that breaking any promise is morally wrong and because utilitarianism allows for exceptions, utilitarianism must be incorrect.) LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES UTILITARIANISM ISUNTRUE – MEN DON’T NECESSARILY MAX PLEASURE AND MIN PAIN Jeanne L. Schroeder, Professor of Law, Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law. Oregon Law Review. 2000. THE ECONOMICS OF RACE AND GENDER: RATIONALITY IN LAW AND ECONOMICS SCHOLARSHIP Indeed, psychoanalysis explains that the reason why people engage in [*228] inconsistent and seemingly self-destructive behavior is not merely conflicting wills or ignorance, but because utilitarianism is incorrect in assuming that subjects seek to maximize their pleasure and minimize their pain. Rather, the pleasure principle is always inextricably linked to the death drive. The theory of jouissance explains that the achievement of ecstacy - as opposed to mere pleasure or happiness - is often achieved through displeasure and pain. The theory of the death drive explains how the utilitarian attempt to pursue everyday pleasure can lead to suffering. UTILITARIANISM UNMEASURABLE James E. Macdonald, Caryn L. Beck-Dudley, Dean of the College of Business at Florida State University. American Business Law Journal, 2001 A NATURAL LAW DEFENSE TO THE EMPLOYMENT LAW QUESTION: A RESPONSE TO RICHARD EPSTEIN, Accessed 8-11-2010 http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ Earlier utilitarians, Jeremy Bentham, n89 J. S. Mill, n90 Henry Sidgwick, n91 and G. E. Moore, n92 were notoriously unable to give any intelligible, useful or durable account of "the greatest happiness" principle. Bentham's "felicific calculus" was recognized as something of an embarrassment from the outset, what with its radical reduction of all goods and evils to quantities of pleasures and pains. J.S. Mill soon thought it necessary for utilitarians to make qualitative (i.e., not merely quantitative) distinctions between higher and lower pleasures; but, of course, in doing so he implicitly gave up the assumption of the single yardstick of quantities of pleasure through which diverse goods and evils could be commensurate and made ready for addition and subtraction. And, with G. E. Moore, the entire reductionist project of defining the good seemed shipwrecked once and for all- utilitari-ans were obliged to recognize an irreducible plurality of goods that, somehow, were to be put together. UTILITARIANISM UNCONSTITUTIONAL – VIOLATES INDIVIDUALS ‘ RIGHTS Geoffrey R. Stone is Harry Kalven, Jr. Professor of Law at the University of Chicago, 1985 INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS AND MAJORITARIAN: THE SUPREME COURT IN TRANSITION, accessed 8-11-2010 http://www.cato.org/pub_display.php?pub_id=917 In his 1984 Sibley Lecture, Solicitor General of the United States Rex E. Lee defended the Supreme Court's record in the 1983 Term against three criticisms: (1) the Court too often sided with the government "over the individual" and surrendered its role as "a protector of constitutional rights"; (2) the Court abandoned principled constitutional interpretation in favor of "cost-benefit' analysis; and (3) as a result of the 1983 Term, "Americans are less free." LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Economic Growth Good Capitalisms are good as they promote innovation and thus advancing society. Schlegel, John. 2008. Professor of Law, State University of New York. THINKING THROUGH LAW’S QUESTION OF CLASS, ECONOMICS, AND INEQUALITY. Buffalo Law Review. Accessed 8/12/10. This evaluative aspect is rooted in the common macro-economic concern with growth. For the authors, technological advance yields economic growth when entrepreneurial innovation is translated into large-scale production of the resulting products or services. The mechanics of this observation turn on two things. The first is a distinction between replicative entrepreneurial activity - think of an additional McDonald's franchisee in 1970 - and innovative entrepreneurial activity, the creation and introduction of disruptive technology that brings forth Schumpeterian "creative destruction." The second is the importance of the large-scale firm for the commercialization of entrepreneurial innovation. Thus, capitalisms are good to the extent that they allow or encourage both innovative entrepreneurial activity and the translation of the fruits of innovation by large-scale firms into salable products or services so as to facilitate economic growth. Capitalisms are bad capitalisms to the extent that they hamper innovative entrepreneurial activity and its translation into new products or services so as to impede growth. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Economic Growth Bad Hegemony of Capitalism Economic growth leads to further want and ignoring morals Hedges, Chris. 2009. Graduate, Harvard Divinity School. THE FALSE IDOL OF UNFETTERED CAPITALISM. Commondreams.org, accessed 8/12/10. The consumer goods we amass, the status we seek in titles and positions, the ruthlessness we employ to advance our careers, the personal causes we champion, the money we covet and the houses we build and the cars we drive become our pathetic statements of being. They are squalid little monuments to our selves. The more we strive to amass power and possessions the more intolerant and anxious we become. Impulses and emotions, not thoughts but mass feelings, propel us forward. These impulses, carefully manipulated by a consumer society, see us intoxicated with patriotic fervor and a lust for war, a desire to vote for candidates who appeal to us emotionally or to buy this car or that brand. Politicians, advertisers, social scientists, television evangelists, the news media and the entertainment industry have learned what makes us respond. It works. None of us are immune. But when we act in their interests we are rarely acting in our own. The moral philosophies we have ignored, once a staple of a liberal arts education, are a check on the deluge. They call us toward mutual respect and self-sacrifice. They force us to confront the broad, disturbing questions about meaning and existence. And our callous refusal to heed these questions as a society allowed us to believe that unfettered capitalism and the free market were a force of nature, a decree passed down from the divine, the only route to prosperity and power. It turned out to be an idol, and like all idols it has now demanded its human sacrifice Economic Inequality is not necessary for economic growth Marcelli, Enrico. 2000. Professor of Economics, University of Massachusetts. ECONOMIC GROWTH AND INEQUALITY IN SAN DIEGO COUNTY. California and Western Law Review. Accessed 8/12/10 The assumption that inequality is a necessary condition for competition and that competition alone drives economic growth is based on two socially and economically detrimental "enabling myths." An enabling myth is one that neoinstitutional economists claim "enables those who benefit from the status quo to keep on benefiting" at the expense of society as a whole. The first is the "market" myth, which maintains that the distribution of income is determined by an unfettered demand for, and supply of, labor. This is a myth, and inequality is not inevitable because earnings inequality also exists due to socially established institutions such as seniority and other structures of authority in both public and private enterprises. Thus, more than the market explanation is required to justify extant inequality. A second "hierarchy" myth claims that persons in positions of authority are there because they deserve to be, and thus should receive higher compensation than others not similarly situated. They have "paid their dues," so to speak, and their [*310] earnings and benefits are thus determined not solely by market forces but by their position in the hierarchy. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Impacts: Economic Growth Economic Growth is a danger to the world Jackson, Tim. 2009. Economics Commissioner, Sustainable Development Commission. ECONOMIC GROWTH HAS FAILED US. WHAT’S THE ALTERNATIVE? Commondreams.org, accessed 8/12/10. Economic growth is supposed to deliver prosperity. Higher incomes should mean better choices, richer lives, and improved quality of life for us all. That at least is the conventional wisdom. But things haven't always turned out that way. Growth has delivered its benefits, at best, unequally. A fifth of the world's population earns just 2 per cent of global income. Inequality is higher in the OECD nations than it was 20 years ago. Far from improving the lives of those who most needed it, growth let much of the world's population down. Wealth trickled up to the lucky few. Fairness (or the lack of it) is just one of several reasons to question growth. As the economy expands, so do its ecological impacts. In the last quarter of a century an estimated 60 per cent of the world's ecosystems have been degraded. Global carbon emissions have risen by 40 per cent since 1990. Significant scarcity in key resources - such as oil - may be less than a decade away. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES MORALITY BAD DEFINITION OF MORALITY Bernard Gert, Stone Professor of Intellectual and Moral Philosophy “Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,” 2008 THE DEFINITION OF MORALITY, Accessed 8-11-2010 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/ Dictionary definitions of referring terms are usually just descriptions of the important features of the referents of those terms. Insofar as the referents of a term share the features that account for why that term refers to those referents, the term is not regarded as ambiguous. “Morality” is an ambiguous term. What “morality” refers to when used in the descriptive sense does not have most of the important features of what “morality” refers to when used in the normative sense. Further, accepting a descriptive definition of morality need have no implications about how a person should behave. Accepting a normative definition of morality commits a person to regarding some behavior as immoral, perhaps even behavior that he is tempted to perform. Because accepting a normative definition of morality involves this commitment it is not surprising that there are serious disagreements about what normative definition to accept. MORALITY HAS HIGH POLITICAL COSTS Stephen R. Munzer, professor of law at UCLA, Harvard Journal of Law & Technology, 2007, Few need reminding that hESC research is a tricky, even explosive, moral and political issue. Both supporters and opponents of such research might want medical groups to ensure that their members never carry out research that comes within a country mile of moral wrongdoing, and research into the creation of human-nonhuman chimeras could conceivably come within that bound. Likewise, social conservatives and liberals alike might agitate for legal regulations that forbid research that carries the faintest odor of immorality. This point is not intended to be a slippery slope argument. Rather, I argue only that sometimes it is imprudent to incur the high political costs of trying to get social policy or the law to conform exactly to morality. The costs of attempting to achieve that conformance include both the difficulties of getting social policies or legal regulations implemented and the potential loss of faith in public institutions (reputational costs). MORALITY IS ECONOMICALLY INEFFICIENT Henry Mintzberg, Cleghorn Professor of Management Studies at the Desautels Faculty of Management of McGill University in Montreal, Quebec, Canada A Note on that Dirty Word"Efficiency", 1982, Efficiency gets a bad name because it inevitably means measurable efficiency, with three unfortunate consequences. Because costs are typically more easily measured than benefits, efficiency all too often reduces to economy. Because economic costs can usually be more easily measured than social costs, efficiency often produces an escalation in social costs, which are treated as "externalities." Because economic benefits are typically more easily measured than social benefits, efficiency often drives the organization toward an economic morality which can amount to a social immorality. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES MORALITY OPPOSES THE JUSTICE SYSTEM WHICH LEADS TO ANARCHY Lloyd R. Cohen, Associate Professor of Law at George Mason University, Review of: A CRIME OF SELF-DEFENSE: BERNHARD GOETZ AND THE LAW ON TRIAL.. Pp. xi, 253, 1989, To some, it might seem odd that in a nation with such a distinguished record of successful selfgovernment, so many Americans have defended and even praised what, disingenuous posturing aside, was a fairly obvious act of vigilantism by Bernhard Goetz. Why have otherwise respectable citizens chosen to reject the standard response to the vigilante that the punishment of wrongdoers is to be left to the institutions of the state and that the ordinary citizen must not take the law into his own hands? Do they fail to appreciate that there is much to be lost by our civilization if we fall away from the rule of law? Vigilantes exist for they believe that justice is far better served by their methods as opposed to the formal processes of government. They feel that the law enforcement bureaucracy is totally unresponsive to the needs of the citizenry and in many cases they perceive the government as being disinterested in the public safety of the various communities. As a result they sense a moral obligation "to take the law in their own hands" thus circumventing all of the established legal bodies. No Formula for Morality Mochtar Buchori, writer for the Jakarata Post, “Morality a Piece of the National Development Puzzle.” , access date: 8/12/2010 Morality is a cultural issue. So the main problem facing Indonesia today is not economic, but cultural. And cultural problems are much harder to solve than economic ones. Theoretically, any economic dilemma can be solved through economic measures that regulate forces, which are responsible for that particular quandary. But whether these economic measures will be carried out faithfully and honestly, well that is no longer a problem of economics. That is a cultural problem. I was confounded when I heard this explanation. I have been conditioned to think that economic problems are the most basic and the most important among all the enigmas that beset this country. I was not prepared for such a strange perspective. My friend went on to expose and explain his view. He said the disappointing factor was that we did not seem to be aware that such cultural problems existed. We have not done anything to solve our morality problems or any other cultural obstacles. Compared to what we have done to analyze and solve our economic problems, our attempts to solve cultural issues have been infinitesimal. Morality Is A Poor Value for Making Judgments Societal Morality: A Contradiction in Terms Alexis de Tocqueville, French political thinker and historian, Free Market Mojo delivered by Newstex access date: 8/12/110 Morality is certainly important for the members of a society to possess. But society, as a whole, has nothing to gain from possessing its own morality. What good is a morality if instituted through the use of force? If citizens will not act morally by their own accord, they certainly will not do so under compulsion. And even if compulsory morality keeps the symptoms of moral decay in check for a time, an immoral society will reach the same end eventually, regardless of any government intervention. Moreover, any societal adoption of a given morality constitutes a violation of individual rights. Morality lies in the realm of the mind and conscience, government authority only pertains to the realm of action. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES MORALITY GOOD MORALITY DICTATES ALL DECISIONS Garth Kemerling, American Philosopher Kant: The Moral Order, 2001, According to Kant, then, the ultimate principle of morality must be a moral law conceived so abstractly that it is capable of guiding us to the right action in application to every possible set of circumstances. So the only relevant feature of the moral law is its generality, the fact that it has the formal property of universalizability, by virtue of which it can be applied at all times to every moral agent. From this chain of reasoning about our ordinary moral concepts, Kant derived as a preliminary statement of moral obligation the notion that right actions are those that practical reason would will as universal law. MORALITY IS THE BASIS OF JUDGEMENT Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy First published Wed Apr 17, 2002; substantive revision Mon Feb 11, 2008 When “morality” refers to the codes of conduct of different societies, the features that are essential, in addition to some element related to avoiding and preventing harm, are that morality is a code of conduct that is put forward by a society and that members of that society use it as their guide to behavior. In this descriptive sense, “morality” can refer to codes of conduct of different societies with widely differing content, and still be used unambiguously in the same way that “law” is used unambiguously even though different societies have laws with widely differing content. However, there are now other descriptive senses of “morality.” In the sense most closely related to the original descriptive sense, “morality” refers to a guide to behavior put forward by some group other than a society, for example, a religious group. When the guide to conduct put forward by a religious group conflicts with the guide to conduct put forward by a society, it is not clear whether to say that there are conflicting moralities, conflicting elements within morality, or that the code of the religious group conflicts with morality. Members of the society that are also members of a religious group may regard both guides as elements of morality and differ with regard to which of the conflicting elements of the moral guide they regard as most important. There are likely to be significant moral disputes between those who regard different elements as more important. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES MORALITY SUPPORTS ECONOMIC GROWTH George C. Bitros, Emeritus Professor of Economics in the Department of Economics of the Athens University of Economics Morality, “Institutions and economic growth: Lessons from ancient Greece,” 2006. We show that the character and the morality of citizens are important ingredients of economic growth because they go hand in hand with the great institutions of private property, democracy, and free markets. Our approach enables us to establish this result by reference to the structure and performance of the ancient economies of Athens and Sparta during the period 490-338 BC. Athens grew vastly wealthier than Sparta essentially because its institutions were optimally adjusted to confront the basic scarcity of grains, whereas the institutions of Sparta were optimally adjusted to sustain its military supremacy. However, in both cases there emerged systems of morality, which secured the operating efficiency of their institutions. Therefore, poor countries in search of potent strategies for rapid economic growth should not just try to emulate the institutions of economically advanced countries. At the same time, they should put the emphasis of their efforts to setting up agoge systems, so as to infuse into the character of their citizens compatible “ethos”. For, without the latter, no matter how successfully they adapt the institutions of democracy and free markets, rapid economic growth will be inhibited from the lack of an environment of generalized morality. MORALITY SUPPORTS SELF ACTUALIZATION Jeanne L. Schroeder, Professor of Law B.A., 1975, Williams College; J.D., 1978, Stanford University SSRN, BONDAGE, FREEDOM & THE CONSTITUTION: THE NEW SLAVERY SCHOLARSHIP AND ITS IMPACT ON LAW AND LEGAL HISTORIOGRAPHY: PRIVATE LAW AND UNITED STATES SLAVE REGIMES: ARTICLE: COMMENT ON RUSSELL: HEGEL'S SLAVES, BLACKSTONE'S OBJECTS, AND HOHFELD'S GHOSTS: A COMMENT ON THOMAS RUSSELL'S IMAGERY OF SLAVE AUCTIONS Cardozo Law Review, 1996, The one thing that cannot rightly serve as the object of property is that which is capable of selfconsciousness - another person. This is because the teleology of property is the self-actualization of human freedom through the development of subjectivity. To treat another person as an object of property is to attempt to attain subjectivity by depriving another human being of her subjectivity. As such, it is not merely self-contradictory and self-defeating; it is an abstract wrong. It is an affront to the very nature of what it is to be a person. It is a wrong that pre-exists morality and ethics, so that no moral or ethical regime can exist, and no individual selfactualization can exist - if slavery exists. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES MORALITY OFFERS A CORRECTIVE TO UTILITARIANISM Samuel Scheffler, University Professor and Professor of Philosophy and Law at NYU “Human Morality,” New York: Oxford University Press. 1992. Pp. 150. $ 26. I believe that it was opposition to utilitarianism, which first bred arguments claiming in one way or another that a view of morality according to which morality is very demanding is mistaken just because morality cannot be so demanding. On first hearing, this type of argument is liable to seem suspect. Humans should be fit for morality, and unfortunately too often they are not - one is inclined to say. If we find morality too demanding the fault is with us and not with morality. The idea of human morality, in the sense of a morality fit for humans in not being too demanding, is surely, one is tempted to say, a typical modern perversion of the truth. If, however, my conjecture is correct and consideration of the demandingness of morality arose and gained currency in the context of discussions of the merits and demerits of utilitarianism, then this dismissive response is shortsighted. Utilitarianism, whatever its shortcomings, was the first widely accepted view of morality which gave the interests of every sentient being direct and exclusive weight in distinguishing morally right from morally wrong action. To be sure other views of morality held that all human or all rational life is as such of (equal) value. But for no previous view was the road from value to right action so direct, being neither mediated by nor mixed with other considerations. That is why utilitarianism - and any other view of morality, which shares this feature of it - gave rise to concern about the demandingness of morality. If it is wrong for me to act in my own interest whenever I could instead do something that would serve the interests of others more than any act open to me could serve my own interest, then arguably I am only rarely allowed to act in my own interest. This is absurd, and a view of morality of which this is a consequence is surely wrong. Hence the eagerness of utilitarians and others with similar moral views to argue [*1298] that no such conclusion follows from their way of understanding morality. In the last thirty years or so the debate has moved a long way beyond the crude formulations of the previous paragraph. Yet it has never been so carefully and systematically examined as in Samuel Scheffler's Human Morality. n1 Scheffler distinguishes four responses to a view of morality which presents it as being very demanding. Apart from denying its correctness and insisting that morality's demands are moderate, one can also seek to moderate the consequences of a demanding morality without denying that it is demanding, either by claiming that there are actions which are not at all subject to moral judgment (the question of the scope of morality), or by claiming that it is sometimes rational to act against morality since morality is sometimes overridden by other considerations (the question of the authority of morality). Finally one may object to a view of morality because it presents it as demanding by being over intrusive, that is by requiring that every action however trivial (taking a sip from the mug of coffee in front of me) be preceded by a deliberation of the moral permissibility of the act. This raises the question of the role of morality in our practical deliberations. Scheffler's own view is that morality's scope is pervasive, that is that moral considerations bear on any conceivable action, but that it does not impose a pervasive presence in our deliberations. Except when special reasons apply one acts morally if one acts as morality directs and would not have done so had one been aware of moral considerations against the act unless they proved insufficient to prohibit the act. n2 That is, in the majority of cases moral (or morally explicit) considerations need not be present to one's thought. All that is morally required is that had moral reasons against the action been perceptible they would have been given the consideration they deserve. Additionally and most importantly, morality's demands are - according to Scheffler - moderate and not LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES demanding. On the authority of morality Scheffler reserves judgment. He does not believe that no consideration can ever override the ultimate moral verdict on an action. But he leaves the question open. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Freedom of Expression Good Freedom of Expression is too limited Hardy, David. 2008. Professor, University of Arizona. A FRAMING ERA VIEW OF THE BILL OF RIGHTS. Northwester University Law Review Colloquy. Accessed 8/12/10. Tucker is ahead of his time, taking a robust view of Americans' rights. Even in time of "national struggles" limitations on freedom of expression are traps rather than benefits and marks of tyrannical tendencies; Tucker cites as illustrative Virginia's wartime limit on pro-British expression. Tucker's reference to freedom from exemption from "coercion" brings to mind the modern concept of "chilling effects." In all these things, the eighteenth-century academic is surprising modern: he seeks no "clear and present danger" test, even in wartime. While we cannot know how he would view modern issues such as obscenity, civil defamation, or political campaign regulation, his equation of freedom of thought with freedom of expression, and his repudiation of wartime Virginia statutes suggests that he would find the modern First Amendment tests, if anything, to be overly permissive of regulation. Tucker here argues the First Amendment's language is too narrow: the citizenry should be able, not only to petition, but to instruct, their legislators. The right to instruct had been guaranteed in several State constitutions, and in the First Congress, Tucker's brother Thomas proposed its addition to the Federal Bill of Rights. Non-Network Neutrality is a threat to Freedom of Expression. Connor, Michael. 2007. Executive Director, Open MIC. NETWORK NEUTRALITY, FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION AT RISK. Commondreams.org, accessed 8/12/10. As consumers, we have a right to know in advance when and if a service we pay for may be intentionally disrupted by our provider. If we're lawyers who do peer-to-peer file sharing of large digitized documents over the Internet, we may want to use an Internet service provider other than Comcast. Finally, as citizens of a democracy whose most cherished freedom is that of expression, we should be outraged whenever anyone is silenced without very good and clearly stated reasons. So that's what we're asking for: an open, candid and public discussion of the reasons for such actions. Our hope is that such a discussion will lead us to a future where media, information and communication companies profit most by amplifying rather than restricting our freedom of expression. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Internet Neutrality is mandated by Free Speech Krasovec, Jay. 1997. Professor, University of Akron. CYBERSPACE: THE FINAL FRONTIER FOR REGULATION? Akron Law Review. Accessed 8/12/10. The First Amendment is the cornerstone of our Independence. Society has come to value the freedom of speech and expression more than any other of our Constitutional rights. Thus, the First Amendment and its protections have had to continuously adapt to new and unique circumstances and technologies in order to secure these ideals. […] The basic principles of free speech mandate the widest and most far reaching means of communication possible. The Internet's ability to almost instantaneously transmit information and ideas to millions of people and this Nation's strong reaffirmance in unrestricted political speech mandates that our basic First Amendment rights survive online. "The life of the First Amendment has not been logic, it has been experience." Our history and experience tells us that we afford "greater weight to the value of free speech than to the dangers of its misuse." The potential and fear of misuse of the Internet, cannot justify over-reaching regulations encroaching on basic civil liberties. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Freedom of Expression Bad Freedom of Expression must be limited if it harms others Mills, John Stuart. 1869. Philospher. ON LIBERTY: OF INDIVIDUALITY, AS ONE OF THE ELEMENTS OF WELL BEING. Bartleby.com, accessed 8/12/10. Acts of whatever kind, which, without justifiable cause, do harm to others, may be, and in the more important cases absolutely require to be, controlled by the unfavourable sentiments, and, when needful, by the active interference of mankind. The liberty of the individual must be thus far limited; he must not make himself a nuisance to other people. But if he refrains from molesting others in what concerns them, and merely acts according to his own inclination and judgment in things which concern himself, the same reasons which show that opinion should be free, prove also that he should be allowed, without molestation, to carry his opinions into practice at his own cost. Freedom of Speech only allows communicative action. Solum, Lawrence. 1989. Professor of Law, Loyola Law School. A THEORY OF THE FIRST AMENDMENT FREEDOM OF SPEECH. Northwestern University Law Review. Accessed 8/13/10. An important corollary is the proposition that communication is intersubjective; speech acts involve both speakers and listeners. In addition, the theory of communicative action makes a distinction between communicative action -- oriented to the coordination of behavior through rational agreement -- and strategic behavior -- the use of speech to manipulate, [*56] coerce, or deceive. I argue that a theory of free speech can incorporate this distinction to mark the boundaries of the right to free speech: freedom of speech is freedom to engage in communicative action, not strategic action. Freedom of Expression can be limited in times of War Holmes, Oliver. 1919. Supreme Court Justice. SCHENCK V. UNITED STATES. Findlaw.com, accessed 8/13/10. The most stringent protection of free speech would not protect a man in falsely shouting fire in a theatre and causing a panic. It does not even protect a man from an injunction against uttering words that may have all the effect of force. The question in every case is whether the words used are used in such circumstances and are of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will bring about the substantive evils that Congress has a right to prevent. It is a question of proximity and degree. When a nation is at war many things that might be said in time of peace are such a hindrance to its effort that their utterance will not be endured so long as men fight and that no Court could regard them as protected by any constitutional right. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Justice Good MPX JUSTICE IS ACHIEVABLE Feeley, Malcolm M., Claire Sanders Clements Dean's Chair Professor of Law, 1992, Edited by Howard S. Erlanger, Voss-Bascom Professor of Law and Professor of Sociology at the University of Wisconsin, Madison, And Jennifer Earl, 2008 American Bar Foundation Law and Social Inquiry REVIEW ESSAY: THE PROCESS IS THE PUNISHMENT: THIRTY YEARS LATER, accessed 8-11-2010, http://www.lexisnexis.com/hottopics/lnacademic/ Another innovation in TPP is Feeley's discussion of the disconnect between substantive justice and procedural justice. Certainly the distinction [*758] between procedural and substantive justice was not new, but his defense of substantive justice was somewhat novel. To briefly recap, Feeley argues that most defendants do not, in practice, enjoy extensive procedural protections, but most cases are nonetheless handled justly from a substantive perspective. In fact, rejecting claims that procedural justice leads to substantive justice, Feeley opens the book by contending that substantive justice is a separate and achievable form of justice, and he closes the book arguing that even when procedural protections are not in full use, "Officials do not abandon this concern with justice, but rather they create a sense of justice which is compatible with their concern for speed and efficiency" JUSTICE, ACCORDING TO LAW, LIMITS POLITICS Roger Pilon, Director of Cato's Center for Constitutional Studies San Francisco Daily Journal, 2003 TOWARD THE RESTORATION OF LAW, accessed 8-11-2010, https://www.cato.org/dailys/0117-03.html The whole point of having law -- and constitutional law in particular -- is to discipline politics and the raw power it amounts to. For in the end, the triumph of politics is the death of law -- and with it, reason and justice. Social Justice must be society’s core value Hall, David. Professor, University of Arkansas. GIVING BIRTH TO A RACIALLY JUST SOCIETY IN THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY. Little Rock Law Review, 1999. 8-11-2010 Social justice is not a static state. It is not a place we reach. It is a process that we are constantly and forever engaged in. If we are to give birth to a new century, then social justice cannot be an after thought to a well-planned strategy for the 21st Century. It must be the core value of any viable policy or plan for the future. Otherwise, we will continue to live in a society where we make tremendous strides in the areas that are our strengths, and continue to be stymied in the areas where our greatest opportunities for growth exist. If we dismiss this profound calling by labeling it as merely politically correct rhetoric, then we will have forsaken the religious, spiritual and moral foundations of our lives. n26 So, social justice cannot be the period after the sentence about our accomplishment and identity. It must be the core value through which we identify ourselves. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Justice coincides with, subsumes, and includes morality Mill, John Stuart. Philosopher. ON THE CONNECTION BETWEEN JUSTICE AND UTILITY. 1863. It appears from what has been said, that justice is a name for certain moral requirements, which, regarded collectively, stand higher in the scale of social utility, and are therefore of more paramount obligation, than any others; though particular cases may occur in which some other social duty is so important, as to overrule any one of the general maxims of justice. Thus, to save a life, it may not only be allowable, but a duty, to steal, or take by force, the necessary food or medicine, or to kidnap, and compel to officiate, the only qualified medical practitioner. In such cases, as we do not call anything justice which is not a virtue, we usually say, not that justice must give way to some other moral principle, but that what is just in ordinary cases is, by reason of that other principle, not just in the particular case. By this useful accommodation of language, the character of indefeasibility attributed to justice is kept up, and we are saved from the necessity of maintaining that there can be laudable injustice. JUSTICE INCREASES EQUALITY Samuel Freeman, Avalon Professor in the Humanities, Professor of Philosophy and Law, Stanford encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2008 ORIGIONAL POSITION, Accessed 8-11-2010 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/originalposition/ Rawls contends that the most rational choice for the parties in the original position are the two principles of justice. The first principle guarantees the equal basic rights and liberties needed to secure the fundamental interests of free and equal citizens and to pursue a wide range of conceptions of the good. The second principle provides fair equality of educational and employment opportunities enabling all to fairly compete for powers and prerogatives of office; and it secures for all a guaranteed minimum of the all-purpose means (including income and wealth) that individuals need to pursue their interests and to maintain their self-respect as free and equal persons. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES JUSTICE IS SOUND VALUE PREMISE There are many different possibilities for criteria for justice Joseph William Singer, Bussey Professor of Law, The Yale Law Journal, 1984. THE PLAYER AND THE CARDS: NIHILISM AND LEGAL THEORY accessed 8-11-2010 There are many different possibilities for criteria for justice: Rights protection is the core standard for justice. You can use the social contract (in a Lockean sense) to say that we have "contractual obligations" to act a certain way because we have consented to limiting our rights. You can also make arguments saying that because someone has not given consent to a rights limitation, such rights violation is unjust. You can be as specific as you want with rights-based criteria for justice. You can look at negative, positive, social and individual rights, just to name a few. Justice is Good for Our Health Norman Daniels, Mary B. Saltonstall Professor of Population Ethics and Professor of Ethics and Population Health 2000. JUSTICE IS GOOD FOR OUR HEALTH. Accessed 8-11-2010 These social determinants offer a distinctive angle on how to think about justice, public health, and reform of the health care system. If social factors play a large role in determining our health, then efforts to ensure greater justice in health care should not focus simply on the traditional health sector. Health is produced not merely by having access to medical prevention and treatment, but also, to a measurably greater extent, by the cumulative experience of social conditions over the course of one’s life. By the time a sixty-year-old heart attack victim arrives at the emergency room, bodily insults have accumulated over a lifetime. For such a person, medical care is, figuratively speaking, "the ambulance waiting at the bottom of the cliff." Much contemporary discussion about reducing health inequalities by increasing access to medical care misses this point. We should be looking as well to improve social conditions--such as access to basic education, levels of material deprivation, a healthy workplace environment, and equality of political participation--that help to determine the health of societies. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Justice is Bad for Society “Social Justice” initiatives harm society Hall, David. Professor, University of Arkansas. GIVING BIRTH TO A RACIALLY JUST SOCIETY IN THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY. Little Rock Law Review, 1999. Accessed 811-2010 Social justice is not charity. It is not something we give to others, it is something we do for ourselves. In the words of Professor Robert Rodes, "I do not owe any poor person a share of my wealth, but I owe every poor person my best efforts to reform the social institutions by which I am enriched and he or she is impoverished." Justice is a virtue that moves us to render others what is due them, not what we want to give them. It serves as the basis of our integrity and legitimacy as individuals and as a society. If those social institutions are not reformed so that the poor and oppressed truly have access and substantive opportunities to fulfill their dreams, then we have not only undercut the integrity of the system, we have created perpetual nightmares for many. These nightmares produce the social diseases of crime, brutality and homelessness that will ultimately end up at all of our doors. Egalitarian justice leads to the loss of an open society Brunner, Karl, founder of Jornal of Money, Credit and Banking, the Journal of Monetary Economics, and the Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series of Public Policy. ECONOMIC INEQUALITY AND THE QUEST FOR SOCIAL JUSTICE, 1998. Cato Institute. A society guided by an egalitarian vision is committed to choose institutions that establish pervasive instruments of political repression together with conditions of poverty and stagnation. Our search for justice needs certainly to look elsewhere for humane solutions. The process concept of justice deserves substantially more serious attention than it has been granted in the public arena. This conception of justice addresses a fundamental question bearing on the nature of social and political institutions that offer members of society the best opportunity to shape their lives and improve their lot. Such arrangements unavoidably allow a persistent inequality in the distributions of income. This does not mean, however, that specific social groups are permanently locked into particular positions of the income distribution. An open society produces substantial social circulation within the income distribution pattern over successive generations. We need also to emphasize once that a society guided by the egalitarian principle will necessarily develop institutions of control and management that ultimately maintain substantial inequality of economic status and political power. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES JUSTICE FAVORS THE STRONG, OVER THE JUST Eric Brown, Associate Professor of Philosophy Washington University in St. Louis, Stanford Encyclodpedia of Philosophy, 2009 PLATO’S ETHICS AND POLITICS IN THE REPUBLIC, Accessed 8-11-2010 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics-politics/ Predictably, Cephalus and then Polemarchus fail to define justice in a way that survives Socratic examination, but they continue to assume that justice is a valuable part of a good human life. Thrasymachus erupts when he has had his fill of this conversation (336a-b), and he challenges the assumption that it is good to be just. On Thrasymachus' view (see especially 343c-344c), justice is conventionally established by the strong, in order that the weak will serve the interests of the strong. The strong themselves, on this view, are better off disregarding justice and serving their own interests. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES JUSTICE IS NOT A GOOD VALUE FOR DEBATE Justice is an ambiguous value Jo Greenhorn et. Al. The Herald. 2010. GENUINE RESPECT FOR THE TRUTH MUST BE AT THE CENTRE OF ANY SYSTEM OF JUSTICE, accessed 8-11-2010 I have lately listened to certain politicians, including the current Prime Minister, speak about justice and found myself wondering where their particular definition of that word comes from. It is certainly from no dictionary. Those who speak about justice with phony passion, while at the same time doing all in their power to ensure there is no role for the truth in proceedings, are hypocrites. They insult all of us who truly do believe in justice and who believe, with a genuine passion, that if respect for the truth isn’t at the centre of any justice system then that system is not entitled to use the word justice in its title. Justice Is Too Abstract A Value Minh A. Luong. Tournament of Champions Advisory Committee, Assistant Professor in the Ethics, Politics, & Economics Program at Yale University and International Affairs Fellow at the Yale Center for International and Area Studies THE CASE FOR CONTEXTUAL STANDARDS. Rostrum 2001, Accessed 8-112010 debate.uvm.edu/NFL/rostrumlib/Luong%20Perspe.pdf Use of abstract values and even worse, focus of the debate over competing philosophical theories, sidesteps or completely ignores the discussion over the actual debate resolution. Under the present paradigm, it is possible for debaters to discuss the same issues of “justice” or “freedom” despite changes in the resolution. Clearly, current practice is not promoting discussion on the range of issues that is demanded by frequent changes of debate topics. JUSTICE, USED BROADLY, RESULTS IN SHALLOW ANALYSIS Minh A. Luong. Tournament of Champions Advisory Committee, Assistant Professor in the Ethics, Politics, & Economics Program at Yale University and International Affairs Fellow at the Yale Center for International and Area Studies THE CASE FOR CONTEXTUAL STANDARDS. Accessed 8-11-2010 debate.uvm.edu/NFL/rostrumlib/Luong%20Perspe.pdf Most Lincoln-Douglas debaters identify a very abstract value such as ‘justice” or “progress” and try to apply it to a specific empirical context stipulated in the L-D resolution. The result is a lack of context and precision because abstract values are “too high” for empirically applied L-D resolutions to be adequately analyzed in just 13 minutes. This is tantamount to using a meat ax when, in actuality, a scalpel is required. Additionally, current practice is actually counterproductive to the educational goals of debate because it promotes shallow analysis and is difficult for judges to understand. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Quality of Life should be prioritized Life should not be prioritized over Quality of Life Lehmann, Karin. 2006. Professor, University of Cape Town. ARTICLES AND ESSAYS ANALYZING JUSTICIABILITY OF ECONOMIC, SOCIAL, AND CULTURAL RIGHTS. American University International Law Review. Accessed 8/13/10. For instance, an HIV positive patient's interest in receiving anti-retroviral medicine versus a chronic migraine sufferer's interest in receiving migraine treatment because their quality of life is seriously and adversely impaired. The HIV positive patient's life may be extended significantly if she receives anti-retroviral medicine. The migraine sufferer's quality of life will be improved significantly if she receives migraine [*189] medication. Under Bilchitz's formulation, and perhaps most individual's immediate compassionate response, the HIV positive patient's claim must be prioritized. But if that choice would condemn the migraine sufferer to a life of suffering, where her dignity and quality of life was seriously eroded, can one still so readily argue that the one claim inherently trumps the other? Must life always prevail over quality of life? Bilchitz's formulation would, surely, lead to a situation in the health care context where the government must prioritize "terminal illnesses" above other interests, an approach the court expressly and appropriately rejected in Soobramoney. Quality of Life must be considered Neeley, Steven. 1994. Professor, Xavier University. THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO SUICIDE, THE QUALITY OF LIFE, AND THE "SLIPPERY-SLOPE. Akron Law Review. Accessed 8/13/10. It is good that men should feel a horror of taking human life, but in a rational judgment the quality of the life must be considered. The absolute interdiction of suicide and euthanasia involves the impossible assertion that every life, no matter what its quality or circumstances, is worth living and obligatory to be lived. This assertion of the value of mere existence, in the absence of all the activities that give meaning to life, and in the face of the disintegration of personality that so often follows from prolonged agony, will not stand scrutiny. On any rationally acceptable philosophy there is no ethical value in living any sort of life: the only life that is worth living is the good life. A minimum realization of physical well-being is necessary for life to be “good” Neeley, Steven. 1994. Professor, Xavier University. THE CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHT TO SUICIDE, THE QUALITY OF LIFE, AND THE "SLIPPERY-SLOPE. Akron Law Review. Accessed 8/13/10. We may define the good life differently, but no matter what our conception of the good life is, it presupposes a physical basis -- a certain indispensable minimum of physical and social wellbeing -- necessary for even a limited realization of that good life. Where that minimum is failing together with all rational probability of attaining it, to avoid a life at its best can be only vegetative and at its worst run the entire gamut of degradation and obloquy, what high-minded person would refuse the call of the poet "mourir entre les bras du sommeil"? We must recognize no categorical imperative "to live," but "to live well." LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Quality of Life not a priority Diminished Quality of Life doesn’t allow the end of life. Craig, Paul. 1989. Staff, Journal of Health Law. THE SUPREME COURT FACES THE QUEST OF WITHDRAWAL OF HYDRATION AND NUTRITION. Journal of Health Law, accessed 8/13/10. The Missouri court adopted "sanctity of life" as the guiding legal standard, and established a strong presumption in favor of treatment. The court indicated the state interest in preserving life was "unqualified" and not dependent on the quality of an individual's life. The court admitted consideration of Ms. Cruzan's quality of life was inevitable, but stated diminished quality of life does not support a decision to cause death. This vitalist posture is based on the philosophy that the value of life protected by the state cannot be defined by the benefits that the individual's life offers to others, or the relative ability of the individual to realize full human potential. Further, amici argue the danger of a slippery slope in considering diminished capacity and raise the specter of handicapped persons finding "the state or others seeking to terminate their lives and the courts permitting them to do so." LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Cost-Benefit Analysis and Deontology Deontological Constrained CBA is Superior To Alternatives Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 3 Deontologically constrained CBA is more complex than standard CBA. Yet, we maintain that it is superior to its alternatives. For the deontologist, Direct and explicit incorporation of deontological constraints into economic Models are vital to make the analysis normatively acceptable. Less obviously, Most of the consequentialist responses to the deontological critique (such as the Move from act- to ruleconsequentialism) actually recognize or at least imply That sound CBA should incorporate constraints for practical or instrumental Reasons. A consequentialist who embraces one of these responses may thus Welcome our proposal without converting to deontology. Other consequentialist Responses to the deontological critique, such as the "preferences for fairness" Argument, are conceptually unsound and potentially self-defeating. The Deontological Measure Of Morality Should Be CBA Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 27-28 It does not follow, however, that whenever a decision maker faces more than one Deontologically permissible option, the choice between them should necessarily rest on standard CBA. Consider the choice between the following options: (1) deliberately killing one innocent person to save 101 people; (2) spending $10,000,000 to save the same 101 people; and (3) letting the 101 people die. Presumably, the only option infringing a deontological constraint in this example is option (1). If option (1) overrides the constraint against deliberately killing innocent people, then all three options is permissible. The net outcomes of the options are as follows: (1) net saving of 100 lives; (2) saving of 101 lives at a cost of $10,000,000; and (3) no lives saved and no costs borne. At this point, there are two ways to proceed. One way is to employ standard CBA: monetize the value of a person's life, and choose between options (1) and (2) (both of which produce much more good than option (3)), according to whether one life is valued at more or less than $10,000,000. Another approach is to maintain that, whenever an infringement of a deontological constraint is involved, human life is lexically more important than monetary losses, and thus to rank option (2) higher than option (1), regardless of the monetary value attributed to human life. Standard CBA monetizes and aggregates all costs and benefits involved in an act. If, for example, an act involves the killing of some people and saving others, bodily injuries, damage to property, and pecuniary gains and losses, all these costs and benefits are taken into account. While a threshold function may similarly take into account all such costs and benefits (thus deviating from standard CBA only in adding a threshold D), such inclusiveness arguably misses’ significant distinctions between different costs and benefits. Following the philosophical literature, this Section examines several limitations on the types of benefits and costs bearing on the permissibility of infringing deontological constraints. The possible excluders of costs and benefits described below may be endorsed alliteratively or cumulatively. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Cost-Benefit Analysis and Deontology A Deontologically Constrained CBA Must Also Set The Structure Of The Threshold Function Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 45 The constraint may be expressed as an additive or multiplier function, or as a combination of these options. In the present context, the language of thresholds set forth by Title VII and the ADA seems to reflect the additive approach because it determines the threshold irrespective of the actual harm that the discriminatory decision or practice inflicts on the person who is discriminated against. In this sense, these provisions can be interpreted as setting some (possibly high) value K that represents the harms that generally result from not making reasonable accommodations or from applying some otherwise discriminatory practice. Yet, the "necessity" and "undue hardship" standards may also be interpreted as laying down a multiplier threshold in which its size is determined by the extent of the harm Inflicted by the infringing act. This approach finds support in Judge Posner's statement that the assessment whether an accommodation imposes an "undue burden" under the ADA should be made "in relation to the benefits of the accommodation to the disabled worker as well as to the employer's resources." LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Answers to Cost-Benefit Analysis Factoral Morality Counters CBA Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 12-13 In any event, even if rule-consequentialism of some sort were a valid Foundational moral theory, it would not imply that CBA should not include deontological constraints. On the contrary—the more sophisticated versions of Rule-consequentialism is more acceptable precisely because they strive to Explain and justify the role of deontological constraints on the factoral level. To clarify, a factoral moral theory defines the factors that determine the Morality of an act, their relative weight and interaction. Such factors may include the costs and benefits of an act, whether it involves harming other people, and the relationships between the actor and the people affected by the act. In and of itself, a factoral theory neither explains nor justifies the relevance of the various factors and their interaction. This is the role of foundational theories. Interestingly, there is no necessary match between the kind of theory one adopts on the factoral level and the theory one favors on the foundational level."*^ As we have just seen, rule-consequentialism on the foundational level endorses threshold constraints on the factoral level.''^ Thus, CBA should take deontological constraints into account as well. CBA Preferences And Prejudices Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 46 As regards the types of costs and benefits relevant to measuring whether the threshold is met, one must consider whether to take into account discriminatory preferences and prejudices (of either the employer or the firm's customers or other employees). Disregard for antisocial preferences is possible even within a purely consequentialist theory, and has in fact been advocated by some economists.'^' However, this view is more likely to be part of a Deontologically constrained CBA. The constraint against discrimination implies that satisfying racial or sexist preferences should not constitute part of the social good. In a sense, this view is reflected in current antidiscrimination laws. The express limitations on the duties of accommodation discussed above— embodying the notion that the constraint against discrimination has thresholds—do not apply to antidiscrimination norms where compliance does not entail monetary or similar costs. By limiting the application of these limitations to accommodation duties, the law delegitimizes other costs. Objections To CBA Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 57-58 Another possible objection is that even if standard CBA reflects normative judgments, once these judgments have been made, the routine use of CBA requires merely empirical, value-neutral investigations.^^° In response, it should first be noted that many of the normative questions underlying CBA are not yet settled. For example, it is unclear whether the theory of the good underlying standard CBA should be satisfaction of actual preferences or satisfaction of rational or ideal ones.^^' Second, the current state of standard CBA reflects decades of methodological refinement. Constrained CBA may benefit similar academic refmement over time. More precisely, the emergence of methodological conventions regarding the handling of these questions is likely to make the pertinent normative judgments less conspicuous, as has been the case with standard CBA. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES CBA Answers Cont. Agencies Are Restricted Using CBA Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 58-59 As regards regulatory agencies, the requirement to conduct CBA restricts the agencies' discretion and reduces the risk of error.^^^ Authorizing the agencies to engage in philosophical inquiries would arguably broaden their discretion and complicate the oversight process. According to this view, deontological constraints should not be incorporated into CBA, but rather set by other governmental authorities, along with other constraints imposed on agencies.^^"* Indeed, constitutional and institutional considerations dictate that politically accountable bodies such as Congress, rather than regulatory agencies, should construct threshold functions, either mathematical or verbal. It does not follow, however, that-^inasmuch as agencies face decisions involving deontological constraints—these constraints cannot or should not be incorporated into CBA. Once the ethical and policy judgments are made and a threshold function is constructed, the regulatory agencies and other governmental branches may and should routinely employ this function. Agencies specializing in measuring and evaluating costs and benefits are well suited to employ threshold functions requiring assessment of the regulation's harms and benefits. Rather than broadening their discretion, the explicit application of such functions may actually facilitate greater transparency and accountability of agencies' activities. CBA Should Only Be Applied To Market Issues Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 65 Since it is difficult to draw a boundary between a willingness to monetize things such as physical pain and unwillingness to monetize deontological constraints against actively/intentionally harming people, arguably one should either reject money commensuration tout court, or concede to it entirely, at least under appropriate circumstances. A principled anti-monetization implies that CBA and economic methodology should only apply to market issues (and even in this context, they would face considerable difficulties).^^" Taking this position seriously would not only rule out the incorporation of threshold constraints into CBA, but also the very use of CBA in such spheres as health and safety regulation and environmental protection (not to mention family law, criminal law, and human rights). To be sure, a world without economic analysis of nonmarket issues is not inconceivable; it existed only several decades ago and still exists in most parts of the globe. But whatever the normative deficiencies of economic analysis, doing away with CBA as a governmental decision procedure and with economic analysis of law seems most undesirable. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES CBA and Morality CBA On Terrorism Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 51 Answering this question through standard CBA requires comparing the expected direct and indirect consequences of an action against the terrorists with the consequences of inaction, including their expected effects on the motivation of future terrorists and on demoralization.'^" Standard economic analysis does not differentiate between active infliction of harm by the government on a particular group of innocent people and the harm suffered by an as yet unspecified group of innocent people due to the terrorist activity and the government's inaction. This view conflicts with ordinary morality and prevailing constitutional legal norms. CBA Moralizes Preference Theory’s Of Good Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 18 However, neither sophisticated theories of the good, nor the more modest move from actual to ideal preferences, satisfactorily answers the deontological critique.^^ Focusing on the move to ideal preferences, while excluding antisocial preferences indeed reduces the likelihood that purely consequentialist economic analysis would endorse truly deplorable conclusions, it still does not respond to many of the deontologist's concerns. In contrast to deontology and in line with other consequentialist theories, CBA based on ideal preferences would support violating a constraint now to prevent two similar violations in the nature (e.g., murdering one person to prevent two future murders). Furthermore, like the more sophisticated theories of the good, the technique of "laundering" morally objectionable preferences actually aims at imposing constraints on welfare maximization." It is unclear whether an ideal preferences theory of the good can incorporate such distinctions as doing/allowing or intending/foreseeing, but even if it could, the result would be a recognition that threshold constraints are indispensable on the factoral level. Burden Of Proof Using CBA Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 55-56 Burden of Proof In criminal law, the burden of proof determines the ratio between the risk of erroneously convicting an innocent suspect ("false positive") and the risk of erroneously acquitting a criminal ("false negative").For the consequentialist, adjudicative fact-finding needs to minimize the total cost of errors and error-avoidance. Accordingly, the burden of proof should minimize the aggregate costs of the two types of errors.^'^ For instance, if both types impose the same social cost, the optimal decision rule is "preponderance of the evidence," Requiring a higher standard in criminal trials is justified only when the harms generated by false convictions exceed the harms generated by acquittals of guilty criminals.^''' This view ignores, however, notions of injustice of erroneously convicting an innocent person and the individual's right to fairness and equality. These notions may yield a ratio between the two types of errors—and thus a certain burden of proof that exceeds the one endorsed by a standard CBA.^'^ Incorporating a deontological constraint against (risking) false convictions may thus yield a more satisfactory analysis, LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES CBA and Morality Applying Constraints To CBA Is Moral Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 67 Economic analysis of law, and of human behavior in general, is a powerful analytical methodology. At the same time, standard CBA is normatively objectionable on various grounds. This Article focused on the consequentialist aspect of welfare economics, specifically on the lack of constraints on promoting the best outcomes. Moderate deontology is more in accord with commonsense morality and existing legal doctrines, but is less determinate and rigorous. We argued that integrating threshold constraints with costbenefit analysis would overcome both deficiencies, and that it is compatible with, and perhaps even mandated by, the more sophisticated versions of foundational consequentialism. Such integration raises principled and methodological concerns, but we believe that these concerns can all be met. Adding threshold constraints to economic analysis would make it not only normatively more acceptable, but also descriptively more valid, without significantly compromising its methodological rigor. The advantages of constrained CBA are particularly conspicuous in the analysis of non-market spheres, such as constitutional, criminal, tort, and family law, where deontological constraints loom large, but they are significant in market contexts as well. Hopefully, such integration would contribute to bridging the increasing gulf between economic analysis and other approaches to law and legal theory. LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES CBA Is a Versatile Weighing Mechanism Choosing among Permissible Options. Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 27 The models described below aim at determining whether acts or rules infringing a deontological constraint produce a sufficiently large net benefit to override the constraint. At times, this is the sole question facing the decision maker. For example, when a court decides whether a certain statute is constitutional, the only question may be whether the good produced by the statute is large enough to override a certain constraint. In other instances, however, determining whether one or more of the available options violate a deontological constraint is only part of the inquiry. Consider the choice between the following options: (1) deliberately killing two innocent people to save the lives of 280 people (out of 500 facing death); (2) deliberately killing three innocent people to save the lives of 290 (out of the same 500); (3) letting all 500 die. If the threshold of the constraint against actively/intentionally killing innocent people is sufficiently high, only the third option would be permissible. If, alternatively, the threshold is met whenever at least 100 people are saved by killing each person, then options (1) and (3), but not (2), are permissible. The choice between options (1) and (3) may be made using standard CBA, and since option (1) results in net saving of 278 lives and option (3) with the saving of none, option (1) should be chosen. Finally, if the threshold is met whenever killing one person saves at least 90 lives, then all three options are permissible. Using standard CBA to choose among them, option (2) ranks first (net saving of 287 lives), option (1) second (net saving of 278 lives), and option (3) last (no lives saved). In situations like this, the decision process consists of two stages: sorting out those options that do not infringe, or that override, the deontological constraint, and then using standard CBA to choose the one that brings about the best outcomes.'"'' The separation between the two stages is necessary because—as demonstrated below—the factors taken into account in each stage and their interrelations are not similar. CBA Analysis Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 56-57 While conceding the normative flaws of standard CBA, economists may still endorse a division of labor between economic analysis and deontological concerns to preserve the alleged value-free and objective nature of economic analysis. However, as many commentators have long pointed out, the idea that standard CBA is a value-free, "scientific" mode of analysis is false,'^'^ The choice between competing notions of distributive justice within the consequentialist framework (such as mere maximization of utility or a Rawlsian maximum) is anything but value-free. The same is. true regarding the choice of the underlying theory of the good.^'^ Even the Pareto criterion entails non-trivial normative judgments.'^'^ Thus, while adding deontological constraints to economic analysis obviously reflects a normative judgment, disregarding such constraints does so as well. There is nothing more "subjective" in setting objectively defamed constraints to maximizing well-being than in not setting such constraints. The Angle Of CBA Is Looked At May Have Differed Applications Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008, California Law Review, p. 64 From a different angle, the scope of any threshold constraint in a given legal system may (at least theoretically) be derived from a comparison between the existing rules and the rules that would have been set on a purely consequentialist basis. For example, assume (counterfactually) that standard CBA unequivocally calls for breaching contracts whenever performance, is inefficient (the "efficient breach doctrine").^''^ The extent to which existing contract law deviates from the efficient breach doctrine by "excessively" deterring breaches may reflect a deontological constraint against promise breaking. If all other variables are monetized, then one should be able (at least in theory) to extract the money value of the legally imposed constraint as well. Applying CBA To Economic And Social Behavior LD VALUE/CRITERIA FILES Zamir, Eyal and Barak Medina, Professors of Law, 2008 California Law Review, p. 58 A related objection is that even if standard CBA reflects normative judgments, and even if some of these judgments are still debated, economists do not have the philosophical expertise necessary to engage in the moral deliberation required for setting deontological constraints. In considering this argument, one should distinguish between academic use of CBA and its use by governmental agencies. As regards academic analysts and particularly those engaging in economic analysis of law, to the extent that one can distinguish between normative and positive analyses,^^^ constrained CBA is primarily germane to the former; though it may also contribute to positive analysis of people's behavior, influenced by ordinary morality, and of the legal system, embodying such constraints. Inasmuch as economic analysis of law aims to enhance the normative discussion of legal issues, consideration of deontological concerns seems both essential and feasible. Just as mainstream legal theory has embraced the economic perspective, and as mainstream economic analysis of law is gradually embracing the insights of cognitive psychology (the so-called "behavioral law and economics"), there is no compelling reason why economic analysis of law should not pay heed to moral concerns and incorporate them into CBA. Constrained CBA would contribute to the operationality of moderate deontology and may even enrich the philosophical debate about threshold constraints