Response to Betzler and Löschke Simon Keller My book Partiality tells a story about why we should give special treatment to people with whom we share special relationships, even though those people are no more important than other people.1 Why should I favor my own child, when I know that other children matter just as much as her? What reasons do I have sometimes to be partial, rather than impartial? The answer offered in my book is a version of the “individuals view.” It says that the best explanation of our “reasons of partiality” is grounded in the value of the people with whom our special relationships are shared. According to the individuals view, my reason to favor my own child is ultimately to do with her special value, not with how much she matters to me or with the value of our parent-child relationship. I am grateful for the careful criticisms offered by Betzler and Löschke. I will try to answer some questions raised by their commentaries while also giving a decent overall sense of the content of the book. In the first two sections I will explain how I present and respond to the problem of partiality; this will involve pointing to some places in Löschke’s commentary at which I think I am misinterpreted. Then I will go over the two broad views that I reject: the relationships view, which Löschke favors in his commentary, and the projects view, which Betzler develops in hers. The puzzle of partiality The puzzle of partiality is the puzzle of saying why there are special reasons within special relationships: relationships like those between friends, close family 1 Simon Keller, Partiality (Princeton University Press, 2013). 1 members, and romantic partners. It is a puzzle, not because anyone (much) doubts that reasons of partiality exist, but because their existence is difficult to explain within the compelling “impartialist” picture of ethics. On the impartialist picture, all people matter, and they matter because of how they are inherently. No one matters more just because she stands in some relationship to you. From within that picture, special relationships look as though they are morally irrelevant, and it is difficult to see how they could produce special reasons. The question, then, is how to make room for reasons of partiality while retaining whatever is correct about the impartialist picture. There are several different respects in which your being in a special relationship can make a difference to your ethical situation (Partiality, pp. 2-4, 144). I want to mention two of them here. First, if you share a special relationship with someone then you can be permitted to prioritize her over others. Second, if you share a special relationship with someone then you have a moral duty to prioritize her over others. It is one thing to explain special permissions of partiality, another to explain special duties. In identifying ethical questions about special relationships, I speak of the problem of “partiality.” Löschke asks why I do not instead speak of the problem of “agent-relativity,” and why, when I do speak of agent-relativity, I do not do so in the “standard” manner; I do not define agent-relative reasons as always involving ineliminable back-reference to the agent (Löschke, 676-7). The reason why I do not take agent-relativity as my defining topic is it arises in many contexts beyond special relationships. Talk of “partiality” seems better to capture the ethics of special relationships in particular. I characterize agent-relativity as I do in order to give a place in the debate to views on which reasons of partiality can be reduced to agentneutral reasons: most obviously, the utilitarian view that we should give special 2 treatment to our nearest and dearest because that will promote overall utility. In setting up the problem, I wanted to leave open the possibility that the agent-relative nature of partiality can ultimately be explained by deeper agent-neutral considerations. I need to be clear, however, that I eventually reject that possibility. Löschke ascribes to me the claim that all agent-relative reasons can be reduced to agent-neutral reasons, citing an example in which I show how some agent-relative reasons can be so reduced (Löschke, 676-7). His rendering of my view here is misleading. My way of characterizing agent-relativity “allows for the existence of agent-relative reasons that are reducible to agent-neutral reasons” – that is all the example is supposed to illustrate (Partiality, 17). It is not my view that reasons of partiality, or agent-relative reasons generally, are in fact reducible to agent-neutral reasons (Partiality, see especially 127-129 and 150-152). My defense of the individuals view No one has more value than anyone else just because she shares a special relationship with you. The challenge for the individuals view is to say how you can nevertheless have reason to treat a person differently, just in response to her value. My response to the challenge has two elements. First, I argue that persons have a special kind of incommensurable value, from which it follows that once you are exposed to one person’s value, it can make special demands on you, independently of the existence of other similarly structured values (Partiality, 139-144). This explains why you can have permission to give differential treatment to one person once you have become vulnerable to her value, as usually 3 happens within a special relationship. This is what Löschke calls the “particularist” element of my view (Löschke, 678). Second, I argue that social and biological considerations can make it desirable, and sometimes compulsory, for people to respond to the value of some people and not others: for a parent to become vulnerable to the value of her own child rather than a neighbor’s child, for example (Partiality, 144-152). This explains why there are moral duties of partiality and why those duties vary with cultural context. They explain why a parent in a society with family-based parenting practices can have different duties from a parent in a society in which children are raised communally. This second element of the view I would call “universalist.” Löschke calls it “consequentialist,” which I think is a little misleading (Löschke, 679). The wider considerations that determine duties of partiality need not (only) concern overall best consequences; they could also be considerations of individual rights, for example. That, anyway, is the view. It is not supposed to be obvious. The arguments for it are in the book! But let me turn to some of Löschke’s objections. Löschke worries that the view’s universalist element will lead it to say that you should neglect a person with whom you share a special relationship if you can thereby produce greater goods for other people (Löschke, 677-8). I seek to avoid this result in the book by saying that universalist considerations can only tell us to whose special value we ought to become vulnerable. Once you are vulnerable to a particular person’s value, you respond to the person properly by responding to her needs and interests directly, because they are hers. This is the proper response, I argue, because it best acknowledges the incommensurable nature of a person’s value. Universalist considerations might explain why, in this society, you should pay special attention to the self-standing value of your child, in preference to other children. But once you are 4 exposed to your child’s value, it makes demands upon you in its own right, not by way of universalist considerations (Partiality, 139-144, 150-152). As Löschke notes, my view here is, in one sense, particularist. It depends upon the idea that you can respond properly to a person’s value by responding to it in its own right, not as an instantiation of a value held by people in general. But this is different from the kind of particularism that worries Löschke, on which reasons behave unpredictably and do not generate “fixed norms” (Löschke, 679). A person’s value may be deeply particular and it may generate reasons whose character is not derived from any impartial perspective, but still, the value is there, and the reasons it generates can be predictable and systematic. You may not have children, but you may know that if you do have a child, then you should come to love her and take special responsibility for her, and you may know a good deal about what sorts of actions that will require. That involves knowing something about how you should respond to her special value in preference to the similar value of other children, well in advance of actually encountering that value. The book offers a number of arguments for the individuals view, but the main one is the argument from the “phenomenology of partiality.” Using a series of examples, I try to show that when you act well towards another person within a special relationship, you are moved by considerations of her in her own right, not in her capacity as a participant in one of your projects or in one of your relationships. I argue that the experience of acting well towards another person within a special relationship has (defeasible) authority, and hence that if that experience involves treating certain considerations as reasons, then we should conclude (tentatively) that they really are reasons (Partiality, 25-27, 84-96). 5 Löschke doubts that the phenomenology of partiality reveals much about our reasons of partiality. He suggests that it might tell us what reasons we have to act well towards someone to whom we are already partial – “reasons from partiality” – but does not think it can tell us what reasons we have to be partial towards someone in the first place – “reasons for partiality” (Löschke, 680-2). The distinction is well-taken, but we should not assume that reasons from partiality are sharply different from reasons for partiality, or that phenomenological considerations are relevant only to uncovering reasons from partiality. Consider two cases. Imagine, first, a man who sees no reason to treat his own children differently from other children. It may be impossible to change his mind just by arguing with him (Partiality, 151). Perhaps we can explain to him why it makes sense (around here, now) for parents to take special care of their own children, but that will take him only so far. What is more likely to work is to have him spend time with his children, become acquainted with their distinctive perspectives and interests, and become vulnerable to their value as individuals and their own special points of view. It is by having that experience, if I am right, that the father is most likely to find reasons for partiality towards his children, not just reasons from partiality. Imagine, second, that you are losing motivation to act well towards your mother. Perhaps you are feeling annoyed or angry with her, and cannot be bothered making any special effort for her sake. The best way to reinvigorate your motivation in such a case is to renew your acquaintance with your mother, finding a way to escape from yourself and to think more closely of her and her interests (Partiality, 93). This, again, would be an experience of finding reasons for partiality, not just reasons from partiality. There is phenomenological evidence that can be brought to 6 bear on each of Löschke’s questions. If the arguments in my book are correct, then the evidence in both cases supports the individuals view. The relationships view The most popular account of reasons of partiality is the “relationships view,” on which reasons of partiality arise from the self-standing value or reason-giving force of relationships (Partiality, 12-13, 45-48). Löschke supports a version of the view, suggesting that relationships are intrinsically valuable because they contribute directly to the good life, and that they generate special reasons because that is a condition of their existence (Löschke, 679-80). In the book I argue at length against this suggestion, but I want to pick up here on Löschke’s qualification regarding destructive relationships. Destructive relationships, Löschke says, are not intrinsically valuable because they do not contribute to good lives. Whether a relationship contributes to good lives – whether or not it is destructive – depends on what it does for the individuals within the relationship. A friendship characterized mostly by competition and jealousy, for example, might be destructive, because it ultimately makes the two friends less happy and less virtuous. This puts a condition on the value of relationships: a friendship (for example) is valuable only if it contributes in the right ways to the lives of the individuals within the relationship. Once the qualification is in place, the explanation of whether and why a friendship is valuable will always refer back to the value of individuals. Further, in explaining what special reasons, exactly, a particular friendship generates, we will ask how that particular friendship can enhance the lives of the particular individuals within it (Partiality, 97-98). 7 Perhaps there remains a sense in which the value of special relationships can be called “intrinsic.” The crucial point, for my purposes, is that all the important work in determining the normative significance of relationships is done by the value of individuals. Take, for example, Löschke’s claim that a genuinely valuable friendship must involve special duties between the friends. If that is right, then the reason must be that there is some profound contribution to individual lives that can only be made by friendships that involve special duties. The task is then to identify that contribution and explain its significance. The value of individuals remains crucial, and claims about the self-standing significance of relationships become explanatorily redundant, at best. The projects view The projects view says that we have reasons of partiality because we incorporate special relationships within our personal projects. The chapter arguing against the projects view is the shortest of my book. Betzler’s commentary shows that the projects view deserves more careful consideration, and also – I would like to think – that when the projects view is given a more sophisticated expression, it has affinities with the view I defend. In responding to Betzler’s commentary, I will explain how I see the ethical significance of personal projects in light of her remarks, and what connections I see between personal projects and reasons of partiality. Let me start with three cases. Consider first a competitive runner. The runner may desire to improve her best times and to achieve certain placings in her races, and may be committed to the running lifestyle. She may believe that running gives her life meaning and makes her healthier, but those thoughts will not motivate her to go out and train on a cold 8 morning or to push herself harder during a race. She values running not “narcissistically,” but for its own sake (Betzler, 690). She need not, however, take herself to have a duty to run, and she need not be acting wrongly if she stops running. If she were to give up running to pursue other interests, nobody could complain. Does the competitive runner, as described, have running as a project? On Betzler’s conception, it is not clear that she does. The runner has reasons to continue to run, produced by her commitment to running, but they are not reasons it would be wrong for her to ignore (Betzler, 691). Second, consider Betzler’s case of Jacques, who is committed to preserving historic neighborhoods of New Orleans. Like the competitive runner, Jacques has non-narcissistic motives to pursue certain activities over time, and has agent-relative reasons to respond to certain values. The difference is that the value of the historic architecture of New Orleans exists independently of Jacques’ commitment to it. Whatever Jacques thinks or does, the architecture is significant and its preservation matters. Once Jacques comes to understand and respond to its value, he will see reasons why it would be regrettable, at the least, for him to lose his concern for New Orleans architecture and take up other interests instead. That is why there is room to say that it would be wrong for Jacques to ignore the reasons produced by his project. Still, New Orleans’ historic architecture is not the only valuable thing in the world. If Jacques find himself no longer to be affectively engaged by his project, and if he decides, with proper consideration and sensitivity, to change his interests direct his efforts elsewhere, that need not evince any kind of vice. He cannot ignore his reasons, but that does not mean that it would be wrong for him to relinquish his project. Third, consider a variant of the Jacques case. Imagine that Jacques has an obligation, independent of his initial subjective commitments, to become involved in 9 preserving historic neighborhoods of New Orleans. Perhaps his family owns some historic buildings in New Orleans, and perhaps ownership of historic buildings in New Orleans comes with a requirement that owners contribute to the preservation of the city’s architectural character. Imagine that Jacques’ commitment to preserving New Orleans architecture is nevertheless wholehearted. He has a personal project in all the respects explained in Betzler’s version of the example. How are the personal commitments, in the three cases described, like the commitments we have within personal relationships? The commitment of the competitive runner is unlike a commitment you could have to another person, because the values to which the runner responds – running fast, improving her best times, and so on – have value for her only insofar as she cares about them. No person has value only insofar as you care about her. The commitments found in the other two cases, however, do mirror commitments found within personal relationships. As described in Betzler’s original case, Jacques’ commitment to historic New Orleans architecture is structurally similar to the commitment you might have to a romantic partner, for example. You are not obliged to enter into a romantic relationship with anyone in particular – or with anyone at all – but once you are in a romantic relationship, you can come to have special reasons and duties within it. It can be wrong for you simply to abandon the relationship. The value to which you become vulnerable in your romantic partner is real and makes demands on you. Nevertheless, a romantic relationship is valuable partly because it exists as an expression of continuing free choice by both partners. A romantic relationship can end without anyone acting wrongly. The third case, in which Jacques has a pre-existing obligation to commit himself to preserving New Orleans architecture, is similar to cases in which you have 10 a duty to take special care of someone, independently of your pre-existing commitments. You might have a duty to look after your father, for example. To explain how Jacques could have his duty to preserve New Orleans architecture, I needed to imagine a wider social arrangement under which he is given special responsibility for the historic architecture of New Orleans. In the same way, if I am right, we need to go beyond the value of your father – and beyond the relationship you share with your father, considered in isolation – to explain why you could have a duty to prioritize him over other people. We can explain why your father merits special treatment just by understanding his value, but we cannot explain why you are the one to provide that special treatment without looking at a wider social context. There is more to personal projects than I acknowledge in the book. It may be possible to get from an understanding of the normative force of personal projects to an explanation of reasons of partiality. In any such explanation, however, considerations of the value of the objects of personal projects will be central. The nature of the reasons arising from a project depends upon the value of the activities involved in the project. The question of whether it is wrong, and in what sense, to abandon a project depends on the value at the heart of the project and the context within which the agent becomes oriented to that value. When a project concerns a personal relationship, the relevant value is the value of the individuals within the relationship. I think that the projects view can be made most plausible by bringing it within the individuals view. Any account of reasons of partiality will include a story about the normative significance of relationships, and it will say something about why we can and should form certain projects. But underlying and directing the account, I continue to think, must be the self-standing inherent value of individual persons. 11