Notes on Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory by Ian Hacking. Prepared by Andrew D. Cling for PHL/PY 317 Philosophy of Mind Spring 2009 What follows is a summary of some of the main lines of discussion and argument in Hacking’s book. Comments inside brackets—‘[,’ ‘]’—are my own, intended to provoke further reflection. Introduction A chief topic of the book is the attempt to transform the way in which the soul is understood by making it the subject of scientific understanding. The soul is not an unchanging essence or locus of personal identity. Rather, it is “the strange mix of aspects of a person that may be … imagined as inner.” (6) This transformation is closely related to the complex ways in which ways of understanding people interact with the kinds of people who are understood. This has public and private dimensions. [It concerns, among other things, institutions for describing, predicting, explaining, and controlling behavior.] It has implications for the ways in which individuals experience and understand their lives by giving their memories a new organization and new meanings. (6) Chapter One “Is it Real?” Unlike schizophrenia, multiple-personality disorder is not characterized by inappropriate or even bizarre connections between thinking, feeling, and action. In 1980, the diagnostic criteria (individually necessary—conditions that must be satisfied by anyone with the disorder—and jointly sufficient—conditions such that whoever satisfies all of them has the disorder) for multiple-personality disorder specified by the current Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of the American Psychiatric Association, DSM-III were: A. The existence within the individual of two or more distinct personalities, each of which is dominant at a particular time. B. The personality that is dominant at any particular time determines the individual’s behavior. C. Each individual personality is complex and integrated with its own unique behavior pattern and social relationships. (10) In 1987, DSM-III-R was modified to read (significantly, condition C was dropped): A. The existence within the individual of two or more distinct personalities or personality states (each with its own relatively enduring pattern of perceiving, relating to, and thinking about the environment and self). B. At least two of these identities or personality states recurrently take full control of the person’s behavior. (note 10, p. 269) Notes on Hacking’ s Rewriting the Soul, page 2 In 1994, DSM-IV added the condition that the person making the diagnosis must have reason to believe that the patient suffers from amnesia. This reason could either be personally witnessing amnesiac behavior or hearing reports of amnesia made by the patient. By 1994, therefore, memory loss was an official necessary condition of having multiple-personality disorder. (10, see pp. 19, 22) Multiple personality disorder is real in the sense that there are people who satisfy the specified conditions. The question ‘Is it real?’ is unclear, however. Following Austin, we should recognize that definite sense attaches to such a question only if two conditions are satisfied: (i) ‘it is real’ is replaced by ‘it is a real N’ or ‘it is real N’ where the ‘N’ is to be replaced by some noun, and (ii) there is a clear sense of one way in which the thing designated by ‘it’ might not be or might not have been a real N. (11) So, we might ask, is multiple personality a real psychiatric entity, a real biomedical disease entity, or a real disorder? [Consider, in this context, the different terms used for objects of psychiatric interest: ‘disease,’ ‘defect,’ ‘malfunction,’ ‘disorder,’ et cetera. What does each of these suggest about how to think about what is being described? ‘Disease’ suggests that the person with it suffers, whereas ‘disorder’ suggests a kind of less-than-ideal disorganization. ‘Malfunction’ suggests that something is not up to performing its proper function. Are these the same? It seems not, for it seems that one might be unable to perform one’s proper function but not suffer for it, for example. This is important for Hacking since, as he notes later, “[n]ames organize our thoughts.” (17) See also Hacking’s discussion of ‘disorder’ on p. 17.] Multiple personality is not normally iatrogenic (=caused by the interaction of physicians and patients). We should reject the notion that there is a useful distinction between being real and being the product of specific historical or social circumstances. [Chattel slavery was real, for example, despite the fact that it can exist only against the backdrop of historically located social, political, and economic institutions. But does it make sense to wonder whether the distribution of the underlying personality patterns that are necessary conditions for having multiple personality is relatively constant across different societies, whether or not the ways in which those personality patterns are expressed might vary from society to society? If so, wouldn’t this be evidence that multiple personality is a real non-socially-determined personality pattern as opposed to a pattern of thinking, feeling, and behaving that is created and sustained by specific social practices and institutions?]. The major theme of this book is the relations between “multiplicity, memory, discourse, knowledge, and history.” (12) There are two ways to classify mental disorders: (i) by means of observable symptoms (how they look), and (ii) by means of theories about what causes the disorders. (12) The DSMs classify disorders by their symptoms and thus leave open the question of the causes of those symptoms. This is one way in which the question is it real? is left open by DSM. [Why? Because things that are alike with respect to their observable properties might be very different with respect to their underlying causes. Having a rash, for example, might be caused by contact with a poisonous plant or by infection. One way in which a type can be real is by being the sort of thing that is produced by a common cause. Types that are picked out only by symptoms might not be real disease entities in the sense that there is a single underlying cause of that cluster of symptoms. This doesn’t make the symptoms or the accompanying suffering unreal, however.] One way in which we can be confident that a thing is real is by understanding its causes. Another way is by Notes on Hacking’ s Rewriting the Soul, page 3 being able to “intervene and change it.” (12) [These are related: if we know the cause of something, we might have an idea about how to control it by preventing it or eliminating it once it has come into existence, and if we learn how to control something, that knowledge can provide us with clues about its cause.] What therapy is appropriate for multiple personality disorder? Should therapists encourage the personality states of a multiple to become integrated, or should all of the personality states of a multiple be encouraged to manifest themselves [to facilitate understanding, e.g.]? (12–13) “[D]isease and disorder are identified according to an underlying vision of health of humanity, of what kinds of being we are, and what can go wrong with us. That is why … the multiple personality field is so full of models of dissociation.” (13) [‘Dissociation’ refers to the failure of different psychological states or processes to be appropriately connected to one another. So when a person “spaces out” and cannot remember what has happened for a span of time when he or she was otherwise awake and conscious, there is mild dissociation: data normally available to memory is not. Dissociation becomes pathological when it inhibits proper order, proper functioning, or causes significant distress to the subject of dissociation. The presence within the same body of distinct personalities or personality states that are not psychologically integrated in a normal way—for example, by significant memory failures—would be an extreme form of dissociation.] The standard theory of multiple personality is that it is caused by repeated childhood trauma, often the result of sexual abuse. According to this theory, the mind dissociates itself from the trauma by creating an alternative personality (an alter) which contains a memory of the trauma to which the original personality lacks access. (13) [In a review of Hacking’s book in Philosophy of Science, Lynn Stephens asks whether this mechanism is not too complex: if the experience of trauma is given to a distinct personality, why must it also be forgotten? In fact, notes Stephens, sometimes multiples cannot remember traumatic events and sometimes they are remembered, but as the experiences of someone else. What needs to be explained is this curious combination of amnesia and alienation. A theory of memory alone cannot, says Stephens, suffice for understanding the curious symptom of recollecting traumatic events as not being one’s own trauma (see Philosophy of Science, 1997, 185–187).] According to the standard theory, the memories of trauma can be recovered in therapy using such techniques as hypnosis. However, many recovered memories are of ritual satanic abuse and there is no corroborating evidence of widespread ritual satanic abuse. This has caused doubt about whether other recovered memories are false memories. Debate about multiple personality has thus taken on a distinctive moral component. It is common for persons to be given more than one psychiatric diagnosis. In such cases, the diagnostician may judge that one of the disorders—the superordinate disorder—is the underlying cause of the others—the subordinate disorders. Skeptics and advocates of multiple personality disorder frequently disagree about whether it is the superordinate (advocates) or subordinate (skeptics) disorder. Hacking’s interest is not about whether multiple personality is real in any of these deeper senses, but about a collection of ideas about persons and memory came into being and how it has affected human experience, customs, and scientific understanding. (16) This is important because “[n]ames organize our thoughts.” (17) In 1994 DSM-IV replaced ‘Multiple Personality Disorder’ with ‘Dissociative Identity Disorder.’ (17) This represents a shift of focus among some who study multiple personality from separate, integrated personalities to Notes on Hacking’ s Rewriting the Soul, page 4 aspects of personality, consciousness, and memory that are not fully integrated. On this view, the problem is not that there are too many personalities but there is less than one. (18) In the 1994 DSM-IV the official diagnostic criteria became these: A. The presence of two or more distinct identities or personalities or personality states (each with its own relatively enduring pattern of perceiving, relating to, and thinking about the environment and self). B. At least two of these identities or personality states recurrently take control of the person’s behavior. C. Inability to recall important personal information that is too extensive to be explained by ordinary forgetfulness. D. The disturbance is not due to the direct physiological effects of a substance (e.g. blackouts or chaotic behavior during Alcohol Intoxication) or a general medical condition (e.g., complex partial seizures). Note: In children the symptoms are not attributable to imaginary playmates or other fantasy play. (19) Two constants across all of the changes in diagnostic criteria are the importance of memory and of childhood pain. Therapy for multiple personality or dissociative identity is to be centered on the recovery of memories of trauma experienced in childhood. (20) Why do all sides take it for granted that an understanding of memory is the key to understanding the soul? Chapter Two “What is it Like?” An important feature of human social behavior is the “looping effect of human kinds.” [This is a feedback mechanism whereby what one person S1 thinks about another S2 affects what S1 does and says about S2 which, in turn affects what S2 thinks, which affects what S2 says and does, which, again, affects what S1 thinks, and so on (adapted from Daniel T. Gilbert, “Attribution and Interpersonal Perception”). So we have a loop from the thinking and behavior of one person to the thinking and behavior of another and back to the thinking and behavior of the first person, and so on.] This looping effect is particularly potent in therapeutic relationships because persons tend to speak and act as they are expected to by persons in authority, therapists e.g. (21) The phenomena of multiple personality are described very differently by proponents and skeptics. It is difficult to describe individual persons and even more difficult to describe kinds of persons. The DSMs attempt to describe multiple personality by means of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions. Yet amnesia, condition C in the DSM-IV criteria, is usually, but not always, present in cases of multiple personality. So it is not a true necessary condition. In general, we are able to use general terms without a grasp of the necessary and sufficient conditions for a thing’s falling under those terms. Satisfying a cluster of symptoms is sufficient. Wittgenstein suggested that many general terms apply to objects in virtue of “family resemblances” and not because of necessary and sufficient conditions. Theoretical linguists describe the structure of categories in terms of a prototype: types are structured by a thing in the type that is exemplary of what it is to be an instance of the type (e.g. robin is the prototypical bird, but ostrich is not). Objects fall into the type depending upon their degrees of similarity, along numerous axes, to the prototype. Instances of the type are not arranged along a Notes on Hacking’ s Rewriting the Soul, page 5 single axis: the structure is better described as ‘radial.’ (24) Thinking of psychiatric kinds as prototypes is exemplified by the Casebook that is a companion to DSM. “One can make a very strong argument, in the philosophy of language, that what people understand by a word is not a definition, but a prototype and the class of example structurally arranged around the prototype.” (24) During the 1980s the prototype of a multiple was of a middle class white woman in her 30s who comes for treatment for severe depression and has lots of missing time from her narrative accounts. There may be foggy memories of troubling events, flashbacks, severe mood swings, and bad hallucinations. She has problems with alcoholism or drug addiction and has volatile intimate relationships. She has a large number of alters, about 16, including child alters, helpers, and at least one male alter. She was sexually abused while she was a child. She cannot remember significant portions of her past and frequently “comes to” with no memory of the recent past. She is depressed and often thinks of suicide (see summary of prototype on p. 33). The alternative personalities of a multiple—the alters—are typically quite different in personality, outlook, and even gender from the “host” personality. Some alters are aware of the others, some are not. Some therapists think that introducing alters to one another is required in order to integrate the personality. During the 1970s, the standard etiology of multiple personality was introduced. According to this account, multiple personalities are formed in a single person as a defense against remembering childhood trauma, especially the trauma of sexual abuse. Multiples are highly suggestible and are easily hypnotized. Most persons who satisfy the DSM criteria undergo trance states. Chapter 17 “An Indeterminacy in the Past” Different sentences describing actions can vary in truth value (true, false) even if the only difference between them is that they contain different terms for the same things. For example, even if the minister is the Cuban spy, it can be true that Frank intended to give $1500 to the minister but false that Frank intended to give $1500 to the Cuban spy. Hacking thinks that some sentences describing intentional actions are indeterminate: they can lack truth value (true, false) at one time but have truth value at a later time. His key argument for this is given on pp. 249–250 of Rewriting the Soul. Here is my attempt to reconstruct that argument: (1) A statement describing an action has a truth value (=is true or false) only if the terms that appear in the statement describing the action are available at the time the action is described. (2) Some statements describing actions include terms that are not available at the time the action is performed but are available later. (3) ∴Some statement describing actions do not have a truth value (= are neither true nor false) at the time the described actions are performed but are true (or Notes on Hacking’ s Rewriting the Soul, page 6 false) at a later time. (4) If the terms appearing in a statement D describing an action A are not available at the time A occurs and it is not inevitable that those terms will ever be available, then statement D is indeterminate at the time the action it describes occurs. (5) Some statements describing actions contain terms that are not available at the time the actions occur and it is not inevitable that those terms will ever be available. (6) ∴ Some statements describing actions are indeterminate at the time of the action. [If (1) and (2) were true, then (3) would have to be true. The same goes for the second argument: if (4) and (5) are true, (6) must be true. The key argument is the inference from (1) and (2) to (3). If (3) is false, then either (1) is false, (2) is false, or both. The key claim in this argument is (1). What is the evidence for (1)? I take it that a key piece of evidence is provided by the fact that some action descriptions are true and others are false even if the objects or states of affairs described are the same or necessarily connected. So, for example, even if my sawing a board in half is necessarily connected with my damaging a table (these events are the same or necessarily connected) it might be true that I intentionally sawed a board in half but false that I intentionally damaged the table. This indicates that the truth value (truth, falsehood) of an action description depends not only on the features of the event that are partly constitutive of the action, but also upon the way in which the action is understood by the agent. So if the type of action an agent performs is partly determined by the way in which that action is understood, and an agent can come to understand his or her actions differently after a passage of time—as a result of the availability of new terms for describing those actions—descriptions of actions that lack truth value at one time can have truth value later. So, for example, it might not be true in 1960 that in 1960 Sally’s father is a child abuser but it might be true in 2009 that in 1960 Sally’s father was a child abuser. Question: Can a single statement describing an action lack truth value for one person but have truth value for another person at the same time? Suppose one person has, but the other lacks, access to the relevant descriptions at that time. If so, then not only does Hacking’s view imply that propositions that lack truth value at one time can have truth value at another time, but it implies that a given proposition can both have and lack a truth value at a single time. To whom must the relevant descriptive terms be available? If a term is never available to an agent, can that term ever be used in a true description of that agent’s intentions? Is it only agents who can learn to truly redescribe their own earlier actions in new terms?]