KNO WLEDGE OF THE PAST 1. A skeptical argument: A. The nature of knowledge. What we know is normally expressed in terms of declarative sentences, often set in a “that” clause: I know (that) Jean Chretien is Prime Minister. I know (that) the room we’re in is TH 103. Tony Blair knows (that) his government exaggerated the evidence of Iraqi WMDs. The “that” clause indicates what the subject of the sentence knows (sometimes we say it specifies the content of what’s known). Knowledge must meet three conditions: i. Belief: To know something, you must believe it—if you don’t believe these things, you don’t know them. (Sometimes, when the evidence is finally in, someone will say “I just knew it,” when in fact they weren’t at all sure in advance. But this is not literally true—they didn’t know (perhaps they suspected, or feared, or hoped; but none of these states of mind constitutes knowledge). ii. Truth: We cannot know what isn’t true. We can believe things that are false, of course, and be very confident about them, too (and sometimes people express such confidence by saying that they know), but in the end, if it isn’t true, we don’t know it, no matter how confident we are about it. iii. Justification: We cannot know something just by guessing at the truth and getting lucky. We need to have good (sufficient) reason for our beliefs before they can count as knowledge. These three conditions are required, but not sufficient for knowledge, as a very interesting class of examples illustrates. But our argument doesn’t need a definition of knowledge—all it requires is some details about the justification condition. Justification, it is often said, cannot be circular. That is, if I know that p (for some declarative sentence p), then I need a justification for p; last time we described this justification as some further declarative sentences that I know and that constitute(s) a sufficient justification for p. Call these sentences q, q',… Then my justification for p is circular if my justification for one or more of q, q',… depends on being justified in believing p. The problem is obvious—if my justification of p depends on my being justified in believing q, and my justification of q depends on my being justified in believing q, then both justifications are in question. I haven’t really justified either yet. B. Evidence about the past. There are all kinds of things we claim to know about the past; if we’re right about these claims, there must be some way of justifying them. Consider a few things I know about the past: I had a bagel for breakfast this morning. John F. Kennedy was assassinated in 1963. Aristotle taught Alexander the Great. The Sumerians developed the cuneiform system of writing. Glaciers spread across northern Europe and North America within the last 20,000 years. Trilobites were arthropods that thrived during the Paleozoic era. How do I justify these claims? The answers are obvious at first—I remember eating the bagel, and I remember JFK’s assassination and that it took place during the year I was in grade 2. I’ve read about Aristotle and his place in the Macedonian court, which is well-known to ancient history types and well documented. Similarly, I’ve read about cuneiform writing (and its roots in simple accounting techniques). I’ve both directly seen evidence of glaciation (striations, polished pavements, kettle lakes, moraines, drumlins, etc.) and read a lot about the evidence, its history, and the conclusions geologists have drawn from it. Finally, I’ve seen fossils of trilobites and read about them as well; their place in the geological column is secure, and their status as arthropods is likewise firmly established. Is there anything in common amongst these justifications? Here’s something—they all depend on assumptions about processes linking the present situation to some fact(s) about the past: When I talk about what I remember, I assume that there is some process connecting my present memory to the facts I am remembering. Something happened (I ate a bagel, JFK was assassinated) and I was or became aware of it (my senses detected it, in the first case; I heard it over the radio in the second), and that awareness left a persistent trace (a memory) that remains in me today, a trace that somehow encodes information about what happened that I am able to understand. When I talk about documented historical events, different processes are involved, but the same pattern occurs: a present trace encodes information about a past event because of a process linking that event (or certain facts about it) to the present existence and features of the trace. And the same goes for geological evidence and the conclusions we draw from it. C. The Skeptical Argument. Now we’re ready to see the problem. Processes take place over time— any knowledge we have about processes is knowledge about the past. So to justify my knowledge claims about the past, I need more than just knowledge of the present traces. I also need knowledge of the processes that have produced them—that is, I need knowledge of the past to justify knowledge claims about the past. We are stuck in a circle—to justify a claim about the past, we must already know something about the past. So if our knowledge about the past must be founded exclusively on knowledge about the present, we can’t have any knowledge of the past at all. This leads directly to a kind of radical skepticism about the past: No matter what the present facts we now observe are, we cannot justify inferring anything about what has happened before now. D. Responding to skeptics. This kind of circle is a familiar phenomenon. It goes back more than 2000 years, to Diodorus, who proposed an argument called “the wheel”. For Diodorus, the puzzle was about knowledge of truth. There are certain sentences that we take to be true. If someone asks us how we can tell that they are true, we need to provide some criterion that we use to separate truths from falsehoods. But if they then ask how we know that this is a good criterion, we are faced with a difficult choice: Either there is some higher-order (meta-) criterion that this criterion satisfies (and they will surely ask how we know that criterion is a good one), or the criterion is a good one because it reliably picks out sentences we know are true (and they will surely point out that we invoked the criterion in the first place to defend our commitment to the sentences, so surely it’s cheating if we now, circularly, appeal to the sentences to defend the criterion). Here is a diagnosis of the problem: If we assume that we’re starting from zero, we’re in trouble. And so we should be. If we don’t have any idea of what’s true, of what it takes to be true or how to tell if a sentence is true, then we can’t “bootstrap” our way to a defensible account. You can’t find something unless you have some idea of how to tell when you’ve found it! But if we start with a reasonable (if partial, flawed and fallible) account of some things that are true and some ways of deciding what’s true and what isn’t, then we’ve got something we can build on. The same goes for knowledge of the past. If we start with no idea of what processes have taken place in the past, then nothing we observe now can justify conclusions about the past. But if we start with some ideas about what processes have produced various features of the world around us, and compare and test these against the “traces” we find in the world around us, then we can evaluate our claims about the past. The evaluation turns on the coherence and vindication of the accounts we give. Coherence requires a nice fit between all the various aspects of the story we tell—what we observe about present traces and what we say about the processes they are traces of must fit together; the traces must be the sort of traces (and arranged in the sorts of ways) we would expect the processes to produce. (This is the virtue that drives theoretical work, in which we try to invent hypotheses that will explain the evidence.) Vindication requires a little bit more—to vindicate our views, we must apply them successfully—for instance, by making predictions about features of the traces we expect to observe, given our present commitments about processes, and then observe the predicted features. (This is the virtue that drives empirical work, in which we test the hypotheses theorists come up with.) Processes: Let’s list some of the main processes that are central to geological thinking about the earth. As we read through the history, we’ll see many examples of models of these processes (and others, which have fallen by the wayside in geological thinking), together with arguments about how well or poorly these models fit the evidence (i.e. traces) they are meant to account for: Erosion (See especially Hutton, Lyell) Sedimentation/Deposition (see Steno) Formation of rocks & minerals (see Werner, von Buch, Desmarest, Hutton) Fossilization (see Steno, Leonardo, Volcanic activity (see Guettard, Desmarest, …) Orogeny (mountain building) (see de Beaumont, Agassiz, Darwin) Formation of valleys (see Scrope, Cuvier (?), de Beaumont, …) Glaciation (see Peraudin, Venetz, Charpentier, Agassiz, et al.) … Many authors have drawn lines between what are called the historical sciences and the lab, or theoretical sciences. The historical sciences include geology together with paleontology and the application of evolution to account for the history of life, while the lab sciences include physics and chemistry. Creationists have emphasized this distinction, arguing that there is a greater degree of uncertainty about the results of the historical sciences because (at least in most cases) “there are no witnesses to the events they describe,” while the theories of the lab sciences are directly tested (even “proven”) by measurements we can witness today. But this is a serious mistake, as a little thought will tell you. For instance, we have a powerful theory of electromagnetic radiation, embodied in Maxwell’s equations. This theory is a paradigmatic example of a lab science. We have tested this theory over and over again, and (aside from the subtleties of quantum mechanics, which lead to important modifications for small-scale processes) it is as wellconfirmed and reliable as any theory we have. One important result of this theory is that the speed of light turns out to be a fixed quantity, related to the electromagnetic properties of empty space. Similarly, the constancy of spontaneous decay rates for various isotopes is a wellestablished lab result, backed up by a rich theoretical understanding of the quantum mechanical processes involved in such decay. But as soon as we apply these important results from the lab sciences to the world around us, we obtain results that many creationists find unacceptable—and a typical response is to reject these well-supported lab results. Thus, to explain the fact that stars millions of light years away are visible to us, some creationists have proposed that the speed of light was much higher in the past than it is today (others have proposed a version of the 5-minute hypothesis, in which the light we see from these stars was already almost here when the universe was created about 6,000 years ago). And to explain away the results of radioactive dating (which, I might add, coheres beautifully with the independently developed geological time scale), some propose that decay rates are not constant after all, and were much higher in the past. In fact, the purported epistemic difference between the lab and the historical sciences is an illusion. First, with respect to testing our ideas about the past, witnesses are nothing special. In fact, the memories of witnesses are often less reliable (by the standards of coherence and vindication) than other sorts of evidence—the evidence of fingerprints and DNA tests in criminal investigations; the evidence of archeological investigations (which sometimes serve to correct historical reports)… Second, the lab sciences progress by developing extremely general theories of the basic processes that go on in the world—processes like gravitational accelerations and mechanical motions in general, nucleosynthesis in stars (pioneered by Fred Hoyle), chemical changes and their relation to temperatures, pressures and other important physical variables, and so on. Such theories are always vulnerable, since they make so many predictions about what has gone on, and what will go on in the future. Our conviction that these theories are well tested and reliable reflects a reasonable standard of proof for science— but it’s a standard that the historical sciences of geology and biology also meet. The standard I’m talking about here combines two features: 1. Coherence, that is, the processes and principles we accept must fit together coherently with the observations we make (and vice-versa: observations are not open-and-shut proofs; in fact they are often unreliable, and we spend a lot of time establishing the reliability of various kinds of observations, for example, when we develop new instruments for particle physics. 2. Vindication; when we reason with our commitments and reach conclusions about what we should expect to observe or to happen in various new circumstances, we are vindicated when our expectations are fulfilled (when our intervention is successful). Rationalism and Empiricism. (September 16, 2003) The point here is to consider just what really goes on in science—we have these two opposed positions, empiricist and rationalist; the empiricists (Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume (and Bacon)) emphasize the role of observation in scientific knowledge, while the rationalists emphasize our a priori grasp of certain basic principles that must be our guide in reasoning about the world (principles like “every event must have a cause.”) Coherence and vindication provide a kind of combination of these two views. Coherence makes little sense in a purely empirical approach, since any observation stands alone and isolated. Vindication is not much of a concern to the rationalists, since their principles are known a priori and not subject to examination, criticism or change. On to Hutton and Werner—a brief review of their positions & methods (combining observation with principles, looking for coherence and vindication): Neither is a pure empiricist, though both cloak their work in the rhetoric of empiricism. The Arguments: (September 18, 2003) Rhetoric and cheap shots vs. Serious arguments—looking at their roles in science. The main claim: For reasons that are quite interesting and worth looking into, but which we will not go into here, the serious arguments, that is, the evidence and the conclusions drawn from that evidence, do dominate the development of scientific positions (at least over time). But, like any other group of people competing for prestige, authority and other important resources, scientists in general, and the figures we will be studying, do not rely solely on the power of evidence and careful argument—rhetoric, personal attacks, ad hominems, subtle put downs & etc. Consider the quotes we have here—they range from direct personal attacks, to subtle denigration, to concrete claims and arguments based on them. Outcomes (with a caution re whig history): Hutton is right on basalt, granite, angular unconformities (and their implications for the vast duration of geological time). Werner is right on the need for a real universal stratigraphy, on much of the detailed mineralogy, on the formation of some veins by precipitation from water. But he is drastically wrong about the relation between rock types and stratigraphy, as the subsequent development of biostratigraphy by Cuvier and Brogniart in France and Smith in England would show. II. Catastrophists and Uniformitarians. This debate takes on a more professional, scientific air than the previous, acrimonious and often highly polemic and personal debates between Wernerians and Huttonians. But it is extremely intense for all that. A. Methods vs. Systems Uniformitarian method involves applying detailed studies of present processes (volcanic activity, earthquakes, erosion, sedimentation, etc.) to the interpretation of the geological record. The uniformitarian system is a doctrine to the effect that uniformitarian methods will suffice. That is, the interpretation of the geological phenomena doesn’t require anything more than present processes operating at present rates. Catastrophism, as a method, invokes immense forces and violent events to interpret some important features of the geological record (such as the extinctions of groups of fossil species, the contorted and metamorphosed rocks making up mountainous regions, large beds of gravel and rocks apparently transported great distances) The catastrophist system is the doctrine that we need such violent events in order to make sense of the geological record. Progressivism (or directionalism) is the view that geological processes have become less rapid and violent over time. This is compatible with catastrophism, but many actualists (such as Scrope) agree that the intensity and rates of geological processes have gradually reduced over time, while maintaining that the processes themselves remain fundamentally the same. This leads to the following table of positions: Principles of Uniformity (i.e. what is taken to be uniform over time): Nothing (supernaturalism). No basis for inferring past events from present evidence, since anything, including creation ex nihilo, is a possibility. If God is omnipotent, and does not observe any limitations in how she goes about her business, we have no evidence at all regarding the past (except perhaps by means of revelation—but of course we then face the problem of deciding which revelation is the right one). Basic Laws (laws of physics & chemistry, roughly). Catastrophists held that these basic laws have remained in place, but that the conditions under which they operate (and therefore the processes that have occurred) have changed dramatically in the course of geological time. In particular, they claimed that certain dramatic features of the geological record (mountain ranges, deep cut valleys, massive deposits of gravel, deep beds of conglomerate rock) record rapid, large, extremely violent events that have no parallel in our present experience. An important worry for such views is that we cannot give detailed predictions about what we should observe, since we cannot make the necessary calculations to determine what the results of such violent and complex processes would be. So, while they are in principle tenable hypotheses about geological history, they are hard to test. Names: Cuvier, Brogniart, de Beaumont, Buckland, Sedgwick (these last two shifted more towards actualism over time). Geological Processes. Actualists hold that the geological processes presently occurring (volcanic activity, earthquakes, erosion by wind and water, etc.) are responsible for the geological record we observe. This has the important methodological advantage that we can study these processes, and the traces they leave, in great detail right now. As a result, we can test particular hypotheses regarding the processes responsible for particular features very thoroughly. Names: Scrope, Conybeare, Whewell. Geological processes and their rates and intensities. Uniformitarians hold both the processes and their rates have been constant. (So uniformitarians are actualists who reject directionalism/progressivism, the view—widely popular in the 19th century—that as the earth cools and ages, the intensity and rate of geological processes is slowly declining. They may accept that in fact the earth is cooling, but hold that this has made no difference to geological processes over the period of time covered by the geological record we now see (an echo here of Hutton’s “no vestige of a beginning…” remark). The advantage, of course, is that we can make even more detailed predictions, since present processes operating at present rates should leave traces that resemble traces presently forming in all relevant details. The disadvantage is that there is no a priori reason why the assumption should hold. Names: Lyell, Darwin. (Many others were sympathetic, but more impressed by uniformitarian methods than doctrine.) The debate: Prevost’s work cast significant doubt on the sudden and violent nature of transitions between marine, terrestrial and fresh-water environments in the Paris Basin. Attempts by Buckland and others to link particular observations (bones buried with gravel in caves, both in Europe and elsewhere around the world) to the Noachian flood were cast in doubt by the growing recognition that it was presumptuous at best to ascribe such scattered phenomena to a single event. Violent, catastrophist models of the flood such as Elié de Beaumont’s suggestion that the sudden elevation of the Andes could have produced a tidal wave that overwhelmed the entire world, were overturned by Scrope’s observations of loose scoriae that pre-date present river valleys (the Loire) in central France. They were further undermined by Darwin’s observations of an earthquake on the Chilean coast, and his persuasive extension of these observations to a model of the gradual elevation of the Andes. More than anything else, the ongoing success of actualist/uniformitarian methods (Scrope in central France, Lyell on Etna, on freshwater marls, and on tertiary stratigraphy, Darwin on the Andes and coral atolls) pushed geologists to broader and increasingly successful actualist and uniformitarian accounts of more and more geological phenomena. The next chapter deals with a family of phenomena that resisted satisfactory treatment for some time. But the most dramatic and persistent problem for Lyell was not a specifically geological phenomenon. It was the fossil record, with its clear pattern of change through time. More modern looking animals, plants, etc. appear as geological time ranges from the Paleozoic to the Cenozoic. There is an arrow of time here, an arrow that is indispensable to the working geologist. But Lyell’s uniformitarianism, strictly read, allows for no such arrow: conditions, on average, ought to be more or less the same throughout geological history, if he is right. Reconciling this uniformity with the pattern of life’s development over time was a problem to which Lyell had no satisfactory response. (One response he did try was to suggest that there were cycles of conditions & climate that could repeat themselves, along with the life-forms that were suited to them—so that, in the long run, even the arrow of life’s development was really a closed circle. But of course he had no evidence to support this suggestion.) Methods: The use of fossil correlation is crucial to the development of geology in this period. Fossil content of formations is used by Lyell to separate the tertiary into the Eocene, Miocene, Pliocene and … Fossils are used by Cuvier and Brogniart to map out the formations of the (tertiary) Paris Basin and establish the repeated sequences of terrestrial/fresh water/marine environments recorded there. Fossils guided William Smith in the preparation of the first detailed geological maps of England. These maps were refined and extended to older formations in Wales, where the Cambrian, Ordovician and Silurian were established by Murchison, Sedgwick and Lapworth: After a difficult controversy arose over the initial overlap of the systems proposed by Murchison and Sedgwick, Lapworth applied a careful examination of the fossils found in the rocks of these systems to distinguish them into three separate systems. Remark on Hutton: In some respects Hutton’s views sound catastrophist—his talk of the huge forces and violence involved in uplift/collapse (a key part of Huttonian cycles) contrasts sharply with Lyell’s view of uplift and subsidence as gradual processes taking place all around us even now. But there is an important difference. Cuvier says that the “thread of operations is broken,” by which he seems to imply that the processes he claims to have occurred in the past are no longer in operation at all—but for Hutton, these violent processes are quiescent, but still in place, and though we have yet to witness them, in time (oh dear!) we will. What’s Uniform Advantages Supernaturalism Catastrophism Actualism Nothing Basic Laws Geological Processes No limits, therefore immune from test & refutation. Disadvantages Ditto. No basis for doing science. Uniformitarianism Geological Processes and Their Rates Any process Can study Can study present allowed by present processes in detail basic physics processes to and apply it all to and chemistry help reading the is grist for the interpret the geological record. mill. geological record. Hard to model Present There may be complex processes events in the past processes no may not be that just won’t fit; longer enough. problem of occurring, If rates vary identifying therefore hard a lot, may average rates, to apply, test be hard to how much or vindicate interpret. variation. The Ice Age: There are a number of interesting geological phenomena that were poorly understood in the 1820’s and 30’s. These included complex beds of varied sediments, unsorted debris now called “till,” parallel grooves carved in the bedrock of some areas, and (most dramatically) erratic boulders, some of immense size, scattered across the countryside, that had apparently traveled large distances from their place of origin. These had been attributed to the Noachian deluge by the diluvialists, but their models of the flood were loose and largely hand-waving, and provided no testable account of these phenomena. But even as the notion of a single, universal flood was dropped, appeals to massive and violent flooding to explain some of these phenomena persisted. Lyell and others proposed an alternative, based on a period of higher sea level combined with cooler climate: the drift hypothesis. Icebergs were supposed to have carried loads of material, including sediments and erratics, and dropped them as they melted, following currents and often lodged against the bottom where the waters grew shallow. A radical alternative emerge in the late 1830’s—the glacial theory. (Hutton anticipated this account in some respects, but only in passing.) The theory was first suggested in something like its present form by a chamois hunter, Jean-Pierre Perraudin, who had reached his conclusions about 1815. An engineer, Ignace Venetz, was sympathetic to his views, and traced evidence of former glacial action still further from their present haunts. Venetz first presented his views at a meeting of a natural history society in 1821, and continued to pursue his investigations through the 1820’s, announcing an extended and expanded vision of the glacial theory in 1829. Though generally rejected out of hand, the theory was taken up by Jean de Charpentier, who was yet another step up the pecking order: director of a salt mine, and a well-respected naturalist. In 1834, in Lucerne, Switzerland, Charpentier read a paper announcing his results, and crediting Venetz’ pioneering work. He invoked glacial action to account for polished and striated rock surfaces, erratics and other phenomena. One skeptic in the audience was Louis Agassiz, a brilliant and energetic protégé of Cuvier’s who had made his reputation with a massive work on the anatomy of fossil fish. A friend of Charpentier’s, Agassiz traveled with Charpentier in the summer of 1836, looking at glacial phenomena in the Diablerets and Rhone Valley. Dubious at first, he was finally converted. As a student of Cuvier’s, Agassiz was strongly inclined to view these phenomena in catastrophist terms. He went on to propose an extremely fanciful and dramatic account of the “ice age” (die Eiszeit—the term is due to Karl Schimper). Though he acknowledged Charpentier’s priority, his immense energy and enthusiasm led him, more than Charpentier, to be identified as the chief proponent of the glacial theory; this led to a serious rift between Agassiz and his old friend. Again, the general reaction to the idea was skeptical. This time, though Agassiz fame and energy failed to convince in the lecture hall, they at least persuaded many leading geologists to examine the evidence. And again, a good look at the field evidence was widely (though never universally) convincing. Agassiz’ book on the ice age appeared in 1840; Charpentier’s much more carefully argued case appeared a year later. (Other names here: Bernhardi—northern Germany; Esmark—Norway.) In 1840 Agassiz traveled to England, where he worked assiduously at converting prominent English geologists to the glacial theory. He caused “a great stir,” though not a total conversion. And many geologists on both sides of the debate turned their attention to the evidence for glacial action in the British Isles. By 1846, Agassiz had gone on to North America to continue his glacial campaign. By 1844, glacial theory was triumphant in its homeland of Switzerland. Lyell was not persuaded fully until 1857. The continued opposition to glacial action as an account of striations, polished surfaces and till deposits (by the younger de Luc and Murchison) was greatly undermined when a dam burst, investigated by T.F. Jamieson (published 1862), failed to produce any such phenomena. This is a wonderful case study in the development, promotion and final acceptance of a once-radical hypothesis. As Hallam points out, the wilder aspects of Agassiz’ account probably delayed the theory’s acceptance; uncertainties over the physics of ice-flow over nearly horizontal terrain, over exactly how ice could polish and striate rocks (the importance of the rocks carried within the glacier as giving it teeth was not immediately obvious), and over the significance of marine shells found in glacial till (finally identified as erratics in their own right, by Croll and Tiddeman), also delayed general acceptance. By the 1870’s, acceptance was more or less universal, and a new and recent chapter added to our geological histories. This also leads to a worthwhile philosophical discussion, about the nature of facts. The distinction between fact and theory plays an important rhetorical role in debates over evolution and the age of the earth; one popular way to dismiss a claim is to say, “Well, that’s just theory!” This trades on the popular use of “theory” to mean a speculative, and often merely personal, account. But in science, what we mean by a theory is a complex account of some phenomena that gives an explanation of them, and that has some testable consequences. So in the first place, theories are not just speculative, anything goes sorts of things. In the second place, facts are not just a matter of “brute observations.” There are many facts that we are perfectly confident of despite a lack of direct observations, such as the shape (roughly hemispherical) of the back side of the moon, which wasn’t observed until the early days of the space program, with the Ranger probes. The ice age is treated as established fact today, and various theories are advanced to explain what triggers ice ages, to predict more details of the flow of ice over large regions (which depends on how precipitation is distributed, the details of how ice behaves under high pressure, and the effects of meltwater flowing through and beneath glaciers, among other things), and so on. The Age of the Earth By the mid-19th century, actualist/uniformitarian methods had spread widely, and their success in treating a wide range of geological phenomena was generally recognized even by geologists who did not share Lyell’s hard line substantive uniformitarianism. The idea that geological time was immense had been generally accepted, even by the catastrophists; just how immense it might be was suggested by Lyell’s treatment of Etna, which showed that late tertiary formations (a very recent geological period) dated back to something like 10 million years ago. The stratigraphy of the phanerozoic (the period in which fossil life is fairly abundant, including the Paleozoic, Mesozoic and Cenozoic) was well-established, and geologists were hard at work refining the details. The pre-Cambrian was largely a mystery, since the general absence of fossils made correlation of strata below the Cambrian very difficult. But the success of uniformitarian methods depended on the availability of time—if time limits are imposed, then present processes and rates might not suffice even if, given enough time, they would. For Lyell, a further “draft on the bank of time” was always the right move—so long as the observed phenomena (the traces) could be explained by appeal to present processes acting over some period of time, it was always preferable, in his view, to help yourself to the time needed rather than try to invent (and model) entirely new processes. The science of thermodynamics (the physics of heat & energy) was becoming quite sophisticated at this time—it was initially developed to make sense of the workings of steam engines (especially to explain their efficiency, which differed widely). Its mathematical formulation was pursued by figures including Fourier and William Smith (later Lord Kelvin). One of the principle results was the second law, which rules out the possibility of perpetual motion heat engines. Since the earth’s geological processes (and the sun’s radiation) were apparently the result of heat energy, this theory had immediate implications for our ideas about the sun and the earth. Darwin published his Origin of Species in 1859, presenting his evidence for evolution as well as his proposed mechanism (natural selection). Darwin’s views included a strong commitment to Lyell’s uniformitarian approach to geology, which Darwin himself has successfully applied to various geological questions during the voyage of the Beagle. But this was not just a matter of Darwin’s preferences as a geologist—his theory of how evolution occurs, as he acknowledged, would require long periods of time for the present variety of complex life to arise: For Darwin variations arise accidentally and are not directed by any teleological (end-seeking) force. As a result, life evolves only as advantageous variations happen to arise and be ‘selected for.’ In Origin, Darwin actually presented a calculation of the time required to erode a large region of south-east England called the Weald; his result was a figure of 300 million years, a number that fit nicely with the broad sense that his mechanism for evolution would require an immense time to operate in. But Darwin’s calculation was widely criticized, and he backed down rather quickly (it was qualified in the 2nd edition, and removed entirely in the 3rd). In 1862, shortly after Origin appeared, William Thompson (later Lord Kelvin) published a calculation of the time during which the sun could be expected to continue radiating energy at its current rate. Based on Helmholtz’ gravitational theory of the sun’s energy (gravitational potential energy in a dispersed mass equivalent to the sun being far greater than any amount of chemical energy such a mass could contain), Kelvin concluded that the sun probably did not have sufficient energy to continue its present output for 100 million years, and almost certainly didn’t have enough to continue for 500 million years. Hence, as he concluded, the time available for geology and for paleontology must be limited within some such figure; as a result, of course, he completely dismissed Darwin’s calculation of the “denudation of the Weald”. Kelvin later applied similar thermodynamic considerations to the earth, based on a simple model of the earth’s history in which it cooled slowly as a roughly homogeneous molten mass of uniform temperature (convection currents maintaining even temperature during the cooling). Once the earth solidifies, on Kelvin’s model, it begins a gradual cooling that depends on four basic quantities: The initial temperature (= the temperature of fusion for the earth’s rocky material), the conductivity of the earth’s material, and its heat capacity. Straightforward calculations based on these figures, combined with a temperature profile indicating how quickly the earth’s temperature rises as we descend deeper into the earth’s interior gives a figure for the earth’s present age. The result of this calculation was a best estimate of 98 million years, with a lower limit of 20 million, and an upper limit of 400 million. (Kelvin also applied tidal friction and its effect on the earth’s speed of rotation to calculate another limit on the earth’s age.) At this point (during the 1860’s, roughly) Kelvin remained quite modest in his claims. He did not seem as concerned about the specific limits as he was about the point of principle, viz. that some limit on geological time was inevitable: The earth cannot be a perpetual motion machine. But this modesty was to change over the next two decades… Beginning with Philips calculation of 1861, based on the accumulation of sedimentary rock since the Cambrian (= start of the Paleozoic), a series of geological efforts to arrive at a geological time scale were undertaken. These include Croll, who focused on climate change and an astronomical model of ice ages, T. Mellard Reade, who included both solvent erosion and mechanical erosion, and Samuel Haughton, who based his calculations on a supposed link between climate (as indicated by fossil remains) and the earth’s temperature, whose initial figure of 2300 million years was very appealing to uniformitarians, but who later sought to bring his results more in line with Kelvin’s requirements. Clarence King, of the U.S. Geological Survey, constructed graphs representing the earth’s cooling over time embodying Kelvin’s methods combined with new figures for the melting temperature and heat capacity of the earth, obtaining a result of 22-24 million years. And John Joly made a calculation based on the accumulation of salt in the oceans. He assumed that rivers dissolve and carry salt into them steadily over time, and that the salt remains in the oceans indefinitely (while the water evapourates and replenishes the rivers as rain). The resulting estimate, after some sophisticated analysis, put the age of the oceans (which Joly took to correspond to the time sine the earth’s temperature fell below the boiling point) at 80-90 million years. With the drastically shorter estimate from King (and Kelvin’s increasing insistence on shorter limits as well), geologists began to resist the physical estimates more vigourously, beginning in the 1880’s and 90’s. Osmond Fisher, who had other reasons for supposing the earth to be “plastic” below the crust, argued that allowing for some convection currents in the lower earth would have a drastic impact on Kelvin’s figures. Archibald Geicke argued that the independent evidence of geology could not be neglected in evaluating the physical calculations. John Perry, a former assistant to Kelvin, explored alternatives to Kelvin’s assumptions including convection and greater conductivity, and demonstrated that they would allow for considerably more time. Kelvin responded by insisting on his new calculations (Kelvin, 1897: On the Age of the Earth as an Abode Fitted for Life), which allowed a maximum of 24 million years for the earth’s age. Geicke rejected this outright, as did T.C. Chamberlin, in a reply to Kelvin’s paper. Chamberlin proposed a slow accretion model allowing more time for the earth to continue in more or less its present state, and speculated, prophetically, that the sun’s energy might be due to unknown processes that release energies at the atomic level. By this time radioactivity had been discovered (by Becquerel); in 1903 Pierre Curie and his assistant realized that radium salts release heat at a very steady rate. Rutherford (perhaps the greatest experimental physicist of the 20th Century) realized by 1904 that all radioactive elements contained vast amounts of energy that was released in radioactive decay. In the spring of 1904, Rutherford lectured on the topic of radioactivity at the Royal Institution; in that lecture (which Kelvin attended) Rutherford pointed out the implications for Kelvin’s calculations of the earth’s age: a source of replacement energy for the heat lost to space had been found. We no longer needed to regard the earth as a body that was steadily cooling over time. Analyses by Strutt showed that the amount of radioactivity measured in igneous rocks was far more than that required to maintain the earth’s temperature—so it seemed (unless radioactive materials were far more concentrated in the crust than deeper in the earth’s interior) the earth might even be heating up, or have other ways of releasing the heat being produced. It soon became apparent that radioactive decay finished by producing non-radioactive elements, and that the rate of decay was described by a simple exponential equation. The possibility of measuring the amount of decay that had occurred by identifying how much of the original material (“parent isotope”) had been converted into a stable, nonradioactive final product (“daughter isotope”), and thereby determining the age of various rocks, was now obvious, and work on making such measurements began very quickly. There were many technical details to be sorted out (at first, the existence and nature of different isotopes of the same element was not understood; once this puzzle was worked out, the techniques were greatly improved). But from the start the results suggested far larger ages than had previously been accepted either by the physicists or most geologists. Joseph Barrell’s 1917 article, “Rhythms and the measurement of geological time,” was a turning point, establishing the radioactive methods as the best means for estimating geological time. His argument clearly identified key problems with the other geological methods, and why so many of them had produced substantial underestimates of the earth’s age; just to mention one, the existence of many substantial new mountain ranges means that erosion is now proceeding far faster than it has on average over the earth’s history. His figure for the bottom of the Cambrian was 550-700 million years—well in accord with contemporary figures of about 556 million years (Harland, W.B. et al., 1990. A geologic time scale, 1989 edition. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, p.1-263.) Subsequent developments have refined techniques, improved reliability, and added further methods based on other radioactive elements that serve to cross-check and verify the results of these measurements. Detailed but accessible accounts of these techniques can be found in many texts, and on the web at talkorigins.org. Hallam finishes with a discussion of gradualism in geology and biology (an important topic for Darwin). He argues that the “reality” of the Cambrian explosion remains a serious problem for the gradualist. Some claim that the explosion records only an explosion in the number of forms of life with mineralized skeletons and shells; earlier fossils of a wide range of animal life have been found, including recent evidence of a very early proto-vertebrate on the order of 700 million years old. But the Cambrian explosion issue remains one of the most controversial and interesting problems in paleontology (and has attracted more than its share of attention from creationists eager to use it as a club to beat evolution with). Continental Drift. From its first beginnings, in the work of Osmond Fisher, F.B. Taylor, and, later, Alfred Wegner, the idea of continental drift was controversial and exciting. It found supporters early on, but also (and more influential) it found some very aggressive critics, including Dr. –later “Sir”— Harold Jeffreys. While Wegner developed some very persuasive evidence for his theory, evidence that is regarded as very telling today, he also made some embarrassing mistakes, proposed some dubious arguments for it, and had no credible account of the forces and conditions in the earth that would allow for continental drift. Notes for 2233 Lectures on Evolution: Evidence for evolution. Evolution and Natural Selection vs. Creation The key issue at this point is to get clear about the contrast between these views. Creationism as a contemporary movement is a “big tent,” including many very different opponents of naturalistic accounts of evolution. Their main point of agreement is that they all wish to invoke some sort of creator/designer as part of their understanding of the universe, and reject as inadequate or just plain false any view that attempts to dispense with this creator. 1. Conditions for natural selection: The conditions under which natural selection will operate: a. Significant Variation (SV). This is variation amongst individuals in a population that makes a difference to survival and reproduction (i.e. to their “representation” via descendents in subsequent generations). This results (in biology) from two conditions that can be seen to hold: 1. The broad range of variations that arise in living populations. 2. The struggle for existence: Most organisms (in the medium run) must fail to leave any descendents. b. Inheritance of SV. At least some significant variation must have a tendency to be inherited, i.e. the offspring of individuals must have a higher probability of having some significant variation present in the parent(s) than a randomly selected member of their generation. It’s worth noting that this condition is very weak—it does not assume anything about the processes involved in inheritance (unlike, say, Lamark’s inheritance of acquired characteristics). c. Stability. Circumstances making some of the inheritable SV advantageous must be persistent over a substantial number of generations. (Note that this covers selection against some traits implicitly, since, given our definitions above, those who fail to have such traits will be judged to have an advantageous inheritable trait). With these conditions in place, over time the most probable pattern of change will lead the population towards a state where every member of the population will have the inheritable SV traits. Given long enough periods of stability together with a significantly advantageous and heritable SV, this probability becomes a practical certainty. We can regard a and b above as more fundamental, since natural selection could be said to occur even if stability fails to hold—but the upshot will not be any stable trend tending to make the population change in any particular way. In that case, over the medium to long run, the frequency of various traits in the population will tend to vary randomly, and drift will be the right explanation of any long term changes. 2. Limiting NS. There are a number of conditions that may place significant limits on how far NS can go in altering the characteristics (distribution of heritable traits) of a population. a. Limits on variability. The most obvious way to limit this would be to deny that there are any sources of new, heritable variation. A more subtle limit denies that there are any sources of new, heritable and advantageous variation. Either way, NS will be able to change the population, but only by driving out any initial, disadvantageous traits—once that is done, there will either not be any new variation (the first limit), or all the variation there is will simply introduce new, disadvantageous traits that will subsequently be driven back out of the population. (The second strategy is often employed by creationists and ID theorists, who insist, on a variety of spurious grounds, that all mutations are disadvantageous. The first strategy is older, and usually cast in the form of some kind of species-essentialism.) b. Improbability of advantageous variations. This is a still subtler move with the same aim. Defenders of this limitation on NS argue that advantageous variations are typically complex (involving a number of very specific changes that must be combined in one or a very few steps). Since each specific change is highly improbable and the changes are independent of each other (i.e. each is no more or less likely given that some other(s) have occurred), the probability of a substantial number of these happening together (which would be required if any advantage were to result) is vanishingly small. This is the strategy M. Behe pursues in Darwin’s Black Box, and also (with different window-dressing) the strategy of W. Dembski’s The Design Inference and No Free Lunch. Evidence for evolution: 1. Taxonomy: The hierarchical structure of taxonomy in biology: the fundamental pattern is one of shared similarities as the basis for taxonomic groups, with species sharing the greatest number of these similarities, genus sharing a smaller set, families still smaller, and so on, all the way up to phyla and kingdoms. If such similarities are shared because of descent with modification, then we have a credible explanation for the pattern.