Lecture Objectives: After learning this material you will be able to: 1. Present the basic insight of ethical subjectivism: “What may be right for you may be wrong for me depending on our respective feelings.” 2. Understand that ethical subjectivism is not an ethics of tolerance for individual differences, because tolerance itself is a universal principle and universality is denied by ethical subjectivism. 3. Discuss the differences between ethical skepticism and ethical subjectivism. 4. Understand that cultural relativism is an ethical theory that states that our ethical values stem from our culture and that morality is simply socially approved customs. 5. Compare and contrast sociological relativism with cultural relativism. 6. Reflect on the meaning of social Darwinism, especially in terms of politics. 7. Outline the meaning of a “moral community.” 8. Be able to recognize the strengths and weaknesses of ethical relativism. In the last lecture we presented an integral framework for the understanding of ethical theory. We also studied the process of moral reasoning and tried to gain a better understanding of how our resistance to moral reasoning often takes on strong emotional overtones. Finally, we learned about quite a few fallacies that interfere with making clear and analytical moral arguments. In this lecture we will explore the world of ethical relativism, a worldview that is very prevalent today in the United States. First we will learn about ethical subjectivism and then cultural relativism. In the process we will delve deeper into our own values, trying to understand what it is on which we are able to build them and hold them together. Ethical Subjectivism Many times we feel something is right or wrong with a clarity that is not based on rational arguments but on an inner certainty that is self-validating. We “just know.” Thomas Jefferson wrote in the Declaration of Independence that “we consider these truths self-evident,” meaning that these truths should be obvious to anyone who looks within and thinks about Jefferson’s claims. “Ethical subjectivism, also known as individual relativism, makes the claim that people can never be mistaken about what is morally right or wrong because there are no objective or universal moral standards or truths, instead, there are only opinions. An opinion expresses what a person believes. It does not have to be backed up by reasons or facts. What is right or wrong for one particular individual is a matter of personal taste, rather like our preferences for particular foods or hairstyles” (Judith A. Boss, Ethics For Life: A Text With Readings, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2008] p. 77. Hereafter referred to as Boss). The question we will be asking ourselves is whether this type of moral relativity is true or not. It does not really matter if you prefer Mexican food to Chinese food. That kind of relativity is just fine. But does it matter whether you believe women should be subject to men? Is that just a 1 matter of preference? What about torture, child abuse, and female circumcision? Are these kinds of activities simply a matter of personal approval? If not, on what basis can we judge them as good or bad? This is the ethical dilemma facing us in this course, and especially in this lecture. People who tend to “just know” certain things are right or wrong naturally trust this inner intuition because it seems so obvious. This can lead them to hold the position of an ethical subjectivist. “Ethical subjectivists argue that there are no absolute standards by which to judge a person’s moral preferences. If a person sincerely believes something to be morally correct for him or her, then this in itself causes it to be morally true” (Boss, p. 78.) This makes sense, because it just seems so right for us. We don’t usually see the complications until our inner certainty runs into someone else’s inner certainty, but their inner certainty is the opposite of ours! Then we have a problem. When two people see the same thing in opposite ways are they both right? If it is a preference for a vacation spot, then they are both probably right and we can say happily “to each his or her own.” But when it comes to something such as racism, are both parties right? Are people who think Blacks should be subject to Whites equally right with those who disagree? It is because of situations like this that “the great majority of moral philosophers disagree with ethical subjectivism. These philosophers maintain that there are fundamental moral standards by which we can judge people. Philosopher Renford Bambrough, for example, claims that almost all of us would agree that it would be immoral to perform a painful operation on a small child without an anesthetic because we intuitively know that torturing children is wrong. There is no need to prove to someone that torturing children is wrong; it is self-evident” (Boss, p. 78.) This implies that there are universal standards that all people and cultures recognize. But is this true? That is what we are attempting to study. One approach to the problem is to simply ask ourselves why we are resistant to universal values, at least in the modern Western world. The answer is that we hold freedom as one of our greatest values and we don’t want other people telling us what to think or how to act. Individualism In the United States there has been a history of promoting the values of individualism. The goal is to have people think for themselves and not be simple conformists. “Personal tastes or feelings are the only standard. If it feels right, do it. There are no universal moral truths, only individual moral preferences or truths based on each person’s own opinion and feelings” (Boss, p. 78.) People are not supposed to conform to what they are told is right and good, but they are to struggle to find their own personal truth and then live from that discovery rather than from some other authority’s rulebook. 2 This instinct for individual truth is not simply an assertion of ego over community. It also represents an attempt to move away from cultural imperialism and personal superiority. As a result, “many people confuse ethical subjectivism with an ethics of tolerance and respect for others’ lifestyles - an ethics that is often summed up by the phrase ‘live and let live’” (Boss, p. 81.) This seems like a very good value that many of us would subscribe to, and that is why we need to use our critical thinking skills to go below the surface and analyze what is happening here. Notice what is happening. We are accepting the truth of relativity on the basis of a universal value. “Tolerance is a universal moral principle. The statement ‘live and let live’ implies a universal duty to respect others, regardless of how we personally feel toward them, and a duty not to harm them either directly or by interfering with their rights to pursue their own interests. According to ethical subjectivism though, universal moral duties do not exist” (Boss, p. 82.) Our critical thinking skills reveal a basic contradiction. We can’t logically hold both views because they cancel each other out. It appears that something is not quite correct in how we are thinking about this. What is going on? “Some people also confuse ethical subjectivism with the obviously true observation that individuals do hold different views about what is morally right and morally wrong. In the presence of moral disagreement, when asked if a particular person is right, some people will reply, ‘Well, they believe they are right.’ When people say this, they are changing the topic from what a person ought to do to what a person believes is the case - thus committing the fallacy of irrelevant conclusion” (Boss, p. 82.) This is a good example of why we spent so much time learning about the various fallacies that can emerge in our moral reasoning. They have a way of infecting much of our thought processes! We are not simply talking about describing the world. “Ethical subjectivism is a moral theory and it is prescriptive - that is, it is about what a person ought to do. The statement that a person believes something to be right, on the other hand, is descriptive. Ethical subjectivism, however, goes beyond the merely descriptive by claiming that sincerely believing or feeling that something is right makes it right (or true) for that person. By doing this, critics argue that ethical subjectivism fails to recognize the distinction between descriptive and prescriptive statements” (Boss, p. 82.) The fact that we really believe something to be right is true in the sense of being a factual statement. We really do believe that. But this does not allow us to make the further to jump to “therefore, it is right.” This would negate all that we have learned from the past. For example, the vast majority of people used to truly believe that slavery was right, that women were not as smart as men, and that children were simply the property of their fathers. But surely that does not make it right and good. It also does not mean that people holding these views were insincere. They probably really saw the world in this way. By what standard are 3 we able to look at past values and see that they were not as moral as once believed? Moral Uncertainty Another issue we will address is referred to as moral uncertainty. To say that we do not know what is right and good is not to say there is no right and good. It simply means we don’t know and to take it further than this is to go too far. “Ethical subjectivism is not the same as moral uncertainty of the type that may occur when we are confronted with a moral dilemma” (Boss, p. 82.) When someone comes to us for moral advice and we simply tell them to do what they know is right, we could be saying two different things. On one hand, we could simply be saying that whatever they decide is right for them. This is relativity. But on the other hand, we might simply be acknowledging that we trust them and their own integrity to do the right thing. “In other words, don’t confuse trusting someone’s moral judgment in a particular situation with ethical subjectivism. It is also logically inconsistent to claim that morality is a matter of opinion in one case but not in another. If all moral values are a matter of individual preference, as the ethical subjectivist claims, then morality is relative in all situations, not just for moral dilemmas” (Boss, p. 82.) This is why it is important to keep our moral confusion in perspective and not get tricked into thinking that because we don’t know, that means there is no truth to be discovered. It is all too easy to take our confusion as the final impression on certain matters. We have to keep in mind that “disagreement about moral values, in itself, does not imply that objective moral truths do not exist” (Boss, p. 83.) There are all kinds of situations where we already accept this. For example, in medical experiments concerning a new drug we know that some scientists think it will work while others are doubtful. This does not mean that both are correct. It just means we have not figured it out yet. We hold out hope that eventually we will know whether a medicine will help us or not. This same attitude of waiting to understand is helpful in ethics as well. The Kitty Genovese Syndrome Another important issue to be concerned with in ethics in general and ethical subjectivism specifically deals with the matter of responsibility. How do we hold ourselves, let alone others, responsible in a world where good and bad are subjective? “Indeed, moral responsibility, in terms of assigning moral blame or praise, becomes a moot issue with ethical subjectivists because there are no objective standards against which to measure the morality of a person’s actions; ethical subjectivism therefore precludes passing judgment on other people’s or even on our own actions” (Boss, p. 83.) Our whole legal system in the United States is based on the fact that we think we can hold people responsible for their 4 actions. But how can we actually do that if there is no objective right and wrong? One way to do so is to equate legality with morality. We have a social contract that says that certain action are considered wrong by us and if you go against these laws we can hold you responsible. This goes with the idea that we can vote on morality. If a majority of people think something is wrong, then that makes it wrong. This helps us over the initial hurdle of responsibility, but it leaves other problems we will have to face further on in this lecture. Ideas concerning our level of responsibility are important to think about because they are not simply intellectual exercises. These ethical ideas influence how we live our lives. “Ethical theories do not exist in abstraction. Ethical theories inform and motivate our real-life decisions and actions. They shape the way we define ourselves, as well as our community and our ideas of community responsibility. In ethics education, romantic sentimentalism usually takes the form of the values clarification or value-neutral approach, where students are encouraged to express their opinions without fear of censorship or judgment. Values are considered something one clarifies rather than discovers. Moral truths are based on inner feelings rather than on a shared objective reality. Any opinion is just as valid as any other” (Boss, p. 93.) It is good to encourage children to discuss moral issues and wrestle with these ideas. But that is not the same as claiming that their answers are equivalent to moral truths. Studies have also shown that simply discussing moral values does not bring about the growth that educators were hoping it would. “This popular approach to moral education has been shown to have no effect on a student’s actual moral development and, in fact, can even retard its development. Ethical subjectivism, by retreating into pure inner or subjective feelings, neglects to take into account the social context that gives moral sentiments their value in the first place. To remove morality from the social realm is to condone isolation and apathy in the face of others’ pain” (Boss, p. 94.) Unfortunately we have some real life situations that illustrate that the rather modern trend of ethical subjectivism may be leading to disturbing results, such as apathy concerning ethics and living a good life. The most famous case of public apathy has been given the name the “Kitty Genovese Syndrome.” This is a reference to a woman who was assaulted in New York City over a period of a half hour during which time she was constantly yelling for help. Thirty-eight of her neighbors heard her cries, but not one of them even called the authorities. In a subjective world people do not want to interfere with what other people do. They don’t want to take a stand because they think: “After all, who am I to judge?” There is more going on here than subjectivism. There are studies that show that people step up to help when they are alone much more than when they are with others. Perhaps when there is a group of thirty-eight people everyone assumes someone else will step up to help. But there is still something ethical here to struggle with because this idea that other people are responsible rather than myself comes from living in a certain ethical environment. This is because so much of ethics has to do with duties. That is, I 5 am called upon to act in a certain way. If this calling is only a matter of whether I personally relate to it or agree with it or not, then it can lead to some of the many problems we all face today living in our modern society. Critique of Ethical Subjectivism Ethical subjectivism often sounds pretty good until we use our critical thinking skills to discover some of the problems with it as an ethical theory, which can be summed up in the following way. “1. Ethical subjectivism incorrectly assumes that moral disagreement necessarily implies that there are no universal moral standards. We can give reasons for why people should not torture children. We might, for example, cite the principle of nonmaleficence (do no harm) or respect for the rights of others. Or we could appeal to their sense of compassion. In each of these instances, we do this because we have the expectation that the person we are trying to convince acknowledges the same basic moral values that we do” (Boss, p. 96.) But we can only have this expectation if there is something universal that we can hold out as worthy of admiration. We also need to make an important distinction. “What is often interpreted as disagreement about basic moral principles is instead disagreement about the application of these principles in particular situations” (Boss, p. 96.) Just because we are not sure what to do does not mean we don’t have a sense of right and wrong. You can see this particularly well in issues around parenting. Parents often know the values they want their children to have but how to teach these values is not always clear. 2. “Ethical subjectivism is based on the incorrect assumption that we cannot be mistaken in our moral beliefs” (Boss, p. 96.) If we think something is right then it is right for us according to the subjectivists. However, “when our moral views change, we do regard our former views as mistaken” (Boss, p. 96.) But how can we do this if our previous moral views were correct? In other words, we allow for the fact that we can grow in our morality, that we are capable of moral development. This implies that there is a moral good that we can move closer to and this is only possible if there is something beyond our personal opinion. 3. “We do pass judgment on our feelings and actions. At times, we judge that it would be immoral to act upon certain feelings or desires” (Boss, p. 97.) We all have had feelings that we know we shouldn’t act upon. Just because I am feeling angry does not mean I then allow myself to act hurtfully. In other words, “if morality is the same as feeling, then it makes no sense to restrain ourselves from acting on our feelings. To restrain ourselves only makes sense if we are using moral criteria or principles that are independent of our feelings” (Boss, p. 97.) This means we have to question the value that says: “if something feels right, do 6 it” because a closer look reveals that our feelings, while important, are not a reliable source for our ethical decisions. “In real life, we regard acting on certain feelings and desires as immoral. Although moral evaluation can take a person’s feelings into account, for the most part, we judge an action to be moral or immoral independently of the agent’s feelings” (Boss, p. 97.) One of the most difficult things we have to learn when we are young children is to restrain ourselves and practice self-discipline when it comes to acting out our feelings. 4. “Ethical subjectivism is disastrous for the weak and defenseless” (Boss, p. 97.) When you think about it, you notice that if ethical subjectivism were true then it would limit morality to those who were actually able to implement their desires. The more powerful can use their subjective desire to hurt those beneath them anyway they want simply because they feel like it. This does not mean that everything concerning subjectivism is wrong. “Almost all moral theories contain at least a grain of truth, but the problem with many theories arises when theorists mistake this grain of truth for the whole truth. Ethical subjectivists, for example, are correct in noting that morality begins with the individual experience and that these experiences are sometimes at variance with one another. Ethical subjectivists’ belief in the basic goodness of human nature and that our sense of morality is innate may also contain more than just a grain of truth at least for the 96 percent of us who have a conscience” (Boss, pp. 96-97.) But we have to find an ethical way of life that accounts and holds responsible people who seem to be missing a social conscience (sociopaths) and people who disagree with one another. Our conscience and our experiences, especially our formative ones with family and early schooling, are very important. “But moral experience and moral growth do not end with our limited individual experience. Nor are we as humans infallible in discerning the moral voice within us. There seem to be other voices, from both within and without, that compete with our conscience or sense of morality. For us to develop morally, our sense of what is right and wrong must be nurtured, as well as challenged, by our community” (Boss, pp. 97-98.) This is why morality is difficult and why people struggle with ethical issues. If it were easy we could turn our moral decisions over to a computer. As we move forward in our class we will have to keep in mind that the conclusion of most philosophers and religious leaders states: “Ethical subjectivism, if taken seriously, is a dangerous theory. It not only isolates the individual but permits people to exploit and hurt others without ever having to justify their actions or stand in judgment” (Boss, p. 98.) We need to include our feelings, but we also need to see beyond them. We have personal and cultural blind spots and it is only when we are helped to see them that we can expand our awareness and let our circle of compassion grow larger. Cultural Relativism 7 Ethical subjectivism is very prevalent in our society, but it is not the only form of relativism we need to discuss. It is often confused with cultural relativism, but this is something different. Earlier I wrote that one way to hold people responsible without universal morals is to simply vote on what will be good and bad and then pass laws instituting these values. This is a form of cultural relativism. “Like ethical subjectivism, cultural relativism looks to people for standards of right and wrong. Subjectivists claim that individuals create their own moral standards; cultural relativists argue that moral standards and values are derived from groups of people or cultures. Public opinion, rather than private opinion, determines what is right and wrong. There are no objective universal moral standards that hold true for all people in all cultures. Morality, instead, is regarded as nothing more than socially approved customs” (Boss, p. 100.) These insights were especially popular, as we will see, among anthropologists. Once we started exploring the world in a more open and academic way we started to see that different cultures looked at ethics in different ways. The typical and imperialistic way was to simply assume that our way was always better. But many people began to see this as overly judgmental and problematic. Different ways of viewing the world might be just that - different. That does not make one way superior to another, and therefore morality might be simply local rather than universal. “Because morality is nothing more than custom, we have no grounds for judging the moral practices of another culture or another time whether these practices be terrorism or slavery. If two cultures disagree about what is morally right and there is no disagreement about the facts or definitions of key terms, then there is no rational means for continuing the discussion or reaching agreement. Cultural relativists do not argue merely that some moral values are relative to the culture. Rather, they maintain that all moral values are nothing more than cultural customs” (Boss, p. 101.) It is obvious that different cultures have different ways of dressing, different foods, and different customs. In a pluralistic world we can celebrate these differences and enjoy the variety they bring to our lives. But is cultural variety the same as cultural relativism when it comes to ethics? Can we not stand in judgment of some practices, such as terrorism, simply because some people think it is a valid moral option? To wrestle with these problems we will have to define our terms; sometimes it helps to explore what something isn’t before we explore what it is. What Cultural Relativism Is Not We might think that cultural relativism is about honoring the differences between cultures and understanding that people see things in different ways from one another. This is fine. But it is not the same as excusing things we disagree with ethically. “Cultural relativism is not the same as excusing certain cultural 8 practices, such as slavery, on the grounds that the people of that culture sincerely believe that what they are or were doing is morally acceptable. Excusing entails granting an exemption or pardon from wrongdoing” (Boss, p. 102.) But there is nothing wrong with things being different. If we think they are wrong, we need to excuse their behavior. We may not like the behavior of another culture, but how can we condemn it if everything is relative? Remember that we are not talking about describing differences, but about prescribing them. This means that if a culture thinks something such as female circumcision is good, then not only may they do it, but they should do it. “Cultural relativists claim that these practices were actually morally right for the members of that culture” (Boss, p. 102.) If we don’t like it then that only means we come from a different culture with different social customs. It doesn’t mean there is actually anything wrong with female circumcision, headhunting, or terrorism. There is also a difference between respecting differences and tolerating evil. “Cultural relativism is not the same as respect for cultural diversity. Cultural relativism is sometimes mistakenly advocated on the grounds that it promotes tolerance and respect for cultural diversity. However, this is based on a misunderstanding of cultural relativism since this very tolerance may promote intolerance and violation of human rights” (Boss, p. 103.) Tolerance is good, but that does not mean we tolerate child abuse, rape and murder. Tolerance is a wonderful quality until we make it into an absolute that is not balanced with other values. “Stating that the customs of any culture are no better or worse than those of any other precludes us from passing any judgment on repressive customs that violate human rights and dignity” (Boss, 104.) We once again have to use our critical thinking because the impulse behind cultural relativity seems to be a good one and often feels right. Many of us were raised with the idea that we should not judge others and we should be open to what other cultures have to teach us. There is nothing wrong with these aspirations. But there is a difference between trying new foods and music and trying out headhunting while on a study abroad program! How we make these distinctions is what we will be studying over the next few weeks. But it all begins with being able to analyze our thinking about values such as respect and tolerance. We also see how qualities such as respect and tolerance point toward universal values once again. “The fundamental and universal moral principle of mutual respect for the dignity of individuals and their right to self-determination needs to be part of any definition of cultural diversity. Respect does not extend to respect for or tolerance of oppression and inequality within any culture” (Boss, p. 104.) Why respect people unless it is because of the feeling and thinking that states that all people have a basic right to be respected? How can we show respect for this basic human right if we also tolerate policies that disrespect people and their basic needs? We can’t have it both ways, and if we don’t look closely at what it is 9 we are seeking to do then cultural relativism often seems to be encouraging us to have it both ways. We are supposed to respect differences, but if someone does something against respect we can’t judge, because who are we to do so? Defining Our Terms How can we sort out what seems like a fundamental confusion? Where do we start? It is always a good idea to define our terms. We have seen what cultural relativism is not, so now let’s look at what it is. “Cultural relativism is not the same as sociological relativism. Cultural relativism is a theory of philosophical ethics. As such, it is concerned with what ought to be. Sociological relativism, in contrast, is a theory in descriptive ethics, a branchy of sociology that is concerned with what is. Descriptive ethics aims to discover and describe the moral beliefs of a given society. Sociological relativism is simply the observation that there is disagreement among cultures regarding moral values. Unlike cultural relativism, sociological relativism draws no conclusions; it makes no judgments about the rightness or wrongness of different cultural standards. Cultural relativists presuppose that sociological relativism is true, but sociological relativists do not necessarily accept cultural relativism as true” (Boss, p. 106.) By noticing where cultures disagree we can learn a great deal. We may even learn ways to improve our own ethical stances. Many countries, for example, have national health plans that make sure all people receive basic medical care. How does that make us feel about our society? Does it challenge us? Many countries have eliminated capital punishment. Does this challenge us? Other countries that do have capital punishment do it publicly during the half-time break at sporting events. Should we try this out? Acknowledging differences can nudge us to make improvements. But it can also help us see where other cultures need to make improvements. It works both ways. We also have to be aware that just because different cultures have different ways of applying different ethical values, does not mean that there are not some underlying universal patterns also worth studying. “Deeper analysis of the differences in moral practices among cultures also reveals many similarities in the fundamental moral principles. American anthropologist Clyde Kluckholn (1905-1960) claimed that there are basic universal, transcultural moral standards that are recognized in all cultures and that are binding upon all members of a particular culture’s moral community. The existence of cross-cultural values does not, in itself, disprove cultural relativism; however, the presence of these apparently universally accepted values does strengthen the argument against cultural relativism. ‘In no human group,’ Kluckholn notes, ‘is indiscriminate lying, cheating or stealing approved’” (Boss, p. 106.) There are many examples of how when first describing different customs, it looked as though very different moral values were being discovered. A more in-depth examination revealed that it was not so different after all. 10 For example, a classic anthropological study told of Eskimos allowing their elders to die or be killed when they could no longer adequately function in their society. This seems very harsh and it seems like a vastly different value system from our modern value. But a closer look revealed that if they did not do this, then the whole tribe was endangered. It is not as if they wanted to do this, but they had to look at the greater good. One way this became clear was that this practice was almost immediately dropped when these people found themselves in more modern conditions where they could survive without doing this. In other words, it was not because they didn’t care about their parents, but they simply had very different conditions under which they had to function in order to survive. “It is now apparent that much of what initially appeared to be disagreement about basic moral standards may instead be the result of situational differences” (Boss, p. 108.) This is yet another example of why critical thinking is so important in ethics. Without asking good questions and going deeper into the issues it is all too easy to assume that values might not have any common ground, when it appears that many of our basic values are, in fact, shared by most if not all people. Another area of confusion is often clarified by looking at motivations for certain behavior. If people think that women are evil then they might behave in a way we find atrocious as a way of counteracting that “evil.” They might persecute women, or at least certain ones, only to prevent what they feel is a greater evil. This happened a great deal during the witch burnings of Europe and early America. Once people get their facts straight, immoral actions often stop. In other words people were not motivated to do things we disagree with because they were evil but because they misperceived what the good was. This does not justify the actions by any means at all, but it allows us to see that the values that were being protected were simply considered more important than the values that need to be overridden. What we took for a lack of morality was based simply on an ignorance of what the good was. This is why we need to keep perspective when we study different ethical systems and be aware of the context in which people live their lives and make their moral choices. “Very few ethicists believe that morality is completely autonomous - that is, independent of its particular context. As moral decision makers, we live in a world of particulars. Social settings, individual circumstances, cultural values, environmental conditions, and factual and religious beliefs vary tremendously from culture to culture. Acknowledging the influences of these factors in shaping the particular moral practices and values of a culture does not imply that there are no underlying basic universal moral standards. Universal moral standards, rather than determining the exact content of a culture‘s moral values and customs, provide general guidelines and set limits upon the values and customs that are morally acceptable within their particular context” (Boss, pp. 108-109.) If we want to find universal values we are more likely to do so when we look not at a specific behavior, but at the motivations for specific behavior. What are the underlying principles? 11 Social Darwinism One of the things that gave such strength to cultural relativism was that it became an acceptable alternative to the movement known as Social Darwinism. “According to Darwin, human instincts, including the moral sense, are nothing more than response structures that have in the past contributed to the survival of the species. The concept of the ‘good,’ instead of being something peculiar to human nature or part of our ‘divine’ nature, is simply a means of the perpetuation of the species. Morality, in other words, does not exist in some abstract realm but is a part of the natural world and is intimately linked to our struggle for survival within it” (Boss, p. 110.) Morality is just another way to help us survive. How true this might be is debatable, as we will see later in this class, but for now it is only important to note how this theory was used to justify European and American imperialism. How did this happen? Well it was not directly from Darwin, but how others developed his thought. “Social Darwinists, such as biologist Thomas H. Huxley (1825-1895) and philosopher Herbert Spencer (1820-1903), took evolutionary ethics one step farther. Social Darwinism rejects ethical relativism and instead embraces an ethics based on one universal moral principle: survival of the fittest. The social Darwinists expanded the idea of survival of the fittest from individuals to whole societies. Societal fitness was defined by the Social Darwinists in terms of worldly success and progress, which in turn were linked to moral superiority. Much of what we attribute to Darwin, such as the idea of evolution as progress and the survival of the fittest, came from Spencer and the social Darwinists” (Boss, p.110.) This is because Darwin did not speak of progress so much as adaptation to changing environments. The Social Darwinists used the success of Western countries over other parts of the world as proof that this is the way things were supposed to be, since Western people believed themselves to be better than other people and that Western values were better. Because they are better they can be imposed on people who might not have or even want these same values. Cultural relativists wanted to check this because they knew it was used to justify all sorts of atrocities. But the birth of modern anthropology also played a role in the formation of cultural relativism. Ruth Benedict: Cultural Relativism as a Protest Against Social Darwinism As anthropologists dug deeper into the societies they studied, often living with various folks for long periods of time, they began to see the holes in social Darwinism as a theory. Their distance from their normal Western lives also gave them a chance to view the West with a more critical eye. “In her landmark book Patterns of Culture, published in 1934, Benedict uncovered the inconsistencies in the Social Darwinists’ claim that Western society is at a higher level of moral, religious, and social evolution. She claimed that Darwin’s evolutionary theory 12 does not imply that morality is found in a greater degree in civilized societies” (Boss, p. 112.) In fact, their initial studies focused so much on the differences, that sociological relativism, a descriptive tool of the anthropologist, quickly took the guise of cultural relativism, a prescriptive tool. In focusing on differences they also missed, at least at first, the underlying common values. The Eskimo study I discussed earlier makes this point. On the surface things look very different. Probably because Benedict focused on these differences she “argued that there are no objective, transcultural moral standards or rational criteria to analyze the morality of a particular custom. Interpretation rather than analysis stands at the top of the ‘thinking’ pyramid. Our culturally shaped interpretations or worldviews about what is right and wrong are our reality. We thus have no grounds, other than our own cultural norms, for judging the morality of a practice such as cannibalism. Anthropologists such as Benedict and Sumner were not simply promoting sociological relativism. They were not just saying that cannibals believed that eating other humans was right: This is simply stating the obvious. Instead, the cultural relativists claimed that cannibalism was, in fact, morally right for cultures such as the Dobu of New Guinea, who apparently practiced cannibalism before the arrival of the Europeans” (Boss, p. 114.) They might not have been aware that they were making this switch from describing to prescribing, but once they did, their work became a primary foundation of cultural relativism. Once again, we see that the impulse of these anthropologists was a noble one. They wanted to go into these various tribal groups and not impose their own values, not judge what they were seeing, but simply describe the reality they found in front of them. But we now know that there was a certain naiveté in this. “Once we begin to examine cultural relativism, it becomes clear that the early advocates of their theory did not completely think through all the implications of their position. Like the social Darwinists who used evolutionary ethics as a means to legitimate European imperialism, cultural relativists also had a political agenda. By advocating cultural relativism, anthropologists such as Benedict wanted to stop imperialist practices and replace them with greater respect for and tolerance of cultural differences. If moral values are relative to each culture, then no culture’s values can be superior to those of any other culture. And if no culture’s values are superior to those of any other, they reasoned, then Western cultures have no justification for imposing their morality on other cultures. However, as we noted earlier, tolerance for cultural diversity that is not grounded in the universal principle of respect for human dignity necessitates tolerance of cultural customs that violate basic human rights and dignity” (Boss, p. 116.) In fact, they missed the fact that they were saying that their values of celebrating cultural diversity were better than the values of Social Darwinism. Their values of respecting ancient and tribal cultures were better than imperialism. But how can they say these values are better than other values if they have no standard by which to judge such values? Do you see that this is the same trap ethical 13 subjectivism fell into? It is the same trap because it is basically the same argument on a collective level rather than on an individual level. Cultural Relativism and the Moral Community The idea I discussed above concerning how we need to look not just at behaviors but at motivations is a way to begin to understand the question of how we think of our moral community. What is our moral community? It is the group of people who receive our care and concern. It usually starts with our family and then moves in outward rings to include our friends and larger community until it stops. Where it stops and why it stops is an interesting question, but for now we want to see how this circle of care influences how we perceive ethics. In fact, what often looks like different moralities is simply the fact that different people draw their circles in different ways. “Variations in cultural norms are sometimes due to differences in how cultures define their moral communities instead of differences in basic moral standards. Cultural relativism defines the moral community in ethnocentric terms. There are no universal or natural human rights. Someone, or something, has moral value only because his or her society grants this status. There is no source of moral value other than one’s culture. Those who are granted moral status by their culture receive the protection and support of the community” (Boss, p. 118.) Some people are in and some are out. For example, we can even see this in the simple way of how we apply our laws in the United States. Rights are based on citizenship. If you are a citizen then you have certain rights, and if you are not, then you don’t share many of these rights. Notice how this is not based on someone’s humanity, and it is not supposed to be based on someone’s race or age or other such things, but just based on citizenship. The circle is drawn at that limit when it comes to legal rights. This is pretty straightforward. It is much more subtle and difficult to draw the line when it comes to morality, but we see the same thing. Certain people in our moral community receive our care and concern and those outside of it do not. One way we judge a child’s moral development is by watching how they enlarge their “mandala.” “The moral community of a culture can be represented by using a mandala. Mandala is the ancient Sanskrit word for a circle that symbolizes the cosmic order. The mandala includes within its borders all that is sacred or, in moral culture’s moral community, beings who have the greater status in that culture are placed toward the center of the mandala. As one moves further toward the edges of the mandala, one’s moral value diminishes. Beings that are outside the moral community are placed outside the circle” (Boss, p. 119.) Most people place their family at the center and perhaps people of another race and religion at the outer edges of their circle. While not at the center, they still might include them in the sense of acknowledging their basic human rights. Animals, plants, and nature are usually outside the circle, but this is beginning to change. Many people now include their pets within the circle, but not other animals such as insects and flies! The modern ecological movement is asking that people 14 enlarge their circles of care and community even more to include all of nature. Wars are usually the result of countries putting the welfare of other countries’ citizens outside the circle of concern. In fact, they usually have to demonize such people in order to get people to stomach the violence of war. Slavery and the Holocaust It is very easy to see how moral communities work when you look at the issues of slavery and the Holocaust. “Slavery was legal for more than two centuries in colonial America and later the United States. Yet, as any historian can tell you, respect for human equality and a belief in justice were pre-Civil War American values. These values were even written into the U.S. Constitution. What has changed between now and then is not the basic moral principles but the definition of moral community. Slavery could only be morally justified by excluding the victims of slavery from the moral community” (Boss, p. 119.) People often wonder how a good family could sleep at night knowing they had slaves sleeping in shacks? Of course these people loved one another, felt compassion, and did community service. But they only did it for the people inside their moral community and Blacks were not included. Thankfully this changed. We can enlarge our moral community. Unfortunately this change works both ways and we can exclude those who were once included. “The cultural definition of moral community is fluid; it can change over time and even, in the case of ageism, over the course of a lifetime. For example, African Americans who were once outside the moral community are now inside, albeit at the margins. Unborn humans, who were once inside the moral community and protected by law, are now outside. Our animal companions and endangered species enjoy some protection from the moral community. Farm animals, insects, and most wild animals, on the other hand, are excluded from our culture’s moral community and may be squashed, poisoned, shot, experimented upon, or raised in confining and cruel conditions without fear of censure from those at the center of our moral community” (Boss, p. 121.) The Jews were once a part of the moral community of Germany, but then over a relatively short time they were excluded. By demonizing them and moving them outside of the concerns of the moral community, most Germans managed to ignore the great evil that was happening in their midst. Japanese-Americans were in the American moral community, then moved out during World War II, and now they have moved back in. Arab-Americans are currently in the American moral community, but many believe they have been moved to the outer edge and are worried that they may simply be pushed outside of the circle one of these days. Groups on the edge we often refer to as the marginalized. How we treat the marginalized, such as American farm workers, is one of the paradoxes of cultural relativism. “The cultural definition of moral community is, to a large extent, politically and economically motivated. Cultural relativism, in other 15 words, supports a definition of the moral community that serves primarily to maintain the status quo. By doing so, cultural relativism protects the interests of those in power while morally sanctioning the marginalization and exploitation of other groups, thereby promoting ethnocentrism and legitimizing hatred and discrimination as morally acceptable” (Boss, p. 122.) Cultural relativism does not set out to do this of course, so it is very ironic, but also why we need to be vigilant in ethics by looking closely at relativism. If our culture says it is not O.K. to kill farm workers, but it is O.K. to have them work in terrible conditions with no benefits and little pay so that we can keep food prices low, who are we to say no to this? After all, it is our culture that determines whether something is right or wrong and our culture has decided that this is O.K., apparently, otherwise it would be changed. It is hard to believe that something that seems so noble -relativism - can lead to such thinking and behavior, but by understanding this we can break the vicious cycle. The Vicious Cycle In our American culture those with money tend to be closer to the center of the circle of moral community. They can afford to buy the protection and care they need. But those who can’t afford to do this get moved further away. They are then looked down upon. They don’t have the same access to resources as those at the center and so they often will not succeed to the same extent. As a result they are looked down upon, stereotyped perhaps as lazy and useless, and are then moved further away from our circle of concern. “If morality is synonymous with cultural norms, then the exclusion of whole groups of people from the moral community should be fairly uncontroversial. Those in power should have no need to try to convince themselves and others that certain groups deserve a lower status. However, this is rarely the case. When a culture excludes or removes a group of people from the moral community, the culture often feels compelled to justify its actions even to the point of engaging in blatant doublethink. Indeed, the group in power may even justify the exclusion of another group as being for their own benefit” (Boss, p. 124.) This is another example of how we might actually know there are universal values. Otherwise why would we need to justify our actions as if they are wrong according to another standard? The question of asking if some cultures are more moral than others is a crucial one. It must be true if you ever feel the right to step in and tell someone else that they have to stop what they are doing. If you feel that slavery is wrong, not just in the United States, but anywhere, then you are saying that this value is better than another culture’s values if they permit slavery. One area where we need to be careful is that in condemning one practice such as slavery, we don’t condemn the whole culture. We all have blind spots and so do cultures. “Cultural relativism ignores the possibility that other cultures can teach Westerners valuable lessons in how to live the good life and vice versa” (Boss, p. 126.) When we open to the world we find that there are things we can teach and things we can learn. 16 Philosophy and Cultural Relativism You may be familiar with some famous philosophers such as Aristotle and Plato, so I thought it might be interesting to look at a couple of philosophers you may be less familiar with. A philosopher from another century from North Africa that you might not have heard of is Ibn Khaldun (1332-1406). “In his book The Muqaddimah, Khaldun argued that nomadic cultures are morally superior to sedentary, urban cultures. The customs of nomadic cultures such as the Bedouins, he claimed, enhance good traits such as courage, cooperation, and striving for justice; the customs of sedentary and urban cultures encourage immorality. Sedentary people are more concerned with their own individual ends and the indulgence in worldly pleasures. This preoccupation, Ibn Khaldun suggested, leads to moral evils such as injustice, mutual aggression, greed, and lack of courage” (Boss, p. 127.) Many studies have shown that cities, while bringing about many good things, are terrible places in terms of their influence on people. It is notable that the Kitty Genovese case happened in New York City. One wonders if the same kind of apathy would have happened in a small town. There are also many studies that confirm that people act poorly in large crowds in a way they don’t when with small groups or alone. This is where you find the riot mentality. This is why ethical thinking encourages people to think for themselves and not simply accept what their culture offers up to them. When Europeans first came to America they had a superior attitude that caused them to look down on the native people of this land. Slowly Americans have learned that there was, and still is, much wisdom to be learned from these indigenous people. “Sioux Indian philosopher John Fire Lame Deer likewise regards the European American lifestyle as morally unacceptable. He argues that the anthropocentric definition of moral community characteristic of the morality of Whites is destructive not just to the environment but also to the humans who are part of this environment. This destructive attitude of Whites toward nature and our environment, he argues, is based upon the misconception that the earth, the wind, the rocks, and the water are dead or inert. For the Sioux, these elements are ‘very much alive,’ and worthy of moral respect. We are all physical matter. Matter, in all its forms, has its own consciousness and life force” (Boss, p. 129.) This belief that everything is alive - animism - is an example of how our beliefs influence our ethics. If we really believed what Lame Deer is saying then we would naturally treat the world of animals and nature with more respect because they would be included in our circle of moral community. What would a cultural relativist say here about these thinkers? “Can we learn from philosophers such as Ibn Khaldun and John Fire Lame Deer? A cultural relativist would simply dismiss what they say as being right only for them, but not for us, because there are no transcultural moral standards. Plato, Ibn Khaldun, 17 and John Fire Lame Deer, on the other hand, claim that there are universal moral standards that we can use to pass judgment upon other cultures. Rather than dismissing a culture’s values as relevant only to the people living within that culture, a universalist view of morality encourages us to listen to other points of view and to attempt to understand other people. We should also be willing to analyze and, if necessary, revise or reject our own cultural values in light of our new understanding” (Boss, p. 129.) When we do this we have a way of teaching and learning. We might realize that some of our values are worth exporting and some need to be updated and improved by what we import. The Holocaust and Disillusionment with Cultural Relativism Cultural relativism took some heavy hits from the 20th century. How philosophers thought of the world before that violent century has to be reevaluated in light of what we now know. How could Germany, a country that saw itself as the epitome of civilization and superiority, sink to such low depths? How could the rest of the world do nothing for so long? How could a world abundant in food allow so many children to die of starvation everyday? We could go on and on, listing one atrocity after another committed by the best nations and cultures, including the United States. “In 1945, the tribunal at the United Nations Nuremberg Trials put forth a list of universal standards of justice that established parameters on the norms of civilized behavior. The tribunal maintained that these standards - which prohibited ‘crimes against humanity,’ ‘torture,’ ‘waging or preparing for an unjust war’ - were not a cultural creation but universal moral standards and, as such, binding on all people everywhere. According to the charter, we each have an individual moral responsibility not to take refuge in any laws or customs of our culture that run contrary to universal moral standards” (Boss, p. 134.) This is only possible if the cultural relativists are wrong. Hitler had the support of his people, so that would make him right in the eyes of a relativist, where morality is simply the socially accepted norms. Nowhere is this seen with more clarity than with Adolf Eichmann. Eichmann was one of the men most responsible for carrying out Hitler’s plans for the extermination of the Jews. It was Eichmann’s responsibility to collect the Jews throughout Europe and transport them to the death camps. At the end of the war he escaped with his family to South America, but was caught 15 years later and brought to Israel for trial. “At his trial, Eichmann said that, although he did initially have doubts about the extermination program, these doubts were put to rest when he realized that all his friends and professional colleagues supported the program. After all, he thought, ‘Who am I to judge?’ Nobody, not even his pastor, ever reproached him for what he did in the performance of his duties” (Boss, p. 136.) This is a horrible fallacy, the fallacy called the argument from popularity. This means that because a majority of people think something is right then it is right. But we have examples throughout history where the exact 18 opposite is true. In fact, most social reform movements are set in motion by small groups of people, even single individuals, who claim a higher vision of the truth and are willing to go against the majority. If we allow our conscience to be informed by the “crowd,” the majority, by what is popular, then we might very well silence our ability to grow in truth and wisdom and develop our ethical values into allowing us to draw our circles of moral community into ever growing circles of concern and compassion. “If justice is a cultural creation, we then have no justifiable grounds for labeling Eichmann and the Nazi culture unjust or immoral. All we can say is that the Nazi culture was no better or no worse than our culture - just different” (Boss, p. 136.) Surely most people do not want to be in a position of saying this. Critique of Cultural Relativism Cultural relativism made a certain amount of sense as anthropologists explored the world and people became aware of other ways of living life. Relativism comes with a noble intention to respect and tolerate differences. It was certainly a good antidote to Social Darwinism and the imperialism it led to. But hopefully now you see that there are real problems with it as well, and here we will try to summarize them. 1. “Cultural relativism is illogical. Disagreement among cultures does not prove that objective, transcultural moral standards do not exist. To claim that they do not exist is to commit the fallacy of ignorance. At the most, we can adopt an initial position of ethical skepticism regarding the existence of objective moral standards. By claiming that sociological relativism (what is) implies cultural relativism (what ought to be), cultural relativists are guilty of committing the naturalistic fallacy” (Boss, p. 137.) We have learned that what we thought were different moral values were actually differences in how these moral values were applied with the situation faced by various people and within the context of their belief systems. 2. “Cultural relativism does not work in a pluralist society. In today’s world, it is much harder to accept the claim of anthropologists like Ruth Benedict that there is general agreement within each culture regarding moral values. In modern cultures, pluralism is generally an acknowledged fact: The definition of what constitutes a culture can vary from subculture to subculture and even from person to person, and almost all of us are members of several cultures” (Boss, p. 138.) When a society is closed it is easier to get everyone to think the same way. But we have a mix of so many people and values in the United States that it is impossible to do this. This is one reason why you are not supposed to talk about politics or religion at family gatherings. There is usually too much disagreement! So what is relative to our community? What is our community? Cultural relativism dissolves into individual subjectivism, and we have already studied the many problems with that. 3. “Cultural relativism confuses custom with morality. Most of us distinguish between moral values and customs or nonmoral values such as 19 marriage customs, food preferences, religious rites, lifestyles, and preferences in fashion and music. By identifying morality with custom, cultural relativists draw behavior into the moral realm that may be outside the scope of morality. A custom that is inconvenient or even offensive is not necessarily immoral. Nude bathing, cross-dressing, and the use of obscene language in our own society, for example, are not necessarily immoral even though they may offend some people and run contrary to the norms and even the law in some places” (Boss, p. 138.) This means there are areas where we want to tolerate, even celebrate, diversity. Knowing what the difference is between this and moral matters is what the rest of this course is about. 4. “People act more morally when others are not around. Special groups, rather than encouraging us to behave morally, actually seem to inhibit helpful behavior. Our primary motivation for helping others seems not to be social pressure or cultural norms but a sense of personal responsibility that tends to be diffused, rather than reinforced, when one is part of a crowd” (Boss, pp. 138139.) If our morality is culturally formed (rather than informed) then it is curious that culture and society actually has a negative influence on the behavior of individuals. 5. “Cultural relativism does not correctly describe how we make moral judgments. We do pass judgment on the ‘moral’ norms of our own and other cultures. When we make a judgment, we do not do so by examining the customs and laws of, say, North Korea or by checking the latest polls to see how the majority of people in that country feel about a certain practice. Nor do we necessarily judge other cultures in light of our own norms. When we make these judgments, we generally do so by appealing to transcultural values such as justice and respect for human dignity rather than to cultural norms” (Boss, p. 140.) When a country feels the need to justify its actions to the world, this shows that it feels there is a standard it has to live up to. This is also why “international pressure” often really does help in a situation. In the United States local pressure works the same way. People were able to turn away from issues concerning civil rights if they did not actually see it. But once news shows started showing police dogs and fire hoses attacking unarmed and nonviolent citizens exercising their rights, people applied pressure and things began to change. 6. “There are moral values that seem to exist in all or most known societies. The degree of variance among moral values is not as extreme as cultural relativists claim. Many extremes of behavior - such as cannibalism, human sacrifice, and unrestricted sexual activity among children - that have been used to illustrate the irreconcilable differences between moral values in Western and ‘primitive’ cultures have never been documented by reliable sources. Indeed, some people, when they first come into prolonged contact with people from different cultures or subcultures, are surprised at the extent of shared moral values” (Boss, p. 140.) This is another good example of why we need to use critical thinking in our ethical deliberations. We need to ask good questions and get the facts before we rush to judgment. 7. “Cultural relativism is divisive and creates an us/them mentality. Because cultural relativism rules out the possibility of rational discussion between 20 cultures, when cross-cultural values come into conflict and rhetoric or persuasion fails, groups may resort to either apathy and isolationism, when the other culture’s values do not threaten theirs, or violence, when another culture’s values or actions impinge on or threaten them. The latter happens on an international level, in the case of war, and on a national level, in the case of gang warfare and racial, gender, and ethnic violence” (Boss, p. 140.) It is a sad irony that a theory that was set in promotion to reach tolerance and respect can lead to its own opposite. Summary Cultural relativism recognizes that culture influences our ethics and how we see the world. It also points to the values of respecting legitimate differences and respecting other people with different ways of going about things. It only becomes a problem when it takes its version of truth and says that it is the only version of truth. Relativism is one piece of the ethical puzzle; it is not the whole puzzle. “Humans are profoundly social animals. Like language, morality does not exist independently of culture. Just as all human languages share a common grammatical structure, so too, most moral philosophers believe, does morality share a common structure or foundation in all cultures. As with language, culture shapes how we express this common morality. Some cultures do a better job than others. Because of the role of culture in giving morality practical expression, it is important that we understand the norms of our culture and respect them to the extent that they do not conflict with the underlying moral foundation. If we are to grow morally and make more satisfactory moral decisions in our lives, it is important that we be willing to critically analyze our cultural norms in light of this universal, transcultural moral foundation” (Boss, p. 142.) You might be wondering how we can find these universal values. That is the task of the rest of this course. We will begin the next lecture by learning how we can move beyond relativism by first studying the relationship of morality and religion. We will then explore the nature of moral development and how people mature ethically. Until then, be good! Bibliography: Judith A. Boss, Ethics For Life: A Text With Readings, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2008] Donald Palmer, Looking at Philosophy: The Unbearable Heaviness of Philosophy Made Lighter, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2006] Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy, [New York, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1945] 21 Richard Tarnas, The Passion of the Western Mind: Understanding the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World View, [New York, New York: Harmony Books, 1991] Bruce Waller, You Decide! Current Debates in Contemporary Moral Problems, [New York, New York: Pearson, 2006] 22