Back to Realism Applied to Home Page Biological Psychology, 30 (1990), pp. 181-187 Reply_Shanks90.doc SHARING A COMMON LANGUAGE ABOUT CONDITIONING REQUIRES ACCURATE CHARACTERIZATIONS OF EACH OTHERS’ POSITIONS: REPLY TO SHANKS * John J. FUREDY Department of Psychology, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada, MSS IA1 Shanks' characterizations of the positions taken in papers that he comments on are inaccurate on a number of basic counts. For example, the papers were concerned with human autonomic Pavlovian conditioning, whereas Shanks refers to no autonomic evidence in his reply. Again, the two papers more specifically targeted by Shanks (Furedy, 1988b; Furedy & Riley, 1987) do not deny "that cognitive processes have any relevance for conditioning", but rather advocate that both cognitive and non-cognitive factors play roles that need to be empirically determined for different preparations and conditions. And the characterizat ion of cognitive factors in those papers, contrary to Shanks, is not a teleological, intentional one, no matter how fashionable such teleological forms of cognitive psychology may be among many current philosophers and psychologists. We can proceed towards an empirical resolution of disagreements about the role of cognitive factors in human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning only if we both refer to the relevant autonomic conditioning evidence, and also characterize each others' positions with some accuracy. Keywords: Autonomic conditioning, Pavlovian, cognitive theory, intention 1. Introduction I recognize that the hortatory tone of my paper's title may strike some as inappropriate, but consider, to begin with, that the topic of the recent Biological Psychology symposium dealt not with " human Pavlovian conditioning" (Shanks, 1990, p. 171) but with human autonomic Pavlovian conditioning (Furedy, 1988a, p. 77) which is, of course, a sub-class of Pavlovian conditioning. Similarly, the two papers that comprise the main target of Shanks' comments (Furedy, 1988b; Furedy & Riley, 1987) were restricted (both by * The preparation of this paper was supported by a grant from the National Science and Engineering Research Council of Canada. The author is am indebted to M agnus Kristjansson for comments. Address for reprints: John J. Furedy, as above. Editor's note; This is a reply to a commentary paper which appears in this issue (Biological Psychology, Volume 30, Number 2, pp. 171-179. Requests for reprints of the commentary paper should be addressed to its author, David R. Shanks, MRC Applied Psychology Unit, 15 Chaucer Road, Cambridge CB2, 2EF, U.K. 0301-0511/90/$3.50 0 1990 - Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. (North-Holland) 182 J.J. Furedy / Sharing a common language titles and by textual content) to autonomic conditioning. Of course both our and others' (Kimmel & Lachnit, 1988; Lovibond, 1988; Martin & Levey, 1988; Ohman, 1988; Siddle & Bond, 1988) papers made reference to ideas that were not originally developed from autonomic conditioning evidence and theoriz ing, but the discussions of the relevant empirical evidence focussed on autonomic conditioning. In contrast, Shanks (1990) makes no reference to any autonomic conditioning evidence. Accordingly, when Shanks indicates that "it is disheartening to discover that different people who all have an interest in conditioning can fail to share a common language in which to discuss it" (p. 172), I suggest that his pessimistic appraisal of the extent of shared common language is due to his own looseness in characterizing the positions taken in the papers on which he is commenting. Similarly, it is to grossly mischaracterize the Furedy (1988b) and Furedy and Riley (1987) papers as taking a position that "essentially denies that cognitive processes have any relevance for conditioning" (p. 171). At the beginning of the penultimate paragraph of the former paper, I wrote that "although in the present paper I have been concerned to explore S-R factors in HPAC [human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning], it should not be thought that I do not recognize, or am uninterested in, the role of cognitive factors", and ended the description of our research on these cognitive factors by stating that my "interest in measuring relational-learning (cognitive) processes in HPAC continues" (Furedy, 1988b, pp. 148-149); references to those relational-learning measurement papers that began in the early 1970s are available in Furedy 1988b). Rather than citing similar passages from the Furedy and Riley (1987) paper, I shall just quote a book reviewer who read it as proposing a " two process theory in which response learning ... and cognitive learning ... can [both] be tested in dual paradigm experiments" (O'Gorman, 1988, p. 372). Again, then, at least part of the problem of Shanks' complaint about the lack of shared common language stems from his failure to characterize accurately the position on which he is commenting. In the same vein, the following brief comments on Shanks' four points (p. 172) reveal a lack of accuracy in characterizing positions. Regarding (1) the cognitive account that I am concerned with is not the teleological one that assumes purpose and "intentionality", and seeks to provide an explanation of behavior in terms of what is "rational" or "consistent with the purposes" of the organism. It is also true that Tolman combined teleology and cognitivism, but, as stated in one of the two target papers, "the connection between cognitivism and purposivism is merely historical or contingent, rather than logical or necessary" (Furedy & Riley, 1987, p. 16). An example of an ateological, mechanistic cognitive approach to behavior in general by a phil osopher psychologist is a book by Maze (1983), who is strongly committed to a pro-cognitive but anti-teleological position. With regard to cognitive, but ateological strains in my own position concerning human Pavlovian autonomic J.J. Furedy / Sharing a common language 183 conditioning, an example is provided by "the claim that awareness of the CS-US relationship is necessary, but not sufficient, for autonomic conditioning (see, e.g., Dawson, 1973; Dawson & Furedy, 1976; Furedy, 1973) [which] is a position that involves no talk of purposes whatsoever" (Furedy & Riley, 1984). Concerning (2), for reasons given above (and elaborated in Furedy & Riley, 1984, and Maze, 1983), I reject the equation of "cognitive" with "intentional", but agree that an intentional (i.e., teleological or purposive) "theory of Pavlovian conditioning" (or of any other set of psychological phenomena) "would be extremely difficult, a priori" (p. 172) to construct, because of the circularity involved in the explanatory constructs. Furedy and Riley (1984) indicated the difficulties involved in teleological accounts in Skinnerian behaviorism, and similar comments have been made regarding physiological psychology (Furedy, 1989a), and a psychophysiological account of cardiac reactivity (Furedy, 1989b). Shanks' third point that "instead" of the intentional theory, "the evidence points to the view that Pavlovian conditioning consists in the learning of excitatory or inhibitory links between the mental images of the conditioned (CS) and unconditioned (US) stimuli" (p. 172) seems to confuse a priori reasoning (that he apparently uses to dismiss intentional theory) with a posteriori (i.e., evidence-based) reasoning. In addition, the fact that Shanks does not refer to any autonomic conditioning "evidence" renders this point of marginal relevance for either the Pavlovian autonomic conditioning symposium in Biological Psychology (for terms of reference, see Furedy, 1988a), or for the two target papers on autonomic conditioning (Furedy, 1988b; Furedy & Riley, 1987). The fourth point asserts that the distinction between the "mechanism of learning" and the "nature of the knowledge that is acquired during learning" is an "absolutely crucial" one (p. 172). In my reading of Shanks' paper, there is not much in the following text that seems to provide any logical (apriori) or evidential (a posteriori) justification for this strong assertion, but, in any case, the assertion is irrelevant to the two-process view of Pavlovian autonomic conditioning that we have put forward, namely that both cognitive (S-S) and non-cognitive (S-R) processes or mechanisms play a part in the phenomenon, and that the parts played need to be determined by empirical research. The remaining three sections of Shanks' paper do not really refer to issues that were raised in the target papers. For example, the third section discusses the relation between "cognition" and "conditioning", but the former term is taken in its representational, intentional sense, whereas the latter term (from the subsequent text) includes instrumental as well as Pavlovian conditioning, and excludes any reference to Pavlovian autonomic conditioning. Accordingly, the remainder of this reply, rather than being organized in terms of Shanks' sections, will simply make brief comments on a few important mischaracteri- 184 J.J. Furedy / Sharing a common language zations of positions taken in the target papers (Furedy, 1988b; Furedy & Riley, 1987) as these appear in Shanks' paper. 2. Mischaracterizations of positions taken in the target papers Shanks cites our definition of a proposition as "any expression that is statable in the form X is Y" (Furedy & Riley, 1987, p. 3, emphasis added), and considers it to be refuted by the example of "Charles loves Diana" (p. 172). I think Shanks has neglected to note the presently emphasized letters in the definition he cites. The expression "Charles loves Diana" does, of course, qualify as a proposition, since it can, without too much ingenuity, be readily put into an X-is-Y form, i.e. where "Charles", "is", and "a lover of Diana" would serve as the subject (X), copula, and predicate (Y) terms in a proposition which clearly has truth value. Concerning more general aspects of our cognitive/propositional position, it may be more "usual" to "refer to intentional, or representational, mental states", and it may even be true that many people are on Shanks' side in thinking this to be a more " perspicuous" (p. 173) position. However, adopting such a position entails accepting a representational theory of knowledge along with the teleological intentionality concept. This is not the place to detail the difficulties to which this stance leads when one attempts to develop a coherent and non-circular explanatory system (for an account of these difficulties in explaining behavior, see Maze, 1983), but of course the fact that "numerous psychologists and philosophers have advocated the view that cognitive psychology concerns intentional states" (p. 173) does not make it right. In another discussion of related issues, I have conceded that " I have not kept up with the details of the latest fashions in cognitive science" (Furedy, 1989c, p. 131) and I am prepared to make a parallel concession here with regard to being out of step with one form of currently popular cognitive psychology. What I am not prepared to concede, however, is that the position we have put forward in the target papers (Furedy, 1988b; Furedy & Riley, 1987) has to be cast in representational-intentional terms. Rather, our cognitive/propositional position is deliberately ateleological, and specifically avoids representational language in its formulation. Hence when Shanks ends his section by asserting that "Furedy's concern, though, is to see what such a [n intentional, representational] system has to do with conditioning" (p. 174), he has grossly mischaracterized what our concern was, as stated in the two target papers. Perhaps the sentence that contains the most serious inaccuracies is the assertion that the "evidence seems compelling that animals and humans do learn S-S associations, that is, they learn something about the relationship between CS and US, rather than, say, between the CS and UR" (p. 176). TO begin with, if evidence relevant to this claim were properly cited, it would have J.J. Furedy / Sharing a common language 185 to be from human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning (the area of our concern), and no such evidence is cited. In addition, it has been made quite clear that we have not argued that the human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning (HPAC) phenomenon is either a result solely of S-S or of S-R learning. Rather, we have put forward a " ‘two-process view’ (Furedy & Riley, 1987, pp. 10-13), which recognizes both as potentially important determinants of the HPAC phenomenon" (Furedy, 1988b, p. 141). Finally, and most importantly, the quoted, sentence from Shanks misrepresents the S-R position when it suggests that the position asserts that the organism learns something “ about” the “relationship between ... the CS and US” (p. 10), because that constitutes a propositional (in our terms, cognitive) formulation of the S-R position. The CS-UR relation, like “the Hull-Spence rg-ss hypothetical mechanism ... does not express a propositional relationship, because the true/false category cannot be sensibly applied to it” (Furedy & Riley, 1987, p. 3). In Furedy (1988b) I proposed, as a particular formulation of the S-R position, a revised contiguity-reinforcement S-R theory, and both I and Kimmel (1988, p. 196) agreed that revivals of these sorts of S-R positions will probably remain unpopular in terms of receiving experimental research attention. That is a matter of choice. It is not a matter of choice, but of logic, that such S-R positions cannot adequately be characterized in propositional, cognitive terms, as if they asserted that the organism learns about S-R (contiguity between CS and UR) or R-S (reinforcement between CR and US) relations. Another inaccurate characterization is the claim that "Furedy consistently implies that an S-S theory must be an intentional one" (p. 177). Despite the use of italics in the above quote, the citations that Shanks uses to back up his strong claim provide no justification for it. Instead, as indicated at the outset of this paper, the position taken in the target papers refers to cognition in its purely propositional, ateleological sense, even though earlier workers like Tolman, and many later workers, may hold to a teleological, intentional view. Our concern has been with an examination of the role of non-intentional S-S (propositional knowledge) processes as measured by subjective contingency and S-R factors in Pavlovian autonomic conditioning. It should also be noted that my recent discussions on this topic with more cognitively oriented workers like Dawson, Siddle, and Lovibond (of whom only some, like Lovibond, hold a strongly intentional view of cognition) have been based on experimental autonomic conditioning evidence concerning the observed relations between subjective contingency and electrodermal measures. Finally, on the question of whether the Rescorla-Wagner model is cognitive (p. 178), I think it best in the interests of space to refer readers to footnote 2 in Furedy and Riley, (1987, pp. 21-22), which details why, despite the labelling of the authors of this model as a contiguity one, it is really a cognitive-contingency model. Of course to follow this argument the distinction between (propositional) contingency and (nonpropositional) contiguity must 186 J.J. Furedy / Sharing a common language be clearly understood, and talk of learning "about" the relationship between CS and UR must be eschewed. 3. Conclusions In referring to the papers in the special issue of Biological Psychology, Shanks referred to "a casual observer reading these papers" (p. 171). I suggest that readers consider these papers (including the replies by the participants) a little less casually, recognizing, at the very least, that the topic was human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning, even though, of course, other areas are also of relevance. In addition, considering that Shanks' remarks were focussed on my paper in that collection (Furedy, 1988b), and were intended to discuss the role of cognitive factors, I draw attention to the fact that I began that paper with three cognitive accounts of human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning which "all posit propositional information as a central determinant" (Furedy, 1988b, p. 139), and reviewed evidence that was contrary to this account (Furedy, 1988b, pp. 139-141). Shanks fails to refer to any of this (or any other) autonomic conditioning evidence. My hope is that both opponents and proponents of current cognitive views will do so in future discussions, because, to end with the comment made by another contributor to the special issue, "Only a science that admits all the facts can hope to really comprehend any of them" (Kimmel, 1988, p. 196). References Dawson, M.E. (1973). Can classical conditioning occur without contingency learning? A review and evaluation of the evidence. Psychophysiology, 10, 82-86. Dawson, M.E., & Furedy, J.J. (1976). The role of a wareness in human differential autonomic classical conditioning: The necessary-gate hypothesis. Psychophysiology, IS, 50-53. Furedy, J.J. (1973) Some limits on the cognitive control of conditioned autonomic behavior. Psychophysiology, IO, 108-111. Furedy, J.J. (1988a). Issues in human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning: Introduction. Biological Psychology, 27, 77-78. Furedy, J.J. (1988b). Arguments for and proposed tests of a revised S-R contiguityreinforcement theory of human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning: Some contra-cognitive claims. Biological Psychology, 27, 137-151. Furedy, J.J. (1989a). The state of psychological theory as illustrated by Melzack’s new conceptual nervous system model/theory: Strong on imaginativeness but weak in inference. Canadian Psychologist, 30, 711-712. Furedy, J.J. (1989b). On approaches to explaining cardiovascular reactivity: Towards explanations that explain. Psychophysiology, 26, 483-485. Furedy, J.J. (1989~). On the relevance of philosophy for psychological research: Fashi ons versus fundamentals. Australian Journal of Psychology, 41, 131-33. J.J. Furedy / Sharing a common language 187 Furedy, J.J., & Riley, D.M. (1984). Undifferentiated and 'moat -beam' percepts in WatsonianSkinnerian behaviorism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 7, 625426. Furedy, J.J. & Riley, D.M. (1987). Human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning and the cognitive paradigm. In G. Davey (Pd.), Conditioning in humans (pp. l-25). Chichester: Wiley. Kimmel, H.D. (1988). Restructuring of cognitivism in conditioning. Biological Psychology, 27, 195-19s. Kimmel, H.D., & Lachnit, H. (1988). The Rescorla-Wagner theory does not predict contextual control of phasic responses in transswitching. Biological Psychology., 27, 95-112. Lovibond, P.F. (1988). Predictive validity in human causal judgement and Pavlovian conditioning. Biological Psychology, 27, 79-93. Martin, I., & Levey, A.C. (1988). Classical conditioning in a cognitive era. Biological Psychology, 27, 153-166. Maze, J.R. (1983). The meaning of behaviour. London: Allen and Unwin. O'Gorman, J.G. (1988). Review of cognitive processes and Pavlovian conditioning in humans. Psychophysiology, 25, 370-371. Ohman, A. (1988). Nonconscious control of autonomic responses: A role for Pavlovian condition ing? Biological Psychology, 27, 113-135. Shanks, D.R. (1990). On the cognitive theory of conditioning. Biological Psychology, 30, 171179, this issue. Siddle, D.A.T. & Bond, N.W. (1988). Avoidance learning, Pavlovian conditioning, and the development of phobias. Biological Psychology, 27, 167-183.