Back to Realism Applied to Home Page Biological Psychology 27 (1988) 191-194 Towards_ev88.doc TOWARDS EVIDENTIALLY BASED, NON-CIRCULAR EMANATIONS OF HUMAN PAVLOVIAN AUTONOMIC CONDITIONING AS A GENUINE PHENOMENON A REALIST PERSPECTIVE John J. FUREDY * Department of Psychology, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S IA1 Reflecting on the papers of my fellow participants has suggested the following five prescriptions that would, in my view, facilitate our making genuine progress towards more scientifically-based explanations of human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning. 1. Test basic assumptions of models rather than models themselves Models themselves cannot really be tested, because they do not assert anything, being mere analogies or metaphors that are useful only for generating hypotheses. However, there are basic assumptions that underlie each model. These assumption are genuine assertions about the world, and are therefore open to test, even though the proponents of the model themselves may not welcome such tests, especially when the tests turn out to be disconfirmatory. The paper by Kimmel and Lachnit is the best example of this sort of basic-assumption testing, where the assumption under examination is that background tonic and phasic CSs are functionally equivalent. As shown by Kimmel and Lachnit, this is a basic assumption of the Rescorla-Wagner model in the sense that it can be derived from their formulation. It is also a genuine, testable assertion about conditioning, as is indicated by the fact that it can be stated in terms that are independent of the model's terminology. The assumption is tested and falsified (though not disproved, because no experimental evidence is ever known to be certainly true) in the experiments reported by Kimmel and Lachnit. My added interpretative suggestion is that Kimmel and Lachnit's evidence shows that conditioning is not just a purely cognitive, S-S process, but also involves response-learning processes, in this case the interaction between phasic and tonic CRs (my emphasis) as suggested by Kimmel and Lachnit (p. 96) following Asratyan (1965). Siddle and Bond deal with broader issues than do Kimmel and Lachnit, but their approach is similar in as much as they attempt to bring evidence to bear * I am indebted to Maria Gurevich for comments on an earlier draft of this paper. 0301-0511/88/$3.50 0 1988, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. (North-Holland) 192 J.J. Furedy / Non-circular explanations of Pavlovian conditioning on genuine assertions such as the claim that avoidance involves both classical (Pavlovian) and instrumental conditioning, or that "Pavlovian conditioning plays only a minor role in the development of human phobias." (p. 175). With regard to the latter issue, my comment would be that it matters crucially whether one accepts the currently dominant cognitive accounts of Pavlovian conditioning. If one views Pavlovian conditioning as simply a contingency-registration process, then the experiments one designs tend to reflect this, and they may not provide a sufficiently effective US to generate fear (which, in S-R terms, is the conditionable component of the unconditional pain response). 2. Treat human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning (HPAC) as a specifiable phenomenon in its own right This prescription runs contrary to viewing HPAC as a mere index of some other underlying process. The nature of the underlying process is typically determined by whatever the current theoretical predilection happens to be, which was S-R oriented several decades ago and is "cognitively" oriented nowadays. So I oppose any assignment to HPAC of a mere "role" (Öhman) in the pantheon of current cognitive constructs, but rather would advocate studying HPAC to determine, empirically, the extent to which it is influenced by cognitive and non-cognitive processes. A more subtle form of selective treatment of HPAC as a subsidiary rather than genuine phenomenon is one where only those forms are recognized as genuine conditioning phenomena which fit in with the current cognitive framework. A good example of this in HPAC is long-interval skin-conductance-conditioning conditioning, where the second-interval response (SIR) is considered to be a clearer case of conditioning than the first-interval response (FIR) on the (often implicit) grounds that the SIR more clearly reflects (cognitive) CS-US predictive processes. But the brute fact that is usually ignored is that, in terms of the basic, neutral, atheoretical criterion of conditioning (i.e., CS + performance exceeding CSperformance), it is the FIR rather than the SIR which is far more reliable in SCR conditioning. Again, when Lovibond argues against the (mostly) FIR-based counter-cognitive evidence from the Toronto laboratory (pp. 84485) he ignores the fact that the autonomic/cognitive correlation required by the cognitive position failed to emerge in one experiment which did measure SIRS (Schiffman & Furedy, 1972). More importantly, I suggest that examination of the second half of his paragraph indicates that he has erected a number of arbitrary and over-rigorous methodological requirements that would, if applied to any other HPAC conditioning experiment, disqualify it from being considered as methodologically adequate. So, for example, given that in all the Toronto experiments, the difference between negative- and zerocontingency CSs was clearly J.J. Furedy / Non-circular explanations of Pavlovian conditioning 193 reflected in expectancy ratings, what does one do with the criticism that the "negative contingency programmed in the explicitly unpaired group was relatively weak" (p. 84)? 3. Define basic terms with precision and avoid metaphysical distinctions Currently it is the term "cognitive" that is the main instance of a term that is used without sufficient precision, and without pointing to specific authors, I think it is fair to say that many papers in a number of places follow the prevalent practice of using an almost infinite extension for this term, so that it can apply to all psychological processes. By metaphysical distinctions, I mean those that are not grounded in empirically specifiable aspects, but rather refer to differing pre-theoretical predilections. The most ubiquitous such distinction which runs through a number of papers is that between animal and human processes, where this refers not to the (empirically specifiable) difference in subjects, but to some metaphysical difference in purported level of complexity, as in the contrast between "animal conditioning and learning" and "human memory". Unless one subscribes to the Cartesian view of there being a fundamental difference between human and animal processes, dividing areas along human/animal lines makes no sense. And although it may be administratively convenient for reasons of subject maintenance to separate animal from human researchers, that cannot constitute an epistemological basis of distinction. In epistemological terms, it is the processes being investigated rather than the subjects used that determine the content of scientific areas. Another such distinction, which is specifically referred to by Öhman, is that between the following set of terms on the one hand-automatic, dumb, unconscious, and primitive-and the opposite terms on the other hand-controlled, intelligent, conscious, and advanced. Although these opposites can be used in a scientific sense, provided one specifies how the distinctions referred to can be tested, they can also be used in a literary, global sense which refers to metaphysical, non-empiricallyspecifiable distinctions. In the latter case, one is involved more in literature than in science, no matter how effective that involvement may be. An instance of that effectiveness, at least for me, is Öhman's choice of his initial quote from Clive James, of whom I am a great fan as a literary figure, but not as a scientifically accurate describer of experimental psychological positions. 4. Fight narrowness of conception with facts not fads I agree that it is overly narrow to: not measure human CS-US expectancy directly in conditioning experiments (Lovibond); not pay attention to affective and individual-difference factors (Martin & Levey); view HPAC as "mindless 194 J.J. Furedy / Non-circular explanations of Pavlovian conditioning and mechanic" (Öhman). However, narrowness of this sort is, in the end, not well repaired by noting that the current fashion is now against these views. It is better to point to evidence that is logically relevant to the view, and/or to suggest tests that would assess whether these narrow conceptions are correct. 5. Avoid gross mischaracterizations of the literature Compared to professions such as the law, scholarship in experimental psychology is notoriously poor. Each of us knows only the mis-citations of our own papers, so I shall take the Dawson and Furedy (1976) and Furedy and Riley (1987) papers as my examples. The former is mischaracterized by Öhman, when he groups it with other papers that "endorse strong statements" (p. 114) about awareness underlying conditioning, whereas much of the Dawson and Furedy (1976) data show that awareness is not even correlated with conditioning. The Furedy and Riley (1987) paper is mischaracterized by Martin and Levey when they cite it to support the (cognitive) view that, in conditioning, the "subject is learning something about the probability of reinforcement, the signalling properties of the paradigm, and is forming expectancies (my emphasis) about them" (p. 162). This thoroughly cognitive characterization of Furedy and Riley (1987) is inaccurate. Recent reviews characterise this chapter as providing "caution against ill-defined and uncritical 'cognitive imperialism”’ (Thomas, 1988. p. 187) and proposing a "two-process theory in which response learning... and cognitive learning... can [both] be tested in dual paradigm experiments" (O'Gorman, 1988, p. 372). References Asratyan. EA. (1965). Compensator adaptation, reflex activity, and the brain (S.A. Carson. Trans.). New York: Oxford University Press. Dawson, M.E. & Furedy, J.J. (1976). The role of awareness in human differential autonomic classical conditioning: The necessary-gate hypothesis. Psychophysiology, 13. 50-53. Furedy, J.J. & Riley, D.M. (1987). Human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning and the cognitive paradigm. In G. Davey (Ed.), Conditioning in humans (pp. l-25). Chichester: Wiley. O'Gorman, J.G. (1988). Review of Cognitive Processes and Pavlovian Conditioning in Humans. Psychophysiology, 25, 370-371. Popper, K.R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson. Prokasy, W.F. (Ed.) (1965). Classical conditioning: A symposium. New York: AppletonCentury-Crofts. Schiffmann, K. & Furedy, J.J. (1972) Failures of contingency and cognitive factors to affect long-interval differential Pavlovian autonomic conditioning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 96, 215-218. Siddle, D.A.T., & Remington, B. (1978). A comment on Furedy & Paulos (1977). Psychophysiology, 15, 609-610. Thomas. G.V. (198X). Review of Cognitive Processes and Pavlovian Conditioning in Humans. Biological Psychology, 25. 1X7-8.