THURSDAY NIGHT LECTURE PROFESSOR ADRIAN SNODGRASS TRANSCRIPT OF INTRODUCTION: GLEN HILL I must say it is a pleasure to be asked to introduce Adrian. I’ll start by doing a little bit of scene-setting. I joined the faculty as a PhD student in the early 90’s intending to do a PhD on ecologically sustainable architecture. And, for reasons that are still unclear to me, I was given Adrian as a supervisor. His first piece of advice was that I should go immediately and begin reading Martin Heidegger. And although I was too embarrassed to say it, I do remember thinking ‘who on earth is Martin Heidegger’? But the advice proved very fruitful, not just because Heidegger’s work grounded the deep ecology movement that I was interested in at the time, but because it opened a rich vein of thought that could be mined (and as you’ll see I’m still mining it) to reveal many new understandings of architecture. As an observer of the drama that was playing out within the Faculty at that time, I can only say that it seemed to me that Adrian, and his collaborator Richard Coyne, were on a sort of evangelical mission to rid the world, beginning with the faculty, of all outbreaks of positivist, metaphysical thinking. Adrian and Richard refer to it rather understatedly in their book as ‘countering regressive scientism’. Looking back now, I am in a way thankful that these pockets of positivism did exist, and that they did provoke in response such an eruption of intellectual energy that it resulted the production of a remarkable series of texts in such a short space of time. These texts have of course become a central part of the book that is being launched tonight. The task I see Adrian engaged in is not one of small consequence, and it cannot easily be summarised. At issue is whether metaphysics will ultimately triumph in every domain, including in the way we think about design, or whether another path can be allowed to emerge. The central question is one of truth, but not truth in any empirical or factual sense. In a newly released book called ‘The New Heidegger’, the claim is made that for Heidegger, (and I quote) ‘there is a certain undecidability at the heart of truth itself.’ And that ‘this undecidability is the domain of the utmost decision, the domain in which history as such is being decided.’ (endquote) This is a big claim. The author goes on to clarify this claim by posing the question of whether two possible trajectories for history now confront us. Whether, on our current path (and I quote) ‘truth will recede more and more into the open and the disclosed only, whether there will ultimately be only beings — whether metaphysics will ultimately triumph across the board.’ (endquote) Or whether another path is possible where (and I quote again) ‘a counter movement will be initiated in which the self-concealing itself will be brought to bear on thought, on culture in general.’ (endquote) It may sound paradoxical to claim that truth might recede into the open. We might instead expect that truth comes closer, is clearer, when it is brought into the open. The point is, however, that our endeavours to gather more and more facts, more knowledge, clearer descriptions of everything in our world, is causing something more significant to be concealed. Modernity has long been on a path of attempting to articulate greater and greater knowledge about our world. The pace at which we are disclosing knowledge about our world has become more and more frenetic (and is perhaps most frenetic in the very type of institution we are now gathered). Our attitude has become one of: if we don’t know it, we will come to know it. In other words, everything is conceived as an object that is potentially knowable. However, by frantically filling our world with these facts, these objects of knowledge, these truths, we become less and less able to see beyond them, and to recognise that they are themselves grounded in something else. Heidegger wants to make it clear that this something else that grounds our knowledge cannot itself be disclosed as an object of knowledge. This ground is not like some extra set of facts that has yet to be revealed, some new object of knowledge that awaits discovery. For Heidegger it is a groundless ground, an abyss. So what is the nature of this groundless ground, this abyss, which is being covered over by all the knowledge we continue to accrue? To give you some hint of my sense of this abyss, I want to tell you about a class I used to teach. Until recently I taught a subject that was aimed at helping students think about the design process. Inevitably during the course the question would arise: ‘will computers ever be able to design?’ At this point I would give my safe answer: ‘Not the way we do.’ But persistent students would then ask, ‘but what about when computers are able to be programmed with every bit of data about a design situation, what then?’ At this point I would tell them a short, rehearsed, anecdote. I would ask them to imagine a book about some subject or other (hold up book). And to imagine that we had the task of programming all knowledge about the book into the computer. So we put in the author, the publication details, every fact contained on every page of the book and so on, until we had captured all aspects of the book. At this point I ask them to imagine that we are sitting at our computer and we notice that the table on which the computer is resting is wobbly. (Some of you will be ahead of me here). We look under the table and see that one leg of the table is shorter than the rest. We are faced with a design problem. Without thinking we reach for the book that is handy (hold up) and I shove it under the short leg — a design solution. And this, I try to persuade my students, is not a solution that the computer could have generated. Tenacious students might then object and question why the exact thickness of the book, its mass, density, impact resistance and so on were not programmed into the computer. My response would be that, firstly, doing so would amount to thinking up possible solutions in anticipation of possible design problems and then entering these as data. At this point I would claim we are doing the designing rather than the computer. But even more significantly, experience (in this case our previous experience of books, table legs etc) which grounds any design move, is not anything like an object with properties or articulations that are somehow already present and ready for cataloguing (as data for example). Even as they occur, we are not thematically aware of all the dimensions of our own experience, a condition that we use inadequate words like ‘tacit’ or ‘embodied’ to describe. And, if we consider the way in which we remember our experiences, their remembering varies according to the context in which the remembering occurs. The word re-member carries that very implication, as the members, the parts of experience, are reassembled, re-membered into a new whole with each remembering. Experience thus appears to exist only as a potential or virtual reservoir, capable of grounding limitless future articulations in limitless future contexts. In my story, it is my experience of books that enables me to reinterpret a book as a wedge. My contention is that experience has something of the quality of the groundless ground, the abyss to which Heidegger points. And, parallel to Heidegger’s warning regarding truth, our capacity to generate representations of experience (as memories, as descriptions, as possible design solutions, and so on) might lead us to believe that the articulations, the representations, of the experience are the truth of the experience, thus concealing the unrepresentable potentiality of the experience itself. Importantly the claim here is not that the articulations, the representations, the ontic facts gathered from experience are wrong. They are in the proper sense correct. It is rather that by giving these representations the status of final ground, as our Western metaphysical tradition has done, their own unrepresentable ground, their abyssal ground, has been concealed. And here is where I situate Adrian’s mission in the book. The remonstrations contained in this book against the various manifestations of positivism, representational and metaphysical thinking in design, architecture and architectural education, are not about claiming that these representational formulations are factually incorrect. The issue is instead that such representational Western thinking is reductive and limiting, and conceals, as Heidegger states, a more significant truth. The alternatives pursued in the book are attempts to remove the certain grounds of Western rationalism, thus exposing a groundless ground, an abyss. And this of course is where the anti-foundational thinking in the book, which arrives from contemporary continental philosophy, resonates with Adrian’s scholarship on traditional Eastern thinking, where notions such as the abyss are more familiar. So as I said at the beginning, Adrian is engaged in no small task. I see his work as part of a struggle to keep open the now tiny window of opportunity that may allow another history to emerge, a history that might counter our current reductivist path. Now for those of you who are perhaps getting a little twitchy with all this talk of the abyss and ontological uncertainty, here is the ontic version of my introduction: a set of facts about Adrian. At the age of twenty-five Adrian ‘escaped’ from the parochial Australia of the 1950’s and went to Sri-Lanka and India, where he worked and studied aspects of Indian thought, art, architecture and religion for more than six years, acquiring a knowledge of Tamil and Sanskrit. He then spent seven years in Japan where he studied forms of Far Eastern Buddhism, and learned Japanese and Chinese. This was followed by a number of years in Hong Kong and Indonesia. In 1976 he returned to the University of Sydney where he taught in both the Department of Religious Studies and the Department of Architecture. His Masters thesis, The Symbolism of the Stupa: was completed in 1981. The Symbolism of the Stupa was published in 1985 and is now widely recognised as a classic. In 1981 Adrian accepted a joint appointment as Japan Foundation Lecturer in Religious Studies and Architecture, and began work on his doctoral dissertation, which he completed in 1985. The dissertation, Stellar and Temporal Symbolism in Traditional Architecture, used Chinese, Indic, pre-Columbian, African, Christian and Islamic materials to analyse the ways in which temporal concepts and cycles of time are incorporated in buildings. This work was later published as Architecture, Time and Eternity. In 1988 Adrian published a third major work on Asian architecture, The Matrix and Diamond World Mandalas in Shingon Buddhism. Adrian then extended his scholarship into the field of contemporary western philosophy with numerous ground breaking papers which drew together contemporary hermeneutic philosophy, architecture and design. Some of which are contained in the book being launched tonight. After retiring from his full-time position at the University of Sydney in 1998 Adrian continues to pursue and develop his research interests. He is currently an Honorary Research Associate with our own Faculty of Architecture, editor of the journal Architecture Theory Review, and Adjunct Professor in the Centre for Cultural Research at the University of Western Sydney. Will you please join me in welcoming Adrian Snodgrass.