RHETORICAL CITIZENSHIP AS A CONCEPTUAL FRAME IN ACADEME or: WHAT WE TALK ABOUT WHEN WE TALK ABOUT RHETORICAL CITIZENSHIP Introduction In suggesting the theme of rhetorical citizenship for this conference, Christian and I and the other conference planners hoped to learn more about what colleagues near and far think about and do with this concept, what they consider it to cover, and where they find its strengths and weaknesses. While we think that rhetoric has something valuable to contribute to the study of citizenship, it cannot possibly do the work alone. Rhetorical citizenship, we believe, is compatible with a much wider cross-disciplinary scholarly project including political scientists, media scholars, philosophers, discourse analysts, just to mention some. During this conference, we have already heard several highly interesting presentations showing the breath of what other people do with the notion of rhetorical citizenship. However, we recognize an obligation to share some reflections springing from our own work with rhetorical citizenship. We will do so by addressing the definition, purpose, scope, and academic relevance of the concept. 1. Definition Rhetorical citizenship was from the beginning an umbrella term. Lisa was interested in ideas about rhetorical agency (in other words how citizens might gain access to and influence on civic life through symbolic action); Christian was mainly interested in how citizens may relate to and evaluate the public rhetoric in which they are involved not as participants but as “recipients”. We have maintained this dual focus on what you might call the participatory and the receptive aspects of civic discourse, and in the section about scope we’ll try to illustrate it. First of all, it bears underscoring that rhetorical citizenship is not a new idea. The notion that rhetoric is what makes civilized society a possibility goes back to the ancients, and many great scholars have prepared the way for our thinking of citizenship as something that is in part discursively based. Also, plenty of theorists have written about how citizenship is not just a formal or rights-based category but also a more qualitative, participatory, process. We see rhetorical citizenship is a conceptual frame that emphasizes the fact that legal rights, privileges and material conditions are not the only constituents of citizenship; discourse that takes place between citizens is arguably the basis of what it means to be a citizen. With this conceptual assumption our aim was to figure out a research platform that would allow different strands of rhetorical scholarship to come into contact: including studies in public argumentation and deliberation on the one hand, and studies in rhetorical agency on the other. Whereas argument and deliberation theories tend to rely on normative standards that are too pure and clinical, rhetorical agency theory for its part could do with more conceptual precision and a more concrete research agenda. We thought either might benefit from being brought into contact with the other. For example, argumentation studies and deliberative democracy theory might look more at real and less than ideal practices, and rhetorical agency theory from being applied and exemplified in case studies. If not synthesis, there might be synergy. Complementary strengths and perspectives might coalesce in a common pursuit. Rhetorical citizenship does not easily yield to definitional precision because we never intended rhetorical citizenship as a theoretical concept as such, but rather as a conceptual frame, and because our inspiration draws on rather heterogeneous theory and no one methodological approach. In our introduction to Rhetorical Citizenship and Public Deliberation we stated its core as “a way of conceptualizing the discursive, processual, participatory aspects of civic life”. The goal of the book was to develop “an understanding of citizenship as a discursive phenomenon in the sense that important civic functions take place in deliberation among citizens and that discourse is not prefatory to real action but in many ways constitutive of civic engagement.” You might also say that rhetorical citizenship is about rhetoric in society as it relates to the individual citizen. Our interest in the concept is related to “the trend in modern political theory which sees the essence of democracy in the idea of deliberation. If we are to connect these two ideas, citizenship and deliberation, and reflect constructively on their meaning in present-day democracy, then we should not only talk about rights and freedoms, but also about rhetoric”. Also, we might add that while rhetorical citizenship as a concept has no ideological bent, it is clearly normative in its attention to notions of empowerment, inclusivity, and discourse ethics. This is perhaps where our project differs the most from some other approaches to citizenship. 2. Purpose As I just said, rhetorical citizenship as a conceptual frame has a descriptive and a normative side and its purpose is ultimately critical, just like any other kind of rhetorical criticism. But by understanding the particular communicative event in relation to a greater social context (whether representative or extraordinary) our focus is less how effective the particular utterance is, but more how suited it is to contribute to constructive civic interaction. We are interested in this at different levels: most fundamentally, there is a descriptive element in simply mapping how people present arguments or positions in the public realm. Such basic analysis leads to questions about how this behavior reflects ruling discursive norms. By examining such norms, whether they are recognized or not, we have a better basis for critique because it takes into account the ruling doxa and social and other constraints which can sometimes be at odds with more abstract idealizations of civic discourse. Such grounded criticism is, we believe, one way to supplement crossdisciplinary scholarship on citizenship, which is often primarily theoretical or focuses on greater trends and quantifiable observations. Case studies are useful in two respects: First, they are suited for pedagogical purposes because they are concrete and easy to remember. Also, they allow for studying what’s odd or somehow marginal. Whether under the aegis of rhetorical agency or not, rhetorical critics of e.g. minority and women’s’ rhetoric have expanded of our appreciation of the multiple ways in which rhetorical citizenship is manifested. To sum up, we think of rhetorical citizenship as an impetus to forge more explicit links between particular utterances and their role in the maintenance and development of civic life. We’re trying to give renewed emphasis to the critical and social potential of rhetoric by teaching students to appreciate that the way we “do” citizenship discursively and the way we talk about society are both constitutive of or influential on what civic society is and how it develops. Thomas Farrell said that “important civic qualities – such as civic friendship, a sense of social justice – are actively cultivated through excellence in rhetorical practice” (82). This line of thought echoes founding rhetorical thinkers like Isocrates and Cicero who believed that human societies could not have been built and sustained without rhetoric; most recently, Robert Danisch (2012) has maintained that the sophists, from Protagoras on, saw rhetoric as a ‘prudential pragmatism’ and taught it to equip citizens to participate in their polity. If this is so, then citizenship inherently has a rhetorical side. And rhetoric is not merely persuasion but also society-building. 3. Scope Rhetorical Citizenship as a conceptual frame emphasizes the fact that laws, rights, and material conditions are not the only constituents of citizenship; discourse among citizens (in other words: rhetoric in society) is arguably just as constitutive and important. The concept gathers under one heading citizens’ own discursive exchanges – the active or participatory aspect of rhetorical citizenship – and the public discourse of which they are recipients. At the same time it integrates two complementary aspects of both these categories: on the one hand, the rights that we, as citizens, are accorded and the expectations they are entitled to have in regard to discourse among citizens; on the other hand the expectations that other citizens are entitled to have to us precisely because we are citizens; you might also refer to these as our discursive responsibilities or duties as citizens. These two dimensions, much like the cardinal directions of a compass rose, define four broad areas of interest. The North-South axis here represents the active or participatory aspect versus the ‘passive’ or receptive aspect; the West-East axis represents the citizen’s rights versus their responsibilities or duties. Active Rights Responsibilities/Duties Passive This compass rose shows how various rhetorical concerns are connected, but also how much recent thinking in other disciplines addresses rhetorical concerns; thus interdisciplinary contact becomes an obvious agenda. For example, the idea that citizenship not only involves citizens’ rights but also what might be expected or demanded of them is stated clearly as an emerging insight in an overview on citizenship research by the philosophers Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman from 2000: “most theorists now accept that the functioning of society depends not only on the justice of its institutions or constitutions, but also on the virtues, identities, and practices of its citizens, including their ability to co-operate, deliberate, and feel solidarity with those who belong to different ethnic and religious groups”. As for the distinction between the active and the receptive aspects of rhetorical citizenship, it parallels what the political theorists Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson call the “principles of accommodation.” These principles, they say, "make two kinds of general demands on citizens; one concerns how citizens present their own political positions, and the other how they regard the political positions of others" (1996, 80). The compass rose, as we saw, encompasses four quadrants or sectors, which we have numbered 1-4 in the figure below. The citizen’s ... rights: duties: with regard to ... the 1) Rhetorical agency 2) ’Responsible’ active/participatory public rhetoric aspect of rhetorical citizenship: with regard to ... the 3) Access to public 4) Engagement in passive/receptive aspect rhetoric that enables ’deliberation within’, of rhetorical citizenship: ’deliberation within’ ‘listening rhetoric’ Sector 1 is about a citizen’s rights or rightful expectations with regard to rhetoric in society. Citizens not only have the right to speak, they also need the capacity and position to speak so that they may be heard. Studies of rhetorical agency and how it is achieved by some and denied to others belong here. How is rhetorical agency manifested – or contested: what does it take to gain a hearing? What counts as participation in public debate? What counts as legitimate points of view in issues of common concern? How can we account for changes in these categories? Sector 2 has to do with the responsibilities or duties incurred by those who speak. If there are such things as standards of responsible discourse or even of deliberation, they belong here. Many scholars in other disciplines than rhetoric have reflected on what such standards might be. Recently, Political theorist John Dryzek has recognized rhetoric as a necessity in democracy, while not per se a positive factor. He argues for a “systemic” test to distinguish between “desirable and undesirable uses of rhetoric,” and after analyzing how rhetoric may be either ‘bridging’ or ‘bonding,’ he concludes that we should be “asking whether or not the rhetoric in question contributes to the construction of an effective deliberative system joining competent and reflective actors on the issue at hand” (2010, 335). Simone Chambers is another political theorist who has addressed the ‘standards’ issue. She believes that deliberation is needed in a democracy, but also that “the mass public can never be deliberative.” Democratic deliberation in small groups of citizens is fine, but it is not enough. However, she believes in the potential of the public rhetoric we hear, mainly through the media, for providing deliberation. Regrettably, such rhetoric is not always deliberative, which means that it does not engage citizens’ “capacity for practical judgment”; much of it is what she calls “plebiscitary,” based on pandering and manipulation. So we must critically assess public rhetoric and the media that gives it to us, because we do have the task and at least some means of “making the mass public more rather than less deliberative.” “If rhetoric in general is the study of how speech affects an audience then deliberative rhetoric must be about the way speech induces deliberation in the sense of inducing considered reflection about a future action” (2009, 335). Chambers’ call for public rhetoric that is truly deliberative belongs in sector 2, but also shows the connection between sector 2 and sector 3 and 4, which concern the rhetoric whose receivers or audience we are. Sector 3 is about what a citizen, as a deliberating member of the polity, has a right to get. We citizens have a right to expect that public rhetoric is deliberative precisely because it may then help us deliberate on shared issues – by providing information and reasons that help us make informed choices of what policies to endorse, and whom to elect. But just as we have a right to expect this, so the polity may expect from us that we will indeed weigh in our minds the information and reasons we hear. Even citizens who do not actively participate in debate and other discursive exchanges have a responsibility to listen to reasons, even those supporting other views than their own, and to information that is new and perhaps unwelcome. The political theorist Robert Goodin has emphasized the importance of what he calls ‘deliberation within,’ pointing out that “very much of the work of deliberation, even in external-collective settings, must inevitably be done within each individual's head” (2000, 83). In modern nation states there is no way everyone can speak up and be heard by everyone else on any issue. But we may “ease the burdens of deliberative democracy in mass society by altering our focus from the ‘external-collective’ to the ‘internalreflective’ mode, shifting much of the work of democratic deliberation back inside the head of each individual.” Goodin adds that “internal-reflective deliberations might hope to secure better representation of the communicatively inept or the communicatively inert than external-collective deliberations ever could.” Sector 4 is about what the non-participating but deliberating citizen can be expected to do in relation to the discourse of which he or she is a recipient. One important reference here might be to the rhetorician Wayne Booth’s concept of ’listening-rhetoric’ (2009). 4. Academic relevance We believe that rhetorical citizenship has potential as in interdisciplinary conceptual frame to interpret the relevance of rhetoric studies, in their practical as well as their theoretical and/or critical manifestations. One thing rhetorical citizenship might certainly be is a pedagogical project: With an increasingly heterogeneous population, public education has a growing responsibility to teach students not only about democracy and civic rights, but also about their own roles and obligations in civic life; and that should include training them in the practical skills necessary to participate in, and to receive public discourse. In 1998, a committee in Britain, led by the political theorist Bernard Crick, published a report, Education for citizenship and the teaching of democracy in schools. The report identified a number of “skills and aptitudes” that schools should teach, and most of them might clearly be seen as parts of a rhetorical education. Among them are the abilities “to make a reasoned argument both verbally and in writing,” “to consider and appreciate the experience and perspective of others,” “to tolerate other view points,” and “to recognise forms of manipulation and persuasion” (44). So, without even mentioning rhetoric, the report shows that citizenship is in large part a rhetorical concept, and that citizenship education should in large part be rhetorical too. Inviting citizenship thinking and rhetoric studies to meet at the crossroad of rhetorical citizenship happens to resonate well with tendencies in Scandinavian educational thinking. There might, however, be more emphasis on the fact that ordinary citizens (not just the politicians or other leaders we see in the news) have important civic work to do in their everyday lives, whether as critical voters, grass root activists, or just conversation partners. At the university level, we would like to see rhetorical citizenship develop more in the direction of critical analysis of and reflection on the workings of civic life. 5. Closing remarks We believe rhetoric has a place in the study of civic life in virtue of the discipline’s dual nature as an everyday practice and a field of academic inquiry. Lots of rhetoric takes place every day. Sometimes it inspires us, sometimes it irks us, sometimes we are part of it, and sometimes we don’t even notice it. Rhetoric makes society hang together. We as academics can assist in showing how praxis is both inventional and reflects civic norms. By paying close attention to what people say and do in various civic settings, we stand to learn about how people understand their society and their own role in it. The way they speak and what they say are keys to this understanding, which through rhetorical analysis and criticism might promote. Studying the kind of argumentative “work” certain viewpoints or topoi are being used to accomplish or how they travel from vernacular settings to government discourse (or not) may be a way of understanding the workings of society better. Sometimes expectations might be confirmed, but other times new arguments or new angles might emerge. As a practice, rhetoric holds a built-in impetus of improvement. This is where the normative aspect rests, both on the practical and the theoretical level. With its keen eye for contingency and indeterminacy, rhetoric is equipped to deal with the imperfect nature of civic discourse, at once serving as a resource for improvement and a sober acknowledgement of the constraints of the situation. Rhetoric, in the words of Thomas Farrell, is “practical reasoning in the presence of collaborative others” (1991, 189). It is, he believed, “more than the practice; it is the entire process of forming, expressing, and judging public thought in real life. …this enhanced understanding needs to include the condition of being a rhetorical audience. This is a condition in which we are called to exert our own critical capacities to a maximum extent. We have to decide – quite literally – what sort of public persons we wish to be”. (96) References Wayne C. Booth, The Rhetoric of Rhetoric: The Quest for Effective Communication. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2004. Simone Chambers, “Rhetoric and the Public Sphere: Has Deliberative Democracy Abandoned Mass Democracy?” Political Theory 37 (2009): 323-350. Robert Danish, “Stanley Fish is not a Sophist: The Difference between Skeptical and Prudential Versions of Rhetorical Pragmatism” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 42 (2012): 405-423. John S. Dryzek, “Rhetoric in Democracy: A Systemic Appreciation”. Political Theory 38 (2010): 319-339. Education for citizenship and the teaching of democracy in schools: Final report of the Advisory Group on Citizenship 22 September 1998. London: Qualifications and Curriculum Authority, 1998. Thomas Farrell, “Practicing the Arts of Rhetoric. Tradition and Invention” Philosophy and Rhetoric 24 (1991): 183-212. Reprinted in Contemporary Rhetorical Theory. A Reader. John Louis Lucaites, Celeste Michelle Condit, Sally Caudill. Guildford Press, 1999: 79-100. Thomas Goodnight, A "New Rhetoric" for a "New Dialectic": Prolegomena to a Responsible Public Argument Argumentation 7 (1993): 329-342. Robert E. Goodin, “Democratic Deliberation within” Philosophy & Public Affairs 29 (2000): 81-109. Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996. Gerard A. Hauser, Vernacular Voices. The Rhetoric of Publics and Public Spheres. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 1999. Robert L. Ivie “Rhetorical Deliberation and Democratic Politics in the Here and Now” Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5 (2002): 277-285. Christian Kock and Lisa Villadsen, “Introduction: Citizenship as a Rhetorical Practice” Rhetorical Citizenship and Public Deliberation. Christian Kock and Lisa Villadsen (eds.) Penn State Press, 2012: 1-10. W. Kymlicka and W. Norman, Citizenship in Diverse Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. Karen Tracy, James P. McDaniel, and Brice E. Gronbeck, The Prettier Doll. Rhetoric, Discourse and Ordinary Democracy. University of Alabama Press, 2007.