Spatial Dimensionality as a Classification Criterion for Qualities Florian PROBST 1, Martin ESPETER Institute for Geoinformatics, University of Münster, Germany. Abstract. We discuss how the spatial extent of physical endurants influences the conceptualization of their spatial qualities. Comparing the spatial dimensionality of a physical endurant with the spatial dimensionality of its qualities leads to an interesting formal ontological question. Should a spatial quality be conceptualized as having a value range instead of a single value when its bearer has a higher spatial dimensionality? For example, the one-dimensional depth quality can be conceptualized as having a value range when it is assigned to the threedimensional water body of a lake. In terms of the foundational ontology DOLCE, the “value” of a quality, sometimes called quale, is located at an atomic region at a certain time. Allowing a value range at a time is to model qualities as being located at non-atomic regions at a time. That might be philosophically debatable, yet, this modeling approach enables the development of information discovery systems that can cope with ontologically imprecise user queries and can assist the user in defining ontologically precise quality specifications. This brings formal ontology closer to practical applications. The investigation is based on the foundational ontology DOLCE and introduces a classification for spatial qualities based on their spatial dimensionality. Keywords. formal ontology, spatial feature, geospatial ontology engineering Introduction In the context of open and distributed information sources, successful discovery of an information source requires a precise description of the offered information and a precise formulation of a query. Formal ontology has proven a useful basis to enable precise descriptions. One can expect that professional ontology engineers take the burden of providing semantic annotations for information sources offered via the web that are consistent with a foundational ontology2. But can one expect an information requester to be able to formulate queries that are consistent with a foundational ontology? Natural language leaves a substantial range of ambiguity in the meanings of words denoting qualities. This has proven to be efficient and powerful in direct human communication but turned out to be the central drawback when no direct dialog for 1 2 Corresponding Author: Florian Probst, Robert-Koch-Str. 26-28, 48149 Münster, Germany; Email: f.probst@uni-muenster.de We employed DOLCE as foundational ontology for the investigations presented here. http://www.loa-cnr.it/DOLCE.html agreeing on the meaning of the used symbols is possible. One can observe that (geospatial) questions which appear valid when stated in natural language cannot be aligned consistently to the foundational ontology DOLCE [1]. For example, "What is the depth of Lake Constance?" The emerging problem with quality specification is as follows. According to DOLCE, a quality can have only one quale (value) at a certain time. In this sense, stating that a lake has a depth quality implies that the lake has only one depth “value” at a time. This is problematic since one can conceptualize the water body as having a single depth quality whose depth values increase from zero (at the lake shore) to a maximum depth value. In other words, the depth quality’s quale changes in time as well as in space. Yet, the change in space is limited to the space region occupied by the lake’s water body. We present an approach that takes spatial dimensionality as central criterion for classifying qualities of physical endurants. In this context, two contradicting modeling possibilities arise. 1. A quality can be conceptualized as having a quale located at a non-atomic quality region when the quality is inherent in an entity with a higher spatial dimensionality. In other words, the quality has a “value range”. For example, the depth of a lake. 2. An entity with spatial dimensionality n is modeled with an infinite number of qualities with dimensionality < n, each quality having a single value. For example, a lake (3D) has infinitely many depth qualities (1D), each with a single quale (value). In this paper, we make a case for possibility 1). Allowing a quality to be located at a non-atomic quality region may be debatable from a philosophical point of view, but it allows the user in the process of discovering suitable information sources to enter the discovery process with a rather imprecise question. It is important that systems are able to accept such imprecise queries and assist to turn them into precise queries. We assume that users tend to take the context of their query as obvious or even as the only possible context, thus they tend to neglect the need for a precise quality specification. While driving a truck, the question, "What is the height of the tunnel?" seems to refer obviously to the minimum height quality. We show that dimensionality plays a crucial role in the way we assign spatial qualities to physical objects. The results contribute to the development of semantic reference systems as introduced in [2]. The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. The background section introduces the notions of physical endurant, feature, quality, quality space and quale as well as our assumptions about physical space and spatial dimensionality. We introduce our view on how endurants extend in physical space and emphasize in this context the importance of spatial features and their spatial dimensionality. We provide an axiomatization of spatial qualities and their extent in space. We then discuss the consequences, when a spatial feature and its spatial extent quality have a different dimensionality, thus are located at non-identical space regions. We conclude by discussing the benefits of this quality specification approach for the discovery process of information sources. Background Our work is based on the foundational ontology DOLCE [1]. The following section introduces the categories relevant for our purposes. Furthermore, we briefly introduce our assumptions regarding physical space. Physical Endurants The main characteristics of a physical endurant are its location in space, its complete presence at a certain time and its participation in some perdurant, which is sometimes called temporal entity. Any physical endurant has some direct physical quality apart from having a spatial location. It can be a part of some other physical endurant as well as having other physical endurants as part. DOLCE provides three subcategories of physical endurant: Amount of Matter, Physical Objects and Features. Since features are relevant for our purposes here, they are briefly introduced. The main characteristic of a feature is its one-sided generic dependence ([1] axiom Ad 70) on its host, which means that the host can exist without the feature but not vice versa. For some spatial features however, we assume that even mutual generic dependence applies. Examples for such features are body or surface. They are essential parts of their hosts. For example, an apple has a feature apple surface and the apple cannot exist without it. The feature’s constituting amount of matter can be changed, e.g. the apple can shrivel, yet there is still a surface. The most important distinction between feature and quality is that qualities are the only entities that can be directly observed or measured. A feature does have physical qualities. The surface feature has an area quality. The area quality can be measured in contrast to the surface which cannot be measured. It is important to note that the qualities of a feature indirectly characterize the feature’s host. Fore example, the volume quality of an apple’s body characterizes the apple. A feature can be part of another physical endurant as well as having another feature as part. In contrast, qualities inhere in other entities, they can be neither part of an entity nor have parts. Quality, Quality Space and Quale Qualities are seen as the basic entities we can perceive or measure, for example shapes, colours, weights or lengths [1]. Every physical endurant comes with certain qualities, which exist as long as the endurant exists. DOLCE defines a strict distinction between a quality (e.g., the colour of a specific rose), and its “value” (e.g., a particular shade of red). The “value” of a quality is understood as atomic quality region and is called a quale. Quality regions are abstract entities. Currently, DOLCE requires that a quality can be located at exactly one quale at a time. Over time however, the quale can change. Together, the regions at which the qualities of a certain quality type are located form the quality space of that quality type. As described in [3], the general idea is that for each perceivable or conceivable quality a region in at least one associated quality space exists. Assumptions about Physical Space Since we aim to provide a classification of qualities based on their extent in physical space, we briefly introduce our assumptions about physical space. Several ontology projects that attempt to account for physical space are summarized in [4]. We assume that a three dimensional physical space exists. We assume all physical endurants to be in this physical space. In DOLCE, the spatial location quality is the central spatial quality accounting for being located in physical space. We understand this quality in a Newtonian sense as identifying the region in physical space that a physical object occupies. In this sense, the spatial location quality identifies its absolute position in space. In this investigation, we take physical space to be a quality space with three orthogonal location dimensions. This has the side effect that physical space as such is understood as an abstract entity. We assume that within this three dimensional physical space, regions with lower dimensions can exist. See definitions (1-3) below. A potential misunderstanding is that the quality space for spatial location accounts directly for the volume, shape, area or length qualities of an entity. This holds only indirectly. An entity which has a volume or an area quality does necessarily have a spatial location quality, yet volume and location qualities are distinct qualities. More generally, a quality space for spatial location requires a spatial reference system in order to turn the absolute locations in space into comparable and measurable space regions. This is inline with Kuhn and Raubal [5], proposing that spatial reference systems are special kinds of semantic reference systems. Physical Endurants and Their Spatial Qualities After introducing physical endurants, qualities, their associated quality spaces and the assumptions about physical space, we now discuss the spatial qualities of physical endurants. Being in Space versus Extending in Space Being in space and being extended in space are often understood as synonym. In our approach, it is important to distinguish between both. In DOLCE, being in space is reflected in the spatial location quality that any physical endurant necessarily entertains. The quality space of the spatial location quality directly refers to physical space; physical space is the quality space of the spatial location quality. In other words, any physical endurant has a spatial location quality that has as “value” the space region it occupies. We assume this quality to be the most central spatial quality since it is a prerequisite for an entity to be in space. But how to describe being in space more precisely? Here, the spatial qualities extent and figure (shape) come into play. The distinction between being in space and being extended becomes apparent when taking physical endurants into account whose spatial location qualities are located at atomic regions in space. Casati et al. [6] indicate that a theory of spatial representation should account for the fact that the different types of spatial entities bear different types of relations to space. The corner of a desk top, the midpoint of a desk edge or the balance point of a desk surface are examples for physical endurants which are in space, yet which do not extend in space, since they do not entertain qualities like volume, area or length. Here, we depart from the assumptions made in Asher and Vieu [7] and Borgo et al. [8], that the entities we deal with in space do necessarily extend in three dimensions. We assume that surfaces, edges or corners do play a role in our every day interactions in space and that it is exactly their lower dimensional spatial extent that plays a crucial role in the way we assign spatial qualities (indirectly) to physical objects. We see some support for this assumption in the approach to deal with boundaries presented by Casati and Varzi [9]. Spatial Features and Spatial Qualities A prominent argument why the spatial qualities extension and shape are most central is given by Kant [10, p. 17]: "Thus, if I take away from our representation of a body all that the understanding thinks as belonging to it, as substance, force, divisibility, etc., and also whatever belongs to sensation, as impenetrability, hardness, color, etc.; yet there is still something left us from this empirical intuition, namely, extension and shape.” We assume that Kant’s notion of body refers here to what we will define as spatial feature. In our approach, we restrict spatial extension qualities and shape qualities to inhere exclusively in spatial features. This in turn leaves physical objects to entertain spatial qualities only indirectly via the spatial features that they necessarily have. We propose the category SPATIAL FEATURE as a direct sub-category to FEATURE with four sub-categories: 1D-FEATURE, 2D-FEATURE, 3D-FEATURE AND EXTESNIONLESS FEATURES (Fig. 1). All spatial features do necessarily have a host that is a physical object. DOLCE: physical endurant DOLCE: feature spatial feature extensionless feature 1D-feature 2D-feature 3D-feature Fig. 1. Proposed sub categories of FEATURE. DOLCE is intentionally not restricted to a certain dimensionality of space. To be practically applicable in geospatial application we introduce three feature types classified according to their dimensionality. The position of extension-less-features is debatable. 3D-Features.The feature body is conceptualized as extending in all three dimensions of physical space. In other words, its spatial location quality is located at a space region that extends in all three spatial dimensions of physical space. All features whose spatial location quality is located at a 3D region are individuals of the category 3DFeatures. 2D-Features. The feature surface is conceptualized as extending only in two spatial dimensions. For example, an apple’s surface has a two-dimensional extent since the space region at which its spatial location quality is located extends only along two of the three spatial dimensions. Still, the surface’s two-dimensional region is part of the three-dimensional physical space. In contrast, the apple’s peel is a physical object and as such located at a three dimensional region. 1D-Features. Features with a spatial location quality that is located at a region that extends only along one of the three spatial dimensions belong to the category 1DFEATURE. For example, a tabletop can have edges. Extension-less Feature. Finally, a feature that is located in physical space but does not extend in physical space is an extension-less feature. Being located in physical space but at the same time being extension-less means to have an atomic spatial location quality in either a 1D-, 2D-, or 3D-region. In this sense, extension-less features are special kinds of the above defined feature types. Apart from the spatial location quality, an extension-less feature has consequently no spatial extent qualities like a volume, area or shape. For this reason, we can observe extension-less features only indirectly via features which extend in space. The category of extension-less features requires further investigation. Types of Space Regions The spatial location quality is located in a quality region that accounts directly for a region in physical space. The region is-a space region. We assume three types of physical space regions that are distinguished according to their number of spatial dimensions: 1D-, 2D-, and 3D- space regions. 1D-S(x) 2D-S(x) 3D-S(x) S(x) (from DOLCE [1]: S :: space region) (1) We can imagine that an individual of each of these region types can shrink to an atomic extent. This leaves us with three kinds of atomic space regions. Only an extension-less (0D) feature can be located at such atomic regions. We leave the discussion about extension-less features open. The focus is on features that are located in non-atomic regions with one, two or three dimensions. In the following, we introduce the relations is-spatial-location-quality and isspatial-location-quale, which we require for defining spatial feature (4). A spatial feature is a feature which has a spatial location quality which in turn can be located at either a 1D-, a 2D,- or a 3D-spatial region. The fact that a spatial feature can be located at any space region type differentiates it form a physical object. “x is a spatial location quality of y” slqt(x,y) ≜ qt(x,y) SL(x) (SF(y) SQ(y)) (2) (from DOLCE [1]: SL:: spatial location (quality)3; qt:: is-quality-of (Ad38). The characterizations of the predicates SF (spatial feature) and SQ (spatial quality) are given in (4) and (5).) “x is a spatial location quale of y (at time t)” slql(x,y,t) ≜ ql(x,y,t) (1D-S(x) 2D-S(x) 3D-S(x)) SL(y) (from [1]: ql:: is-quale-of (Ad 58)) (3) Spatial Feature SF(z) → F(z) (y (slqt(y,z)) x,t (slql(x,y,t) ) (1D-S(x) 2D-S(x) 3D-S(x)) (from [1]: F::Feature ) 3 (4) For better readability we would prefer the label SLQ over SL to indicate that spatial location is a quality, but we keep the notation introduced in DOLCE [1]. A spatial feature has a spatial location quality that has its quale in a one-, two- or threedimensional region of physical space (1D-S; 2D-S; 3D-S). Dimensionality of Spatial Qualities The previous section introduced spatial features. Relevant for our classification of features is their spatial location quality that accounts for being in space, or more precisely, that accounts for the dimensionality of the space region in which the spatial location quality is located. Additionally to that spatial quality essential for any physical endurant, we introduce the categories SHAPE QUALITY and SPATIAL EXTENT QUALITY. Fig. 2 shows three sub-categories of SPATIAL QUALITY. According to DOLCE, any physical quality has the same location in physical space as its bearer [1, axiom Dd37], and is called a spatial quale. We do not follow this approach here. In DOLCE, a depth quality would have the same spatial location as the lake it inheres in. For our purposes we need the possibility to state that the location quale of a quality is either identical with the location quale of its bearer or that it is a lower dimensional part of its bearer’s location quale (8). This requires that any spatial quality itself has an individual spatial location quality, independently of the location quality of its bearer. DOLCE: physical quality spatial quality shape quality has quality spatial extent quality DOLCE: physical region DOLCE: physical space region DOLCE: spatial location quality located at has quality Fig. 2. Proposed extension of the category SPATIAL QUALITY. Note, any spatial extent quality and any shape quality themselves have a spatial location quality that in turn is located at a region in physical space. Spatial Quality SQ(z) → PQ(z) y (slqt(y,z)) (from DOLCE [1]: PQ :: Physical Quality) (5) We define a spatial quality (SQ) as a physical quality (PQ) which, at any time it exists, has a spatial location quality (SL). Spatial extent qualities (SEQ) can have spatial location qualities that are located at 1D-, 2D-, or 3D-space regions. This is axiomatized in the relation is-spatial-location-quality-of (2). As Casati and Varzi [9, p.123] state, “regions are those things that are located at themselves”. This allows to categorize spatial location qualities as spatial qualities. We do not provide formalizations for shape qualities since they are not in the scope of this paper. Spatial Extent Quality SEQ(z) → SQ(z) (6) “x is a spatial extent quality of y” seqt(x,y) ≜ SEQ(x) SF(y) (7) Spatial features and spatial extent qualities are related via the is-spatial-extent-qualityof relation (seqt). Both, spatial extent qualities and features can entertain spatial location qualities (2) these in turn can be located at any of the previously defined space regions (1),(3). In Fig. 3, the three proposed sub-categories of SPATIAL EXTENT QUALITY are depicted. The individual spatial extent qualities are categorized according to the region type to which the regions of their spatial location quality belong. A spatial extent quality that has a spatial location quality that is located at a 3D-space region is categorized as 3D-spatial extent quality. At this point, we draw the attention to a possible source of confusion. Central to a quality is that it is an observable entity. This is reflected by the fact that is has a quale (Ausprägung). The quale is a region in the quality’s quality space. According to DOLCE, a quale is an abstract particular. In turn, a quality is understood as an entity which itself can have qualities. It is important to distinguish between the direct quale of a quality and the qualia of its qualities. Direct and indirect qualia are located in different quality spaces. In the case of spatial extent qualities, the quality has a direct quale for a spatial extent, e.g. a volume, an area or an elongation. Additionally, any spatial extent quality has a location quality. The location quality has its quale in the quality space corresponding to physical space. DOLCE: physical region spatial quality shape quality 1D-extent-q has quality DOLCE: physical space region spatial extent quality 2D-extent-q has quality 3D-extent-q 1D-space region 2D-space region 3D-space region has quality located at located at located at DOLCE: spatial location quality Fig. 3. Any spatial extent quality does itself have a spatial location quality. The spatial location quality of a spatial extent quality is located in a 1D-, 2D-, or 3D-space region. (All statements made above for spatial extent quality do apply in analogy for shape quality, too. Yet, they are omitted for readability.) Non-Atomic Quality Regions In the previous sections, we introduced the spatial dimensionality of features and spatial qualities. We continue by discussing the possible consequences arising when a spatial feature and its spatial extent quality entertain spatial location qualities that are located in space regions of different types. The mereological relations between the physical space region at which the spatial extent quality is located and the physical space region at which the spatial feature is located are at the core of the investigations presented here. We identify the following relations between the space region of a feature and the space region of its spatial extent quality. “x is a lower dimensional part of y” In order to distinguish the dimensionality of a spatial extent quality and the dimensionality of its bearer, the type of space region at which their location qualities are located need to be compared. If a space region is located in another space region and if this space region has a lower dimensionality than the space region in which it is located, the following relation applies: ldp(x, y) ≜ PP(x,y) ((1D-S(x) (2D-S(y) 3D-S(y))) (2D-S(x) 3D-S(y))) (from DOLCE [1]: PP:: proper part (Dd14)) (8) “v is an atomic-quale-quality of w”. A feature and its spatial extent qualities each are located at a spatial region. If the space regions are identical, then the spatial extent qualities each have an atomic quale. Such an atomic quale can be approximated with a single value, e.g. 2km3. This relation applies for example between a water body and its volume quality: aqlqt(v,w) ≜ seqt(v,w) y,y’((slqt(y,v) slqt(y’,w)) t (x,x’(slql(x,y,t) slql(x’,y’,t)))) → x x’ (from DOLCE : P(x,y) P(y,x) → x = y (Ad6), P :: Parthood) (9) ”v is a non-atomic-quale-quality of (spatial feature) w” If the region at which the spatial extent quality’s spatial location quality is located is a lower dimensional part of the region at which the spatial feature’s spatial location quality is located, then the spatial extent quality has a non atomic quale. This relation applies for example between a water body and its depth quality. This relation is depicted in the lower part of Fig 5. The relations are labelled “q-location of depth quality” and “q-location of feature”: naqlqt(v,w) ≜ seqt(v,w) y,y’(slqt(y,v) slqt(y’,w)) t (x,x’(slql(x,y,t) slql(x’,y’,t))) → ldp(x, x’) (10) These definitions entail: If a quality is conceptualized to be inherent in a feature that occupies a higher dimensional space region, then the spatial location of the quality is not exactly defined. It can “move” within the region of the feature. A 1D-space region has one degree of freedom within a 2D-space region, and two degrees of freedom within a 3D-space region. Fig. 4 shows an example for a depth quality inherent in the feature water body of river. In the example, the depth quality is conceptualized as 1D quality, thus its spatial location quality is located at a 1D-space region. The depth quality has two degrees of freedom within the 3D-space region occupied by the water body. Thus, it is impossible to locate a spatial extent quality at an atomic region (assign a single value to it) if the dimensionality of its location quality differs from that of the feature it inheres in. In other words, the quale of a quality with a lower dimensionality does not only vary in time but also in space. Such a quality takes a range of possible values at a time. It is located at a non-atomic region in its quality space. depth 3 depth 2 depth1 Fig. 4. Example: The water body of a stream is located at a 3D space region. If a depth quality is assigned to it, then the 1D space region of the quality has two degrees of freedom within the region of the water body. Exemplarily, three possible locations are depicted. In the context of information sources dealing with observations and measurements, it appears essential to make sure that the observed quality, e.g. the depth of a river is located at an atomic region of its quality space. This requires that qualities with lower dimensionality than their bearers are further specified. This can be achieved in two ways. 1. The spatial location of the quality is defined exactly. In the river example, this is achieved when the water level at a certain location is measured. The depth quality is further specified as the depth quality at a certain location and a certain time. 2. The quality is defined to take an atomic quale that takes a clearly identifiable location in the quality space at a certain time. In the river example, this could be the maximum depth, the average depth, or any other quale that can be singled out of the range of possible atomic-regions at which the quality can be located. A DOLCE: feature DOLCE: physical quality DOLCE: physical region spatial quality spatial feature 1D volume region 3D-quality q-location DOLCE: physical space region 3D-space region 3D feature has quality volume quality has quality water body q-location of volume quality has quality spatial location quality q-location of feature B DOLCE: feature DOLCE: physical region DOLCE: physical quality elongation region spatial quality spatial feature 1D-quality DOLCE: physical space region q-location 1D-space region 3D feature depth quality has quality has quality water body has quality spatial location quality 3D-space region q-location of depth quality lower-dimensional part q-location of feature Fig. 5. A: The volume quality of a water body has exactly one “value” (quale). The region to which the volume quality refers has no degree of freedom, since it is identical with the space region the water body occupies. B: The depth quality has a “value range” since the depth quality’s spatial location quality is located in a space region that has two degrees of freedom within the space region of the water body. Summary and Conclusion To enable successful discovery of geospatial information sources providing observation results, the first step is to specify precisely the qualities for which observation results are provided and in which physical endurants the quality is inherent. We presented a first cut at an ontology for spatial qualities based on the foundational ontology DOLCE. Central to our approach is the spatial dimensionality of spatial qualities. This implies that a spatial quality itself has a spatial location quality, and thus a location in physical space. In our approach, a spatial extent quality has a direct location in its associated quality space as well as an indirect location in physical space via its spatial location quality. For example, the spatial extent quality volume is located directly in its one-dimensional quality space for volume as well as indirectly in a three-dimensional region in the quality space accounting for physical space. In order to talk about dimensionality we introduced the categories 1D-SPACE REGION, 2D- SPACE REGION, and 3D- SPACE REGION as subcategories of SPACE REGION, as well as four subcategories for SPATIAL FEATURE (4), where the individuals are classified according to their spatial dimensionality. A consequence of our approach is that a spatial feature and its spatial extent quality both have an individual spatial location quality. Central to our approach is that the space regions (spatial qualia) of these two spatial location qualities can be identical. In this case, the relation atomic-quale-quality-of (9) holds between the feature and its spatial extent quality. It indicates that the quality has a single “value” at a time. For example, the volume of a lake has exactly one value at a time. different. In this case, the relation non-atomic-quale-quality-of (10) holds between the spatial extent quality and its feature. It indicates that the quality has a value range at a certain time. For example, the depth of a lake has a value range at a time. In the context of information source discovery, discovery systems that implement ontology based-search according to our approach will allow the information requester to start her search with basic level concepts [11]. For example, assume a user interested in observation results of depth qualities of lakes in a certain region. An information discovery system will allow the user to start his search with the notions depth and lake. Since the depth quality is a one-dimensional quality (see Fig. 5) and the water body of the lake is a three-dimensional spatial feature, the spatial location quale of quality and feature are not identical. Thus, the relation defined in (10) holds, indicating that the depth quality has a value range at a certain time. At this point, the information discovery system informs the user that she can request only value ranges for this combination of quality type and feature type. It is possible that the user implicitly assumed that the notion “lake depth” always refers to the maximum depth quality. Information discovery systems based on our approach would enforce to state these assumptions explicitly, e.g. the user has to choose the qualities for which it is possible to return a single observation value, such as the maximum depth quality. In addition to that, our approach allows to specify variances, or any other quality characterizing the value range of a quality. The variance accounts for the way in which the “values” of a quality vary. Variance is a quality frequently used in geospatial applications, thus it is important that the underlying ontology can account for it. Variance qualities are only possible if lower dimensional spatial qualities are conceptualized to inhere in higher dimensional spatial features. Future Work Spatial extent qualities like height or volume are often assigned as direct qualities to physical objects. In this paper, we proposed that only spatial features should have spatial extent qualities. One could further require that only amounts of matter, which constitute physical objects, can have physical qualities like temperature, mass or color. Temporal qualities in turn are direct qualities of perdurants in which a physical object participates. A physical object may play a certain role. Yet, it is the role, which entertains abstract qualities like monetary or historical value. This raises the question: Which direct qualities can be assigned to a physical object? This investigation was focused on qualities understood as unary characteristics of entities. Further investigations are required to incorporate other kinds of observable entities into the approach, for example binary characteristics such as directions or distances between spatial entities. Acknowledgements Discussions with Krzysztof Janowicz, Eva Klien, Claudio Masolo, Stefano Borgo, Michael Lutz and Werner Kuhn have greatly influenced the ideas presented here. The work has been supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG) grant KU 1368/4-1 (Semantic Reference Systems) and the SWING project (IST-FP6-26514). References [1] Masolo, C., Borgo, S., Gangemi, A., Guarino, N., Oltramari, A. WonderWeb Deliverable D18, Ontology Library (final). http://wonderweb.semanticweb.org/deliverables/documents/D18.pdf [2] Kuhn, W.: Semantic Reference Systems. International Journal of Geographical Information Science 17 (2003) 405-409 [3] Guizzardi, G.: Ontological Foundations for Structural Conceptual Models. Enschede, Netherlands (2005) [4] Bateman, J., Farrar, S.: Towards a generic foundation for spatial ontology. In: Proc. Formal Ontology in Information Systems (2004) [5] Kuhn, W., Raubal, M.: Implementing Semantic Reference Systems. In: Proc. AGILE 2003 - 6th AGILE Conference on Geographic Information Science (2003) 63-72 [6] Casati, R., Smith, B., Varzi, A.: Ontological Tools for Geographic Representation. In: N. Guarino, (ed.) Formal Ontology in Information Systems. ISO Press (1998) 77-85 [7] Asher, N., Vieu, L.: Towards a Geometry of Common Sense: A Semantics and a Complete Axiomatization of Mereotopology. In: Proc. 14th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (1995) 846-852 [8] Borgo, S., Guarino, N., Masolo, C.: A Pointless Theory of Space Based On Strong Connection and Congruence. Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (1996) [9] Casati, R., Varzi, A. C.: Parts and Places. The Structures of Spatial Representation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1999) [10] Kant, I.: Critique of Pure Reason (translation: F. Max Müller). The MacMillan Company, London (1896) [11] Rosch, E.: Principles of Categorization. In: E. Rosch and B. Lloyd, (eds.): Cognition and Categorization. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates (1978) 27-48