Bad Language = Bad Science The language in which a science is framed is all important. Terms with imprecise or multiple meanings, strong, cathected connotations, or even those inviting of alliteration (word play in general), have to be avoided as much as possible. This was evident in Physics already at the time of Newton, who often resorted to Latin (as does Law) to express himself more precisely (and in Newton’s case perhaps to think unencumbered by connotation). It is also one reason (though a minor one now) why so much of the language of physics is mathematical. For chemistry to come of age, it had to release itself from the shackling language-culture of alchemy, a triumph we associate with the name of Lavoisier. For biology to come of age …. Well it has still to do so, still to struggle free of its stultifying burden of its anthropomorphisms, ambiguities, imprecisions and its heavy load of cathected connotations. […buys you nothing to invoke it; explains your problem—…away The root problem in biology is, of course, the language-culture of Darwinism, which has stood for a century as an enormous boulder in the path of our proper understanding of evolution—in a proper formulation of the science of biology, that is, biological organization. Darwinism, however, is a problem too vast to deal with in the present context. But, the science of biology has many “teapot versions” of this great one in its language-culture cabinet. And the one of especial interest to at this point is the continued useage of the term/concept “Prokaryote”, not simply in microbiology, but throughout biology. Every time this Trojan Horse of a term is used, in with it come tacit concepts that staunch creativity, that prevent us from recognizing, properly interpreting, what lies there before us. The great 1 physicist Erwin Schrodinger branded such concepts/explanations as “guesswork solutions”. “Such a fake” he said, “removes the urge to seek after a tenable answer.” Moreover, “[s]o efficiently may attention be diverted that the answer is missed even when, by good luck, it comes close at hand”. Like it or not, that is the “Prokaryote”. And it is time that “prokakyote” – the term and embedded concept – be removed from biology’s lexicon. The issue behind the issue of the Prokaryote Uncharacteristically, the concept “prokaryote” had a unique origin. Neither the term nor its contemporary meaning were in the microbiological lexicon before 1962-3, and this first usage traces to a single source, the microbiologist Roger Stainer. In 1962 Stanier and a co-author Cornelius van Niel invoked the term for the first time (in English), and for the first time made genuine scientific substance of it. They were not interested in the prefix “pro-”, however. That had come from an earlier incarnation of “prokaryote” in its casual useage among certain protozologists to distinguish the objects of their interest from the bacteria in general; In its early informal usage the term prokaryote had had evolutionary implications, vaguely suggesting that bacteria were simpler and/or prior or possibly (some or all of them ancestral to what then would be called “eukaryotes”, the nucleated cells that comprise the world of animals, plants, and protests. But the purpose for which the older informal name was now intended was different. Stanier and van Niel were to use the term and the prokaryote/eucaryote couple in their intent to put to rest once and for all microbiology’s foundational issue. What was at issue here? 2 Since the serious study of the microbial world began microbiologists had struggled to make a basic science of it. It was far more the potpourri of disease problems, sterility problems, fermentation problems, which had initiated its investigation. The microbial world obviously presented a major biological challenge in its own right and, therefore, had to be recast in a scientifically proper setting. To do so required great improvements in technique, initially in microscopy, but also in isolation and general handling of the organisms involved. Enormous problems awaited in the surprisingly and highly variable physiologies of microscopic organisms and in their peculiar and varied communal organizations. But to properly study the microbial world the early pioneers had first and foremost to create the proper axiomatic base for their new discipline – recognizing the naturally defined categories, selecting the pertinent facts and key concepts – from which to bring forth the right “language” in which the discipline could productively work, could be deeply and broadly explored. There was, in my opinion, a crucial moment in the development of microbiology at which the axiomtic foundation began to take concrete form. Had it continued to do so, microbiology would have been a very different discipline than it would become during the 20th century; and could have well changed the course of the biology we know today, instead of standing by as a passive witness of biology’s conceptual development. But it came and went with the career of one man, Martinus Beijerinck -- arguably the greatest microbiologist in the history of the discipline. The crucial moment, when Beijerinck briefly explained the bases for his study of the microbial world occurred during his acceptance of the Leeuwenhoek Medal--microbiology's highest honor---in 1905. At the ceremony a member of his audience had risen to ask his conceptualization of the discipline’s foundational issue—i.e., asked him his view and practice of microbiology. 3 Beijerinck’s answer was: "[My] approach can be concisely stated as the study of microbial ecology, i.e., of the relation between environmental conditions and the special forms of life corresponding to them. It is my conviction that ... this is the most necessary and fruitful direction to guide us in organizing our knowledge of that part of nature which deals with the lowest limits of the organic world, and which constantly keeps before our minds the profound problem of the origin of life itself." What Beijerinck was sketching here were the foundations for the proper study of the microbial world, something that would require another century to develop. He understood what his successors did not: that organisms cannot be understood apart from the ecologies and their communal organizations. Indeed, he understood that the organism does not define the organismal community, so much as the reverse. And he understood that the microbial world was and exquisite study in the origin of life and, so, evolution. Beijerinck was a true biologist who understood that microorganisms must be studied in their own terms! Albert Jan Kluyver succeeded to Beijerinck’s post. He was basically a chemist with an interest in natural products. Microbiology required a lot of on the job training for him. He never had an abiding interest in bacteria as organism; and less, it appears, in their community structures and ecological relationships. But he could and surely did understand them in a physiological, biochemical sense. Under Kluyver’s guidance microbiology underwent, in his own words “a change of face”. It became the most prominent sub-discipline of the burgeoning science of biochemistry. Kluyver would set sail on the same wind that blew through most of the other 20th century disciplines, sum-of-the-parts reductionism. With Kluyver, microbiology’s foundational issue, which Beijerinck had started to resolve, returned; and continued to plague the discipline: biochemistry could never 4 serve as the axiomatic base for an organismal discipline, especially one as unique as the microbial world. The Prokaryote Hypothesis As microbial biochemistry reached its reductionist apotheosis, Kluyver’s discovery of the unity of biochemistry and the tour de force that microbial biochemistry had become, the foundational issue, which had simmered the while, in Stanier and van Niel’s seminal 1962 article “The Concept of a Bacterium”, designed to settle it once and for all. The authors saw the issue as “the abiding intellectual scandal of bacteriology”, which which they declared to be “the absence of a clear concept of bacterium”. This, of course, was not the way Beijerinck had seen it -- for it failed to recognize the interconnectedness of the individual microbe with its ecology, community structure, or evolution. But the recognition of the invidivual bacterium as an organismal entity was still a step above the total reductionism inherent in Kluyver’s “bag of enzymes’ approach to microorganisms. Although “the problem of defining these organisms as a group in terms of their biological organization” had a proper scientific ring to it, the way Stanier and van Niel went about settling the problem did not. It was lacking in its logic, which seemed to betray a prejudice in their approaching the question. Disproof of the Prokaryote Hypothesis 5 -------------------------The beginning of the 21st Century sees institutional biology in a peculiar place. On one hand, the triumphs of molecular biology and genetics have given scientists an entirely new understanding of the mechanisms of cells, and even the power to manipulate the properties of organisms. On the other hand, the common wisdom and education in deep evolution and classification is not in a modern state, and indeed is rotten. And microbiologists stand at the crux of doing something about it. Why do I assert this? How did it happen? What do microbiologists have to do with it? The Problem At issue here is the notion of “prokaryote” and the model of biological organization and evolution that it elicits. This model, explicit in most textbooks and which I term the prokaryote-eukaryote model, posits that fundamentally there are two kinds of organisms, prokaryotes and eukaryotes, defined by the presence or absence of a nucleus (more properly nuclear membrane). Moreover, the model proposes that prokaryotes gave rise to eukaryotes. The course of evolution promoted by the prokaryoteeukaryote model is diagrammed in the accompanying figure. The problem, however, is that there isn’t any such thing as a prokaryote. And therein is the rot. The notion of prokaryote was a logical fallacy from the beginning because the definition, an “organism without a 6 nucleus,” is a negative definition. No one can tell you what a prokaryote is, they can only tell you what it is not. The course of evolution, from prokaryote to eukaryote, was a guess – an untested hypothesis. Yet, institutional biology bit deeply into that hypothesis. The prokaryoteeukaryote model, through the very language, dominates textbooks, journals and discourse in matters of deep evolution. But it proved wrong. Where It Came From - The Short History of Prokaryote It is important to understand that the concept of prokaryote is not based on scientific results. Rather, it is based on historical conjecture. The history of the prokaryote concept and its incorporation into the common wisdom of biologists has been reviewed (###). Prokaryote had its origins in evolutionary models of the 19th Century. Ernst Haeckel, in his fourkingdoms classification trees in the 1860s, put “monera” at the base of the eukaryotic kingdoms of plants, animals and protists (microbial eukaryotes). A century later, in the 1960s, the ecologist ### Whittaker added the kingdom of fungi to Haeckel’s tree, giving us the popular textbook organization of biology into five kingdoms, with monera at the origin. Also in the 1960s, the name “monera” became interchangeable with “prokaryote,” the name popularized by Roger Stanier and his colleagues M. Doudoroff and E.A. Adelberg, initially in the 2nd edition of their widely used textbook “The Microbial World” (###). The terminology of prokaryote was welcomed by microbiologists and then was incorporated into the language of biology in general. It is curious that the nomenclature of “monera” never caught-on among earlier microbiologists, but “prokaryote” was embraced immediately. I speculate that the terminology of prokaryote and eukaryote simply sounded scientific, 7 as if we finally understood something about the process of evolution, had gone beyond Haeckel’s monera. But, in fact, prokaryote was not much more than a name-change from monera. The prokaryote-eukaryote model remains, after all, a 19th Century notion based on what proved to be bad guesses. The Disproof of Prokaryote The notion of prokaryote was disproved in 1977, with Carl Woese’s discovery of archaea and the first articulation of a rudimentary molecular phylogenetic tree that related representatives of the most diverse forms of life (###). Woese, through comparisons of ribosomal RNA (rRNA) sequences from different organisms, saw not two relatedness groups, two kinds of organisms, prokaryote and eukaryote, but three: bacteria, eukaryotes (which indeed proved monophyletic) and what came to be known as archaea. Woese originally named the latter group “archaebacteria,” but this was changed to “archaea” when it became clear they were fundamentally distinct from bacteria. “Archaebacteria” continues to be seen, usually perjoratively, as backhanded criticism of the three-domains concept. Woese’s phylogenetic, three-domains model of relationships and evolution is experimentally grounded and stands in stark contrast to the prokaryote-eukaryote model, as diagrammed in the figure. The threedomains pattern shows that eukaryotes constitute a phylogenetically coherent group, but there is no specific group on which to pin the label “prokaryote.” Both archaea and bacteria would qualify through their lack of a nuclear membrane, but these two groups are not specific relatives. Indeed, one of the two, archaea, is more closely related to eukaryotes than archaea are to bacteria. This relationship is supported not only by molecular 8 phylogeny, but also by many properties of archaeal and eukaryotic cells compared to bacterial cells (###). I know of no scientifically grounded data that would call into question the basic pattern of the three-domains relationships. A substantial and increasing body of scientific evidence refutes the notion of prokaryote. Additionally, the phylogenetic model shows no specific group of organisms that preceded the eukaryotes. The textbook and common wisdom notion that eukaryotic cells arose late in the history of Earth by fusion of two prokaryotes are incorrect. Indeed the mitochondria and chloroplasts were derived by fusion between bacteria, which became symbionts, and ancestral eukaryotic cells (not shown in the figure). But the ancestral, eukaryotes must have been already well in place. This history is seen in the molecular phylogenetic tree as the nuclear line of descent. The tree shows that the nuclear line of descent is as old as the archaeal line and was not derived from either archaea or bacteria. The molecular results say nothing at all about whether or not the earliest eukaryotes possessed nuclear membranes. In fact, in the light of the sequence comparisons, the presence or absence of the nuclear membrane or other morphological property is irrelevant for classification or for deduction of the large scale of biological organization. Some Would Argue Not only did the disproof of prokaryote initially fall on deaf ears, the result was contested and continues to be denied by many. Prokaryoteeukaryote became solidly entrenched in textbooks and journals, and the proponents of the concept of prokaryote continue to argue its merits with religious fervor. 9 They argue for instance that bacteria and archaea are united by their very small size. But they ignore that many microbial eukaryotes overlap the bacterial and archaeal size ranges. They argue that bacteria and archaea are united in use of coupled transcription and translation. This is not meaningful, rather, is just another twist on the presence or absence of the nuclear membrane. The barrier of the nuclear membrane precludes eukaryotes from participation in the comparison. At the last resort, the proponents of prokaryote insist, “You have to call them something.” But that’s the problem: there isn’t any “them.” The molecular phylogenetic results, bolstered by decades of biochemical corroboration, show that there is no natural grouping that would correspond to prokaryote. Some might argue that the prokaryote terminology is a convenient classification (for what?) and that historical usage justifies continued usage. These rationalizations are scientifically inappropriate, however. A critical point here, one usually missed by proponents of the prokaryote concept, is that scientific classification is not a convenience. As scientists we must observe nature and classify accordingly. As Darwin insisted, “Our classifications will come to be, as far as they can be so made, genealogies.” “Prokaryote” doesn’t fit the observed genealogy. It needs to be retired from the language of biology. It has become a distraction, another example of Intelligent Design that didn’t work out. Why It Matters Any scientific field rests on two foundations of understanding, both of which must be grounded on experiment, not conjecture. One foundation requires understanding of the order, the organization, of the subjects of 10 study. Thus, the chemist would refer to the periodic table to understand chemical reactivities; biologists look to phylogenetic relationships to understand properties of organisms. The other foundation of any scientific field is how those subjects of study change. Chemists study reaction mechanisms and radioactive decay; astronomers study the HertsprungRussell series for the evolution of stars; biologists reflect on phylogenetic trees, maps of the course of evolution. Critical foundational issues for progress in biology, therefore, are proper perceptions of phylogenetic groups and relationships, and consequently the path of evolution. The prokaryoteeukaryote notion fails in both these regards. In contrast, the three-domains pattern of life’s organization and large-scale path of evolution is scientifically grounded. What To Do about It and Why Microbiologists are Critical Institutional biology is now heavily invested in the prokaryote concept. The language permeates our literature and thereby pollutes understanding of foundational issues in biology. One problem that faces efforts to rectify matters is that most students, biologists and authors of general textbooks don’t think very much about microbes. Their world is generally that of large organisms. They, unlike microbiologists, are not faced with trying to make sense of a vast diversity of life with comparatively little variation that we can observe without resort to biochemistry and gene sequences. So most biologists ignore, or pay only lip service, to recent discoveries in deep phylogeny; the classification of “prokaryote” sweeps microbial diversity under the rug. The three-domains phylogenetic model is beginning to appear in textbooks, but usually as just another method of classification, along with the Five-Kingdoms scheme. The implications of the three-domain pattern of evolution are seldom broached. What to do about it? 11 The retirement of prokaryote from the lexicon of biology will be slow because it is now so deeply entrenched into institutional biology. Consequently, movement toward the retirement of prokaryote needs to be catalyzed. Microbiologists and teachers of microbiology are in the best position to effect change. Their organisms span the three domains and the phylogenetic perspective is evident and necessary. Proper treatment of these issues by microbiological journals and textbooks will lead to modernized general texts. An early challenge to microbiologists is to stop using the term “prokaryote.” This is hard to do because of long conditioning. Those tempted still to use it must realize, however, that they saddle their students with misconception and muddy their thinking about foundational issues in biology. How can teachers broach this issue in the face of the currently pervasive reference to prokaryotes in journals and textbooks? One way is to use the discordance between recently emerging data and the textbook notions as a wonderful example of how science, biology in this case, is an ongoing, living process. Bringing the subject to students shows them how new information based on experimental evidence can fundamentally change understanding. Dealing with the prokaryote issue provides a good example of testing specific hypotheses with experimental data, with results important for biology. Phylogenetic trees, maps of evolutionary relationships, are straightforward metaphors for the course of evolution and are not hard for students to understand in essence. The three domains concept of course poses many questions, but it also provides a solid foundation for progress toward answering those questions. 12 13