Arguing with Socrates t.chappell@open.ac.uk Reading 1.1 (Socrates and Laches): If we want to educate our sons in virtue, we need to know what virtue is. But looking at the whole of virtue would be too big a task. So let’s just look at a part of it—courage. Once we know what courage is, we can investigate how it is acquired. Reading 1.2 (Socrates and Laches): A definition of courage can’t just give us an example of courage; it must give us what all examples have in common. Compare the case of quickness, which Socrates shows how to define. What is the parallel definition of courage? Reading 1.3 (Socrates and Laches): Laches’ definition: “Courage is endurance.” Instantly refuted, because not all endurance is good, whereas all courage is good. Reading 1.4 (Socrates, Nicias, and Laches): Nicias’ definition: “Courage is knowledge of what’s fearful and what’s encouraging, whether it’s in war or any other situation.” Reading 1.5 (Socrates, Nicias, and Laches): Socrates: But Nicias’ definition implies that lions, stags, bulls, and apes aren’t courageous. Nicias: Yes, and this is a key advantage of Nicias’ definition: It explains why children and animals (and Nicias would add, women) aren’t truly courageous—because they don’t have understanding or foresight. Reading 1.6 (Socrates and Nicias): Socrates: “Knowledge of what’s fearful and encouraging” = knowledge about what will be fearful and what will be encouraging = knowledge of what it will be right to run away from and what it will be right to stand up to without running away = knowledge of what will be good and what will be evil But there’s no such thing as knowledge of what will be F or not-F without knowledge also of what was F or not-F and of what is F or not-F. If you have knowledge about Fs at all, it can’t be tensed in this way. So if courage is knowledge of what will be good and what will be evil, it is also knowledge of what was good and what was evil and knowledge of what is good and what is evil. So Nicias’ definition means that courage is knowledge of good and evil in general. Reading 1.7 (Socrates and Nicias): But anyone who has a general knowledge of good and evil has all the other virtues (temperance, justice and piety) as well as courage. So if courage is merely one part of virtue, Nicias’ definition must be wrong. Reading 1.8 (From Plato’s Meno: Socrates and Meno): Knowledge and correct opinion are equally useful in practice, because both get us to the truth. But knowledge is more worth having than correct opinion. When you have correct opinion which isn’t knowledge, you don’t understand why your opinions are correct. (That’s the difference between knowledge and correct opinion.) So your correct opinions will be easily changed into incorrect opinions. When someone challenges them, they’ll be overturned just as easily as if they were incorrect. By contrast, your knowledge will stay put when it’s challenged, because you will be able to explain your view. This conception of knowledge unlocks some puzzles: ● Why Nicias’ definition of courage fails in the Laches—even though Plato thinks it is roughly correct. The definition fails because Nicias doesn’t know how to defend it. What he should say, according to Plato, is that courage isn’t just part of virtue: it’s the same thing as the whole of virtue. But Nicias doesn’t see this possibility. ● Why Plato thinks that you can’t be courageous without thinking things out in advance. You don’t have to have one think per courageous act! But you do have to sit down and do some thinking before you can do any truly courageous acts. Until you know about good and evil in general, you can’t be truly courageous. ● Why Plato thinks you can’t be courageous in an unjust cause. Because if you know good and evil in general, you will see that bad ends are not worth risking anything for. Unless you take risks only for just causes, you’re not really being courageous at all. ● Why Plato thinks you can’t choose to do what you know to be wrong. You can choose something that you have a correct opinion is wrong, because this opinion is easily removed or made to “scamper off”. But you can’t choose what you know is wrong. For when you have a full understanding of its wrongness and why it is wrong, you won’t be able to choose against that understanding. To think about further Why are Plato and Socrates so interested in the virtues in the first place? The answer is that they are trying to answer the question “How should life be lived?” (Republic 452d7-8). To answer “How should life be lived?” we need to know what kind of people we need to be to live well. The answer to this is given by identifying the qualities of character that we will need to live well. These qualities are the virtues. Plato’s view that all the virtues are the same thing, and that thing is knowledge, can look very strange when you think about it. In our society, we happily count characteristics like patience, a sense of humour, humility, and honesty as virtues. It’s odd to say that patience is the same thing as a sense of humour, or that honesty and humility are identical character traits. It’s even odder to say that patience, a sense of humour, humility and honesty are all the same thing as knowledge. Is this because our understanding of the virtues has changed since Plato’s time? Well, we do recognise different virtues from Plato’s era, but the same oddity occurs with the five main virtues that Plato’s society recognised—wisdom, temperance, justice, courage, and piety. Plato’s contemporaries were quite as puzzled as we might be by his thesis that all the virtues are the same thing. Plato’s view is puzzling because it’s a rationalist view, and an anti-traditionalist view. Plato thinks that the justification for his view is (1) that there are decisive arguments in its favour; and (2) that if his view is right, then we can decide how to live by using reason to think out how to live. His view has the backing of reason, and it is an enthronement of reason. Since his view has reason on its side in this very strong sense, Plato doesn’t really care if his thesis puzzles traditionalists. Not at any rate at the early stage in his career that the Laches represents. In later works he does try and modify his views a bit, or soften their tone, to try and make them less puzzling to traditionalists. And he does get less confident about what reason can achieve. But his basic rationalism never changes.