Introduction to Symposium on Capitalism, Corporations and the Social Contract: A Critique of Stakeholder Theory Samuel Mansell I’d like to begin by thanking Pedro Francés-Gómez and Lorenzo Sacconi for organising this symposium on my book. I’m also grateful to the audience for coming to participate in the discussion. The central question addressed by the book is: in whose interests should a corporation be run? In other words, what is the ultimate purpose of the corporation? This question is worth asking because of the widely held belief that recent corporate scandals have resulted from a mistaken ideology called ‘shareholder value theory’. This is the idea that corporations should be run exclusively in the interests of shareholders, rather than for the benefit of any other stakeholder group, and that what shareholders desire is the maximisation of the financial value of their investment (see Friedman, 1970). My book engages with the possibility of alternatives to this normative position. It therefore asks whose interests should count in the determination of corporate aims. Who is to decide the purpose of the corporation, and what should that purpose be? To whom, and for what, should directors be accountable? When considering answers to these questions, there are those, most notably perhaps Joel Bakan (2004) in his book The Corporation, who hold that in a broadly free-market capitalist system a corporation in anything like its current form cannot be the site of genuine responsibility or accountability. The solution to these questions would therefore entail an overhaul of the very concept of the corporation, or of the economic system in which it operates. Though many hold to this position, my interest is in an alternative view known as ‘stakeholder theory’. This theory received its major impetus from R Edward Freeman’s (1984) Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach and has since flourished as an idea in the fields both of strategic management and business ethics. Stakeholder theorists claim that without any radical changes to the way corporations are structured as legal persons, or to the basic ethical framework of a capitalist economy, a corporation can be run to create as much value as possible, not merely for shareholders, but for all its primary stakeholders: customers, employees, suppliers, financiers and communities, all of whom are assumed to have a ‘stake’ or vested interest in the success of the firm (Freeman et al, 2010). And ‘value’ here means not just financial value but the well-being or happiness of these stakeholders, and stakeholder theorists have proposed various measures for capturing stakeholder happiness in nonfinancial terms (Harrison and Wicks, 2013). How do stakeholder theorists justify the view that management should be accountable to all stakeholders, and not merely to shareholders? One type of justification is an explicitly pragmatist line of argument: i.e., it’s impossible to maximise the value created for any one stakeholder group without creating as much value as possible for all the other stakeholder groups. Whatever the purpose of an individual firm, it is just good business to create as much as value as possible for all stakeholders without resorting to trade-offs, and this should be the proper focus for the management of any business (Freeman, 2011). However, I argue that there are categories of stakeholders (whether or not one calls them ‘stakeholders’) whose interests and well-being may be affected by what a corporation does, but whom a corporation does not rely upon for its immediate profitability and survival. For example, a corporation could create value for its employees, suppliers, financers, etc, while ignoring its impact on future generations or non-human nature, for example. We therefore need to look beyond strategic pragmatism to the moral justifications given for a corporate purpose that encompasses the interests of particular stakeholders and demarcates the stakeholder interests that count, in determining corporate objectives, from those that do not. A range of ethical theories are employed by stakeholder theorists, the most common being from the field of political philosophy: namely, the social contract. In this tradition of political theory, which dates back to the work of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke in the 17th century, Jean-Jacque Rousseau and Immanuel Kant in the 18th century, and more recently John Rawls’s work A Theory of Justice (1999), it is held that all citizens of a state have an identical interest in consenting to the existence of that state and to the rule of a sovereign power that is able to keep peace among them and thus secure the life and property of every citizen. It can be asked on what terms free, equal and independent members of society would agree to this contract; the most extensive answer to this question appears in John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice, with the use of his so-called ‘veil of ignorance’, which is designed to represent equality between human beings as moral persons. Here it is assumed, as a thought- experiment, that individuals are ignorant of their class position or social status, their natural abilities, their conception of the good, their risk preferences, the level of culture of their society, or the generation to which they belong. Behind this ‘veil of ignorance’, individuals must decide once and for all what is to count among them as just or unjust, and Rawls’s aim is to deduce exactly what rational individuals would agree to under such conditions. Many stakeholder theorists, whose arguments I analyse in the book, take Rawls as their inspiration and consider the corporation to be a contract between employees, customers, suppliers, financiers and local communities placed behind a veil of ignorance (e.g., Donaldson, 1982; Freeman and Evan, 1990; Freeman, 1994; Sacconi, 2006). Management are then authorised to run the firm in the joint interest of all the relevant stakeholders, in accordance with the terms that these stakeholders would rationally accept as conditions for the contract. If one accepts this argument, at least in outline, then it is a short step from here to see the corporation as a democracy of all its stakeholders. The major question I try to answer in my book is whether this theoretical approach, along with several others that stakeholder and CSR theorists have proposed (e.g. Phillips, 2003), can provide a justified alternative to shareholder value theory. Even if these arguments can be argued to fail, and accountability to a range of stakeholders for pursuit of the corporate purpose has not received adequate justification, then it can still be asked whether shareholders have a moral obligation to hold managers to account, not merely for maximising the financial value of that investment, but also for the effects of the firm’s activity on the well-being of its stakeholders (Mansell, 2013). So that’s what the book is about, and to find out how well I have answered these questions, I’ll now hand over to Lorenzo and Pedro. Thanks very much. References Bakan, J. (2004) The Corporation: The Pathological Pursuit of Profit and Power. London. Constable Donaldson, T. (1982) Corporations and Morality. New Jersey. Prentice-Hall Freeman, R. (1984) Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach. London. Pitman Freeman, R. (1994) The Politics of Stakeholder Theory: Some Future Directions. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4 (4): 409-421. Freeman, R. (2011) Managing for Stakeholders: Trade-offs or Value Creation. Journal of Business Ethics, 96: 7-9. Freeman, R. and Evan, W. (1990) Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal of Behavioural Economics, 19 (4): 337-360. Freeman, R., Harrison, J., Wicks, A., Parmar, B., de Colle, S. (2010) Stakeholder Theory: The State of the Art. Cambridge University Press. Friedman, M. (September 13, 1970) The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine. Harrison, J. and Wicks, A. (2013), Shareholder Theory, Value, and Firm Performance. Business Ethics Quarterly, 23 (1): 97-124. Phillips, R. (2003) Stakeholder Theory and Organizational Ethics. San Francisco. BerretKoehler Publishers, Inc. Mansell, S. (2013) Shareholder Theory and Kant’s ‘Duty of Beneficence’. Journal of Business Ethics, Rawls, J. (1999) A Theory of Justice Revised ed. Oxford. Oxford University Press. Sacconi, L. (2006) A Social Contract Account for CSR as an Extended Model of Corporate Governance (I): Rational Bargaining and Justification. Journal of Business Ethics, 68 (3): 259-281.