Nelson, “The King is the Only Sovereign of the Empire”: Prerogative, Representation, and the American Founding Précis My paper at the July 2012 session of the workshop argued that those who made the “patriot” case in the late 1760s and early 1770s understood themselves to be reviving the Royalist political and constitutional theory of the 1630s and 1640s. Their goal of denying parliament any jurisdiction over British North America could only be achieved through the assertion of sweeping new prerogative powers for the crown—powers that the reviled Stuart monarchs had insisted upon, but which had been extinguished by the whig settlement of 1689. The American writers, therefore, found themselves abandoning the whig tradition (and, in particular, the whig theory of popular sovereignty) and arguing that, in the great constitutional crisis of the seventeenth century, the Royalists had gotten it right after all. None of this was lost on their opponents: defenders of the British administration during this period did not accuse the patriots of being crypto-republicans, as so many scholars have regarded them since the 1960s, but rather of being de facto Jacobites and “prerogative men.” Patriots defended their new position historically, by endorsing the Stuart conception of the royal prerogative, and philosophically, by reviving the Royalist theory of representation (the latter was needed in order to explain why the existence of prerogative powers in the crown was consistent with the liberty of subjects— that is, to defend an alternative, monarchical conception of popular sovereignty). It is, I suggest, not at all coincidental that those who were most active in developing and propagating this neo-Stuart defense of the royal prerogative in the 1770s—John Adams, James Wilson, Alexander Hamilton, James Iredell, and others—also became the leading advocates for sweeping prerogative powers in the executive in the 1780s. Indeed, Wilson himself defended the Federalist vision of executive power in the Constitutional Convention by remarking that, during the Revolution, “the people of Amer[ica] Did not oppose the British King but the parliament—the opposition was not ag[ains]t an Unity but a corrupt multitude.” The American Revolution, unlike the two seventeenth-century English revolutions and the French Revolution, was a revolution against a legislature, not against a king. It is this basic fact, more than any other, that explains the trajectory of American constitutionalism in the 1780s. I tell the full version of this story in a book manuscript, currently entitled “The Royalist Revolution.”