Zappa 1 Frank Zappa Dr. Jeremy Kirby PHIL 389 April 11, 2012 I Really Just Want to Believe Batman Exists Claims concerning the nature of existence have persisted in the philosophical community for eons; of particular interest are works by Bertrand Russell, Amie Thomasson, and Stephen Yablo. In these works, the authors attempt to explain how language accounts for typical problems regarding the nature of non-existents. In addition to puzzling through competing theories and presenting new or reconceived theories, Yablo elaborates on the debate between Quine and Carnap, which he believes demonstrates two differing approaches (quizzical and curious) to the problem of existence. When these competing theories are weighed against one another, Thomasson’s conceptualization of fictional objects as artifacts does the best job explaining how language accounts for non-existent objects, particularly fictional characters. In response to Frege’s theory of language and existence, Bertrand Russell offered his own account in his work “On Denoting.” The article discusses the problem of propositions and how phrases like “The present king of France is bald” seem to focus on a non-existent subject. Frege and Russell both ask how we, the listener, make sense of statements that do not refer to any existent thing; Russell offers a compelling theory to explain how we understand propositions. For example, Russell dissects the phrase “The present king of France is bald,” breaking it down into three separate claims: (1) There is at least one person who is the present king of France. (2) There is at most one person who is the present king of France. (3) Whoever this person is, he is bald. If understood in this way, the subject of the phrase is no longer the non-existent present Zappa 2 king of France; rather, the subject becomes “one person,” which is a tangible, existent object (Russell, 55). In addition to helping us understand the way we make sense of sentences containing nonexistents, Russell’s theory allows for us to make sense of sentences asserting and denying the existence of certain objects (“Pegasus does not exist”). When these propositions are broken down into the three component parts Russell suggests, he is able to assert the proposition’s uniqueness (there is at most one and at least one person) and shift the subject to an actual object, thus predicating the term “one person” (Russell, 47 ). In cases where the speaker asserts that an object does not exist, this method separates the proposition into three separate claims making the subject into “everything.” If understood this way, the phrase “Pegasus does not exist” means “Everything fails to Pegas-ize.” If everything fails to be Pegasus, then we are talking about everything that exists. The typical problems associated with non-existents are thought to dissolve when faced with Russell’s theory. However, the heart of Russell’s argument rests on the assumption that non-existents do not refer. To some, this assumption is unwarranted and ensures that fictional objects and characters will need to be addressed with theories like Russell and Frege’s. If we adopt Meinong’s conception, however, we have no need to replace the subject “present king of France” or “Pegasus.” These objects are simply things that subsist rather than exist. This conception, Russell argues, allows for objects like “the round square” to “subsist,” which does not explain how we understand them (Russell, 54). We still might ask, with regards to Meinong’s theory, what exists and what subsists; however, simply questioning whether or not certain ideas or concepts exist can be problematic in itself. Yablo, in his critique of Quine and Carnap, shows different approaches to these ontological questions, offering the possibility that we are mistaken Zappa 3 because we ignore the context in which we ask ourselves ontologically philosophical questions like whether or not numbers exist. Yablo believes that philosophers address ontological existence claims in one of two ways: the first option is the quizzical, the other curious. A quizzical approach doubts there is much information to be gained by questioning the existence of Chicago, numbers, and other abstract objects (Yablo, 231). The curious, often associated with analytic philosophy, is more concerned with finding the answers to the ontological existence questions raised (Yablo, 230231). The quizzical approach is underrepresented in the philosophical community today; Yablo argues that this is because of Quine’s devastating refutation of Carnap’s conception of the analytic/synthetic distinction and the ensuing discussion of the external/internal distinction (232). Though Yablo feels the quizzical camp may have interesting information to offer to the debate, but ultimately asserts that Quine’s theory is better suited to deal with existence claims: Quine’s idea was that our ordinary methods could be ‘jumped up’ into a test of literal truth by applying them in a sufficiently principled and long-term way. I take it as a given that this is the one idea with any hope of attaching believable truth values to philosophical existence-claims. (Yablo, 259) Yablo then concludes that most philosophical questions are likely “moot,” and that Quine would solve any important philosophical existence claims satisfyingly. Part of his conclusion rests on arguments made regarding the analytic/synthetic distinction, which in turn invites a metaphorical/literal distinction (Yablo 233). Here, “[n]ot even Quine considers it ontologically committing to say in a figurative vein that there are Xs” (Yablo, 233). Carnap relies on “a standard to which all meaningful talk is subject, an appropriate sort of discipline or rule-governedness” (Yablo, 233). This makes his conception of existence contextdependent, and to a certain degree Yablo agrees, noting that the curious approach is a Zappa 4 traditionally analytic methodology used in philosophical contexts. When discussing existence within a specific framework, the question of existence is internal. Curious (or analytic) philosophers are typically more concerned with these types of questions; Yablo believes these sorts of questions may be pointless since they are only important in the one context. Quine, typically read, believes existence is derived if and only if “it is a commitment of your best theory, i.e., the theory’s truth requires it” (Yablo, 245). The metaphorical/literal distinction is fuzzier and harder to distinguish than the distinction between analytic and synthetic; thus, if existence-questions were of any real interest, Quine’s theory would have solved them. Since it does not solve some of the questions, they are pointless questions and Yablo recommends simply adopting Quine and dismissing a large portion of existence-questions (Yablo, 259-260). For Thomasson, questions of existence are rooted in an understanding of fictional objects and characters as artifacts of their creators; in this sense, their existence is dependent on actual people (Thomasson, 59). This conception, better than perhaps Quine or Russell, offers an explanation for why fictional characters in particular go on existing long after the authors who created them have died, and how many of us recognize these characters as something that appears to refer. Two similar characters, for example, are easily distinguishable if their creators are two independent authors; an artifactual account of fictional characters and objects is supported by this observation (Thomasson, 60). Perhaps most interestingly, this particular theory has the potential to widen philosophical surroundings, meaning “the ontology of fiction can thus serve as a model for the ontology of other social and cultural objects in the everyday world” (Thomasson, 64). Confining our understanding of existent objects to “real entities” can be damaging and is sometimes referred to as the “Russelian rut.” In our everyday lives and embedded in our cultures is the overwhelming presence of fictional characters and objects for Zappa 5 which we share an understanding. Thomasson’s unique approach is one that blends Meinong’s broad acceptance of objects both real and imagined with the careful consideration of Yablo when he dissects the real issues undercutting Quine and Carnap’s dispute. One might interpret Thomasson’s theory as one that suggests ignoring the question “Does Sherlock Holmes exist?” in favor of a question about the character’s origin. Similar to Yablo’s question about our approach and agenda when we question the existence of abstract entities, Thomasson is deflecting question about characters’ existence in favor of a more thoughtful examination of the creation and tradition of fictional entities. Their unique conception and “life” after the death of their respective authors makes fictional characters objects in the sense that they were “created at a certain point in time, not merely discovered or picked out” (Thomasson, 65). They exist, at first as characters created by writers, and later continue to exist as characters to which a large audience shares access. This conception solves a persistent problem with Meinong’s conceptualization, which claims fictional characters are simply picked out or discovered among an infinite or untold number of characters authors peruse during moments of inspiration. Many philosophers who address the problem of non-existents refer to Meinong and his initial theory; Russell, Yablo, and Thomasson each reject his theory writ large, but they use his broad conception of existence as a standard against which they may measure their own theories. Russell, seeing that Meinong’s theory fails to make a truly compelling case for the existence/subsistence distinction, offers a unique and logical way of dissecting propositions concerning non-existents so that they refer. Yablo, exploring Quine and Carnap’s theories, asserts that the problem of non-existents is not of any particular interest to the philosophical community since he believes Quine’s theory is the most practical and useful of the theories. Zappa 6 According to Quine, existence depends simply on the utility and usefulness of the object in question’s existence. The many distinctions we wrestle with when trying to accommodate more extreme or confusing cases of existence are only interesting in philosophical contexts, and have no real-world application. The problem, for Yablo, is a non-problem. In contrast, Thomasson believes our inability to explain the existence or role of non-existents in language and philosophical ontologies to be a result of ignoring these objects’ and characters’ artifactual backgrounds. Thomasson’s account, which focuses on the linguistic role of storytelling and the realworld objects with which characters and objects are often associated, is the most generous that does not assert the real physical existence of Pegasus, the round square, and the character Sherlock Holmes. In some ways, this is the most intuitive response, since we often associate characters with their authors. As argued above, whenever we are confused about similar fictional objects, we defer to their creators for definitive answers regarding their “identities.” Perhaps Russell’s theory could accommodate this by understanding statements like “The present king of France is bald” to mean, “the fictional entity known as ‘the present king of France,’ conceived by me, is bald.” This way, we acknowledge that the abstract entity is abstract and fictional without also asserting that these things simply do not exist. There is no reason to claim “Everything fails to be Pegasus” when we can simply refer to the Greek authors who inspired and created the fictional creature we understand to be Pegasus. According to Thomasson, it might be thought that Pegasus does in fact exist through its continued use and presence in literature both old and new. Similarly, Yablo’s argument may also be able to work in conjunction with Thomasson’s artifactual theory. Perhaps it is useful and essential to our ontology and overall theory of Zappa 7 language to grant fictional objects and characters existence; otherwise, our language is severely flawed and we rely on this flawed system in order to communicate and make sense of the world, physical and not, that surrounds us. The metaphorical/literal distinction, similar to the internal/external distinction, is not important when characters are dependent on intentional acts of creation. These fuzzy distinctions disappear in Thomasson’s distinction, which also avoids problems commonly associated with Sartre and Meinong (Thomasson, 70). Even though Yablo seems to lament the complete abandonment in the face of Carnap’s “loss” to Quine during a debate concerning existence, ontology, and the analytic/synthetic distinction, Yablo dismisses the problems even Quine’s theory fails to address (Yablo, 259-260). These complicated cases do not create problems in Thomasson’s theory, which is simple in that abstract entities exist when they have been intentionally created by a person. Thomasson’s theory does not answer the problem of certain abstract entities; her focus on fictional characters prevents the theory from explaining in real detail how we understand abstract entities like “April” and “Chicago.” These are not intentionally constructed concepts that we repeatedly associate with a particular author or creator. Rather, “April” is a socially agreed-upon abstract entity that persists much like a fictional character persists through our repeated exposure to him or her through literary works. Though we might understand abstract entities in this way, the argument for their existence is not as compelling as her argument regarding fictional characters. Here, Russell’s theory provides the most consistent answer, though his theory does not seem to adequately capture how we understand fictional characters. An important facet of human life and our linguistic tradition, fictional characters must be included in a competitive ontological theory. Their presence across all cultures alone makes their inclusion in any ontological theory temptingly necessary. Both Russell and Quine seem to want Zappa 8 the speaker to refer to fictional characters as fictional characters. We must qualify statements about Holmes by prefacing them with “In Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s books,” or “the fictional character Sherlock Holmes.” These qualifiers either alter the context of the discussion or create space for Holmes as a sort of object insofar that he is an acknowledged character. However, when these sorts of phrases are included, otherwise perfectly comprehensible statements like “Sherlock Holmes is my favorite fictional detective” do not make sense. Similarly, to say the fictional character Holmes is a detective is actually false since fictional characters cannot be anything other than fictional characters. Thomasson’s theory, which establishes fictional characters as intentional artifacts, makes it possible to discuss Holmes as a fictional character and as Holmes, an inhabitant of a created literary world. Humanity’s rich storytelling tradition hints that we are committed to fictional characters; this paves the way for other fictional entities to exist similarly. Though there may not be a singular author or creator for these other abstract objects, they can be thought to exist in a similar manner. They are tied to reality and existence through our continued understanding of these words and phrases as communicative tools. In this sense, Thomasson’s argument is markedly different than either Russell’s or Yablo’s; her attention to the importance of fictional characters as functioning abstract entities in our day-to-day ontologies remains an unanswered strongpoint in her argument for fictional characters as artifacts. Zappa 9 Works Cited Russell, Bertrand. “On Denoting.” Logic and Knowledge. The MacMillan Company: New York. 1956. Print. Thomasson, Amie. “If We Postulated Fictional Objects, What Would They Be?” Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. 1999. Print. Yablo, Stephen. “Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72. pp. 229-283. 1998. Print.