Who Do You Marry? 2: Using Know-How ‘Who do I marry?’ Since times lost in history for most people the answer to this question has been ’you marry your cousin’. Last session we learned that some social scientists argue that this is the result of a rule, which you must obey. This week we will learn that other social scientists disagree: ‘You marry your cousin’ is the result of people using their know-how. Bourdieu’s Criticism of Levi-Strauss on Kinship Rules Last session we learned that Mauss and Levi-Strauss have an elegant and convincing argument that explains why Matrilateral Cross-Cousin Marriage is common, and why other types of Cousin Marriage are rare or exceptional. Bourdieu argues that this explanation is an illusion. Why? Anthropologists have been talking mostly to men. Sure enough, if an anthropologist interviews Kabyle men and asks a father ‘Who will your son marry?’ the father will reply ‘My brother’s daughter’. So the anthropologist goes away with the idea that the Kabyle have a rule, Patrilateral Parallel-Cousin marriage (you marry your father’s brother’s daughter). This is true, they do have this rule, but the anthropologist has missed a vital piece of information. This is only Official Kinship. There is another network of marriage practices, Practical Kinship. Official Kinship This is used by Kabyle people in special circumstances. Kabyle people refer to the father’s brother’s daughter rule on formal occasions (like when an anthropologist from the University of Paris asks them about their marriage practices!) On such formal occasions, Kabyle men’s job is to represent their kin group to outsiders. Using official kinship is mostly a male domain. But high-prestige Kabyle actually do obey the rule. This signals their high status, their difference from the common sort. Practical Kinship Kabyle people do practical kinship when a marriage is on the agenda, when a boy or girl in their kin group is reaching adolescence. This is the key issue. Kabyle people rely on help from their kin, kin-by-blood and kin-by-marriage, when dealing with problems (problems which we in the UK would probably turn over to the state). Page 1 of 5 So the Kabyle keep a close eye on getting help with future problems when they arrange a marriage. The Kabyle kin group aims to create a marriage alliance with another kin group who will help if they run into problems. That target group’s got to have the resources to help; it’s got to be living near enough to help; and it’s got to be reliable. Kabyle women play the major part in fixing this. Table 1: Ahmed’s marriage to Khedouja Great Grandfather Ahmed Ahcene Ardjab Koula Mohand Our Ahmed = Athman Our Khedouja Page 2 of 5 Ahmed’s Marriage to Khedouja So what’s going on here? Arranging an Alliance Koula is probably the key player. With an eye to getting help with future problems, she has figured out her best option out of those people she has to hand. Her plan is to marry her nephew Ahmed to her daughter Khedouja, which will unite both sides of her family as able, nearby and reliable partners. She will have laid out her plan for the marriage to her brother Mohand and her husband Athman. Problems with Koula’s Plan But Koula’s plan has a serious problem which could hit both sides of her family. Jealous neighbours may accuse Ahmed of marrying his father’s sister’s daughter. See the short dashes in the diagram. This accusation would raise a big scandal that will hit both sides of Koula’s family, husband’s and brother’s. Official kinship rules say Ahmed should be marrying his father’s brother’s daughter. Official Kinship has come into play. Jealous neighbours may call Ahmed ‘his mother’s son’, which is a deadly insult for the Kabyle. Calling someone ‘his mother’s son’ is used in witchcraft accusations, which could end up with a mob murdering Ahmed. And that could provoke a blood feud as his family retaliate by murdering other young men. So it’s time for the men in both families to put their weight behind Koula’s plan and take the lead in representing their kin groups publicly to outsiders. In public the families, led by their senior men, claim that Ahmed is related to Khedouja through the males in his family, not through his mother. The planned marriage is in line with official kinship rules. Official Kinship is in play again. See the long dashes in the diagram. Ahmed is related to Khedouja through his father Mohand, through his grandfather Ahcene, through his grandfather’s brother Ardjab, and through his grandfather’s brother’s son Athman – who is Khedouja’s father. So are they using know-how, not rules? It certainly looks like it. Koula certainly knows how to fix partnerships of able, nearby and reliable families out of the alternatives she has ready to hand Nevertheless, certainly the Official Kinship rules come into play. Page 3 of 5 Koula’s plan falls foul of the rules and both sides of her family have to deal with that to avoid a potentially deadly scandal. But then we must look at how the families deal with Official Kinship rules – they use know-how. Both families, the men who must make the public case taking the lead, know how to argue that Koula’s plan fits the official rules. We could say that ‘they know how to work the rules’. The rules don’t just determine what they do. This is an excellent moment to refer back to what we have learned from philosophers and theorists, Wittgenstein above all. What is it to Obey a Rule? Let’s revisit Philosophical Investigations. Sections §185-§239 focus on the seductive idea that our next step, what we will do next in many settings, is determined by following a rule. We can see that ‘Marry your father’s brother’s daughter’ would be an example. Wittgenstein argues that the idea gets its seductive power from an overlap with the image of a machine, so that the machine acts as a metaphor for a rule and vice versa. Thus, if we are familiar with a machine, its movements seem completely determined, as if its parts could only move in a particular way. It’s the same with a rule: it seems as if a rule could only produce a determinate outcome. Wittgenstein says this is wrong. A rule needs an interpretation. The interpretation needs an interpretation. And so on to infinity. (This is known as the problem of infinite regress.) This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because every course of action can be made out to accord with a rule… if everything can be made out to accord with the rule, then it can be made to conflict with it. And so there would be neither accord nor conflict here. [Wittgenstein: §201] This looks very much like Koula’s family arguing that Ahmed’s marriage is “in accord” with the official Kabyle Father’s Brother’s Daughter rule. So what is it to obey a rule? Following Wittgenstein, we can say that the official Kabyle rule is like a signpost, saying ‘go this way’. And we can get more from Wittgenstein. Page 4 of 5 Let me ask this: what has the expression of a rule - say a sign-post - got to do with my actions? What sort of connexion is there here? - Well, perhaps this one: I have been trained to react to this sign in a particular way, and now I do so react to it. [Wittgenstein: §198] This looks very much like Koula’s family knowing how to work the father’s brother’s daughter rule. Conclusion The conclusion is that there is no either/or here: neither just following rules nor just using know-how. There are rules and we follow them, cousin-marriage rules of various sorts included. But we must know how to follow the rules and, as Ahmed’s marriage shows, this includes knowing how to work them to suit you. Bibliography Bourdieu, Pierre (1990) The Logic of Practice. Cambridge: Polity Press. Susse, Jennifer, (1995) “Obeying a rule: Wittgenstein’s Stress on Obedience in Sections 198-202.” Conference, A Journal of Philosophy and Theory. 5(2): 15-28. Wittgenstein, L. (1996). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell. Page 5 of 5