Israeli Nationalism: Between the European Union and the Islamic State By Joseph Agassi, Tel Aviv University and York University, Toronto In its recent verdict against the appeal of some Israeli citizens to be registered in the ministry of the Interior as of Israeli rather than Jewish nationality, the Israeli Supreme Court has observed that there are two concepts of citizenship, the liberal and the romantic, and siding with the romantic concept the Supreme Court rejected the appeal. This is a hot political issue in Israel, since the Israeli premiere is planning a bill declaring that the State of Israel is the national state of the Jewish People, and since his demand that the Palestinians recognize this is an obstacle to the continuation of the peace process. It puzzles many non-Israelis, friends and foes alike, that Israel does not recognize the Israeli nation. That Israel recognizes the fictitious Jewish nation troubles very few, although it should trouble the non-Israeli Jews in whose names Israel often speaks. All this requires some clarification that I have discussed elsewhere. (The Israeli Supreme Court has referred to my book on the issue, although the decision is contrary to my recommendation.) Here my aim is to explain why people who are troubled by the question of their own national identity hope to see a relief in the project of United Europe. In his celebrated Nationalism: Past Neglect and Present Power, Isaiah Berlin wrote about the politically potent nationalist passion that traditional philosophy either ignored or pitched against liberalism (as the Israeli Supreme Court has done (2013 8573/08)) and even against the liberal idea that individuals should have the right to choose their sense of identity and to act on it as much as they wish. This sense of identity is usually identified with a sense of pride in one’s belonging to one’s collective, be it a nation or a tribe or anything else. This is a mistake: identity is a mix of pride and shame, of care and concern. Nationalism, says Berlin, is both the general sense of identity and the specific nationalist ideology. The ideology is the collectivist philosophy of the nineteenth-century romantic philosophers, especially Georg Friedrich Wilhelm Hegel (who died in 1833). This philosophy declared that nations and only nations deserve political sovereignty. This of course renders nationalism anti-liberal, and liberal philosophers should offer an alternative to it―which they have failed to do. And so the romantic theory prevailed and raised the problem, what constitutes a nation? The answer is the proper essential definition of nations, and the theory of essential definitions is passé. Still, it has a tremendous appeal, and so debates about the essence of a nation rage. For example, an item in the essential definition is that the nation has a national language. This is obviously refuted and the refutations are dismissed on diverse excuses. The claim that the Jews are or are not members of this or that nation rested on claims that they partake or do not partake in the national culture. The claim that they are not members of the nation are accompanied by the claim that they comprise or do not comprise a nation. Those who said they are a nation sought the national territory that is required for a nation by the essential definition of a nation. This debate is as arbitrary as any debate can be. The liberal idea of a nation identifies it with the country’s citizenry. This led to the confused idea that the liberal idea of the nation is that the country belongs to all its citizens. This reduces the significance of national identity. It is better to consider the modern liberal democratic state a state that belongs collectively to its nation, and thus only indirectly to its citizens. In liberal nation-states nationality and citizenry are identical, and the citizens identify with the nation, not with the state. The identification with the state is dangerous, as the experience with totalitarian countries shows and as the increase danger of anti-democracy in Israel shows too. Remember that not only in fascist countries but also in the Soviet Union state replaced nation as the object of identification. In the United States, where the ideology of the Enlightenment Movement was strong, national identity first found its expression in communities, especially in religious communities. This was rectified by the official recognition of the American nation in diverse ways. In Israel, most of whose citizens belong to the non-existent Jewish nation, the absence of religious communities make the identification with the state most natural and most dangerous. This is in part due to Israel being in a state of siege, of course. And indeed, its very existence depends on its having a strong army. Yet this is dangerous as there is a great interest there in maintaining the status quo: the Israeli and the Palestinian authorities coordinate their interest in the status quo: when one part is more willing to compromise, the other hardens its position. This quick and superficial overview already allows for some interesting observations. First, all societies, the more sophisticated or less, they all need identification. Indeed, this is true even of smaller parts of a society. During World War II the USA organized its forces rapidly and created an ad hoc brigade of odds and ends called the Rainbow Brigade. Sociologists were surprised to find that its members developed pride in their brigade very quickly and for no reason at all except for the need to belong. Politically, however, there is no substitute for political belonging and for the political sense of belonging or for the sense of political belonging, it is hard to judge. And candidates for the object of political identification in the modern world are the nation and the community. This does not have to be so, and indeed the European Union offers a third option, but perhaps it is too early to judge it. For my part, I think it is a matter for the political leadership of the European Union to decide about and to act on some rational decision on this matter. Still, for now let me dwell more on the past for a while. The point that Berlin made, about the neglect of the need for identification, led to the development of the nation state rather spontaneously. With the failure of the French revolution and with the ensuing Napoleonic wars a reaction to liberalism developed and it had two different expressions, both reactionary in tendency, of course. First, rather than speak of individual liberty, as did the French Revolution, the reaction spoke of national liberty. And whatever were its guiding ideas that it expressed in the discussion of the definition of the nation that deserves liberty, its chief aim was to present the traditional community as a substitute for the modern nation: the civil society is atomized and so its members have no community life and so they suffer from a newly diagnosed illness: alienation. The word was new and it came from the technical vocabulary of psychopathology: both the American Revolution and the French Revolution led to the improvement of the lot of the mentally sick, and a leading psychiatrist, Philippe Pinel pleaded on their behalf, requesting that they be considered not deranged but mentally alienated (1801). This is not to doubt that loneliness is absent or that it is a severe condition that demands attention. This is not to deny that the rise of rapid urbanization contributed to it significantly. It is nevertheless an open question whether in modern society this condition is more severe and more common than in other societies. Some philosophers see it as a part of the human condition. This is neither here nor there: the question is empirical and there is too little study of this phenomenon and even of the phenomenon of alienation from work that is decidedly due to modern life and that there is a global movement for curing it, the movement for the improvement of the quality of working life. However humble the success of this movement is, it disproves the idea of the nineteenth-century German philosophers―especially Hegel―and sociologist―especially Ferdinand Tönnies. The latter is known for his distinction between civil society and traditional community, a distinction that is as obvious as possible. After all, social life throughout history and to date, with the exception of the modern liberal societies, were and still are organized in communities, whereas civil society is an invention conceived by western liberal thinkers. Philosopher-anthropologist-sociologist-politologist Ernest Gellner has suggested that the industrial revolution would be impossible without the prior development of civil society. Yet what Ferdinand Tönnies suggested is that communal life is real and civil life is but a shadow of it. This shows he was aware of the fact that it is possible to fight alienation without returning to communal life, since he opposed this. Today a new communalist movement is evolving and seems to be ambitious in its advocacy of communal life. Some of its leaders are reactionaries, but not all of them: the democrats among them rightly suggest that civil and communal social structures need not compete and can indeed cooperate. The separation of church and state should be conducive to it since communal life usually centers in churches. Indeed, this is the chief source of the immense strength of religious life in the United States that runs contrary to decades of predictions to the contrary. Israel does not separate state and church. The political leaders strengthen the religious sentiment by boosting religion―mainly financially but also by other perks, including release from military duties. It looks as if the is not true of the European Union, since its individual members do not impose any religious discrimination. Yet the debate about the application of Turkey to join show that possibly things are not that simple. True, the official reason for the rejection of Turkey has to do with its maltreatment of its Kurdish minority. Yet it would have done better had the European Union promised to accept its application one the trouble with the Kurds will be over. Indeed, quite a few political commentators in the European Union spoke of Turkey as non-Christian, even though most of them were not themselves members of any religious community. It is my contention that the political leadership of a liberal nation―and perhaps also of a union of nations―should facilitate communal life but not urge it upon citizens in any way, and that it should see to it that the citizens can identify with the nation, so that if a group is alienated, some action is required, whether the alienated group is religious, ethnic, or intellectual. That, further, the inability to develop civil society and identification with it is a result of low level of political education unless it is an intended ideological attitude. That is to say, reactionaries appeal to the uneducated best. I take it that the most conspicuous example against my view is Israel. Though Israel is not as civilized as I hope it will become, it is still much more civilized than its neighbors. I know this will raise the wrath of the followers of Edward Said, but I cannot help it. It is a fact that we Israelis are still not disposed to shout in political meetings, in unison Allahu Akbar! Allahu Akbar!, or Stalin! Stalin! Stalin!, although we are on the way there. We probably will never arrive there. For, to repeat, Israel survives due to its military strengthe. This strength is all too obviously not due to the great number of soldiers or of great gun-power but due to the quality of the Isreali soldier. Thus, to take a marginal example. Israeli soldiers are not famous for the mutilation of enemy corpses as the other side is. For another example, when the Holy Places were not in Israeli hands, we did not plead freedom of worship as the Palestinian leaders do now. This does not excuse the ineptness of the Israeli authorities, of course, and this ineptness, to repeat, is what takes us away from civilized conduct fast. The anti-Israeli public opinion systematically ignores Israel’s moral superiority over her neighbors. This movement operates in the hope to put pressure on Israel to behave in a more civilized manner. Yet their lack of all sense of proportion dooms their actions to failure at best. The interesting question is, why can they not speak openly and honesty? I do not know, their belonging to the civilized world makes it unthinkable that they are fools rather than liars. Of course, this is not judgmental since we are liars too. It is an expression of a sincere wonderment. Also it is the suggestion that the anti-Israeli activists harm not only the Middle East but also the European Union. They do so by clouding issues. The European Union is in a tough spot these days, mainly due to its gallant undertaking to harbor political refugees, and these refugees are now largely coming from Syria. There is a great need to assess the situation. It is clear that the problem of immigrants rests on the immense gulf between the rich and the poor countries and this will not go away overnight, but in the meanwhile the need for some immediate settlement for some respite is very urgent and so it is becoming increasingly vital for the European Union to have Israel make peace with all of her neighbors and sign the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons and join the liberal community of nations. These activists prevent this by clouding issues, by deciding secretly on what is agenda and what is not and by making it taboo to discuss important questions.