THE CHILD AND THE IRISH CONSTITUTION CONTENTS Introduction 4 I Implied Constitutional Rights of the Child 6 The Preamble 6 Citizenship 7 Article 38 and the Right to a Fair Trial 7 Article 40 and Personal Rights 9 Conclusion 10 Express Constitutional Rights of the Child 11 Article 41 and the Family 11 Article 42 and Education 12 Constitutional Limitations on the Rights of the Child 14 Family and Parental Autonomy 14 II III The Interaction Between the Rights of the Child and the Rights of the Family 14 The Subsidiary Role of the State 19 Exceptional Circumstances and State Intervention 20 Comparison with the Rights of Children of Marital and Non-Marital Children 23 Conclusions IV Recommendations for Reform 26 Deletion of Article 42.5 27 Express Recognition of the Constitutional Rights of the Child 27 The Nature of an Express Constitutional Right of the Child 31 Paramountcy 34 Guarantee of the Rights of the Child 37 Wording and the Irish Text 39 2 V Conclusion 41 Appendix 1 Twenty-eighth Amendment of the Constitution Bill 2007 43 Appendix 2 Recommendations of the Constitution Review Group in Respect of The Family and Children 45 Appendix 3 Section 28 of the South African Constitution 3 47 THE CHILD AND THE IRISH CONSTITUTION An article by article analysis of the Constitution demonstrates that the child is seldom expressly referred to in the text. In fact children are only expressly referred to in Articles 41 and 42, and even at that these references are consequential or subject to other constitutional personas i.e. the State or parents. It would appear that the only express constitutional right a child enjoys is that of a minimum standard of education,1 although arguably it is for the State to invoke this provision. It is noted that Article 42.5 refers to the “natural and imprescriptible” rights of the child, but this provision only operates where parents have failed in their duty towards their children. Notwithstanding this, children enjoy other constitutional protections as citizens of this State. The Supreme Court in Re Article 26 and the Adoption Bill 1987 held that a child is entitled, where appropriate, to invoke Articles 40 to 44: “The rights of a child who is a member of a family are not confined to those identified in Articles 41 and 42 but are also rights referred to in Articles 40, 43 and 44.”2 Moreover, Article 40 sets out a general guarantee to protect fundamental personal rights. The courts have affirmed that many of the most important rights of the child – including the right to have his or her welfare taken into account as a key priority in proceedings – derive from this Article. It should be noted, however, that Article 40.3 only obliges the State to safeguard the unspecified ‘personal rights’ of the citizen. The vagueness of this definition creates the possibility that the courts will read rights into, or out of, this provision. It is thus perhaps too imprecise to be regarded as a reliably consistent constitutional commitment to the rights of the child. 1 2 Article 42.3.2°. Re Article 26 and the Adoption Bill 1987 [1989] I.R. 656, at 662. 4 This submission shall first analyse the indirect constitutional rights of the child. These provisions do not expressly refer to the child, but, as a citizen of this State, the child is entitled to rely on these articles. It is then proposed to examine the constitutional provisions that are directly referable to the child. As shall become clear, both the express and indirect rights of a child fail to adequately account for the special position of the child in our society. In fact most of these rights are not directly applicable, but instead operate as a consequence to another event. Furthermore, an examination of the constitutional limitations on the rights of the child shall illustrate the subservient position of the child in the Constitution. On foot of this analysis one could cogently argue that children do not enjoy the benefit of constitutional rights by virtue of the fact that they are constantly undermined by the rights of other constitutional personae, and even if such obstacles can be overcome it is difficult to imagine the circumstances within which the rights of a child may be vindicated owing to the fact that their function has been so narrowly construed so as to only operate in exceptional circumstances. In light of this, certain amendments shall be recommended in the final part of this submission. It is hoped that these suggestions will stimulate debate in this area and be considered in conjunction with the 2007 Bill so as to ensure an informed, reasoned and comprehensive debate on this all important topic. 5 I: IMPLIED CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS OF THE CHILD This section shall examine some of the constitutional provisions that implicitly apply to children. Such provisions tend to be constructed in broad terms, thereby raising the question as to whether they provide adequate and definitive protection to the welfare and interests of the child. The Preamble It should first be noted that the Preamble to the Constitution commits the State to the pursuit of a number of goals, including, inter alia, the ‘promot[ion] of the common good’, the protection of ‘the dignity and freedom of the individual’, and the attainment of ‘true social order’. Relied on by the courts in a series of cases, these objectives could potentially apply to cases concerning the rights and interests of children. In the case of A. v. Governor of Arbour Hill,3 wherein the Applicant sought to be released from imprisonment on the grounds that the offence of unlawful carnal knowledge under s.1 of the Criminal Law Act, 1935 of which he had been convicted, had subsequently been struck down, Murray C.J. in justifying his decision to refuse the application for release relied, in part, on the Preamble’s desirous notion of ‘true social order’. Nonetheless the Preamble’s references to ‘the common good’, ‘dignity and freedom’, ‘Prudence, Justice and Charity’, and ‘true social order’ are so vague and indeterminate that it is difficult to predict the manner in which they may be interpreted in particular cases. Their generality means that in any individual case “they add little to the more precise terms of the relevant Articles”4 in question. It is thus impossible to conclude whether they might have a positive or negative impact on the constitutional position of the child. As Hogan and Whyte have noted, from the point of view of the citizen 3 4 [2006] 4 I.R. 88. A.G. v. Southern Industrial Trust (1960) 94 ILTR 161, at 175. 6 (or child) seeking to rely on the provisions of the Preamble they “can be as easily used against them as in their favour”.5 Citizenship Article 2 sets out the entitlement of every person born on the island of Ireland to Irish citizenship. The language of the text thus dictates that every child born in the Republic of Ireland, or in Northern Ireland, is entitled to claim Irish citizenship, and all the privileges, duties and rights entailed therein. This is clearly an important right for the child, as citizenship is a prerequisite to the enjoyment of certain rights, such as, for example, the right to obtain an Irish passport.6 This has been qualified by Article 9.2.1° however, which provides that a child born in the island of Ireland will not automatically be entitled to citizenship if he or she does not have “at least one parent who is an Irish citizen or entitled to be an Irish citizen”.7 This restriction only applies to children born after 1 January 2005, at which date the Irish Nationality and Citizenship Act 2004 came into force. This Act bestows citizenship on those children whose parents were resident in Ireland for three of the four years before birth, thereby demonstrating a genuine link to the State. Article 38 and the Right to a Fair Trial Article 38.1 provides that “no person shall be tried on any criminal charge save in due course of law”. This has been held by the courts to create a constitutional right to a fair trial which equally applies to children. Therefore, in cases where a child is accused of a crime he or she shall receive the same constitutional protections as any other citizen. That said however, in cases where a child is a victim of an offence, Article 38 might be seen to create problems from a child protection perspective. As the constitutional source of the various procedural protections to which an accused is entitled, this 5 Hogan & Whyte, Kelly: The Irish Constitution (4th ed., Butterworths, 2003), at 56. The State (M) v. A.G. [1979] I.R. 73. 7 This provision was inserted by way of referendum on the 24 th day of June, 2004 in light of the Supreme Court decision in the case of A.O. & D.L. v. Minister for Justice [2003] 1 I.R. 1. 6 7 Article can sometimes be perceived as a limitation on the ability of the State to vindicate the interests of a victim of an alleged crime. This opinion was notably voiced by media commentators in respect of the decisions in C.C. v. Ireland8 and A. v. Governor of Arbour Hill Prison.9 In the case of C.C. the Supreme Court deemed the strict liability offence of unlawful carnal knowledge of a girl under 15 years of age, pursuant to section 1(1) of the Criminal Law (Amendment) Act 1935, to be unconstitutional. On foot of that decision the case of A. concerned a habeas corpus application on the basis that the Applicant was been imprisoned on foot of an unconstitutional offence. These cases sparked a mass public debate which, amongst other things, called for a constitutional amendment to expressly recognise the rights of the child. There are a number of difficulties with seeking to invoke such an amendment so as to prevent the recurrence of similar cases. First it is salutary to note that in a trial situation the case is between the accused and the State, not the victim. Therefore the individual rights of the victim, or any amendment thereto, may not affect the course of a trial. Secondly, it is important to realise that the Supreme Court in C.C. did take into account the rights of the child as “a legitimate end to be pursued by appropriate means”. The interest of the State in child protection was thus already a factor in the Court’s conclusion in this case. However, the court held that, despite this objective, the infringement of the accused’s rights was not justified. As Hardiman J. noted, the consequence of section 1(1) was that an individual who reasonably believed that a girl was not under the age of 15 would have their constitutional rights reduced to nought on the basis of a general social interest in deterring underage intercourse. A morally blameless individual would thus have their constitutional rights sacrificed on behalf of a social policy. The key problem with any attempt to restore a strict liability regime is that it is so offensive to our existing constitutional conception of the rule of law that it is almost impossible to justify. It is thought that a specific constitutional recognition of the importance of child protection would not alter the outcome of the case because, as already stated this was a factor to which the court had regard. 8 9 [2006] 4 I.R. 1. [2006] 4 I.R. 88. 8 Moreover, even if the interests of the child were to be given constitutional status so as to be taken into account in the course of a criminal trial where the victim is a child, an argument could be made that the strict liability regime itself actually offends against the rights of any accused who is also a child. It is arguable that children, by virtue of their greater exposure to, and interaction with fellow children, are more likely to be at risk of unwittingly committing the offence of unlawful carnal knowledge. A strict liability regime therefore would criminalise those children who have consensual sexual intercourse with other children. Therefore a constitutional amendment seeking to safeguard the rights of children may not provide a solution to a C.C. situation. Article 40 and Personal Rights This Article guarantees a number of important fundamental rights, including the right to equal treatment, the right to life, the right to liberty, freedom of expression, freedom of association and assembly, and the inviolability of the dwelling place. It also commits the State to the protection of the ‘personal rights’ of the citizen, an open-textured formulation which has been interpreted by the courts to include rights which are otherwise not specified in the Constitution, commonly referred to in legal parlance as unenumerated rights. Although none of the various elements of Article 40 make specific reference to the position of the child, some attempts have been made to identify the rights of the child under the Article 40.3 guarantee to protect the “personal rights of the citizen from unjust attack”. O’Higgins C.J. in G. v. An Bord Uchtála found, for example, that: “The child has the right to be fed and to live, to be reared and educated, to have the opportunity of working and of realising his or her full personality and dignity as a human being.”10 Finlay-Geoghegan J. expressed the view that: 10 [1980] I.R. 32, at 56. 9 “[T]he right of a child to have decisions in relation to guardianship, custody or upbringing, taken in the interests of his/her welfare is a personal right of the child within the meaning of Article 40.3 and therefore one which the State pledges to vindicate as far as practicable.”11 MacMenamin J. applied this right in the ‘Baby Ann’12 case in reaching the decision to grant custody of the child in question to her prospective adopters, rather than her natural parents. However, this decision was reversed on appeal to the Supreme Court which favoured the more traditional approach in determining that the interests and welfare of a child are best protected within the child’s constitutional family. Conclusion As is evident from the foregoing the broad terms of the Constitution are capable of incorporating the interests of the child, but it is equally clear that each such reference is capable of being overruled by another provision. These references lack the clarity and certainty required to definitively state that our Constitution does adequately cater for the interests of children. As shall become imminently clear the following analysis of the express constitutional rights of the child does little to appease this opinion. 11 12 F.N v. C.O. [2004] 4 I.R. 311, at 323. N. v. Health Service Executive [2006] 4 I.R. 374. 10 II: EXPRESS CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS OF THE CHILD This section examines the constitutional provisions directly referable to the child and his or her upbringing. As shall become evident, the child in a constitutional context is only expressly referred to in relation to other constitutional personae, most notably parents and the family unit, with the State occupying a subsidiary role. As a supplement to this section, the subsequent section shall demonstrate the truly subservient role which children’s rights currently engage in the Irish Constitution by virtue of the limitations and restrictions contained therein. Article 41 and the Family Article 41 concerns the family based on marriage. Although the only express reference to a child in this Article is in relation to the requirement to make proper provision upon divorce, it is implicit that as a member of a constitutional family the child does benefit from consequential rights. Finlay C.J., relying on Articles 41 and 42 stated that: “The infant, being the child of married parents, now legitimised, has … rights under the Constitution as a member of a family, which are (a) to belong to a unit group possessing inalienable and imprescriptible rights antecedent and superior to all positive law; (b) to protection by the State of the family to which it belongs, and (c) to be educated by the family and to be provided by its parents with religious, moral, intellectual, physical and social education.”13 Indeed the child of a non-marital family enjoys the same rights, as is evident from the dicta of Gavan Duffy P. in Re M. wherein he confirmed that a child born outside marriage “has the same ‘natural and imprescriptible rights’ as a child born within 13 In re J.H. [1985] I.R. 375, at 394. 11 wedlock”.14 However, a child does not enjoy the right to be a member of a family solely by virtue of his or her birth to his or her parents, as in the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights in interpreting the European Convention on Human Rights.15 Instead, under Irish jurisprudence a child only becomes a member of a family if his or her natural parents are married to one another. There are various concomitant effects arising from this mode of thinking which most notably arise in the context of adoption. The recent Supreme Court decision in the ‘Baby Ann’ case is demonstrative of the fact that in the eyes of the Irish courts the welfare and best interests of a child are best served by placing the child within a constitutional family which consists of parties who may well be strangers to the child, rather than allowing the child remain in the custody of parties who have acted in loco parentis for the majority of the child’s life. It is difficult to decipher what constitutional rights, if any, of the child are being vindicated and protected in such a scenario. Instead it would appear to be bolstering the rights of the natural parents, which may well be contrary to the best interests of the child in question. It is pertinent to remember that a natural parent’s right to his or her child may not always accord with the child’s right to have his or her welfare protected. Article 42 and Education Article 42 deals with the right to education, although it is true to say that it has more to do with the Family, thus almost acting as an addendum to Article 41. The constitutional concept of education is broader than scholastic education and includes the general upbringing of the child which is a duty bestowed upon parents with the State acting in a subordinate role. Although the State is obliged to provide for free primary education, Article 42 also acknowledges the primacy of the Family as an educational provider. Article 42.3.1° further specifies that the State cannot oblige parents to send their children to a particular school, or type of school “in violation of their conscience and lawful preference”. 14 [1946] I.R. 334, at 344. This was repeated by the Supreme Court in State(Nicolaou) v. An Bord Uchtála [1966] I.R. 567. 15 Keegan v. Ireland (1994) 18 E.H.R.R. 342. 12 Education has been interpreted broadly by the courts to include forms of developmental training beyond those involved in traditional academic schooling. This Article was thus relied on in relation to claims by children with disabilities that the State was making inadequate provision for their educational welfare. The utility of this right was, however, arguably limited by the refusal of the Supreme Court in Sinnott16 and T.D.17 to compel legislative and executive expenditure on the enforcement of this socio-economic entitlement. 16 17 Sinnott v. Minister for Education [2001] 2 I.R. 545. T.D. v. Minister for Education [2001] 4 I.R. 259. 13 III: CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITATIONS ON THE RIGHTS OF THE CHILD This section shall examine the limitations imposed by the Constitution itself on the exercise of the rights of a child. The analysis thus far has demonstrated that children’s rights play a minor role at best within the Irish Constitution. The following examination shall demonstrate that when considered in conjunction with other constitutional rights, the rights of the child occupy a subservient role within the Constitution as it currently stands. Family and Parental autonomy The Constitution’s protection of the notion of parental or familial autonomy has the potential to produce sub-optimal welfare outcomes for the child members of such units. It is submitted that the constitutional portrayal of the family as an autonomous unit, immune from everyday State intervention, adversely impacts on the protection of the rights of the child. Articles 41 and 42 of the Constitution demonstrate a strong commitment to the conception of the family as an independent decision-making body. The family is described as the “primary educator” of children, its significance assured by the Constitution’s depiction of it as a “moral institution possessing inalienable and imprescriptible rights”. As the “natural primary and fundamental unit group of society”, it is thus heavily protected from State interference. The Interaction Between the Rights of the Child and the Rights of the Family It is submitted that at the crux of any proposed amendment in relation to the rights of the child it is necessary to contend with the issues arising from the current interaction between the rights of the family unit and those individuals within it. Article 41 has been held by the courts to protect the autonomy of the family as an institution. Costello J. concluded in Murray v. Ireland that: 14 “The rights in Article 41.1.1 are those which can be properly said to belong to the institution itself as distinct from the personal rights which each individual member might enjoy by virtue of membership of the family.”18 Kenny J. had similarly held in Ryan v. Attorney General that Article 41 addressed the question of the constitutional protection of the family “in its constitution and authority”.19 This Article thus appears to govern the relationship between the family unit and external actors, such as the State. Article 42, on the other hand, addresses the distribution of authority within the family unit, vesting primary responsibility for the education of the child in its parents. It is clear therefore that the family’s right to autonomy from State interference is established in strident and expansive terms in the constitutional text. The courts have, however, emphasised that these rights, despite being described as imprescriptible and inalienable, are not absolute.20 The Constitution’s commitment to the independence of the unit could not, for example, overbear an individual’s right to be protected against injurious attack by another family member.21 An infringement of Article 41 and 42 could similarly be upheld where the dictates of public policy or of the common good so demanded.22 It is thus inaccurate to suggest that the rights of the family automatically outrank the rights of the child. As Denham J. stated in her decision in the case of North Western Health Board v. H.W.:23 “The child is the responsibility of the parents. The rights of the parents in exercising their responsibility are not absolute; the child has personal constitutional rights. The child has rights both as part of the unit of the family and as an individual.” 18 [1985] I.R. 532, at 538. Ryan v. A.G. [1965] I.R. 294, at 350. 20 See, for example, Murray v. Ireland [1985] I.R. 532; and A.O. & D.L. v. Minister for Justice, Equality and Law Reform [2003] 1 I.R. 1. 21 The People (DPP) v T. (1988) 3 Frewen 141. 22 A.O. & D.L. v. Minister for Justice, Equality and Law Reform [2003] 1 I.R. 1. 23 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 718. 19 15 The courts evidently accept that there is a need for a balance to be struck between the personal rights of individual family members and the autonomy of the unit, and of the parents. Denham J., in her judgment in H.W., subsequently commented: “The court has a constitutional duty to protect the life or health of the child from serious threat and the court has a constitutional duty to protect the family. A just and constitutional balance has to be sought.”24 The particular nature of this balance must therefore be a key concern for any examination of the Constitution’s protection of the rights of the child. The focus of this analysis will thus fall on the courts’ perception of the point at which State intervention on behalf of the child is constitutionally permissible. The first obstacle to any attempt by the State to undertake child protection measures is the presumption that the welfare of the child is best served by its membership of the constitutional family unit. The Supreme Court in J.H. held that the protected autonomy of the marital family established a “constitutional presumption that the welfare of the child … is to be found within the family”. 25 Furthermore, Finlay C.J., in reliance on Article 42.5, concluded that this presumption could only be rebutted where: “[T]he Court is satisfied on the evidence that there are compelling reasons why [the welfare of the child] cannot be [found within the family], or … the Court is satisfied that the evidence establishes an exceptional case where the parents have failed to provide education for the child and continue to fail to provide education for the child for moral or physical reasons.”26 The recent Supreme Court decision in the ‘Baby Ann’27 case reiterated this constitutional presumption and emphasised the importance of establishing a failure of parental duty, thereby illustrating the prevailing acceptance of this traditional constitutional balance. 24 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 726. [1985] I.R. 375, at 395. 26 [1985] I.R. 375, at 395. 27 N. v. Health Service Executive [2006] 4 I.R. 374. 25 16 The fact that this reasoning established a very high threshold for State intervention was clearly demonstrated in the case of North Western Health Board v. H.W..28 The case concerned the refusal of a child’s parents to allow a diagnostic PKU test to be conducted on their child. The test involved the taking of a sample of blood by way of a heel-prick, and had been proven to reduce the incidence in Ireland of a number of serious childhood illnesses. The performance of the test was thus, as Murphy J. admitted “beyond debate … in medical terms, … unquestionably in the best interests of the infant”.29 The majority of the Court nonetheless concluded that the parents were entitled to refuse to allow their child to undergo the test. The constitutional presumption that the child’s welfare is generally found within the family unit thus operated to expose the infant in question to a danger which, the deciding judges accepted, was not in his best interests. “Unwise and disturbing”30 as the parent’s decision appeared, the Supreme Court felt that the autonomy of the parents prevented the State from ensuring that the child received the medical treatment which an overarching concern for his welfare would require. In keeping with his judgment in H.W., Hardiman J. in the later case of ‘Baby Ann’ appeared to regard the rights of the child in terms of the relative rights of parents and third parties. In interpreting the rights of the child Hardiman J. appears to suggest that these rights do not have an independent existence. Rather, a child’s rights operate in practice as a right to decisional primacy over the care of the child. The child does not appear in the court’s assessment of individual entitlements. The question instead is one of whether the parents or some third party ought to exercise control: “A right conferred on or deemed to inhere in a very young child will in practice fall to be exercised by another on his or her behalf. In practice, therefore, though such a right may be ascribed to a child, it will actually 28 [2001] 3 I.R. 622. [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 729. 30 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 741, per Murray J. 29 17 empower whoever is in a position to assert it, and not the child himself or herself.”31 Hardiman J. thus envisaged the constitutional protection of the rights of a child as a choice between the effective vesting of those rights in the parents, on the one hand, or a third party such as the State, on the other. He thus argued that the current regime “does not prefer parents to children”, but rather “prefers parents to third parties, official or private, priest or social worker”. There is, of course, some merit in this view. However, it is arguably based on a narrow conception of the character of a child’s entitlements under the Constitution. Hardiman J. views these in strictly subjective and autonomous terms. A right, in his opinion, is necessarily connected to an individual’s autonomy. It guarantees the individual’s ability to make his or her own judgments and decisions in respect of particular matters. In the context of a child, these decisions are those related to the upbringing and welfare of the child. This sort of autonomy-entitlement cannot be exercised by a young child. Hardiman J. neglects, however, the possibility of a constitutional entitlement to an objective level of treatment. Such an outcome-oriented conception of entitlements is alien to our traditional understanding of the rights of adults in a liberal system. In terms of children’s rights, however this welfare-oriented understanding of rights has been accepted by many commentators. This is important from the point of view of any possible amendment to the Constitution. On Hardiman J.’s analysis, the rights of the child are effectively vested in another party until such time as he or she is in a position to exercise them himself or herself. Thus, any greater protection of children’s rights would simply increase the rights of the party holding those rights. If there is a desire to increase the objective protection of children from harmful situations, it may therefore be necessary to include an express welfare component in 31 N. v. Health Service Executive [2006] 4 I.R. 374, at 503. 18 any definition of the rights of the child. Any amendment would necessarily have to declare that the entitlement being created is one to an objective level of treatment, if it was to achieve its aim. This would not necessarily have to reduce the primacy of the parents’ subjective decision-making, when compared to that of the State. It would, however, ensure that where the decisions of any party, parent or State, could be shown to adversely impact on the child, its entitlement to have its welfare ensured would be vindicated by the courts. The Subsidiary Role of the State The court’s interpretation of the constitutional text reflects a clear conception of the State as simply an ancillary protector of children’s rights. Denham J., having identified the necessity for a balance between parental autonomy and the personal rights of the child, felt that “[t]he people have chosen to live in a society where parents make decisions concerning the welfare of their children and the State intervenes only in exceptional circumstances”.32 Murphy J. agreed that the Constitution “relegat[ed] the State to a subordinate and subsidiary role”, concluding that “[t]he failure of the parental duty which would justify and compel intervention by the State must be exceptional indeed”.33 From the point of view of child protection, there are, therefore, two chief objections to the Constitution’s approach to parental autonomy. The first is that it “plainly accords a primacy to the parent and [that] this primacy … gives rise to a presumption that the welfare of the child is to be found in the family exercising its authority”. 34 The second difficulty is the fact that the courts have, by analogy with the terms of Article 42.5, generally allowed the State to rebut this presumption and intervene on behalf of the child only in the narrow and limited context of ‘exceptional circumstances’ of parental failure. In light of the courts’ conclusion that the personal rights of the child arise in Article 40.3, the judiciary’s treatment of the State as the subsidiary guarantor of these rights 32 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 722. [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 732. 34 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 764, per Hardiman J. 33 19 is somewhat surprising. Article 40.3, after all, obliges the State to “defend and vindicate” these rights “as far as practicable”. There exists, therefore, a positive duty on the State to actively protect the personal rights of all citizens. However, in the case of children, this duty is effectively delegated to a third party. Furthermore, the duty is delegated to a third party which, by virtue of Article 42.5, is immune from State scrutiny or intervention except in exceptional circumstances. Alone of the State’s citizenry, the State therefore appears to owe its children a reduced obligation under Article 40.3. For all others, the State must act “as far as practicable” to uphold their rights. For children, however, the State is not obliged and in fact is not entitled to intervene except in a very limited context. This high threshold for State intervention thus undermines the extent to which a child can successfully assert its entitlements under Article 40.3. Exceptional Circumstances and State Intervention The Supreme Court held in Re Article 26 and the Adoption Bill (No.2) 198735 that Article 42.5 applied not only to the failure of parents to provide education but also to a failure to secure the “other personal rights of the child”. This Article, with its requirement of “exceptional circumstances” of “physical or moral” failure, thus became the jurisdictional template for State intervention in defence of the rights of the child. In the context of the adoption of children of married couples Finlay C.J. held that the requirement of failure would not be satisfied by a “mere inadequacy of standard in the discharge of parental duty”. Failure must be total, and must arise for physical or moral reasons. It must be a joint failure by both parents but it need not be blameworthy. Such a strict definition of the concept of failure implicitly precludes State intervention in a situation in which actions of parents which fall short of total failure nonetheless have an adverse impact on the welfare of their child. 35 [1989] I.R. 656. 20 The statutory insistence on proof of abandonment, which is interpreted in an objective manner, in the context of what became the Adoption Act 1988 was described by Finlay C.J. as indicative of a “special regard for the constitutionally protected parental rights”. This leaves open the question of whether a requirement of abandonment is actually mandated by the Constitution’s commitment to parental autonomy. At present, however, it is regarded as a necessary additional proof in cases of adoption. Thus, the possibility exists that the requirement of abandonment might not be satisfied, even in situations where a total failure of parental duty has been established.36 This should, however, only apply to the actual adoption of the child. It ought not preclude State intervention in defence of its welfare. The State’s ability to ensure the welfare of the child in the constitutional family is inhibited not only by the court’s strict construction of the concept of failure, but also by the insistence on proof of exceptional circumstances. This is further compounded by the approach taken to date by the Irish courts in examining such cases. As already noted, there is a presumption that the best interests of the child are served within the constitutional family. In addition the Supreme Court has taken the view that, in cases in which the actions of a parent are at issue, “[i]t is presumed that his or her actions are in accordance with the best interests of the child.”37 This clearly indicates that the courts will not examine the welfare implications of a parent’s conduct unless some positive “evidence [is] produced that it would not serve [the child’s] best interests”.38 As highlighted in the earlier examination of the decision in J.H., as upheld in the recent ‘Baby Ann’ case, the State will only be permitted to intervene where it can satisfy the Court that there are exceptional circumstances, or compelling reasons, to allow it. This was reiterated in the decisions of the majority of the Supreme Court in H.W.. The individual judges furnished a variety of examples of situations in which they would regard State intervention as justified. Denham J. felt that exceptional circumstances could include the existence of an immediate threat to the health or life of the child. Murray J., as he then was, similarly spoke of an immediate and fundamental threat to 36 In re Article 26 and the Adoption Bill (No.2) 1997 [1989] I.R. 656, at 664. McK. v. Information Commissioner [2006] 1 I.R. 260, at 267. 38 Ibid,. at 268. 37 21 the capacity of the child to continue to function as a human person, deriving from an exceptional dereliction of parental duty. Murphy J. meanwhile referred to an instance of parental neglect which would constitute an abandonment of the child and of all rights in respect of him. Furthermore, the threshold for State intervention was, if anything, raised by the recent Supreme Court decision in ‘Baby Ann’. The Court in that case emphasised that the constitutional presumption in favour of parental autonomy could only be rebutted where a failure of parental duty had actually been established. The judges went further, however, to consider what could constitute a failure of duty on the part of the parents. The Court held that, where no issue of physical incapacity was raised, a failure of moral capacity would have to be established. A failure on this ground could only be established by blameworthy or culpable parental conduct. The mere giving up of a child for adoption could not, in the Court’s view, be regarded as blameworthy. This decision arguably makes the already elevated criteria of Article 42.5 even more difficult to satisfy. This is especially so given the general reluctance of courts to attribute blame or fault in such sensitive matters. A court may be unwilling (and, arguably, it would be unsatisfactory on policy grounds) to readily accuse individuals of morally culpable conduct in their dealings with their child. This is reflected in Hardiman J.’s view that: “[I]n a case such as this where there is no question of physical incapacity to rear a child, an allegation of failure in duty to the child is … a very grave allegation.”39 These tests create an obvious risk that the State could be prohibited from intervening to prevent parental actions which have a negative impact on the welfare of the child, where those actions fall short of these raised thresholds, a point starkly evident in the above mentioned case of H.W.. 39 N. v. Health Service Executive [2006] 4 I.R. 374, at 533. 22 In his judgment in H.W. Hardiman J. appeared to suggest an additional restriction on State intervention under Article 42.5. The learned judge was of the opinion that the authority of the family is incapable of temporal subdivision.40 He thus envisages intervention by the State only in situations in which it is to supplant the place of the parents entirely. This would logically seem to prohibit any transient interventions by the State to address a temporary risk. This could further expose a child to the danger of occasionally detrimental conduct on the part of its parents which nonetheless fails to justify its removal from the family entirely. Comparison with the Rights of Children of Marital and Non-Marital Parents The presumption that the welfare interests of a child coincide with its membership of a marital family, allied to the Article 42.5 inspired exceptional circumstances threshold for State intervention, clearly reduces the level of protection which a child is entitled to expect from the Irish constitutional order. That this is unquestionably the case is demonstrated by a comparison of the way in which the courts have treated the rights of children under Article 41 and 42, with the rights of those children of unmarried couples which rest entirely on Article 40.3. The absence of an Article 41/42 dimension allows the court to treat the welfare of the child of a non-marital couple as its primary and paramount concern. The rights of the child’s parents are recognised by the courts, but are only a subsidiary factor in its overall welfare assessment. In the cases of K. v. W.41 and W.O’R. v. E.H.42 the applicants were natural fathers seeking to assert guardianship rights over their children so as to partake in any subsequent adoption process involving the respective children. Although dismissing both applications the Courts set out the rights of the natural father in a child-centred fashion. Unencumbered by pre-existing assumptions, the welfare of the child was examined in the context of the actual circumstances of his case. The constitutional entitlements of the father were thus dependent on the extent to which the relationship would benefit the child. Hamilton C.J. summarised the position as follows: 40 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 758. [1990] 2 I.R. 437. 42 [1996] 2 I.R. 248. 41 23 “[T]here may be considerations appropriate to the welfare of the child … as may make it desirable for the child to enjoy the society, protection and guardianship of its father …. The extent and character of the rights of the [natural] father of a child … accrue not from any constitutional right vested in the natural father to be appointed guardian but from the relationship of the father to the child.”43 A similar overriding concern for the welfare of the child is evident in the court’s treatment of the rights of the natural mother. The rights of the natural mother in respect of her child have long been established as more extensive than those of the father.44 Unlike the father, for example, the consent of the mother was required in the case of an adoption. Despite the Constitution’s strong protection of this right, however, the courts have subjected these rights, where appropriate, to the interests of the child. In Northern Area Health Board v. An Bord Uchtála,45 for example, McGuinness J. allowed an adoption to proceed without the consent of the mother where the mother was regarded by experts as unable to care for her child. It would appear, therefore, that two very different child protection regimes exist within the parameters of the Irish Constitution. In cases concerning the children of non-martial couples, the welfare and interests of the child are treated as the court’s primary concern. Issues of parental rights are examined in terms of their impact on the welfare of the child. The court is charged with the contextualised assessment of the evidence before it, aiming to establish, on balance, what will actually be in the best interests of the child. Cases involving the rights of children of marital couples are of a very different order. The court is not asked to examine the best interests of the child. On the contrary, the task in such cases is to consider if exceptional circumstances of parental failure have been shown, such as would allow the State to intervene to protect the child. The logical corollary of this type of analytical approach is that neither the courts nor, consequently, the relevant State authorities, are entitled to act in situations in which W.O’R. v. E.H. [1996] 2 I.R. 248, at 261-262. State (Nicolaou) v. An Bord Uchtála [1966] I.R. 567, at 644; G. v. An Bord Uchtála [1980] I.R. 32, at 55. 45 [2002] 4 I.R. 252. 43 44 24 welfare-adverse treatment of the child exists, but does not satisfy the designated constitutional criteria. From the point of view of child protection, this is obviously unsatisfactory. The fact that, as the decisions in H.W. demonstrate, the threshold for State intervention is set at such a high level inevitably exposes children to the risk of unchecked infringements on the part of their parents of their Article 40.3 rights. The conclusion to be drawn from this overview of the constitutional caselaw must therefore be that the continuing influence of Article 42.5 constitutes the biggest single obstacle to a successful child protection regime. The notion of parental autonomy, of itself, need not overbear the interests of the child. However, a situation in which the State is entitled to act – in fulfilment of its express constitutional duty to uphold the personal rights of its citizens – only in a limited and much-constrained context is a matter of concern. Conclusions As is clear from the foregoing analysis, the operation of Article 42.5 is the antithesis of an effective constitutional child protection system. Its fundamental premise is contrary to the desired objective. Article 42.5 is based on establishing a failure of parental duty and is therefore constructed in negative terms and indeed has been interpreted accordingly. It is submitted that what is required is a positive and purposive approach to child protection within the Constitution. There is a need to adequately recognise the child as being an individual constitutional persona entitled to, and capable of, enjoying the benefit of constitutional rights. To achieve this it is necessary to positively vest constitutional rights in the child. Such an amendment would remove the need to prove that there has been an initial failure on the part of other persons or entities before asserting the child’s constitutional entitlements. Rather, the child will always be deemed entitled to enjoy the benefits which the Constitution may bestow on him or her. In light of these observations the following section details a number of recommendations for reform. 25 IV: RECOMMENDATIONS FOR REFORM The commentary thus far demonstrates that the Irish Constitution fails to protect the welfare and interests of children with the degree of clarity, certainty and force deemed necessary in today’s society. In particular, the inability of the State to intervene in defence of a child’s rights in any situation which does not constitute “exceptional circumstances” is a matter of concern. It is thought that the crux of this problem lies in the fact that the Constitution, and its interpretation to date, focuses on the need to establish a parental failure as opposed to adopting a positive approach in simply expressly recognising the rights of the child and allowing them to be taken into account in a similar manner to those of parents and/or the family unit. There is a need to recognise the individual constitutional persona of the child and not to have regard to children in consequence to other constitutional personae, most notably parents and the family unit. Essentially what is called for is a child-centred approach. At present the Joint Committee on the Constitutional Amendment on Children is considering the Twenty-eighth Amendment to the Constitution Bill 2007 (hereinafter referred to as the ‘2007 Bill’). It proposes to repeal Article 42.5 and substitute a new Article 42A.46 This submission does not intend to merely analyse this proposed amendment, rather it seeks to set out a number of amendments that can be made. Also, additional models are considered and discounted for the reasons set out below in an effort to provide an objective analysis. It is hoped that this submission will be of assistance to the Joint Committee. In addition, reference shall be made to the proposed reforms posited by the Constitution Review Group (CRG) in its report published in 1996.47 As part of a radical overhaul of Article 41 and 42, the CRG made a number of recommendations in relation to the protection of children. 46 47 See Appendix 1. See Appendix 2. 26 Article 42.5 In tandem with the proposed amendment contained in the 2007 Bill it is recommended herein that Article 42.5 of the Constitution be deleted. As is clear throughout this submission one of the key problems with child protection in the Irish Constitution is the presumption that the welfare of the child is best protected within the constitutional family, and the elevated threshold of proof required to rebut this presumption. Family autonomy and child protection need not operate as two exclusive objectives. Rather, family autonomy and child protection can operate in conjunction with one another as is evident from the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights. So as to achieve a balance between these two objectives the “exceptional circumstances” requirement of Article 42.5 needs to be removed. As shall be seen below it is recommended that this be accompanied by amendments to Articles 40 and 41 so as to strike the appropriate balance between family autonomy and child protection. An amendment to just one article of the Constitution is not sufficient to adequately meet the requirements of child protection. It is necessary to adopt a comprehensive approach and to consider all consequential and related factors. Express Recognition of the Constitutional Rights of the Child It is recommended that the Constitution be amended so as to provide express recognition of the constitutional rights of the child. Article 42(A).1 in the 2007 Bill seeks to provide such. However, it is argued that such a right ought to be included in Article 40 under the heading of personal rights as opposed to Article 42. The reasoning for this is as follows. So as to invoke a truly child-centred approach to any reform in this field it is necessary to recognise the child as being an individual constitutional persona. Therefore a child needs to enjoy the benefit of constitutional rights purely by virtue of his or her existence and not arising out of a relationship with another party or consequential to an event or failure of duty of another. By including the specific rights of the child in Article 40 it underlines the relationship between the State’s obligation to protect the child, and its existing Article 40.3 duty to defend and vindicate the personal rights of its citizens. Children, as citizens, are already entitled to rely on these rights. Any express incorporation of children’s rights should therefore be regarded as a restatement of their personal rights in a specific form. To locate the rights of children elsewhere in the Constitution would be to suggest that their rights are of a different order to those of other individuals, thus implicitly 27 treating children as a sub-group of citizens. Given the difficulties which the guarantee of the autonomy of the family has posed for the protection of children, it would be particularly unfortunate to include a section on children’s rights in Article 41 and 42. Any amendment should contend with the variety of issues that might arise from the usage of the phrase “natural and imprescriptible” in reference to the rights of the child. Article 41.1 provides that the constitutional family also enjoys imprescriptible rights. In proposing any amendment to the Constitution in relation to the rights of children it is necessary to consider the effect of Article 41 on any such amendment. The interpretation of Article 41 posits a perception of the family, and thus of parents, as an autonomous unit which is generally immune from State intervention. It is possible therefore that conflicts could arise between Article 42(A).1 and Article 41.1 as to whether the rights of the child or the family should prevail. To avoid such difficulties there are two possible models of reform. The first as suggested by the CRG is to delete the references to “inalienable” and “imprescriptible” in Article 41. Such a reform would have to be accompanied by a deletion to the phrase “imprescriptible” in Article 42(A).1, as to otherwise leave this reference in place may lead to a situation whereby children enjoy a constitutionally paramount position over others which can lead to additional problems as shall be discussed below. Again, however, it is submitted that an amendment in this form would do little to alleviate the present difficulties in seeking to align the balance between the rights of the child and his or her parents and family. The second, and favoured, model of reform is to insert a qualifying clause into Article 41. This Article protects the constitution and authority of the family, securing its autonomy from State intervention. It is these values with which the rights of the child are more likely to conflict. Thus, it seems more sensible to include the qualifying clause in this Article as opposed to amending Article 42. Such a clause should transform the relationship between parent and child from one of parental rights into one of parental responsibilities. This would revive the understanding of the 28 Constitution outlined by O’Dálaigh C.J. in Ryan v. Attorney General48 and Walsh J. in G. v. An Bord Uchtála wherein he stated: “One of the duties of a parent, or parents, be they married or not is to provide as best the parent or parents can for the welfare of the child and to ward off dangers to the health of the child.”49 Such a qualifying clause may take the following form: Article 41.4 Nothing in this Article shall be understood to reduce, weaken or otherwise undermine the primary responsibility of parents and, where necessary, of the State to protect a child from physical, mental or emotional harm as far as is practicable. A number of features of this clause should be noted: (i) Parental responsibilities In its language, it embraces the notion of parental responsibilities, thereby advancing a purposive understanding of parental rights as connected to the protection of the child. The autonomy of the family unit is thus connected with the defence of the rights of the child, rather than being conceived as a rival value. (ii) The role of the State The proposed Article 41.4 also refers to the role of the State in supplementing the responsibility of the parents. The reference to ‘primary responsibility’ is intended to reflect both its status as the most prioritised parental obligation, and the fact that it vests, initially, in parents rather than in the State. The State thus continues to be envisaged in a subsidiary role. This aims to reflect the fears, expressed by McCracken J. in H.W. and expressly approved by Hardiman J.50 48 [1965] 1 I.R. 294. [1980] 1 I.R. 32, at 68. 50 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 757. 49 29 on appeal, that a reorientation of this relationship between parent and State would result in a “Brave New World’ in which the State always knows best”.51 Nonetheless, the threshold of necessity – although somewhat lacking in specificity – is evidently lower than that which has existed up to this point. This therefore would have serious implications for the State. At present, the State is only entitled to intervene in cases of exceptional circumstances. The relevant authorities thus fulfil a primarily fire fighting role. However, if a lower threshold is introduced, the State will not only be entitled, but obliged to intervene in many more sub-exceptional cases. This will require considerable changes to be made to the way in which the relevant agencies in this area currently operate, imposing on them additional obligations in terms of ongoing supervision and intervention. This would therefore expose the State to potentially greater liability in situations in which harm ultimately befalls a child. Although the parents retain primacy of care, the lower threshold for State intervention would oblige the State to attempt to ensure it is aware of when intervention might be necessary. This would apply not only to the functioning of the relevant child welfare authorities but also to the legislative action (or inaction) of the State. The State could, for example, be regarded as failing in its duty if it neglected to ensure an adequate system of reporting obligations in cases where there are suspicions of some form of child abuse. (iii) Necessity The necessity threshold is, as noted, relatively imprecise. This would therefore entrust the courts with a considerable discretion to decide in what cases the State is required to act. The clear connection drawn between necessity and the protection of children from harm is designed to provide some sort of concrete focus for cases in this area. As this is, however, a primarily policy choice, an alternative calibration of the balance between parental autonomy and state action to protect the rights of the child may be desired. 51 [2001] 3 I.R. 622, at 635. 30 Nonetheless, it must be remembered that the setting of this threshold at too high a level has been at the root of many of the problems encountered in this area in the past, and indeed may be at the root of future European Convention on Human Rights orientated problems. Necessity is, it is submitted, the most constrained conception of the State’s ability to act which will ensure that the rights of the child are not overborne by the protected autonomy of its parents. (iv) Imprescriptible Rights It is suggested that if such a qualifying clause is inserted into Article 41 and an express recognition of the rights of children is provided for in Article 40 then any reference in such a provision to the “imprescriptible” nature of those rights is not problematic, and indeed may in fact be beneficial. In his seminal judgment in Ryan v. Attorney General Kenny J. shed some light on the meaning of this phrase stating “imprescriptible’ means that which cannot be lost by the passage of time or abandoned by non-exercise”.52 Children ought to be prevented from losing their rights because practically speaking the vast majority of children will not be in a position to exercise such rights. This is an inherent feature of childhood, and should not deprive children of the benefit of these rights. The Nature of an Express Constitutional Right of the Child The CRG recommended that a constitutional amendment in this context be worded in such a manner so as to seek to ensure that the best interests of the child are always considered. It is respectfully submitted that such an approach not be taken. A provision centred on the best interests of the child is inherently problematic. In order to illustrate this point a comparative analysis with the position in South Africa is instructive. Following the apartheid era, the South African state made a conscious attempt to construct a constitutional order which would be characterised by a firm commitment to the defence and vindication of the human rights of its citizens. The 1996 Constitution was thus inspired by a desire to ensure that the South African system 52 [1965] 2 I.R. 294, at 308. 31 would be a model of best practice in the protection of human rights. One important point to note, however, is that the South African constitution makes no specific provision for a right to family life, or for any particular protection of marriage or of the family unit. In this, it obviously differs sharply from the Irish text. The South African courts have inferred a right to family life from the individual members’ right to dignity.53 The absence of a guarantee of autonomy for the unit, however, suggests a situation in which State intervention is much more readily justifiable than in Ireland. This should be borne in mind in any comparison of the caselaw between the two jurisdictions. Placing a particular emphasis throughout on the interests of its most vulnerable citizens, the Constitution thus included a series of guarantees in relation to children’s rights.54 Section 28(2) specifically provides that “[a] child’s best interests are of paramount importance in every matter concerning the child.” The best interests test has long been criticised as a vague and indeterminate term:55 “If human rights norms in general can be said to be inherently indeterminate, the best interest principle is located by most of its critics at the most indeterminate outer margins of even that body of norms.”56 Its lack of clarity confers considerable discretionary powers on any court asked to interpret it. The law, as a result, risks inconsistency and unpredictability, thereby denying individuals the capacity to understand the law, and orient their behaviour accordingly. The South African experience with the section 28(2) ‘best interests’ guarantee reflects the accuracy of Mnookin’s complaint. Some courts have regarded this as an independent right of the child,57 some have described it as a standard which aids in the 53 Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others (2000) (8) BCLR 837 (CC), at para. 37. 54 See Appendix 3. 55 Mnookin, “Child custody adjudication: Judicial functions in the face of indeterminacy” (1975) 39 Law and Contemporary Problems 226. 56 Rodham, “Children under the law” in Freeman (ed.), Children’s Rights (Cromwell, 2004). 57 Minister for Welfare and Population Development v. Fitzpatrick (2000) (7) BCLR 713 (CC). 32 evaluation of the child’s other rights, while others have treated it as some sort of interpretative principle. More importantly, the way in which this provision has been treated by the courts has generated considerable confusion. In its emphasis on the evidential specifics of a particular case, it appears more like a common law principle than a human rights norm. Courts asked to examine asserted infringements of human rights usually have to ascertain if the right has been infringed, and if that infringement is therefore justified. This is a fundamentally negative analytical exercise. On the contrary, an enquiry into what constitutes the best interests of the child in an individual case requires the reaching of a positive conclusion on the basis of an involved examination of the evidence before the court. The best interests test thus involves a very different approach from the balancing exercise which usually characterises cases involving human rights. This necessarily produces a situation in which constitutional issues involving children are decided on a case-by-case basis. This creates a degree of uncertainty in an important area of the law. The indeterminacy of the test also renders it peculiarly susceptible to judicial prejudices and assumptions. In South Africa, for example,: “Some courts have ignored the existence of the [best interests] principle, or at least its constitutional manifestation. Other courts have assumed that its inclusion in the Constitution has made no legal difference since existing common law rules adequately cater for the best interests of children, while a last category of cases enthusiastically use the best interests principle to change the common law.”58 Aside from the charges of unpredictability this situation obviously attracts, it also underlines the possibility that the insertion of a ‘best interests’ provision into the Irish Constitution might not, of itself, produce the desired results. Pre-existing assumptions as to what constitutes a child’s best interests might still prevail. Given the current Irish presumption is that the welfare of the child is best served within the confines of 58 Bonthuys, “The best interests of children in the South African Constitution” (2006) 20 (23) IJLP&F. 33 the autonomous and effectively unsupervised family unit, this has particular relevance for any proposal for Irish constitutional reform. Given the Constitution’s strong protection of the authority and autonomy of the family unit, this could lead the courts, in their interpretation of the test, to find that the best interests of the child are presumed to be found in its membership of the family unit. This would continue the current approach to child protection and defeat the purpose of the amendment. One possible solution to this issue is to incorporate a guarantee that a court will take account of the wishes of a child who is of sufficient age and maturity. This obviously would not oblige the court to accede to the wishes of the child. It would, however, concentrate the attention of the court on the position of the child, ensuring that its interests are factored into the court’s conclusions. Furthermore, it would underline the child’s status as an autonomous individual with distinct rights and interests. The second recommendation of this submission is therefore that a reference to the need to take account of the views of the child be inserted in place of an overarching commitment to the child’s best interests. Paramountcy Not only did the CRG recommend a “best interests” orientated provision, but it also stated that the “best interests of the child shall be the paramount consideration”.59 It is submitted that this type of supra-constitutional status is generally inadvisable. As set out above Section 28(2) of the South African Constitution prescribes the best interests of the child as being paramount. Again an analysis of the relevant South African jurisprudence is helpful in considering the potential effects of such a clause in Ireland. The court in Laerskool Middelburg60 held that the constitutional reference to paramountcy meant that children’s interests prevailed over all other interests and rights. In general, however, the South African courts have begun to recognise the interests of the child as occurring in communion with the interests of its parents, and 59 60 Constitution Review Group, Report of the Constitution Review Group 1996. Laerskool Middelburg v. Departementshoof (2003)(4) SA 160 (T). 34 those of the common good. In V. v. V.,61 for example, the High Court found that access should not be understood solely as a right of the child but was “part of a continuing relationship between parent and child”. Similarly, the Constitutional Court in Grootboom refused to allow parents of children to assert a superior entitlement to shelter over those families who were without children. The Irish courts have consistently rejected the existence of a hierarchy of constitutional values. As the troublesome cases of A.G. v. X.62 and Re Ward of Court63demonstrate, it is difficult, and arguably unwise, to attempt to prescribe a fixed scale of constitutional rights. This is especially so in the context of a guarantee which can clearly give rise to unforeseen claims. With so many areas of the law potentially impacting upon the interests of the child, it seems imprudent to regard these interests as always paramount. There are obvious tensions, for example, between the interests of the child, that of society and those of its parents. An amendment prescribing the rights of the child to be paramount could, of course, confine the guarantee to cases of custody, adoption or guardianship. This has, however, already been done by statute. Paramountcy is perfectly acceptable within the confines of a specific statutory regime. In the Constitution, however, it is liable to impact upon an unforeseeable array of situations. From the point of view of existing caselaw, for example, this type of amendment would arguably require a reconsideration of the decisions in A.O.64 and T.D.65. If the rights of the child are constitutionally stated to be paramount, it would be very difficult to assert that they should be subject to a non-particularised public interest in a coherent immigration policy, or an implicit constitutional doctrine of separation of powers. In particular, an obligation to treat the child’s interests as paramount would seem to require at the very least that Fennelly J.’s concerns in A.O. about the 61 (1998) (4) SA 169 (C). This approach is also evident in, for example, President of RSA v. Hugo (1997) (4) SA 1 (CC); and Bannatyne v. Bannatyne (2003) (2) BCLR 111 (CC). 62 [1992] 1 I.R. 1. One of the key factors in this case was the Constitution’s express provision that the rights of the mother and child were equal. This greatly complicated the courts’ task of trying to balance the two rights. 63 [1996] 2 I.R. 79. 64 A.O. & D.L. v. Minister for Justice [2003] 1 I.R. 1. 65 T.D. v. Minister for Education [2001] 4 I.R. 259. 35 availability of review be reflected in the introduction of an ‘anxious scrutiny’ type standard in this area. Furthermore, the issue would probably arise in other areas of the law. Could a juvenile offender be imprisoned if his rights are to be paramount? Would any type of punitive sentence be appropriate? Could the cross-examination of child witnesses be prohibited on the grounds that it could expose the child to emotional strain? Would the interests of child consumers predominate in cases of commercial or competition law? The risk would also arise of the child being used as a vehicle for the articulation of claims to paramountcy by third parties. The South African case of S. v. Howells66 is an instructive example of how the rights of the child can be used in support of the arguments of its parents. In this case it was argued that a parent could not be sentenced to a term of imprisonment upon conviction for a criminal act on the ground that this would not be in the best interests of his child. Evidently, this was not a case to which section 28 was intended to apply. Nonetheless, it is a plausible construction of the constitutional text. The court ultimately held that the interests of the child were subject to the societal interest in the effective punishment of crime. However, this does illustrate the risk that a general constitutional commitment to the best interests of the child will impact on cases far beyond the scope of traditional family law. This could lead to a situation in which parents of children are entitled to greater constitutional protection of their own interests (portrayed as in the interests of their children) than those citizens who do not have children. In light of the Constitution’s guarantee of equality, this would be unacceptable. From a practical point of view, the courts would have to devise a way of avoiding the logical consequences of a guarantee of paramountcy. It is thus argued that it would be better not to incorporate it into the Constitution in the first place. Some acknowledgment of the need for a court to pay particular interest to the position of the child would be preferable as it would encourage the courts to maintain a strong commitment to the interests of the child, without having to treat it as a constitutional 66 (1999) (1) SACR 675 (C). 36 trump in evidently unsuitable cases. Therefore it is recommended that the Constitution require that ‘special regard’ be had by the organs of the State to the rights and interests of the child. Guarantee of the Rights of the Child The final issue therefore is the nature of the proposed Article 40 guarantee itself. Although it has been argued that children’s rights should not be constitutionally described as being paramount there is still a need to direct the court’s attention in such a manner so as to give due weight and regard to such rights. The CRG’s preference was for an express enumeration of the rights of the child. This removes the element of uncertainty which exists in the courts’ current doctrine of unenumerated rights. However, it also fossilises the rights of the child at a particular moment of constitutional enactment. Any attempt at the enumeration of the rights of the child in Article 40.3 would not preclude attempts to assert additional rights in the future. The proposed clause, it should be borne in mind, is included as an attempt to restate the particular importance of ensuring the protection of those rights which the child is already guaranteed under Article 40.3. To some extent, therefore, any effort at introducing certainty into this area of the Constitution is doomed to failure, unless there is a more radical removal of unenumerated rights from the Constitution entirely. It is therefore proposed that a more general guarantee of children’s rights be inserted into the Constitution. That should not be taken, however, as an implication that the inclusion of a specific selection of children’s rights would be inadvisable. On the contrary, it would ensure that particular children’s rights would have to be enforced by the courts. The specifics of such a list are, however, very much a matter of political choice. Because of this, and because of the Constitution’s current preference for more general guarantees, any amendment of Article 40.3 could take the following form: Article 40.3.4 - (i) The State acknowledges childhood as a unique and vulnerable state, which requires it, in its actions and enactments, to have special regard to the rights and interests of the child. 37 (ii) A court shall accordingly have due regard, where appropriate, to the views of a child, provided that child is of sufficient age and maturity. This restates the personal rights of the child in a form which underlines the reasons why it deserves particular prominence in the decisions of government organs. The obligation to have ‘special regard’ to the rights and interests of the child is confined to the State, thus preserving an area of autonomy for the family unit. Taken together with the specific reference in the proposed Article 41.4 to the responsibility of the parents, and the State, to protect the child from physical, mental or emotional harm, it should increase the protection of children’s rights without a significant distortion of the existing constitutional regime. As regards the obligation on the court to take account of the views of the child ‘where appropriate’, this should be confined by the courts to situations in which the interests of the child are at stake. The danger here is in overextending the scope of the right by a reference, for example, to ‘all cases concerning children’. The language of appropriateness therefore attempts to allow the courts to confine the application of this right to suitable situations. The vagueness of these Articles would leave a number of issues for resolution by the courts. Perhaps the most noticeable of these is what is intended by ‘physical, mental or emotional harm’. Does this impose an enforceable obligation on parents in respect of the development of a nurturing and loving environment? It would be hoped that the reference to practicability would rebut any such arguments. This should also apply in respect of any attempt to impose responsibility on the State for the acts of a third party against the child. Perhaps the key objection to these proposals is their vagueness. This necessarily entrusts the courts with considerable power in ascertaining what is appropriate in this area. This does, however, also allow the courts the freedom to deal sensibly with situations as they arise, rather than excessively fettering them with the unintended consequences of ill-advised specifics. Furthermore the amendments as proposed seek to remain, as far as possible, within the existing constitutional orthodoxy. Although 38 they should increase the protection of children’s rights under the Irish Constitution, it is to be hoped that they would not lead to unexpected developments in other areas, which ought to be a significant concern in any process of constitutional reform. Wording and the Irish Text In constructing any constitutional amendment in this field it is imperative to have due regard to the Irish text of such an amendment. Article 25.5.4° clearly states that in the event of conflict between the English and Irish text of the Constitution, the Irish text shall prevail. This has had specific consequences in the context of children. References to children in the English text appear in the Irish version as leanbh (and its derivatives leanaí and linbh) or clann. Leanbh is generally taken to refer to an infant child of approximately pre-school age. There is thus a potential argument that the rights of the child when referred to as leanbh actually vest only in children of a very young age. This interpretation of leanbh as a phrase applicable only to individuals of a certain age was accepted by Hardiman J. in Sinnott.67 In that case, counsel for the plaintiff had argued that ‘child’ in Article 42 referred to the individual’s membership of a family unit, rather than his age. On this analysis, the phrase ‘child’ indicated that the individual was the offspring of his parents rather than that he was of a particular age. This implied that the right to education was temporally unlimited. In his consideration of this question, Hardiman J. expressly alluded to the Irish text. Leanbh, in his view, carried connotations of age. He thus concluded that he “[could not] accept the artificial construction advanced on behalf of the Plaintiff: that the word “child” or its equivalent in the national language should be interpreted as extending to a person of any age who has an ongoing need for education”.68 Hardiman J.’s judgment stands as authority for the proposition that the phrase leanbh can only be used in relation to children of a certain age. The learned judge did not, however, clarify what ages were covered by this term. 67 68 Sinnott v. Minister for Education [2001] 2 I.R. 545. [2001] 2 I.R. 545, at 690. 39 In a similar vein, the obligations of parents in respect of the care, education and welfare of their children appears in the Irish text as a duty towards the clann, or family unit. As a slightly broader term, there is, again, an arguable discrepancy here. This disparity could support the suggestion that a court called upon to examine allegations of a failure of parental duty should require the failure to be in respect of the family in general, rather than in relation to an individual child. Once more, however, this would not reflect the current caselaw.69 Therefore, it is clear that any proposed amendment in this field must be cognisant of the Irish text. There is a need to consider the purpose of each amending provision to determine the appropriate language to be used. It would be unfortunate to say the least if children’s rights would only vest in children of a certain age, e.g. 12 years old, leaving those in their remaining teenage years before majority in a constitutional lacuna. In addition, if children’s rights impose corresponding duties on others, e.g. parents, then the text should adequately protect each individual child in this regard. 69 Re J.H. [1985] I.R. 375. 40 V: CONCLUSION The primary focus of this submission is to analyse the current constitutional standing of the child in Ireland and to submit recommendations for reform. As we enter 2008 the impending amendment to the Constitution on the rights of the child draws nearer, and as this submission illustrates there is an urgent need to engage in the issues involved. The fact that the child is not adequately protected under our Constitution is evident as sections I, II and III of this submission demonstrate. The crux of the present problem is the constitutional focus on the need to establish a failure on the part of parents of a child before the rights of the child are considered. This constitutes a negative approach in the quest to protect children in our Society. Following the fallout from the Supreme Court cases of CC. v. Ireland70 and A. v. Governor of Arbour Hill Prison,71 public consensus appeared to be in support of a reform to our law in this regard. The Twenty-eighth Amendment to the Constitution Bill 2007 was introduced on foot of this. This submission proposes a number of recommendations for reform, and it is hoped that these recommendations will rekindle the debate on this topic before any referendum. In order to adequately provide for the position of the child in our Constitution a comprehensive and considered approach is required, with a childcentred approach being adopted and the fundamental objective of ensuring that the interests and welfare of the child are protected. There is a need to examine the nature and effects of Articles 40, 41 and 42. For the reasons put forward in Section IV the following recommendations are submitted: (i) Article 42.5 of the Constitution be recalibrated. (ii) The rights of the child be expressly recognised in Article 40 of the Constitution, thereby demonstrating that the child is in fact an individual constitutional persona entitled to rights and protections by virtue of its being. 70 71 [2006] 4 I.R. 1. [2006] 4 I.R. 88. 41 (iii) So as to account for the need to balance the constitutional relationship between the family unit and the child the following clause ought to be inserted as Article 41.4: Nothing in this Article shall be understood to reduce, weaken or otherwise undermine the primary responsibility of parents and, where necessary, of the State to protect a child from physical, mental or emotional harm as far as is practicable. (iv) It is recommended that any constitutional guarantee of the rights of the child not be framed in such a manner so as to impose a ‘best interests’ type test, or to render the rights of the child paramount. Instead special regard should be had to the rights and interests of the child. (v) In light of the foregoing the following guarantee ought to be inserted into Article 40 of the Constitution so as to protect the rights and interests of the child. Article 40.3.4°: (i) The State acknowledges childhood as a unique and vulnerable state, which requires it, in its actions and enactments, to have special regard to the rights and interests of the child. (ii) A court shall accordingly have due regard, where appropriate, to the views of a child, provided that child is of sufficient age and maturity. (vi) Consideration should be given to the Irish text of any such amendment so as to avoid ambiguities that may arise, particularly in relation to any references to the ‘child’ in different contexts. 42 APPENDIX 1 ———————— TWENTY-EIGHTH AMENDMENT OF THE CONSTITUTION BILL 2007 ———————— BILL entitled AN ACT TO AMEND THE CONSTITUTION. WHEREAS by virtue of Article 46 of the Constitution, any provision of the Constitution may be amended in the manner provided by that Article: AND WHEREAS it is proposed to amend the Constitution: BE IT THEREFORE ENACTED BY THE OIREACHTAS AS FOLLOWS: 1.—The Constitution is hereby amended as follows: (a) section 5 of the Irish text of Article 42 shall be repealed, (b) section 5 of the English text of Article 42 shall be repealed, (c) the Article the text of which is set out in Part 1 of the Schedule shall be inserted after Article 42 of the Irish text, (d) the Article the text of which is set out in Part 2 of the Schedule shall be inserted after Article 42 of the English text. 2.—The amendment of the Constitution effected by this Act shall be called the Twenty-eighth Amendment of the Constitution. This Act may be cited as the Twenty-eighth Amendment of the Constitution Act 2007. 43 SCHEDULE PART 2 CHILDREN Article 42(A) 1. The State acknowledges and affirms the natural and imprescriptible rights of all children. 2. 1In exceptional cases, where the parents of any child for physical or moral reasons fail in their duty towards such child, the State as guardian of the common good, by appropriate means shall endeavour to supply the place of the parents, but always with due regard for the natural and imprescriptible rights of the child. 2Provision may be made by law for the adoption of a child where the parents have failed for such a period of time as may be prescribed by law in their duty towards the child, and where the best interests of the child so require. 3. Provision may be made by law for the voluntary placement for adoption and the adoption of any child. 4. Provision may be made by law that in proceedings before any court concerning the adoption, guardianship or custody of, or access to, any child, the court shall endeavour to secure the best interests of the child. 5. 1Provision may be made by law for the collection and exchange of information relating to the endangerment, sexual exploitation or sexual abuse, or risk thereof, of children, or other persons of such a class or classes as may be prescribed by law. 2No provision in this Constitution invalidates any law providing for offences of absolute or strict liability committed against or in connection with a child under 18 years of age. 3The provisions of this section of this Article do not, in any way, limit the powers of the Oireachtas to provide by law for other offences of absolute or strict liability. 44 APPENDIX 2 RECOMMENDATIONS OF THE CONSTITUTION REVIEW GROUP IN RESPECT OF THE FAMILY AND CHILDREN 1 All family rights, including those of unmarried mothers or fathers and children born of unmarried parents, should now be placed in Article 41. 2 Delete existing Articles 41.1.1°, 41.1.2°, 41.2.1°, 41.2.2° and 41.3.1°. 3 The description of any rights or duties specified in Articles 41 or 42 should not include adjectives such as ‘inalienable’ or ‘imprescriptible’. 4 A revised Article 41 should include the following elements: i) recognition by the State of the family as the primary and fundamental unit of society ii) a right for all persons to marry in accordance with the requirements of law and to found a family iii) a pledge by the State to guard with special care the institution of marriage and protect it against attack subject to a proviso that this section should not prevent the Oireachtas from legislating for the benefit of families not based on marriage or for the individual members thereof iv) a pledge by the State to protect the family based on marriage in its constitution and authority v) a guarantee to all individuals of respect for their family life whether based on marriage or not vi) an express guarantee of certain rights of the child, which fall to be interpreted by the courts from the concept of ‘family life’, which might include: a) the right of every child to be registered immediately after birth and to have from birth a name 45 b) the right of every child, as far as practicable, to know his or her parents, subject to the proviso that such right should be subject to regulation by law in the interests of the child c) the right of every child, as far as practicable, to be cared for by his or her parents d) the right to be reared with due regard to his or her welfare vii) an express requirement that in all actions concerning children, whether by legislative, judicial or administrative authorities, the best interests of the child shall be the paramount consideration viii) a revised Article 41.2 in gender neutral form which might provide The State recognises that home and family life give society a support without which the common good cannot be achieved. The State shall endeavour to support persons caring for others within the home ix) an amended form of Article 42.5 expressly permitting State intervention either where parents have failed in their duty or where the interests of the child require such intervention and a re-statement of the State’s duty following such intervention x) an express statement of the circumstances in which the State may interfere with or restrict the exercise of family rights guaranteed by the Constitution loosely modelled on Article 8(2) of ECHR xi) retention of the existing provisions in Article 41.3.3° relating to recognition for foreign divorces. 46 APPENDIX 3 SECTION 28 OF THE SOUTH AFRICAN CONSTITUTION (1) Every child has the right: (a) to a name and a nationality from birth; (b) to family care or parental care, or to appropriate alternative care when removed from the family environment; (c) to basic nutrition, shelter, basic health care services and social services; (d) to be protected from maltreatment, neglect, abuse or degradation; (e) to be protected from exploitative labour practices; (f) not to be required or permitted to perform work or provide services that – (i) are inappropriate for a person of that child’s age; or (ii) place at risk the child’s well-being, education, physical or mental health or spiritual, moral or social development; (g) not to be detained except as a measure of last resort, in which case, in addition to the rights a child enjoys under sections 12 and 35, the child may be detained only for the shortest appropriate period of time, and has the right to be – (i) kept separately from detained persons over the age of 18 years; and (ii) treated in a manner, and kept in conditions, that take account of the child’s age; (h) to have a legal practitioner assigned to the child by the state, and at state expense, in civil proceedings affecting the child, if substantial injustice would otherwise result, and; (i) not to be used directly in armed conflict and to be protected in times of armed conflict. (2) A child’s best interests are of paramount importance in every matter concerning the child. (3) In this section, ‘child’ means a person under the age of 18 years. 47 Section 37 further provides that section 28(1)(d), section 28(1)(e), section 28(1)(g)(i) and (ii) are non-derogable, and that section 28(1)(i) is non-derogable in cases involving children who are 15 and younger. 48