Page 511 45 Marx against Morality Allen Wood i Introduction Marxists often express a contemptuous attitude toward morality, which (they say) is nothing but a form of illusion, false consciousness or ideology. But others (whether they consider themselves Marxists or not) often find this attitude hard to understand. The Marxists condemn capitalism for exploiting the working class and condemning most people to lives of alienation and unfilfilment. What reasons can they give for doing so, and how can they expect others to do so as well, if they abandon all appeals to morality? The Marxist rejection of morality, however, begins with Marx himself. And it is, I will contend, a defensible view, a natural consequence, as Marx says it is, of the materialist conception of history. Even if we do not accept Marx's other views, his attack on morality raises significant issues concerning the way we should think about morality. ii Marx's Anti-Moralism 1478 Marx is habitually silent about the sorts of issues which interest moralists and moral philosophers. But from what he does say, it is clear that this silence is not due to benign neglect. His attitude is rather one of open hostility to moral theorizing, moral values, even to morality itself. Against Pierre Proudhon, Karl Heinzen and the German 'true socialists', Marx regularly employs 'morality' and 'moralizing criticism' as epithets of abuse. He bitterly condemns the Gotha Programme's demand for 'just wages' and 'just distribution', asserting that such phrases 'confound the realistic outlook' of the working class with 'outdated verbiage' and 'ideological trash' which his scientific approach has rendered obsolete (MEW 19: 22, SW 325). When others do prevail upon Marx to include bland moral rhetoric in the Rules for the First International, he feels he must apologize to Engels for it: 'I was obliged to insert two phrases about ''duty" and "right" . . . ditto about "truth, morality and justice", but these are placed in such a way that they can do no harm' (CW 42, p. 18). Marx regularly describes morality, along with religion and law, as forms of ideology, 'so many bourgeois prejudices behind which lurk just as many bourgeois interests' (MEW 4, p. 472; CW 6, p. 49495; cf. MEW 3, p. 26; CW 5, p. 36). But he does not condemn only bourgeois ideas about morality. His target is morality itself, all morality. The German Ideology claims that the materialist con- 1479 Page 512 ception of history, by exhibiting the connection between moral ideology and material class interests, has 'broken the staff of all morality', irrespective of its content or class affiliation (MEW 3, p. 404; CW 5, p. 419). When an imaginary critic charges that 'communism does away with all morality and religion instead of forming them anew', the Communist Manifesto replies not by denying that this charge is true, but instead by observing that just as the communist revolution will involve a radical break with all traditional property relations, so it will also involve the most radical break with all traditional ideas (MEW 4, p. 48081; CW 6, p. 504). Evidently it is Marx's view that just as doing away with bourgeois property will be one task of the communist revolution, so 'doing away with all morality' will be another. Marx even goes so far as to side with moral evil against moral good. He insists that in history 'it is always the bad side which finally triumphs over the good side. For the bad side is the one which brings movement to life, which makes history by bringing the struggle to fruition' (MEW 4, p. 140; CW 6, p. 174). Some, such as Karl Kautsky, have interpreted such remarks as pleas for the 'value freedom' of Marxian social science. But that reading is both implausible and anachronistic. It is not at all what the passages themselves say. And the idea that science should be 'value-free' was largely a neo1480 Kantian invention; Marx wrote at a time, and in a tradition, which was both unfamiliar with and unsympathetic to it. No reader of Marx could possibly deny that he makes 'value judgements' about capitalism, and Marx never attempts fastidiously to segregate his scientific analysis of capitalism from his angry condemnation of it. When Marx accuses capitalism of stunting human potentialities, stifling their development and preventing their actualization, he avails himself unashamedly of judgements about people's needs and interests, and even of a (recognizably Aristotelian) naturalistic framework of ideas concerning the nature of human well-being and fulfilment. Judgements about what is good for people, what is in their interests, certainly are 'value judgements', but they are not necessarily moral judgements, since even if I care nothing about morality at all, I may still be interested in promoting the interests and well-being of myself and others whose welfare I happen to care about. It would be entirely consistent for Marx to reject morality and nevertheless advocate the abolition of capitalism on the ground that it frustrates human well-being, so long as his concern with human well-being is not based on any moral values or principles. Marx's attack on morality is not an attack on 'value judgements', but it is a rejection of specifically moral judgements, especially those involving the ideas of right and justice. 1481 iii Historical Materialism It is the materialist conception of history which Marx credits with 'breaking the staff of all morality'. Historical materialism treats history as divided into epochs, each characterized fundamentally by its mode of production. A mode of production consists of a set of social relations of production, a system of economic roles assigning effective control over the means, processes and fruits of social production to the 1482 Page 513 occupants of some roles and excluding the occupants of other roles. These differences between roles are the basis of class differences in society. On the materialist theory, social change comes about because society's powers of production are not static but change, and on the whole tend to grow. At any stage of their development, the employment of the powers of production and their further growth are facilitated more by some social relations than by others. No one set of production relations has a permanent advantage over all others in this regard; instead, at different stages of the development of productive powers, different sets of social relations are better suited to promote productive development. Eventually, any given set of production relations becomes obsolete; they become dysfunctional in relation to the employment of the productive powers, and they 'fetter' their further development. A social revolution consists in a transformation of the social relations of production which is required by and for the growth of the powers of production (MEW 13, p. 9; SW, p. 183). The mechanism by which social relations are adjusted so as to promote the development of productive powers is the class struggle. The social relations of production divide societies into groups, determined by their roles in production and their degree and type of control over the 1483 material instruments of production. These groups are not themselves classes, but they become classes as soon as there exists a political movement and an ideology representing their class interests. The interests of a class are based on the common situation of the class's members, and especially on its hostile relation to other classes. Generally speaking, members of those classes which control the conditions of production have an interest in retaining their dominance, and those over whom this control is exercised have an interest in wresting it away from those who have it. These individual interests, however, are not directly class interests. Since classes are not just categories of individuals but social and political organizations or movements bound together by ideologies, the interests of a class are always something distinct from the interests of the class's individual members. In fact, Marx identifies the interests of a class with the political interests of the movement which represents the class (MEW 4, p. 181; CW 6, p. 211). Ultimately, the interests of a class consist in the establishment and defence of the set of relations of production which assign control of production to the members of that class. But it does not follow from this that class interests are simply the self-interest of the class's members, or that class interests are pursued in the form of egoistic interests. For in a war between classes, as in a war between nations, victory is sometimes possible only through the sacrifice of individual interests. The individuals 1484 who are called upon to make such sacrifices see themselves as fighting for something greater and worthier than their self-interest; and in this they are right, for they are fighting for the interests of their class. iv Ideology This greater and worthier thing, however, is seldom presented to them as the 1485 Page 514 interest of a social class. Instead, a class shapes from its material conditions of life 'a whole superstructure of different and characteristic feelings, illusions, ways of thinking and views of life' (MEW 8, p. 139; CW 11, p. 128) which serve its members as the conscious motives of the deeds they do in its behalf. When these feelings, thoughts and views are the products of a special class of mental labourers working in the class's employ, Marx has a special name for them: ideology. The products of ideologists of priests, poets, philosophers, professors and pedagogues are, on the materialist theory, typically ideological. That is, the content of these products can best be accounted for by the way in which it represents the worldviews of particular social classes at a particular time and serves the class interests of these classes. In a well-known letter to Franz Mehring, Friedrich Engels describes ideology as 'a process carried out by the so-called thinker with consciousness, but with a false consciousness. The real driving forces that move him remain unknown to him; otherwise it would not be an ideological process. Thus he imagines to himself false or apparent driving forces' (MEW 39, p. 97; SC p. 459). According to this, the chief illusion in any ideology is an illusion about its own class basis. This is not ignorance, error or deception about the individual psychology of one's actions. When ideologists 1486 think they are being motivated by religious or moral enthusiasm, very often they really are Engels does not mean to claim that they are necessarily victims of the sort of self-deception which occurs when I act self-interestedly but deceive myself into thinking I am acting from moral duty or philanthropic love. But the question is: what does it really mean to act on moral, religious or philosophical grounds? What is the relation of such actions to the social life of which they are a part? When we act from such grounds, what are we really doing? When they are motivated by ideologies, people do not understand themselves as representatives of a class movement; but they are just the same. They do not think of class interests as the fundamental explanation of the fact that these ideas appeal to them and to others; but that is the correct explanation nevertheless. They do not act with the intention of promoting the interests of one social class as opposed to others; but they go right on doing so, and sometimes all the more effectively just because they truly have no such intention. For if they truly knew what they were doing, they might not continue to do it. v Ideology as Unfreedom The Marxist attitude toward ideological false consciousness reflects the fact that it is taken to be a form of unfreedom. On the most obvious and superficial level (where, in the 1487 English-speaking liberal tradition, issues about freedom usually remain) freedom is taken away from us when we are frustrated in the pursuit of our goals by external obstacles, such as prison bars and threats of violent harm. Going a little deeper, we may also recognize internal obstacles (such as compulsive desires and incapacities) as destructive of freedom. If we go deeper still, we may 1488 Page 515 see that ignorance can be unfreedom, when our intentions are formed without accurate knowledge of the way our actions affect the outcomes we care about, or without correct ideas about the range of alternatives open to us. The threat to freedom posed by ideology is something like this, yet not quite the same, since it is quite possible for victims of ideology to be fully informed as regards the things they care about. The problem is that the full significance of our actions may extend beyond what we care about, even beyond what we are capable of caring about, because it extends beyond what we understand about ourselves and our actions. I act from religious motives, for example, but I promote the interests of a certain class without realizing that I am doing so. When this happens I am unfree in what I do because the meaning of my actions eludes my free agency; because it is not I as a thinking and self-knowing being who does it. This is not the unfreedom of being unable to do what I intend; in fact, one could describe it as the unfreedom of being unable to intend what I do. I am fully free in this respect only if my actions have what we may call 'self-transparency': I know these actions for what they are and I do them intentionally in light of this knowledge. When a certain system of ideas is socially available to me because of the class interests it serves and my actions are motivated by it, then I can be fully free in 1489 performing those actions only if I understand the role which class interests play in my actions and choose those actions in light of that understanding. But if the system of ideas itself inhibits such an understanding by disguising or falsifying the role played by class interests in its own genesis and effect, then it destroys self-transparency of action of those who act on it; it undermines their freedom. Self-transparency of action is not merely a theoretical value. For knowledge is subversive: if we clearly understood the social basis and significance of what we do, we would not go on doing it. Humanity may be unacquainted as yet with any social way of life which could be led self-transparently by its human participants. If Marx is right, then all societies based on class oppression and that means every social order which history records, including our own depend for their stability on the fact that their members are systematically deprived of the freedom of social self-transparency. The oppressed can be kept in their place only if their ideas about that place are suitably mystified; and the system might be threatened even if the oppressors acquired excessively accurate ideas about the relations which benefit them at others' expense. Revolutionary classes can more effectively enlist the support of other classes, and even that of their own members, if they present their class interests in a glorified form. Ideology is not a marginal phenomenon, but essential to all social life as it has existed up to now. 1490 vi Morality as Ideology In the light of this, it should not be surprising that Marx regards morality, along with law, religion and other forms of social consciousness, as fundamentally 1491 Page 516 ideological. Morality is a system of ideas which both interprets and regulates people's behaviour in ways which are vital for the workings of any social order. It also has the potentiality for motivating them to make large-scale social changes. If the history of past societies is fundamentally a history of class oppression and class struggle, then it is only to be expected that the prevalent systems of moral ideas would take the form of ideologies through which class warfare is being simultaneously waged and disguised. In this way, Marx thinks that historical materialism has 'broken the staff of all morality' by revealing its foundation in class interests. Perhaps we are not surprised to find Marx attacking morality in this way, but we may think his position exaggerated and needlessly paradoxical, even if we grant him for the sake of argument that historical materialism is true. Some moral precepts (such as minimal respect for the lives and interests of others) seem to have no conceivable class bias, but apparently belong to any conceivable moral code, since without them no society at all would be possible. How can Marx want to discredit these precepts, or think that historical materialism has discredited them? Further, if all class movements need morality, then apparently the working class will need it too. How can Marx want to deprive the proletariat of an important 1492 weapon in the class struggle? To reject morality, however, is not necessarily to reject all the behaviour morality enjoins and advocate the behaviour it prohibits. There may be some patterns of behaviour common to all moral ideologies, and we might expect moral ideologies to emphasize them, since it helps to disguise the class character of the ideology's more characteristic features. If people must do and refrain from certain things in order to have a decent social life, then Marx would certainly want those doings and refrainings to continue in the communist society of the future. But Marx would not want them to be done because some moral code enjoins them, since moral codes are class ideologies, which undermine the self-transparency of the people who act on them. Perhaps the fear is that without moral motives, nothing will prevent us from falling into the uttermost barbarism. Marx does not share this fear, a first cousin of the superstitious fear that if there is no God, then all is permitted. The task of human emancipation is to build a human society on rational self-transparency, free from the mystification of morality and other ideologies. Marx knows that at present we have no clear conception of what such a society would be like, but he believes that humanity is equal to the task of bringing one into being. Marx has powerful reasons for refusing to exempt working1493 class moral ideologies from these strictures. The historic mission of the working-class movement is human emancipation; but every ideology, including working-class ideologies, undermines freedom by destroying selftransparency of action. Marx rails against moralizing within the movement because he regards the 'realistic outlook' brought to it by historical materialism as indispensable for its revolutionary task (MEW 19, p. 22; SW, p. 325). 1494 Page 517 vii Justice Marx supplements his attack on working class moralizing with an account of the justice of economic transactions. The justice of transactions which go on between agents of production rests on the fact that these transactions arise out of the production relations as their natural consequence. [The content of a transaction] is just whenever it corresponds to the mode of production, is adequate to it. It is unjust whenever it contradicts it. (MEW 25, p. 3512; C 3, p. 33940). A transaction is just whenever it is functional within the existing mode of production, unjust whenever it is dysfunctional. From this it follows directly that the exploitative transactions between capitalist and worker, and the system of capitalist distribution resulting from them, are perfectly just and violate no-one's rights (MEW 19, p. 18; SW, p. 3212; MEW 19, pp. 359, 382; MEW 23, p. 208; C 1, p. 194). But equally, once we see that this is what it means for capitalist exchanges and distribution to be just, we will no longer take the fact that they are just as any sort of defence of them. As Marx tells us, his conception of justice rests on the way in which moral norms arise out of relations of production. It is not an account of justice which either a defender of the system or a moral critic of it would give, and it is not 1495 intended to be a conception of justice which captures the way in which social agents think about the justice of the transactions they regard as just. But it is an account which intends to identify what in fact regulates their usage of terms like 'just' and 'unjust', and in this way it anticipates certain features of some contemporary philosophical theories of reference. According to these theories, people's use of a term like 'water' refers to H2O if people's use of this term is regulated by the fact that the substance they refer to is H2O, even if they would not accept this as an account of what they mean by 'water' (because, for instance, they have no concept of H2O, or because they have superstitious folk-beliefs about the nature of water). Analogously, Marx holds that people's use of terms like 'justice' and 'injustice' of economic transactions is regulated by the functionality of these transactions for the prevailing mode of production, and hence that these are the properties of the transactions to which such terms refer even though understanding justice and injustice in this way has the effect of depriving these terms of the persuasive force they are usually taken to have. In Marx's view, it is only moral ideology which makes us regard moral properties such as justice as inherently or necessarily desirable. (Once we come to understand what justice really is, we will acquire a more sober view about how desirable it is.) viii Morality and Rationality 1496 There are some conceptions which are essentially selfdefining, through an activity which is associated with them. Scientific rationality, for example, is not limited to 1497 Page 518 what people have called 'science' in the past, because the activity of science consists in criticizing itself, rejecting its present content and giving itself a new one. What has in the past been considered 'rational' behaviour, even the very criteria of rationality, may be subjected to self-criticism and now treated as less than rational. In modern culture, there has been a strong tendency simply to identify morality with practical reason, and consequently to regard moral reasoning too as a self-critical and self-determining notion. On this view, all errors in moral thinking are errors in the content of particular moral beliefs; 'morality itself always (perhaps even 'by definition') transcends all moral errors, at least in principle. Marx's view of morality involves the denial that morality can be regarded in any such way. If there is a kind of practical thinking which is self-correcting in this manner, morality is not it. The reason is that morality, moral concepts and principles, moral thoughts and feelings, have already been appropriated to quite a different sort of task with quite a different method of operation. Along with religion and law, the essential tasks of morality are social integration and class advocacy, its essential method is ideological mystification and self-disguise. A morality which understood its own social basis would be as impossible as a religion which founded itself on the clear 1498 perception that every belief in the supernatural is a superstition. ix The Illusion of Impartial Benevolence We can see why this is so if we attend to one fundamental feature of morality as such. It is characteristic of moral thinking to present itself as founded on such things as the will of a universally benevolent God, or a categorical imperative legislated by pure reason, or a general happiness principle. Whatever the theory, morality is depicted as the standpoint of impartial or disinterested well-wishing, which takes account of all relevant interests and gives preference to some over others only when there are good (impartially based) reasons for doing so. It is this feature of morality which renders it fundamentally ideological. No doubt people can think they are behaving in such a manner, and a particular action may even actually be impartially benevolent as regards the immediate interests of the small number of people whom it immediately affects. As long as we think only of our particular actions and their immediate consequences, as morality encourages us to do, there is no general problem about achieving the impartiality it demands. But morality also encourages us to think of our actions as conforming to a moral code which is valid for others as well as for ourselves. When we do this, we implicitly represent our actions as conforming 1499 systematically to principles of impartial benevolence which we imagine as possibly effective on a large scale. It is at this point that the illusory character of moral impartiality becomes evident. For in a society based on class oppression and torn by class conflict, there can be no socially significant and effective form of action which has this character of impartial benevolence. Actions which are commended as 'just' 1500 Page 519 (because they correspond to the prevailing mode of production) systematically promote the interests of the ruling class at the expense of the oppressed. Actions taken to overthrow the existing order, which may be commended by some revolutionary moral code, advance the interests of the revolutionary class at the expense of other classes. According to Marx, the most pervasive characteristic of ideology is its tendency to represent the standpoint of one class as a universal standpoint, the interests of that class as universal interests (MEW 3, p. 4649; CW 5. p. 5962; MEW 4, p. 477; CW 6, p. 501). This is precisely what moral ideologies do: they represent actions which benefit the interests of one class as disinterestedly good, as actions in the common interest, promoting the rights and well-being of humanity in general. But it would be an illusion to think that this deception could be remedied by some new moral code which succeeds in doing what these class ideologies only pretend to do. For in a society based on class oppression and torn by class conflict, impartiality is an illusion. There are no universal interests, no cause of humanity in general, no place to stand above or outside the fray. Your actions may be subjectively motivated by impartial benevolence, but their objective social effect is never impartial. The only actions which do not take sides in a class war are actions which are either impotent or 1501 irrelevant. All this is just as true of the working class as of any other. Marx thinks the working-class movement is in the interests of 'the vast majority' (MEW 4: 472; CW 6: 495); but working-class interests are the interests of one particular class, not the interests of humanity in general. Marx does believe that the working-class movement will eventually abolish class society itself, and thereby achieve universal human emancipation. But its first step toward this must be to emancipate itself from the ideological illusions of class society. And that means that it must pursue its class interest in its own emancipation consciously as its class interests, undistorted by ideological illusions which would portray its interest in a glorified, moralized form for instance, as already identical with universal human interests. Marx thinks that it is only by becoming clearsighted about itself in this way that the revolutionary proletariat can hope to create a society which is free both from ideological illusions and from the class divisions which create the need for them. x Can Marx do without morality? Marx was a radical thinker, and his attack on morality is clearly one of his most radical ideas. The Marxian idea of a revolutionary social movement and even a radically new social order which would abolish all morality was intended 1502 to shock, frighten and challenge its audience, to test the limits even of what it could conceive. Perhaps it is understandable that many who are sympathetic to Marx's critique of capitalism should find this idea useless, barely intelligible, embarrassing, and that they should think the only viable or sympathetic interpretation of Marx is one which reads it entirely out of his texts. Marxist antimoralism combines badly with the widespread notion that the monstrous atrocities which have disillusioned 1503 Page 520 our century (and for which self-proclaimed Marxists have borne no light burden of responsibility) have been due fundamentally to calamitous moral failures on the part of politicians, parties and peoples. The notion itself may be highly dubious typical of the sad human tendency to react first with moral blame toward whatever we hate and fear but do not understand. But to those for whom it is second nature, a Marx who attacks morality is easily groomed as someone whose thought leads straight to the purge, the gulag and the killing fields. But this way of thinking rests on some erroneous assumptions, and some invalid reasoning. To reject morality is not necessarily to approve of everything morality would condemn, nor is it even to deprive oneself of the best reasons for disapproving of it. We may reject morality and nevertheless have a rational, humane outlook as Marx did. Morality is not the only possible remedy for the abuses which Marxism has suffered, nor is it even, I venture to say, a very good remedy. Fanatics continue to prove every day that even the purest moral intentions cannot prevent us from committing the most monstrous crimes unless we successfully employ our intelligence along with our moral fervour. Thus a better remedy might be simply to address the human intellect seriously to deciding whether our means will in fact achieve our ends, 1504 and whether our ends truly answer to our considered desires. But the fear will be that without morality we have no way of trusting our desires. Why should we bother to overthrow capitalist oppression, or avoid the nightmares of totalitarianism, if, on reflection, we don't happen to want to? What if our own self-interest happens to lie on the side of the oppressors? What, if not morality, could provide the necessary counterpoise? But it is a basic tenet of historical materialism that the human motivation which is most powerful in human affairs, and explains the fundamental dynamics of social change, falls neither into the category of self-interest nor that of morality. Marx regards self-interest as an important human motive, but he thinks the selfinterest of individuals as such is too varied in its effects to effect any world historical transformation. On the other hand, a high-minded concern for the universal interest or for justice in the abstract is going to achieve results only if it serves as the illusory pretext for the promotion of definite class interests. It is these class interests themselves which are the real driving forces of history. Class interests are far from impartial they do not aim at the general welfare or impartial justice, but at the achievement and defence of a certain set of production relations, those which signify the emancipation and dominance of a certain social class under given historical conditions. It is solely to the class interests 1505 of the revolutionary proletariat that Marx means to appeal in advocating the overthrow of capitalism and the establishment of a more emancipated and more human society. Marx does think that proletarian class interests will appeal to some who are not themselves proletarians but who have risen to a theoretical comprehension of the historical process (MEW 4, p. 472; CW 6, p. 494). This appeal arises from an informed identification with a concrete historical movement, not from crude self-interest, and even less from any impartial commitment to moral principles 1506 Page 521 and aims which the movement is thought to serve. Those who join the proletarian cause with the latter attitude have not risen to a theoretical comprehension of the historical movement; they have simply been caught in the snares of moral ideology. It is evidently from Hegel that Marx derives the idea that abstract (Kantian) morality is impotent, and that the motives which are historically effective always harmonize individual interests with those of a larger social order, movement or cause. (Similar neo-Aristotelian or neoHegelian ideas have recently been defended by Alasdair MacIntyre and Bernard Williams, among others.) But Hegel (like these more recent philosophers) attacks 'morality' only in a narrow sense, while trying to save it in a larger one. He locates the harmony of individual interests and social action in 'ethical life', which remains something distinctively moral by the fact that its ultimate appeal to us is supposed to be the appeal of impartial reason. The system of ethical life is a system of right, duty and justice, which actualizes the universal good; it even includes 'morality' (in the narrower sense) as one of its moments. Marxian class interests, however, are not 'moral' even in an extended sense. They are the interests of one class which stands in a hostile relation to other classes, and they can be advanced only at the expense of the interests of their class 1507 enemies. All this holds, moreover, as much for proletarian interests as for those of any other class. To represent working-class interests as universal interests or as something impartially good (as happens when they are treated as a morality) is for Marx a paradigm of ideological falsification and an act of betrayal against the workingclass movement (MEW 19: 25, SW 325). xi Has morality any future? There is one passage in Anti-Dühring in which Engels contrasts the ideological moralities of class society with an 'actual human morality of the future' (MEW 20, p. 88; AD, p. 132). This passage conflicts with the anti-moralism characteristic of Marx (and of Engels too, in many other passages). But we ought to be clear about just where the conflict lies, and how profound it really is. There is a direct conflict between the claim that there will be morality in future communist society and the Communist Manifesto's assertion that the communist revolution will 'do away with all morality instead of founding it anew'. But perhaps the conflict does not go very deep after all. Morality thinks its principles are impartial and universally human, and that following them will give your actions a justification which transcends the conflicting interests of particular individuals and groups. The Marxian view is that this cannot be done as long as class society exists, and that the fundamental 1508 ideological deception of morality is the way it passes off particular class interests as universal interests. But Marx and Engels think that after class society has been abolished, it will be possible for individuals to relate to each other simply as human beings, whose interests may diverge at the margins but are fundamentally identified through their common participation in a fully human social order. It is the classless society, therefore, which will actually 1509 Page 522 accomplish what morality deceptively pretends to do. And on this ground, it may be understandable that Engels should speak of the 'actual human morality' of future society, even though this involves a revision in the more characteristic (and clarifying) Marxian concept of morality as essentially the false pretence to universality found in class ideologies. The point not to overlook, however, is that Engels regards this 'actual human morality' as something future, not something available to us now, while we are still the prisoners of class society and its inevitable conflicts. Engels is emphatic in denying that there are any 'eternal truths' about morality. He plainly thinks that the principles of an 'actual human morality' belonging as they do to a future social order are as unknowable by us as the scientific truths which will belong to some future theory which lies on the far side of the next major scientific revolution. Nothing in Engels's remarks gives any comfort to those who would use moral standards to criticize capitalism or guide the working-class movement. xii Conclusion Marx's anti-moralism is not an easy idea to accept. It is not clear how we could think of ourselves and our relations with others entirely in non-moral terms. If all morality is an illusion, then a clear-sighted person must be able to go 1510 through life entirely without moral beliefs, moral emotions, moral reactions. But is it possible for anyone to do this? Yet Marx's anti-moralism is far from being his only shockingly radical proposal for humanity's future. After all, communism as Marx conceives it would abolish not only all morality, but also all religion, law, money and commodity exchange, along with the family, private property, and the state. Marx's anti-moralism actually appeals to some of us as it surely must have appealed to Marx himself precisely because it is such a radical, dangerous and paradoxical idea especially since, as I have been trying to argue, it is at the same time a disturbingly well-motivated idea in the context of Marx's materialist conception of history. Yet even if we are not persuaded by historical materialism, Marx's critique of morality raises some troubling questions for us. Do we pretend that we understand the real social and historical significance of the moral standards we employ? Can we be sure that we would still accept those standards if we did understand their significance? In the absence of such understanding, how can we suppose that a devotion to moral ends and principles, which we so closely associate with our sense of self-worth, is compatible with the autonomy and dignity which we want to ascribe to ourselves as rational agents? And what sort of life, individual or collective, might there be without morality? What does it look like, that territory which lies (in 1511 Nietzsche's uncanny phrase) beyond good and evil? Modern moral thought sees itself as essentially critical and reflective, not merely preaching traditional morality but questioning received moral ideas and seeking out new ways of thinking about both our individual lives and our collective life. Marx belongs to a radical tradition of modern thought about morality a tradition which also includes Hegel, Nietzsche and Freud thinkers who have 1512 Page 523 made us painfully aware of the ways in which the moral life involves us inevitably in irrationality, self-opacity and selfalienation. What this tradition suggests is the enigmatic and abysmal possibility that it may not be feasible for modern moral reflection to go all the way with its critical thinking without undermining the moral character of that thinking. To paraphrase Marx (MEW 1, p. 387; CW 3, p. 184): what may turn out to be Utopian is a merely reformist thinking about morality, which hopes to make repairs in the structure of our moral convictions but still to leave the pillars of the house standing. References Writings of Marx and Engels are cited in both the German and a standard English translation. All translations presented here, however, are my own. I use the following system of abbreviations: MEWMarx Engels Werke (Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 196166), cited by volume and page number. CW Marx Engels Collected Works (New York: International Publishers, 1975 ), cited by volume and page number. C Marx, Capital (New York: International Publishers, 1967), cited by volume and page number. SW Marx Engels Selected Works in one volume (New 1513 SC AD York: International Publishers, 1968), cited by page number. Marx Engels Selected Correspondence (New York: International Publishers, 1965), cited by page number. Engels, Anti-Dühring (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1962), cited by page number. Kautsky, K.: The Materialist Conception of History, trans. J. Kautsky (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1988). Further Reading Brenkert, G.: Marx's Ethics of Freedom (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984.) Buchanan, A.: Marx and Justice (Totawa, NJ: Rowan and Littlefield, 1982). Cohen, G. A.: Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defense (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978). Cohen, M., Nagel, T. and Scanlon, T., eds.: Marx, Justice and History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980). Elster, J.: Making Sense of Marx (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Geras, N.: Marx and Human Nature (London: New Left Books, 1983). Henry, M.: Marx: A Philosophy of Human Reality (Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press, 1982). 1514 Kamenka, E.: The Ethical Foundations of Marxism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1972). Lukes, S.: Marxism and Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984). 1515 Page 524 Miller, R.: Analyzing Marx: Morality, Power and History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984). Nielsen, K.: Marxism and the Moral Point of View (Boulder, Col.: Westview Press, 1989). Nielsen, K., and Patten, S., eds.: Marx and Morality (Guelph: Canadian Association for Publishing in Philosophy, 1981). Wood, A.: Karl Marx (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981). 1516