LAW: ITS BOUNDARIES AND FRONTIERS AND THE NIGERIAN SOCIETY BY MUHTAR ETUDAIYE DEFINITIONS A subject such as this one can hardly be discussed without recourse to definitions. Foremost is the question, what is society? For a working definition, we may define society, in the aftermath of the evolution from a hunting and gathering society to a sedentary one where roles and responsibilities were shared with authority in the hands of one man, as a group of people living together who have agreed implicitly and or explicitly to proceed in common under certain beliefs and customs etc. This is indeed buttressed by a string of political scientists. The International Ecyclopaedia of Social Sciences defines it as “a relatively independent or self-sufficient territory of cultural distinctiveness and sexual rescruitment”. Kathleen Heasman has defined society in its more concrete and specific way to refer to large sections of people who have some characteristic and in a restricted sense to mean the social contacts found in a group like the society found in a factory1. It is a self sufficient system of action which is capable of existing longer than the lifespan of an individual, the group being recruited at least in part by the sexual reproduction of the members. Inclusiveness and self-sufficiency are very important. What is undeniable is that society must be constituted by a group or what the sociologists call a human group. Sprott2 defines a group in the social psychological sense as “a plurality of persons who interact with one another in a given context more than they interact with anyone else”. He adds that, “A village may be said to form a group in this sense because there is more interaction between its inhabitants than there is between them and people living in the next village. A nation may be called a group because the members of the nation interact with one another more than they interact with the members of the nation across the frontier”3. Deutsch sees a group as existing “to the extent that the individuals comprising it are pursuing promotively interdependent goals”4. Law is a simple and uncomplicated concept until the pointed end of a stiletto pierces it open to reveal its schismatic factionalisation. Thus it is acknowledged that “the definition of ‘Law’ could be an exhaustive and very endless exercise”5. Law has simply, but in the realm of jurisprudence inadequately, been defined by Justice Aderemi as “order”. He adds: 1 In the Study of Society, 1976 Sprott, W.J.H., Human Groups, 1958, p. 9 3 Op. cit. 4 Deutsch, Morton, Group Dynamics, ed. Cartwright D. and Zander A.F., 1955, P. 330 5 Justice Aderemi, Pius Olayiwola: Law as a Factor for Political Stability in the Third Republic; Paper delivered during the Law Week Programme organized by the Nigerian Bar Association, Ilorin Branch on February 1, 1989. 2 It is a form of discipline. It is a combination of justice and fair-play. It is a phenomenon that is ever present in every aspect of human life. It is certain and ascertainable …”6 and it begins again to take the appearance of that “very endless exercise”. Order is an inappropriate definition for law. Rather and more appropriately, the purpose of law and the reason why it is necessary is to maintain order; to order the affairs of man in a way that one man’s right stops where the next man’s right starts. A learned author7 appears to join in this assessment: “The recognition that even in the simplest form of society some system of rules is necessary seems almost inevitable. In any society, whether primitive or complex, it will be necessary to have rules which lay down the conditions under which men and women may mate and live together; rules governing family relationships; conditions under which economic and foodgathering or hunting activities are to be organized; and the exclusion of acts which are regarded as inimical to the welfare of the family, or of larger groups such as the tribe or the whole community. Moreover, in a complex civilized community, even if simplified to the degree dear to the heart of an anarchist like Read, there will have still to be a large apparatus of rules governing family, social and economic life. The idea that human community on whatever level, could ever conceivably exist on the basis that each man should simply do whatever he thinks right in the particular circumstances is too fanciful to deserve serious consideration. Such a society would not be merely, as Read puts it, ‘a society without order’, but the very negation of society itself”8. Law may be defined as rules legislated by the government or other authority but indeed that would be a very narrow definition for it is acknowledged that courts indeed also have legislative roles in that sometimes they make law by the decisions they make which decisions may by the principle of judicial precedent be binding on other courts. On the other hand it would not be out of place to refer to the courts of law as “authority” which brings it within the purview of the above definition. But law may also flow from judicial writings which may be adopted by the courts and may thereby wear the toga of a precedent or they may derive from custom whose origins are not so apparent but which, as the legal field matures, may become embodied in statutes or may themselves become rules of law pronounced by judges and consequently become precedent. Law however may result in unsavoury consequences at least in some eyes. Thus, Mr. Bumble in Charles Dickens’s Oliver Twist blurted, on being informed that he was liable for his wife’s actions, that: 6 Op. cit. Lloyd, Dennis: The Idea of Law (1987); Penguin Books 8 Ibid. at p. 24 7 “If the law supposes that, the law is an ass – a idiot”. Some have ventured to add that “the law is a veritable ass”.9 That kind of sentiment formed the basis for the introduction of the principles of equity which sought to cushion the unfair impact of the strict application of the law to the letter. It would again be impossible to relate law to society without at first a consideration for the origins of law. The issue of the origins of law has provoked protracted arguments about the fountain of legal authority. But perhaps there is need to look at the logical origins of a society and from there pinpoint the origins of law. Sprott lends credence to this assessment of origins: “Of course, if you consider two people who belong to any culture – a system of standards accepted by the wide community of which they are members – meeting for the first time, it is perfectly true that they will be equipped already with expectations about each other. They will have learnt to deal with strangers, according to the rules of their larger group; that among other things is what manners are for. Their initial contact, if they have been adequately trained, will be smooth enough; they will not have to develop standards of their own for the purposes of superficial or temporary interchange. If, however, they go on meeting, and form a group of two, each will have to respect the ‘little ways’ of the other; they will have common interests, in the arts, in sport, in financial enterprises or in anything else. Gradually mutual customs peculiar to themselves will be accepted by each, and form a set of mutually harboured expectations which form the standards of their interacting, over and above what one would call the ‘common rules of politeness’. In addition, action in accordance with these standards will be regarded as ‘right’, and unexpected action, where an expectation is present, is something which has to be explained – it is somehow inappropriate and threatens the harmonious existence of the group”10. Soon according to him, without the members of the group noticing it: “… a set of customs becomes established which are regarded as ‘right’ within the context in which the group operates, and they are felt by each member as being in some sense outside himself. He does not think: ‘I must do so and so because of B’s expectation; he thinks, if he thinks about the matter at all: ‘I must do so and so because it is our way ofbehaving’; or, ‘because if I do not, I shall get black looks’. The group, if it 9 Segun, Mabel: Friends, Nigerians, Countrymen, Chapter 7, p. 29 (1977) Sprott, W.J.H., Human Groups, Penguin Books 1958, pp. 12-13 10 has been in being for a time, assumes a kind of independent existence in the minds of its members, and the rules are ascribed to it”11. Herodotus12 provided the fifth century Greek insight into political thought with the categorization of the acknowledged beauty of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy. There was a tendency for the monarchy to disintegrate into a tyranny. But democracy, because it propagates the equality of all men before the law is wont to become mob-rule. Thus a government by the best available men, in his estimation, is to be preferred. Whether government by these men will eventually and ultimately translate into rule by men who are headed by a man who utters words such as: “Well, when the President does it, that means it is not illegal”. – Richard Nixon remains a moot point to be mulled for eternity. Herodotus did not stop there. The undisputable best, in his estimation, had to be rule by the one best man. Whether that rule by the one best man will eventually and ultimately translate into rule by men who utter words such as: “They charge me with the commission of great crimes. Men of my stamp do not commit crimes”. – Napoleon no one will probably ever know. Aristotle believed that what was just by law did not always tantamount to what was just by nature. There was a concept of natural justice valid universally with the same force. These conclusions he drew from his observation of the Greek city states. The Greek city states such as Athens prided themselves in their adherence to natural justice. In other words every man be he a man of means or the wretched low down must receive his just due. In Euripides’s Phoenician Maidens appears this exhortation to honour: “Equality, which knitteth friends to friends, Cities to cities, allies unto allies. Man’s law of nature is equality”13. A lot was to be garnered from a glimpse at the Greek political institutions of the time. There was in place an assembly at which every Greek male of above the age of twenty was entitled to attend and magistrates were made answerable to it. 11 Ibid. at p. 13 Herodotus: History, Bk. III, 80-82 13 Ll. 536-542 (Way’s trans.) as reproduced by Sabine, G.H., A History of Political Theory, 3 rd. ed., Harrap 1961, p.26 12 The tenure of the magistrates was brief and reelection was outlawed giving a leeway to other citizens to aspire to the same heights. The magistrates tried both law and man and quashed the laws it held to be unconstitutional. There was trial by jury and the members of the jury were nominated from a body of six thousand elected each year. There was an intricate system of what, in modern parlance, is called checks and balances in place. Pericles drooled with pride on the glory of Athens in this famous funeral oration: “I would have you day by day fix your eyes upon the greatness of Athens until you become filled withlove of her; and when you are impressed by the spectacle of her glory, reflect that this empire has been acquired by men who knew their duty and had the courage to do it, who in the hour of conflict had the fear of dishonour always present to them, and who, if ever they failed in an enterprise, would not allow their virtues to be lost to theircountry, but freely gave their lives to her as the fairest offering which they could present at her feast”14. Tyranny was assailed: “No worse foe than the despot hath a state, Under whom, first, can be no common laws, But one rules, keeping in his private hands The law”15. Law, it appeared, was meaningless to a society without these ideals of patriotism. From whence did natural justice flow? Is it from the laws of a Supreme God and can the laws of this Supreme God be made subservient to the laws of man? In Greek settings of that time, the Sophocles’s Antigone is often cited. It is said that Antigone was charged with having breached the law by undertaking the burial rites of her brother. Her response: “Yea, for these laws were not ordained of Zeus, And she who sits enthroned with gods below, Justice, enacted not these human laws. Nor did I deem that thou, a mortal man, Could’st by a breath annul and override The immutable unwritten laws of Heaven. They were not born to-day nor yesterday; They die not; and none knoweth whence they sprang”16. 14 As recited by Sabine, G.H., ibid. at p. 12 Euripides, The Suppliants, II. 429-432 (Way’s trans.) as reproduced by Sabine (ibid.) at p.18 16 Ll. 450-457 (F. Storr’s trans.) as reproduced by Sabine (ibid.) at p. 29 15 Or is law merely conventional? Is justice merely the rule, rather than of right, of might in the eyes of nature? Some hold that indeed nature is representative of the master-servant relation as between the strong and the weak on earth. Callicles17 states that: “If there were a man who had sufficient force … he would trample underfoot all our formulas, and spells, and charms, and all our laws which are against nature”18. Legal justice in those circumstances would merely buffer the weak against the might of the strong. Cicero would later offer of a true law, right reason, diffused in all men, constant and everlasting. There was always a tendency to relate natural law to theology. The Calvinist, Johannes Althusius (1557-1638) relied on theology as a basis for his theory that there was a law binding on all peoples universally. His fellow Calvinist traveler, Grotius moved on from there insisting that there was such a thing as the natural law even if it were to be supposed that God does not exist or is not concerned with human affairs. Thomas Hobbes came along and defined a law of nature “lex naturalis” to be “a precept of general rule found out by reason, by which a man is forbidden to do that which is destructive of his life”. Grotius and Hobbes thus assumed the mantle of the leading lights of the natural law school. Plato, a student of Socrates, had immense distrust of democracy and this was only matched by his distrust of politicians whose ignorance and incompetence, in his view, were the peculiar bane of democracy. He was a student of his master’s philosophy that virtue is knowledge. The pilosopher, the scholar, the scientist the men of knowledge ought to possess and exercise decisive power in government on the basis singularly of their knowledge. Through that he propounds his theory of the enlightened despotism. Thus government had to be an art depending on exact and precise knowledge. Second, society is a mutual satisfaction of needs by persons whose capacities supplement each other. Sabine says that: “So firmly was Plato convinced of the pernicious effects of wealth upon government that he saw no way to abolish the evil except by abolishing wealth itself, so far as soldiers and rulers are concerned. To cure the greed of rulers there is no way short of denying them the right to call anything their own”19. 17 Gorgias 484a (Jowett’s trans.) as reproducd by Sabine (ibid.) at p. 31 19 Ibid. at p. 57 18 The 18th century French philosopher Jean Jacques Rousseau opined that for the law to qualify to be obeyed, some sort of social contract freely agreed by free citizens must exist. But John Austin the English jurist argued instead that laws are nothing more than a series of commands from the ruler, the sovereign to the ruled. Simultaneously, Friederich von Savigny was proposing in Germany that law was a thing that grew naturally out of a nation’s spirit, environment and history. Von Savigny referred to the volksgeist (the spirit of the people) and proposed that the nature of any particular system oflaw had to be a reflection of the spirit of the people who had evolved it. There was still another insight. The field of Legal Realism is itself realistic for the law is the law until defined by the judge. When once pronounced upon by the judge the law may at once wear a new toga. And from pronouncing upon the law the judge may indeed have pronounced the law. It is indisputable that judges make law and that the law is what the judges say it is. BARENBLATT V. UNITED STATES20 is one good example of judge made law. The First Amendment to the United Staetes Constitution provides in clear language that Congress shall pass no law abridging freedom of speech, press, assermbly or petition. Period. Barenblatt, a college professor was named by a witness before the Congressional Committee on Un-American Activities as having been a communist during his school days. He was summoned to testify but refused on the ground that the Committeeby so doing violated his First Amendment rights and that it was conducting a legislative trial. His contept conviction was upheld by the court of appeals. At the Supreme Court the minority held that the First Amendment could not be read by any stretch of imagination to say that “Congress shall pass no law abridging freedom of speech, press, assembly and petition, unless Congress and the Supreme Court reach the joint conclusion that on balance the interest of the Government in stifling these freedoms is greater than the interest of the people in having them exercised” as the majority had done but they were overridden by a majority that turned to its refusal “to blind itself to world affairs” and the conclusion that “the balance between the individual and the governmental interests here at stake must be struck in favour of the latter and that therefore the provisions of the First Amendment have not beenoffended”. Where necessary, judges have widened thedefinition of law beyond, some might say, its bounds. In one case21 a Supreme Court justice had his life threatened by a disappointed litigant named Terry and the Attorney General consequently assigned a United States marshal, Neagle, to protect him. When Terry appeared aboutr to assault him, Neagle shot and killed him and was then held on a charge of murder by State authorities. The Federal Government sought Neagle’s release on habeas corpus under a federal law that made the writ available to a person “in custody for an act done or omitted in pursuance of a law of the United States”. The snag was that Congress had enacted no law empowering the President or the Attorney General to assign marshals for the 20 21 360 U.S. 109 (1959) In Re Neagle 135 U.S. 1(1890) protection of justices. The United States Supreme Court while discharging Terry from custody held that: “In the view we take of the Constitution of the United States, any obligation fairly and properly inferable from that instrument, or any duty of the marshal to be derived from the general scope of his duties under the laws of the United States, is ‘a law’ within the meaning of this phrase”. This inevitably leads to the subject of “political questions” which is an exercise of law making functions by the courts and over which the courts especially in the United States have held for quite a while that they have no jurisdiction. It is said that the “political questions” doctrine was first applied in 184922 in a case in which the Rhodes Island government still operated under its 1663 charter. There was rebellion by a liberal faction and two competing governments co-existed, sometimes violently, for a while. When a private citizen brought an action for a trespass against an official of one of the governments the official contended that he was acting on the authority of the lawful government. Had the court reached a decision, it would have been compelled to go into which government was the legitimate one. It therefore declined to decide it being a political question. A learned jurist23 has conceptualized the doctrine: “Controversies which meet the test of justiciability are nevertheless occasionally refused adjudication by the Supreme Court on the ground that they involve ‘political questions.’ Like justiciability, the political questions doctrine is a manifestation of the general principle of judicial self-restraint. It is based in part on constitutional doubts about the scope of judicial power and in part on a prudent awareness of the practical limitations of courts and judges. The constitutional element in determining justiciability is the extent of judicial power under Article III; the constitutional element in determining the political questions doctrine is the separation of powers. Consideration is given, in other words, not only to the proper scope of the judicial power but also to the powers and duties assigned to the legislative and executive branches”24. But BAKER V. CARR25 has become the locus classicus on this principle and the judgment of Mr. Justice Brennan as the authoritative exposition of it. He there made the sound distinction that because a case comes within the description of “political cases” does not necessarily bring it within the political questions doctrine: “It is apparent that several formulations which vary slightly according to the settings in which the questions arise may describe a political question, 22 Luther V. Borden 7 How. 1 (1849) C. Herman Pritchett: The Federal System In Constitutional Law (1978); Prentice Hall 24 At p. 70 25 369 U.S. 186, 82 S. Ct. 691, 7 L. Ed. 2d 663 (1962) 23 althougheach has one or more elements which identifies it as essentially a function of the separation of powers. Prominent on the surface of any question held to involve a political question is found a textually demonstrable constitutional commitment of the issue to a coordinate political department; or a lack of judicially discoverable and manageable standards for resolving it; or the impossibility of deciding without an initial policy determination of a kind clearly for nonjudicial discretion; or theimpossibility of a court’s undertaking independent reslution without expressing lack of the respect due coordinate branches of government; or an unusual need for unquestioning adherence to a political decision already made; or the potentiality of embarrassment from multifarious pronouncements by various departments on one question. “Unless one of these formulations is inextricable from the case at bar, there should be no dismissal for nonjusticiability on the ground of a political question’s presence. The doctrine of which we treat is one of ‘political questions,’ not one of ‘political cases.’ The courts cannot reject as ‘no law suit’ a bona fide controversy as to whether some action denominated ‘political’ exceeds constitutional authority …” There will be further reason to consider the principle relating to political questions in the Nigerian context shortly. Thusly, natural law, positive law, leagal realism and the others each on its own, believing itself to exclusively define law, engages merely in fatuous scholarship. Fused together however and feeding off one another, they tend to better define law however inadequately for each bears one valid component that the other may have shunned. This deluge not only of laws but of its natural, social, scientific, psychological and philosophical concept utterly provoked Sandkuhler’s26 paradoxical view of law that swung law up and about like a yo-yo: “The situation in which we debate law is a paradox one. In modern times the enforcement of subjectivity and individual rights has given rise to a collision of interests and because of this has made necessary the juridification or regulation by law of the life relations of society which were previously regulated by conformity in morals and ethical practice. This paradox can be reduced to the following simple formula: The more freedom, the more law; the more law, the more state; the more state, the less freedom; and the less freedom, the greater the necessity of law”. THE POSITION OF LAW IN NIGERIA Juxtaposing these concepts of law with the jurisprudential status in Nigeria may well result in the diagnosis of anarchy in its classical sense. An eminent jurist and 26 Sandkuhler, Hans Jorg: Pluralism and The Universality of Rights Justice of the Supreme Court27 embarked on an analysis of the of the volksgeist doctrine of Von Savigny and raised real and substantial intellectual questions about the spirit of the Nigerian people and how they are reflected in the laws that govern it. He applied the clinical methodology of tracing the history of Nigeria’s legal development till the present. A brief summary of his findings traced this from the advent of the British merchants in 1861 and the creation of the colony of Lagos the following year, the introduction of Ordinance No. 3 of 1863 etc. There were however the customs of the people which however the merchants considered to be barbarous. These laws were permitted to exist “but only to the extent of their compatibility with imperial rule”28. Thus arose the phrase “repugnant to natural justice, equity and good conscience” which have embossed its statutes till the present. Honourable Justice Eso then asked, “Could the Jurisprudence then be regarded as emanating from the ‘GEIST’ of the ‘VOLKS’?29” When analysed, natural justice, a supposedly universal concept ingrained in the soul of each man begins to take the well-defined shape of merely a village, not to mention an individual and peculiar posture. The recent events in Anambra State of Nigeria where the Okija Shrine which has existed for quite a while has been popularly and unanimously reviled presents itself as an illustration. The dead bodies, the gory scenes corpses littering every inch of space and the bloodletting immediately assail the sensibilities of the universe that translate into a repugnance to natural justice, equity and good conscience. Assuming however as the Chief Priest says, that the people of the area have always relied on the efficacy of the shrine, that when two parties reach an agreement they come before the shrine to swear to their good faith at the pain of death in the event of fraud, that the shrine merely takes the life of the cheats (who, for added effect, had given prior consent by the very act of oath taking) but never the innocent party etc. Regardless of the thinking of right thinking people the world over, would these process amount to a system of justice that is repugnant to natural justice, equity and good conscience? If these assumptions were true, then to the man in that community, Okija Shrine would be a glittering example of natural justice and everything antithetical to repugnance to it. Thus those people would not hold those beliefs to be universal. That in itself raises a valid question – these principles of natural justice, equity and good conscience, are they merely English beliefs put forward by force and influence as universal beliefs in-built in each man? Similarly, the advocacy of legal realism or the expression of the will of the state by means of the instrumentality of the courts falls upon harsh grounds in Nigeria. In a situation of anarchy and multiplicity of laws where English law is often in 27 Justice Kayode Eso Hon. Justice Kayode Eso: Whither Nigerian Jurisprudence, Volksgeist; Paper delivered at the University of Ibadan, Faculty of Law 2nd Faculty Public Lecture on March 7, 1986, New Nigerian March 22, 1986, p. 12 29 Op. cit. 28 conflict with customary beliefs, are the judges not encouraged to make new law according, not to their knowledge of it, but to their perception which perception is in turn shaped by the circumstances of his birth, race, religion and nurture? Better still, are the judges, never mind their scholarship and erudition, not prone to errors arising from a lack of conviction in the laws they are supposedly duty bound to apply? Elsewhere in this study, the concept of political questions has been enunciated. The Nigerian courts have also applied the doctrine of political questions and the leader in this department is the decision in ONUOHA V. OKAFOR & ORS. delivered by the Supreme Court on October 14, 1983. There the court decided that the courts have no jurisdiction to direct any political party to sponsor any particular candidate for an election on the ground that it was a political question and that the answer to the question so raised must be in the negative for a positive or an affirmative answer will instantly project or propel the court into the area of jurisdiction to run and manage political parties and politicians. It asked, ”Can the court decide which of the two candidates can best represent the political interest of the Nigerian Peoples Party? And it answered, “In all honesty, the court will in so doing be deciding a political question which it is ill fitted to do. It is political decision for which in the light of the provisions of the 1979 Constitutuion and the Electoral Act 1982, the political party (whose sponsorship is desired) is empowered to make”. Indeed this decision was reached in spite of section 6(6)(b) of the 1979 Constitution30 which extend the judicial powers of the courts to “all matters between persons or between government or authority and to any person in Nigeria, and to all actions and proceedings relating thereto, for the determination of any question as to the civil rights and obligations of that person” and of Section 236(1) 31 which “Subject to the provisions of this Constitution and in addition to such other jurisdiction as may be conferred upon it by law the High Court of a State shall have unlimited jurisdiction to hear and determine any civil proceedings in which the existence or extent of a legal right, power, duty, liability, privilege, interest, obligation or claim is in issue…”. Persuasive as the apex court was in that judgment, it is submitted that the “political questions” doctrine was misapplied. The most obvious reason is that the “political questions” doctrine exists for grievances that arise out of the acts of a political department. A political party is an entity outside the scope of government. It is not a department of government much less a political department. Secondly, the principal guiding light is the advancement of the doctrine of separation of powers. If the doctrine of separated powers is not put in something of jeopardy, the political questions doctrine is inapplicable. A political party is neither an arm of government nor a department of government. How then does the decision of the court threaten the principle of separated powers? Thirdly, the issue may be raised much in the same way as a conventional 30 Retained in the 1999 Constitution Save for the new clause making the High Court’s jurisdiction subject to the exclusive urisdiction of the Federal High Court in revenue matters in section 251, this is largely retained as section 272(1) of the 1999 Constitution 31 custom, do the rules, regulations and guidelines not constitute convention by which all the members of the party ought to be legally bound? Fourthly, it clearly does not come within the formulations so explicitly made by Mr. Justice Brennan32. On a close examination there must be: (a) a textually demonstrable constitutional commitment of the issue to a coordinate political department. Little need arises for further consideration; (b) a lack of judicially discoverable and manageable standards for resolving it. The parties always lay down rules, regulations and guidelines for such elections popularly called primaries. There it is to be found who can validly canvass for votes, who can validly vote, by what majority the winning contestant may emerge etc. clearly there are judicially discoverable and manageable standards for resolving these disputes; (c) the impossibility of deciding without an initial policy determination of a kind clearly for nonjudicial discretion. This does not exist; (d) the impossibility of a court’s undertaking independent resolution without expressing lack of the respect due coordinate branches of government. A decision of the court in disputes of this kind do not run the risk of showing disrespect for the other branches in the tripartite system knowing as it is that the political party is indeed not a member of any of the coordinate branches. The Court in the Onuoha decision indeed, and rightly so, pointed out that by statute the choice of a candidate for a party was not reserved for the Electoral Commission; (e) an unusual need for unquestioning adherence to a political decision already made. The only argument offered by the Court that betrays a semblance of this requirement was in the dictum that “the answer to the question so raised must be in the negative for a positive or an affirmative answer will instantly project or propel the court into the area of jurisdiction to run and manage political parties and politicians”33. But on a closer scrutiny we must submit that there is no unusual need for unquestioning adherence disclosed in that dictum. The court constantly intervenes in corporate takeovers and disputes between contending directors and shareholders of corporations. It has never declined jurisdiction based on a fear that the court will instantly be propelled into the area of juridiction to run and manage corporations; (f) the potentiality of embarrassment from multifarious pronouncements by various departments on one question. Here again it is needless to stress that a political party is not a political department. There is no risk of multifarious pronouncements for the decision to be made is to be by the political party according to rules laid down by it and subject to the scrutiny of the courts in the event of the need arising. Pritchett adds regarding the “political questions’ docrine that: 32 33 Supra Supra “Where the authority to make a certain decision appears to have been assigned by the Constitution exclusively to the Congress or to the President, the courts will refuse to interfere, although the case may be otherwise justiciable. The conclusion that the Constitution assigns authority to solve a particular problem to the two political branches of government is usually supported by practical considerations. Either the matter is not one suitable for handling by the judicial methods of taking evidence and hearing legal arguments, or enforcement of a court order would require an undesirable degree of interference in the affairs of other government agencies or for other reasons be unusually difficult”. (Italics supplied to emphasise the scope of the “political questions” doctrine) Was Justice Olagunju, no mean jurist, judge of the High Court, justice of the Court of Appeal and to many, one who could have become the Justice William Douglas of the Supreme Court unaware of the Obioha decision when he ventured in 1989: “For a start, let me examine briefly the basis of the union between law and democracy. The three major attributes of democracy as described above form a composite scheme that requires for its operation an arbiter that can adjudicate on the rights created by the foundation that is prescribed for any democratic institution. Conflicts arising from either intra or inter activities of political parties call for adjudication. Objections to the policy of or a given measure taken by a political party by a member of or a section of that party is as much a justiciable issue as a controversy over who between two candidates of opposing parties wins an election in an inconclusive or disputed poll. Similarly, whether an election is free or not is a matter that calls for an investigation … “All these areas of disputation which cut across a broad spectrum of controversies affecting the activities of the citizenry come within the preserve of the judiciary with the assistance of the lawyers. They are the areas that endear the citizens to the law and the cross-roads where the partnership between the law and democracy is formed”34. (Italics supplied) Thus judges make law but the application of the “political questions” doctrine highlights how judges may fatally skew their law making functions. The Obioha decision has till date received but only faithful adherence from both the apex court itself and the lower courts. Invariably then, in misapplying judges may make new law. But that they make all law – that is a bridge too far to cross. 34 Justice S.A. Olagunju: Dilemma of Law in Partnership With Democracy, Paper delivered at the 1989 Law Week of the Nigerian Bar Association, Ilorin Branch on January 30, 1989 It is unclear what exactly propels judges to misapply principles of law in Nigeria. The quality of legal education has deteriorated. Thus judges may be qualified in terms of years at the bar but nothing else. Corruption? Everyone knows that there is corruption running right from admission into the law programme through the appointing process of judges to the determination of individual litigations and other disputes. Timid courts that, aware of their shortcomings, are scared to death of their appointors sometimes even when the appointor takes no notice of events. It is enough that that much is expected of them. An inevitable question must be addressed. And that is –to which kind of society is law beneficial? One such as Nigeria? That poser itself lends fuel to the various attitudes to law. In one sense, law is the dictate of reason. Thus law is only aptly law if it complies with “objective moral principles”35 that can be discovered by natural reason. Thus positive law is the antithesis of law if it does not appeal to those higher standards. Instantly, it begs to be said that Nigeria has taken exception to and exemption from this appeal to higher standards that may not now be located even by means of the most powerful radar systems. For instance when a public officer steals public funds or when a contractor bribes publicc officers to influence the award of a contract in hisfavour, natural reason is inundated with the proverb that it is the hoe available to us with which we cultivate the soil. Never mind Jeremy Bentham, Nigeria constitutes a dent on the natural law school of thought. For if reason has been taken over by the “Nigerian factor” and the nation has lost the balance between right and wrong, what manner of law will reason dictate? The positivists view law as the command of the sovereign paying all attention to the legality, rather than the justice, of a rule and the formal requirements which sets law apart from other rules of existence. There must be a command. It must be given by the ruler to the ruled. It must be enforceable by the threat of a sanction in the event of breach. The landmark case of LAKANMI & ANOR V. A-G (WESTERN STATE) & ORS.36 is an inevitable case in point. There, a Tribunal of Inquiry into the assets of public officers of the Western State ordered the Appellants not to dispose of or otherwise deal with any property standing in their names. The Decree specifically mentioned the names of the appellants and ousted the jurisdiction of the courts. The Nigerian Supreme Court held that in so far as the legislation was targeted at specific individuals and not the generality of the citizenry the Decree became, not legislation, but legislative judgments and therefore an exercise of judicial power infringing on the doctrine of separation of powers. The Court further held that as the Decree was ultra vires the Constitution, the jurisdiction of the court was not ousted. It is now needless to add that this decision was immediately overruled by the military authorities in promulgating the Federal Military Government 35 36 Fitzgerald, P.J.; Salmond on Jurisprudence; 12th ed., Sweet and Maxwell (1966); p. 16 (1971) 1 U.I.L.R. 201 (Supremacy and Enforcement of Powers) Decree No. 28 of 1970 which made it clear beyond any shadow of doubt that a decree is the supreme law over and above the Constitution. After LAKANMI37 and the brutal castration of its precedent, the courts turned largely to understanding decrees to be the commands emanating from a sovereign. Nowadays, it is of utmost common knowledge that bribes and other incentives are paid to legislators by various interest groups but particularly the executive to pass laws. Of course this does not detract from the positive law theory for it is irrelevant that the law is unjust or falls short in any other facet. But one need not imagine what manner of society may come of that arrangenemt. It is to be seen in Nigeria. It is submitted that both in concept, conception and result, the positive law theory best represents what is practiced in Nigeria. Of course with the not so peculiar limitation that the positive law theory is not all encompassing for law must not only be commands but they may also empower and confer rights. Law is enacted also for the protection of the citizen. And that protection may not be found in the half-hearted clauses to be found in Chapter Four of the 1999 Constitution. Thus with the disappearance of reason (a compelling element of the natural law theory) one may conclude that Nigeria has sped indefatigably farther away from natural law and inexorably closer to positive law. This movement in itself is not without justification for in the words of the positivist scholar Gustav Radbruch: “Should no one be able to determine what is just, then someone must determine what is to be legitimate”. It may be concluded, tongue in cheek though it appears, that positive law especially as enunciated by Austin reigns supreme like his “sovereign” in Nigeria. May natural reason be equated with common sense? That question constantly reverberates where there is reason. And it may more probably be equated with it than not. Perhaps then, common sense which may at once be delineated as the epitome of natural law is what Nigeria like all civilizations must strive to infuse its laws with. William Orville Douglas the erudite jurist and justice of the United States Supreme Court has famously said: “Common sense often makes good law”. “It is submitted that these customary law, and customs of the people, were only permitted, and did not exist in the real Austinian theory of command, for the guardian angel was albeit, ‘Imperialism.’ Certainly, and whatever might have been the guise that might have been employed, customary law was never the same as common law”. 37 Supra JUSTICE Varying views but the idea that most current decimal in any idea of law is justice. For law is nothing if not a conduit pipe leading to justice. What is justice? Justice simply means fairness or fair play. In other words “the desire to balance fairly the needs of the individual against the needs of society plus the desire to find a fair balance between the interests of one individual and those of another” 38. It is “the proper administration of laws. In jurisprudence, the constant and perpetual disposition of legal matters or disputes to render every man his due”39. “Two conditions are essential to the realization of justice according to law. The law must have an authority supreme over the will of the individual, and such an authority can arise only from a background of social acquiescence, which gives it the voice of indefinitely greater numbers than those of its expositors. Thus, the law surpasses the deliverances of even the most exalted of its prophets; the momentum of its composite will alone makes it effective to coerce the individual and reconciles him to his subserviency. The pious traditionalism of the law has its roots in a sound conviction of this necessity; it must be content to lay behind the best inspiration of its time until it feels behind it the weight of such general acceptance as will give sanction to its pretension to unquestioned dictation”40. What can accelerate this acceptance? In Nigeria’s instance, there is the need, first and foremost that in the tradition of the LAKANMI decision, there is not one law for the geese and another for the gander. Laws must not deliberately be crafted, leaving vacuums and lacunae, for when the need arises for subtle or worse still, onkus manipulation. As a military Head of State who leaves power must not promulgate, in a decree handing over power to an interim government, that in any eventuality power must devolve to the most senior member of the council knowing who the beneficiary of that clause was, so an anti-corruption decree must not provide inexplicably that there must be a petitioner before an allegation of a corrupt offence may be investigated. In the first instance, the most senior member turned out to be the one who plotted the coup that ousted the interim government. In the latter case, a not so distinguished senator of the Federal Republic of Nigeria who addressed a press conference and admitted to bribing his honourable colleagues to defeat an impeachment move against the serving President evaded action on account of this most hair’s breadth of technicalities. If this anomaly is not corrected, Nigeria will collapse under an invasion of of laws. “When the state is most corrupt”, said Tacitus, “then the laws are most multiplied”. That assertion presents for Nigeria only a dilemma of the dimensions 38 The Mitchell Beazley Joy of Knowledge Library: Man and Society, p. 283 Black’s Law Dictionary, 6th ed., 1990 40 Hand, Learned, The Speech of Justice, 1916, p. 16 39 of the chicken-before-the-egg or the-egg-before-the-chicken. Which brought forth the other – the corrupt state or the multiplied laws? As it is Nigeria overrates the capacity of law. “Laws can discover sin,” Milton correctly asserted, “but not remove”. It is in the light of the foregoing that certain questions need be raised. Newspapers in Nigeria are replete with law-abiding citizens being slain by agents of state daily. A few years gone, when some Nigerians were detained in Saudi Arabia for smuggling cocaine into that Kingdom, the head of Nigeria’s regulatory drug agency trumpeted that they should consider themselves dead. Where was the presumption of innocence? Where were the principles of natural justice? What makes it possible for a dictator who is held responsible for the deaths of two Nigerian journalists in Liberia to be offered protection in the sleepy haven of Calabar with utter disregard for the sanctity of the lives of Nigerians contrary to section 33 of the Constitution? These questions do not canvass utopian standards but only that until those higher standards are put into contemplation, law and its acclaimed function will be but only a red herring. This indeed is not a commercial for natural law as law but rather for the infusion of higher standards, uninfluenced by vice and corruption, into our law makingprocess. In that sense, law will still be the command of the sovereign but a command that appeals to superior reason. As it is wehave demurred to one half of Madison’s admonition but not the other: “it may be a reflection on human nature that such devices should be necessary to control the abuses of government. But what is government itself but the greatest of all reflections on human nature? If men were angels, no government would be necessary. If angels were to govern men, neither external nor internal controls on government would be necessary. In framing a government whichis to be administered by men over men, the great difficult lies in this: you must first enable the government to contyrol the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control itself. A dependence on the people is, no doubt, the primary control on the government; but experience has taught mankind the necessity of auxiliary precautions”41. Perhaps a look at these sequences of conversation between judge and accused (defendants as the Americans call them) will suffice to convince doubting thomases that the standards ought to be high indeed: Mr. Mayberry: I would like to have a fair trial of this case and like to be granted a fair trial under the Sixth Amendment. The Court: You will get a fair trial. Mr. Mayberry: It doesn’t appear that I am going to get one the way you are overruling all our motions and that, and being like a hatchet man for the State. 41 Madison: The Federalist No. 51 The Court: This side bar is over. Mr. Mayberry: Wait a minute, Your Honour. The Court: It is over. Mr. Mayberry: You dirty sonofabitch … and Mr. Mayberry: You are a judge first. What are you working for? The prison authorities, you bum? Mr. Livingston: I have a motion pending before Your Honor. The Court: I would suggest – Mr. Mayberry: Go to hell. I don’t give a good God damn what you suggest, you stumbling dog. and Mr. Mayberry: You started all this bullshit in the beginning. The Court: You keep quiet. Mr. Mayberry: Wait a minute. The Court: You keep quiet. Mr. Mayberry: I am my oewn counsel. The Court: You keep quiet. Mr. Mayberry: Are you going to gag me? The Court: Take these prisoners out of here. We will take a ten minute recess, members of the jury … One accused told the court that if he did not gain access to his papers at night, he would “blow your head off” while another said he would not sit still and be “kowtowed and railroaded into a life imprisonment”. After the accused caused so much commotion the courtroom the court framed a charge of contempt against him and subsequently convicted them. The foregoing did not occur in a comic strip but rather in a judicial decision 42. The American Supreme Court held that the insults were highly personal aspersions and that: “Insults of that kind are apt to strike ‘at the most vulnerable and human qualities of a judge’s temperament’ … Our conclusion is that by reason of the due process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment a defendant in criminal contempt proceedings should be given a public trial before a judge other than the one reviled by the contemnor … In the present case that requirement can be satisfied only if the judgment of contempt is vacated so that on remand another judge, not bearing the sting of these slanderous remarks and having the impersonal authority of the law, sits in judgment on the conduct of petitioner as shown by the record”. The above case is recalled to illustrate how a judicial system may proceed for the dignity of the individual and consequently the greater good of the community. Sandkuhler has formulated a must list for the preservation of the human dignity: “The first and most important condition for the maintenance of human dignity is the safety of the individual and social life. Neither the state nor the rule of democracy provide this safety per se. In the very first instance, the most important condition for the maintenance of human dignity is concretized by the principle of the social state within a democratic constitutional state. This is linked inexorably to four further conditions: man’s equality before the law as the second condition, the upholding of human identity and integrity as the third condition, constraints on the use of state power as fourth, and respect for the bodily contingency of man as the fifth condition. Not until all these conditions are fulfilled can the wordings of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 10th December 1948 be considered to be socuietal reality: “All men are born free and equal in dignity and rights”. Athens fell to Sparta owing to factionalisation but what about Hitler’s Germany etc? ., interpose Common law which is that body of law which is grounded in and has evolved from custom which has not been specifically legislated. “A wise man once said, ‘Convention is like the shell to the chick, a protection till he is strong enough to break it through’”43. 42 43 Mayberry V. Pennsylvania 400 U.S. 455, 91 S. Ct. 499, 27. L. Ed. 2d 532 (1971) Hand, Learned, The Preservation of Personality, 1927, p. 32