Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium IVIember Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/walrasianbargainOOyild Dewey Technology Department of Economics Working Paper Series Massachusetts Institute of WALRASIAN BARGAINING Muhamet Yildiz, MIT Working Paper 02-02 October 2001 Room E52-251 50 Memorial Drive Cambridge, MA 021 42 This paper can be downloaded without charge fronri the Social Science Research Network Paper Collection at http://papers.ssm.com/paper.taf7abstract id =297 168 Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Economics Working Paper Series WALRASIAN BARGAINING Muhamet Yildiz, MIT Working Paper 02-02 October 2001 Room E52-251 50 Memorial Drive Cambridge, MA 02142 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Paper Collection at http://papers.ssm.com/paper.taf7abstract id= XXXXX MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY MAR 7 2002 LIBRARIES Walrasian Bargaining Muhamet Yildiz* MIT October, 2001 Abstract Given any two-person economy, we consider a simple alternating-offer bargaining game with complete information where the agents conditions under which the outcomes of all We offer prices. provide stationary subgame-perfect equilibria converge to the Walrasian equilibrium (the price and the allocation) as the agents become infinitely patient. Therefore, price-taking behavior can be achieved with only two agents. Key Words: Bargaining, Competitive JEL Numbers: C73, C78, D41. Introduction 1 It is in equilibrium, Coase Conjecture commonly believed that, in a sufficiently large, frictionless economy, trade results an approximately competitive (Walrasian) economy allocation. In fact, the core of such an consists of the approximately Walrasian allocations. Moreover, in a bargaining model with a continuiun of patient agents, Gale (1986) shows that we petitive allocation in In contrast, monopoly when case, have a com- any stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium (henceforth, SSPE). there are only two agents, and the outcome in that case, the core will is will it is believed that we will have a bilateral be indeterminate (Edgeworth, 1881). Accordingly, very large, and the SSPE outcome wiU typically differ from the competitive allocation in the usual bargaining models, in which the agents are allowed *1 cially would like to thank Daron Acemoglu, Abhijit Banerjee, Glenn Robert Wilson for helpful the earlier discussions with comments. Murat Sertel I Ellison, Paul Milgrom, and espe- also gratefully acknowledge that when we have worked on the 1 topic. I have benefitted from to offer any allocation.^ In this paper, where the agents discount rates approach to petitive allocation We offer prices. and the 1, we analyze a simple two-agent bargaining model show SSPE the under certain conditions, as the agents' that, allocations and the prices converge to the price, respectively. Therefore, the com- Wahasian equilibrium may have stronger foundations than commonly thought. Considering a pure-exchange economy with only two agents, we analyze the following alternating-offer bargaining Agent 2 either demands a game with complete is reahzed, and the when Agent is offers 2 offers a game a price. he demands ends. If he rejects the offer, price, and Agent either 1 we demands a This goes on until they reach an agreement. Each feasible trade or rejects the offer. agent's utility fimction 1 feasible trade at that price, or rejects the offer. If a trade, the demanded trade proceed to the next date, Agent information: normahzed by at the initial setting to endowment. Agents cannot consume their goods until they reach an agreement, and each discounts the future with a constant discount rate. Notice that we restrict the proposer to and allow the other agent to offer prices, choose the amoimt of trade at that price. For instance, in the case of wage bargaining, how much the luiion sets the wage, the firm has right to choose if labor to hire. Likewise, the firm sets the wage, the workers or the union have the right to choose the of labor they provide. offer In contrast, in the standard models, the proposer any allocation, while the other agent can only accept or if is amount allowed to reject the offer. This is the only major difference. When the agents are restricted to making price offers, while their trading partners are allowed to choose the emerges. To price, the game amoimt see this, consider an ends, hence he of trade at the offered prices, price-taking behavior economy with two goods. When an agent demands the optimal trade this restricts the other agent to offer a payoff vector payoff vectors that can be achieved rates are close to 1, in any SSPE when in z i accepts a at that price. Effectively, the offer curve of agent a price-taker. Moreover, is which on for i when the i, the discount the offers are accepted, both agents are all approximately indifferent between the allocations today and tomorrow. Note that the payoffs associated with these allocations are Therefore, the payoffs in such a 'For instance, as the common on the SSPE must be offer curves of two distinct agents. very close to an intersection of the offer discount rate approaches to 1, the SSPE outcome in Rubinstein (1982) converges to the Nash (1950) bargaining solution (Binmore, Rubinstein, and Wolinsky, 1987), which different from the Wahasian outcome, as noted by Binmore (1987). (Rubinstein's model and abstract, but the set of feasible payoffs is typically allowing the agents to offer any allocation.) is is more general taken to be the set of materially feasible payoffs, curves. many payoff- vector is at such an intersection. Moreover, in canonical economies with a unique Walrasian equilibrium, the Walrasian payoff- vector for Of course, each Walrasian is the only intersection (of the offer curves) in the relevant region. such economies, the payoffs in these payoffs. Moreover, the — as we have SSPE must Therefore, be converging to the Walrasian Walrasian payoffs are obtained only at the Walrasian allocation By strictly quasi-concave utihty fimctions. continuity, this shows that the allocation at these SSPE utility fimctions are continuously differentiable, there exists a continuous inverse-demand also converge to the Walrasian allocation. function, therefore the prices in these We further show that monopoly: he must this to when the also converge to the Walrasian price. any other possible SSPE, an agent must act as a natural in offer his be an equilibrium SSPE Finally, monopoly price, and must be accepted. it for large values of discount rates, the monopoly outcome must be Pareto-optimal under the constraint that one of the agents must be a Ruling out the case that a monopoly is efficient in this sense, In order for price-taker. we conclude that all SSPE allocations (and the prices) converge to the Walrasian allocation (and the price) of the static pure-exchange economy at hand. This limiting behavior where agents can offer is strikingly different any allocation. In that model, agents share the gains from trade in the limit make agents 1). offers, or from that of the Rubinstein (1982) model is for a quasi-hnear solely economy, how the determined by the frequencies the the logarithmic ratio of the discount rates (as they approach to All these are irrelevant for our limit, the Walrasian allocation of the static economy. Therefore, our small change in the allocation of the rights (embedded in the bargaining procedure) has a profound impact on the bargaining outcome, while the bargaining outcome under the new allocation of Oirr result is rights is very robust to other procediual details. related to the hterature on the Coase Conjecture. In the context durable-good monopoly, Coase (1972) argued that, price, then he will price his good at the marginal if a monopoUst cannot commit to a cost. (For the consimaers expects the monopoUst to lower the prices in the future. In a sense, the monopolist peting with its future-selves.) would be com- In an asymmetric information model, Gul, Sonnensrhein, and Wilson (1986) and Fudenberg, Levine, and Tirole (1985) have shown that jecture it is is true in any SSPE, as the discoimt rate approaches to essential that the monopolist does not valuations were ation. Our common know Now, there 1. this con- In this formalization, the buyers' valuation. If the buyers' knowledge, the monopolist would charge each buyer his valu- result extends Coase's notion to a two-person information. of a are two agents (and economy without asymmetric their future selves) setting prices. The outcome becomes Walrasian as the discount There rates approach to 1. a large literature on the relation between the bargaining outcome an the is competitive equilibria (see Osborne and Rubinstein (1990) for a survey). of my To the best knowledge, this literature assrunes a very large economy, except for Rubinstein and Wohnsky Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1990) obtain a similar result to that (1990). of Gale (1986 and 1987) with only finitely economy special in the theorem is we unrelated to the competitive is In Section true. we explain why lay out our model. In Section 3, standard model still agents. However, they consider only a which the core consists of the competitive allocations. in hi the next section, outcome many relegated to the Appendix. we 4, SSPE outcome, and why our derive our result; the proofs of Section 5 contains the lemmas are some coimter examples that show that our assiunptions are not superfluous. Section 6 concludes. Model 2 X Let = p = R" (p\ . > p'' . . G ,p") for all where Good IR"^. k? ^ N. Assume that «, (xi) We = is will = for be the aU price vectors set of taken to be the numeraire, i.e., ((ui,Xi) , where (u2,^2)), x^ of agent i, G X and Ui : X ^f R each i N= E {1,2}. Write lu = Xi + X2. wish to understand the relation between the Walrasian equilibrium of e and the the set of all At date dates. demands a consiunption that X2 is feasible is X2 t E {x = Agent 0, E X\{x — X2) game ends At G {x G X\{x vector [6\ui (xi) , 1 offers -pi = Let T= {0, 1, 2, 0,x < w] — ^ = Xi) 6\u2 [w Agent 1, p2 — We write R for the set of real = 0,x — X2,X2)- 2 offers a price p2, < numbers, M" .} . be either or rejects the offer. (Note — pi.) If X2) ,6\u2 (3:2)), she rejects, we proceed to and Agent 1 either demands w], when the game ends yielding the payoff Xj)), or rejects the offer, space, K",,. for the interior of W\.. If . Agent 2 a price pi G P. yielding the payoff vector [6\ui {w associated with the allocation {w the next date. offering prices. game G {61,62), and can be reached by reallocating the endowments at price she d .mands X2, the ^ and Ui is strictly quasi-concave, continuous, monotonically-increasing, where these two agents bargain altematmgly Xi 1, respectively, for each stationary subgame-perfect equihbria of the following perfect-information which = p^ simply say prices instead of price vectors.) endowment and the utiUty function are the initial and 1 we (Henceforth, Consider a 2-person economy e i P be a commodity space with n goods, and for when we proceed to the next date, the non-negative orthant of a n-dimensional Euclidean when Agent ment. they never reach an agreement, each gets If € {61,62) Any a price again. This goes on indefinitely until they reach an agree- offers 1 approaches to (0, 1) (1, 1). stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium (henceforth, hst (Pi,ii,p2,i2) where, for each whenever he make an to is ^ N, i and offer, Xi : rejects the offer if Xi {pj) = P —y : Di at each (p) = p E P. Since Since w, function. allocation (xi, X2) Assumption X [J {Reject} agent i and x* is Together with arg max {u^ u^ is For each {x)\{x — p < x^) 0, x < any pair is = Xi Di (p, i is made in the interior of (p) for X for each strict quasi-concavity, only to X} w, x E Di each i. i make is each i, and xi -|- also continuous. X2 = p E P A and an w. {p* {xl, X2)) ; (xj,X2) 7^ , E N. the assumption that {xl,X2) In that case, the a weU-defined is (xi,X2)) of a price initial allocation is hence there are gains from trade. The assimiption that x* each € E N, define the (constrained) de- i Maximum Theorem, continuous, by the for offers Xi {pj) if Xi {pj) continuous and strictly quasi-concave, Di E X^ such that > tees that Ui (x*) i the function that is demands There exists a unique Walrasian equilibrium 1 represented by a the price that the agent is pj, the is X by setting Walrasian equilibrium (constrained) (xi,X2), is -^ SSPE) Reject. Basic Definitions and Assumptions mand function Di P P E pi determines his responses: when offered a price X, and We are interested in the case when 0. sure that (p*,(x^,X2)) is is 7^ (xi,X2) guaran- not Pareto optimal, in the interior of X for an "miconstrained" Wahasian equilibrium. Define the offer curves of Agents OCi = 1 and 2 as {(ui {D, {p)),U2 {w - D, {p))) \pEP] and OC2 = respectively. OCt the set of all who wiU then maximize agent i, Vi for an agent agent j is {(«i [w is i, - D2 {p)),U2 {D2 (p))) utihty pairs that can be reached by offering a price to his payoff given the price. In general, given there might be multiple pairs (^1,^2) in to choose \pEP}, OQ. between these pairs by offering different In that case, prices, he will any payoff if the other choose the . maximum pair with To formulate Vj. functions Ui and this, define f/2 (on appropriate domains) by Ui {V2) = max{?'i| U2 = max{i.'2| (^'i,f'2) e OC2} (t'i,t'2) and satisfies is, = = {ui (xj) ,U2 (3^2)) = U2 {ui (xj)) Ui {u2 (X2)) and U2 {xD in OCi (1 (1) payoff'- vector. For our main result, we will assume that this the only intersection in the relevant region (see Assumption 4 below). Throughout the paper, we wiU make the following assumption, which many Since U^ some is satisfied by economies, such as the Cobb-Douglas economies in the Edgeworth box. Assumption 2 For at is the graphs of Ui and U2 (which are typically the offer cvirves themselves) intersect each other at the Walrasian is v* the equations ui (xj) That e OCi}, Note that the Wabrasian payoff- vector respectively. OC2, and (vi) Vj any is each > Uj [Dj {pi)) Vj.) = E N , and Ui is continuoxis single-peaked. single-peaked and cannot be monotonically increasing, G R. (Note that Vj i Vj f/j is strictly increasing at By a monopoly price of an agent and u^ {w - Dj {p,)) = U^ (vj). i, it is maximized at < Vj and strictly decreasing we will mean any price p, E P with any Vj An Example 3 In this section, using a canonical example, we will explain our formulation, and show how the Walrasian outcome typically differs from the subgame-perfect equilibriiun (henceforth tions. SPE) outcome We will in Rubinstein's then explain model where the agents bargain by why our theorem Consider a quasi-linear economy e = "1 {'m, y) m + y" — 1, U2 {m, y) quasi-hnear utihty functions, the first m will -f- true. {{ui, (0, 1)) y° , (^2, (Af, 0))) - M, a € take A" = IR (0, 1), and with two goods where M> 0. Since we have x IR^, allowing negative amounts of good — money. For a single we = = is offering alloca- = 0.5, the offer curves are plotted in Figiire peaked and continuous. The offer curves 1. Notice that both Ui and U2 are OCi and OC2 are simply the graphs of \J.t ^ -7x f 1 /^^S^ 0.35 N 0.3 \ 1 . V [Walrasian payoffs] \he- - ^sX M /"' Vv\ \\^^\ ( ^^iW 0.25 1 ' 1 I 1 I 1 \ ^ \ >:^ \ \ j \ ^2 f ^C 2 ^\ ^\ ^v V \. / y\ - U 5 2 / Pareto Frontier / 0.2 ^^^\^ / / / y 1 0.15 y\ 0.1 , 5 \ U \ \ \^ 0.05 / V 1 0.05 1 1 0.15 0.1 Figure 1: 1 1 0.25 0.2 Offer curves for q 1 = 1/2, 6i 0.3 = ^2 = 0.9. N X 1 0.35 0.4 U2 and L'^i, The Walrasian respectively. where the payoffs are at the unique point offer curves intersect each other. Notice also that the Walrasian payoffs are very asymmetric. One can compute that the Walrasian price is p* = (1, a2^~°), yielding the Walrasian payoff vector +Q 1 —a 1 2° ' 2^ Hence, at the Walrasian equihbrium, the ratio of Agent — (1 q) / On (1 +Q— model As share to Agent I's share is determined by a. 2"), the other hand, cation, the payoffs 2's we have a add up to 2^~° transferable utihty case: in any Pareto-optimal allo- — Then, the imique 1. SPE outcome in Rubinstein's is = (^1,^2) -^ (1,1) at the rate r log ((5i) /log (62), Therefore, in the limit, the ratio of Agent 2's share to Agent I's share by the discount solely rates, or the frequencies at well-known fact imphes that, in the hmit, the SPE is r, which the agents make payoffs in Rubinstein's determined offers. Tliis model carmot possibly be related to the Walrasian payoffs, which are determined by a. In particular, when there is a common discount rate, in the hmit, the SPE distributes the gains from trade equally, while the Walrasian payoffs are very asymmetric. Now that, Di consider the bargaining procediu-e in whenever an agent [pj ) — for the G {61,62)- Lemma accepts a price pj, he i game ends there, as the Rubinstein's bargaining 1 below estabhshes demands the optimal consimiption and thus our bargaining procedure can be considered model where each agent is restricted to offer payoffs the other agent's offer curve. Therefore, as in Rubinstein (1982), there is determined by the intersection 1). In this SPE, an agent i {61,62) of the graphs of 61U1 accepts an offer agent j offers a price that gives is v^ v]'^ {61, iff 62) to he gets at i is and 62U2 least v]^ {61, 62), and Uj [v^ a SPE on that (see Figure and the other {61,62)) to j. But, since v* the unique intersection of the graphs of Ui and U2, as {61,62) -^ (1,1), v"^ {6^,62) -^v*. In the limit, the rate at SPE payoff- vector itself which the discount rates go to 1. is v*. This convergence is independent of the Tliis also suggests that this 8 convergence to the Walrasian equilibrium may hold even the agents would if make offers at different frequencies. As one can easily see from Figure 1, the changes in the agents' discoiint rates do change the bargaining outcome — in a predictable way. When we increase the discount rate of an agent keeping everything else constant, his equiUbrium payoff (if anything) increases, while the other agent's equilibrium payoff (if anything) decreases, provided that there a unique SSPE. is Notice in Figure U2, respectively. 1 and that [vi, U2 (^1)) That is, if an agent (t/i (€'2) , C'2) monopoly offers his of discount rates) the other agent can reject that offer counter-offer. Under price, then property of Ui and U2 hold, all when SSPE the and (for large values and make a Pareto-improving this condition, for large values of discoimt rates, there cannot be other SSPE. Therefore, this are below the graphs of Ui this condition we show and the rmique that intersection converge to the Walrasian outcome — as in example. Theorem 4 In this section, we will describe the sufficient conditions SSPE of G {61,62). We game under which the allocations and the prices at the Walrasian allocation and the price, respectively, as {61,62) Our first Lemma describes the basic properties of Given any 61,62 G (0,1), any 1 G{6i, 62), lemma under Assumption e {Dj Xj {pi) 2. if Xj {pi) 3. if Xj {pi) y^ Reject, then Part 1 ^ , Reject, then Ui {w states that, at that price, for the if u-j - Dj {Dj game ends —hence the second part. SSPE converge to (1,1)- SSPE. E N, any SSPE (pi, £1,^2,^2) of {pi)) G P; {pr)) > there. = Ui {uj {Dj (p,))); Vj. price, he demands his optimal consumption Hence, in terms of equiUbria, our game game where each agent in the other agent's offer curve. of Ui all pi an agent accepts a equivalent to a bargaining j then provide the following are true: Reject} for 1. {pi) 2, ^ i —> all will is restricted to offer a payoff vector In that case, each agent The proof is i offers a point on the graph of this part uses the continuity of the availability of the prices that allow the other agent to demand consumptions t/, and better than his equihbrium demand. Part 3 simply states that each agent's offer is at least as generous as his monopoly price. Our next lemma some necessary conditions lists towards proving our Theorem. The basic argument 2, if i an agent j offering a price pj that will is SSPE. This for a is is the main step the following. Under Assimiption be accepted and that allows the other agent to obtain a higher payoff than his continuation value, then pj must be a monopoly price of j. For, otherwise, j would offer a less generous price that would be accepted and would yield a higher payoff for j. This imphes that either Lemma 1 either (i) 2 Under Assumptions (i) for or G i,j all, distinct for any = some distinct (2) = 6,u,{w-D,{p;)) = i (4) (5) Each equilibrium-offer (3), similar to in Rubinstein (1982). At 61 = 62 is accepted, between accepting (and offers leave the other agents indifferent demanding the optimal consumption) and the equation system (3) = A(P,), = V,. describes a type of equilibrium: and the equihbrium 6,U,{u,{D,{p,)))- and j such that u,(A(ft)) (i) G {81,82), {p\,Xi,p2,X2) of any D,{p,), x,{p,) Condition SSPE below must hold. (ii) A'', u,{D,{p,)) there exist 2, or true: (ii) is x,{p,) (ii) and (i) This indifference yields rejecting the offer. the equation system that characterizes the equihbrium = 1, this equation system is identical to (1), the system of equations satisfied by the Walrasian prices. Condition who always (ii) describes another type of equihbrium: offers his agent's offer is monopoly price, typically rejected. This which is is Now, there when j is an agent i accepted by the other agent. The other an equihbrium iff there curve of j that gives each agent at least the continuation value of payoffs exists a monopoly. In that case, the other agent that must be accepted by the sequentially- rational agent is no point on the offer — the discounted value {i) cannot offer any price j? 'in a bargaining model where the agents bargain over trades (rather than prices), an agent can always offer the trade that will take place in the next date, guaranteeing the continuation value to each agent, but this is not true in our model. 10 Lemma 3 Under Assumptions if (ii) Lemma of 2 i.e., [w - Dj (p,)) the inequality 6^U^ {6jUj [vi)) We will ruling out now assume all Assumption is, SSPE for any {pi,Xi,p2, X2) of any P > , > Uj [Dj (p,))) 3 For {v^,6jUj [vi)) (6) , does not hold. v^ that (6) holds for all i,j an agent i G N, G [61,62), such that some when price in the limit the equilibria of the second tjrpe for large values of 61 and Pi E Uj {Dj {p^))) > (l*„ - Dj (p^)) can offer a price that , P some there exists (W [U, That 2, then there does not exist any Pt E is true, {6^u, and 1 = 62 = 1, 62- such that Uj {Vi)) better than the is 61 . monopoly price of the other agent j for both of them, provided that j maximizes his payoff given the price offered by z. monopoly In other words, any that the agents trade through prices. By is Pareto-inefficient even under the constraint continuity, this assumption implies that (6) holds for large values of {61,62)- Lemma (5,1), 4 Under Assumption and for all i,j G 3, some there exists we have 6iUi{6jUj A'', E 6 (vi)) (0, 1) > Vi, such that, i.e., there exists Pi for all 61,62 G P E satisfying (6). The following Lemma is an immediate corollary to 2, 3, 5 Under Assumptions 1-3, there exists some 6 G (5,l), for all SSPE {pi,Xi,p2,X2) of x,{pj) Ui The Lemmas (A {Pj)) G {61,62), = D,{pj), = 6^Ui and for and (0, 1) all 4: such {W - Dj {pi)) There exists a unique (^1,^2) = 1^1 all 61,62 G (7) = 6^U^ {Uj {Dj (p,))) and intersection in the relevant region. Ui {V2) for G N, we have distincti,j following assumption guaranties that the graphs of Ui Assumption 4 that, > and U2 11 (^1,^2) such that {vi) = V2. . f/2 (8) has a unique At the Walrasian eqmlibrium, each agent 6 Under Assumption 4, U, {u, [D, (p,))) gets at least we have the U2 intersect each other. Therefore, Lemma i and the graphs of Ui and Vt, lemma. following given any pi,p2 £ P, we have = u, (A {Pj)) > ^jeN) (Vi vr This gives us our main theorem. Theorem {61,62) Under Assumptions 1 1-4, if (pf ,xf,p2,X2) is a SSPE of G {6) for each 5 = e{0,lf, then 1™,^*(A0=^; (9) *-»(!, 1) for each distinct i,j G N. Moreover, lim That if ui p* = and U2 are continuously lim pi as the discoimt rates approach to is, = p\ 1, (10) imder Assumptions allocations converge to the unique Walrasian allocation. continuously differentiable, this implies that the rasian price. Notice that the Assumptions 1-4, A = (A f : = [0, l]'^ : D2 (F)) A -^M? Xl, X2) and the correspondence ^ i{6^M) = prices also converge to the existence of Wal- SSPE. (Under n {{xi, X2) G X^IVz G A'', Ui (x,) > v^}. Define 6^Ui {Uj {Xj)) - U, (x,) [l ^ j ^ N) -^ 2^ by {{Xx,X2) G^|/(<5i,(52,Xi,X2) =0}. 6, Moreover, since / is SSPE hy C(l,l) that ^ the the utility functions are If Theorem does not claim the (F) x {0,lf x f^ ((5i, 62, By Lemma SSPE 1-4, one can easUy show that there does exist a SSPE.) Proof. Define also the function differentiable, then is = {(x*,xa)}. continuous, ^ has a closed graph. Since upper semi-continuous. Hence, given any that, for each 61, 62 > 6, for each (xj, X2) G ^ (^i, <52), ||X,-X*||<6. 12 e > and 0, A is compact, this imphes there exists b for each j G A'', G (0,1) such we have (11) On the other hand, by e (61,62) Lemma there exists a 5, <5 G such that, for each S (0, 1) (6,1)2, (f*(p^),x*(p*))G {(61,62). Therefore, by (11) and (12), given any each 6 = (61,62) G (6*, 1)^, we have Towards proving the second e > part, define > max{6, 6} there exists 6* 0, - ||x^ (pf) (12) < x*|| X= proving e, {x G X|0 < P if Uj is exists x'' < w'' \/k any X* [pf) -. X*, by continuity, pf An intuition for the = D;^ Theorem maximizing his utihty at the price utihty at the price set by Agent rates converge to similar, is, D~^ continuously differentiable, then inverse-demand function and continuous, where Di {D~^ 1, [x] [pf)) -> set by Agent 2, The markets will become approximately, each agent is i indifferent D;^ (x*) same by distinct XnD^ i,jE {P) set -^• (P). But, since 1 must be and Agent 2 must be maximizing definition. by different agents will j his As the discount by become between today and tomorrow. Therefore, i. n}, the set between he himself maximizing indifferent price set XnDi : < In equilibrium. Agent clear for = p\ m by the other agent j and the other agent at approximately the G for each Xi '^i one would expect that the prices and each agent at the price set = the following. is 1. i^i)) such that, (9). of consumption bundles corresponding to the interior allocations. For N, = That his utility maximizing her payoff we must be approximately at a Walrasian equihbrium. (The logic of our proof is clearly difTerent from this intuition, for proving convergence to a Walrasian equilibrium turns out to be more straight-forward than proving that the prices converge to the same What is price.) the essential aspect of the Walrasian equihbrium — is it competition or price taking? In the tradition of Coase (1972), but relying on different forces, our suggests that, later may be when the goods are diirable, the competition between the selves sufficient for the price-taking Theorem now and behavior to emerge, provided that the agents are restricted to trade using prices as in this paper. In sequential bargaining models, the outcome and offer when. traditional rights find this a determined by which agent makes weakness of the model and adhere to the view that the bargaining outcome should be determined by the property — not by the Harsanyi, it Some authors is 1977)."* details of the procedure (see Aumann Our theorem has two imphcations on (1987), this issue. Nash On (1950), and the one hand, establishes that a change in the procedure (that the proposers are required to offer who develop a bargaining model with endogenous timing of offers, who analyze the equilibria of the continuous time game that are not "See also Perry and Reny (1993), and Smith and Stacchetti (2001), determined by the temporal monopoly of the proposer. 13 prices rather than allocations wliile the responders are allowed to choose the size of the trade) has a profound effect on the outcome. On rights matters. Therefore, the allocation of procedural the other hand, the limiting behavior under the procedural rights does not depend on can easily show that it how new allocation of the the discoimt rates approach to would not depend which agent makes an that each agent makes offers sufficiently frequently. offer 1. Hence, one when, provided Therefore, such procedural details do not matter for the limiting behavior under the new allocation of procedural rights. Early mechanism design literature had an interest in implementing the Walrasian Nash environment allocation in a Theorem (see Our Hurwicz (1979) and Schmeidler, 1980). establishes that our simple bargaining procedure approximately implements SSPE under the Walrasian allocation in endowments certain conditions, provided that the initial known by the mechanism are designer. Along with the simphfying assumptions monopolies are inefficient and 1 our Theorem assumes that the 2, even under the constraint that one of the agents must be a price-taker (Assumption 3) and the graphs of the relevant region (Assumption 4). f/j and U2 have a unique intersection in Under these assumptions estabUshes that it SSPE outcome converges to the Walrasian outcome. Are these assumptions superfluous? Are there non-stationary subgame-perfect equilibria? These questions are answered in the next section. Counter-examples 5 We will there now may present two examples. SSPE exist example shows first as described in condition to the Walrasian outcome. It also to the Walrasian equilibrium. equilibria, The based on the SSPE (ii) of that, Lemma 2, if Assumption 3 fails, which do not converge shows that there may be multiple SSPE that converge Hence, there may be non-stationary subgame-perfect that converge to the Walrasian equihbrimri. example shows that, when Assiunption 4 fails, SSPE may The second converge to a non- Walrasian outcome. Example 1 Consider the economy e = 2-ayi-Q _ go ^^^ ^^ (x, y) = x^~^y^ — 9^. a= 0.6, P= 0.1, and 61 = 62 = ((uj, (9, 1)) 0.9. Firstly, notice Hence, for large values of (^1,^2), we have a iff ui {Di [p)) > In Figure 61U1 {V2) and X2 (p) SSPE = D2 (p) 14 iff , (u2, (1,9))) 2, that Ui we plot the offer curves for (C'2) > max {vi\U2 (vi) > 0}. = Di {p) {pi,Xi,p2,X2) where Xi (p) U2 (^2 (p)) = where Ui{x,y) > 0. (Recall that p^ is the monopoly price of monopoly and price pi, and that gives i.) it In is tliis SSPE, Agent There accepted. positive payoff to Agent wiU be rejected. Second, observe that, emerges as a monopoly: he 1 is 1 liis would accept so he offers the non-serious price p2, which 2, = for 61 62 two distinct points v and intersect each other at no price that Agent offers = v', 0.9, the graphs of SiUi and 62U2 two more SSPE. Both of yielding these equilibria converge to the Walrasian outcome. Figure The following example is 2: The offer curves for Example 1. taken from Sertel and Yildiz (1994). Using this economy, they show that there cannot be an axiomatic bargaining solution that always pick the Walrasian payoff- vectors. graphs of and U2 C/i Here, we will use the same economy to show that, intersect each other at non- Walrasian payoff vectors, the if the SSPE can converge to non- Walrasian outcomes. Example 2 (Sertel where u{x,y) = and Yildiz, 1994) Consider the economy e (1/45) min{24x4-37/-f- 15,9x -I- 18y,4x -I- 23y -I- 5} = ((«, (0, 10)), (u, (10, 0))) -1. The indifference curves and the offer curves (in utility space and in the Edgeworth box) are plotted in Figure 3. The the diagonal, indifference curves are tangent to each other only at the strip when the common slope of the indifference cin-ves unique Walrasian price in this economy vector V* = (4, 1). In the is p* = Edgeworth box, the 15 (1,2), yielding offer is aroimd —1/2. Therefore, the a unique Walrasian payoff- curves of Agent 1 and Agent 2 are -' 2'-'' ~^^^^^~~^ ^^^/ \\/Walras/ 80U: /v\ \ \ \cy ' -^^ip* /^ 1 ~ ~ ~ ""-----V2 \pi • \" 9'/ h X" ------.': ' Figure 3: 4 The offer — curves for economy e of Example 2 5 Ui the Edgeworth box and in in the utihty space. (The hyperplanes are indicated by the associated prices.) the hne segments connecting the points But [x, a, b, 6', c, d] in the utihty space, the graphs of Ui and Ui {V2) = 5 — V2- Then, the the transferable utility case. SSPE For each and U2 in this ^1, 62 and coincide: economy € (0, 1), is = and 5 — vi as in Rubinstein (1982) for 62^/2 SSPE — — with payoff vector — SSPE payoffs converge to (5/2, 5/2), distinct 1). The SSPE prices p* and pj converge to the from the Walrasian payoff- vector v* = (4, let 5 = <52(l-<5i) 1, 5 (^i) 1-^2 1 — S162 + ^2 we have U2 respectively. there exists a imique determined by the intersections of the graphs of 61U1 and When we fix 61 = [x, a', b, b', g, h], 1 — 6162 = (1,29/37) and P2 = (1)7/11)) respectively. Pi Even though the prices pi and p2 are distinct, the equilibrium allocation is Pareto- optimal in the hmit, for the utility functions are concave but not strictly concave. can shghtly modify the utility fimctions in this utihty functions, yielding the same Walrasian example to construct payoffs strictly One concave and the same SSPE. In that case, the allocation in the hmit would be Pareto-inefficient, but there would not be a Pareto- improving trade that can be achieved through price taking behavior. 16 . Conclusion 6 Consistent with common sense, allocation in a large economy the SSPE in usual bargaining models yield the Walrasian (Gale, 1986), while they typically yield non- Walrasian out- comes when there are only limited niunber are allowed to offer any trade among of agents. In these bargaining models, agents we the bargaining parties. Here, present a simple bargaining procediu:e where the agents are restricted to offer prices, while their trading partners optimize at these prices. SSPE the of this mechanism As the discoimt yield the rates go to 1 , under certain conditions, Wahasian equilibrium. Therefore, the Walrasian equilibrium does not necessarily require a large economy. simply corresponds to price- It taking behavior, which can be achieved even with only two agents. A Lemmas Proofs of This appendix contains the proofs of the Lemmas. [Lemma Proof. 1] hence we must have Xj (Part 1) If Xj (p,) In order to prove Part some p E P = Dj 2, we (pi) Xj {pi) j^ Reject, Assume that i will first show offers pi , it Ui {Dj Xj (p,) i.e., > {pi)) pi node, Reject, then there exists < = u, [D, iP,)) Dj {pi). If {pi) ^ > 0. (13) Uj {Dj {pi)) and Xj, = w— = p* 0, pi Dj ^ {pi) satisfies ^ x {w - Dj Now, Xi. must be that {w - D, (pO) (14) the Separating-Hyperplane Theorem, there exists a price pi such that Di Xi.For any > ^ that, if x^ (pi) Hence, Dj 0. u, By final decision such that Assume that since then we are in a (p,). u, {D, (pO) (13). ^ Reject, Xi with pi {pi) - {x = Xi) — pi Xi) {xj < 0, - Dj < Ui {x) 0. {pi)), i.e., p, Together {Dj {pi) (14), this - Xj) < {pi) = imphes that 0. Since u^ is monotonically increasing, this implies (13). (Part 2) Assume that Xj (pi) ^ Reject, i.e., Xj {pi) = Dj {pi). But, by stationarity, the continuation values do not depend which offers are rejected, hence, for any pi with Uj {Dj {pi)) > Uj {Dj {pi)), we must have Xj {pi) — Dj {p^)) < Ui {uj {Dj {pi)))Ui then exists some e > and some price p' such that Suppose that {w 17 ^ Reject, Since Ui and thus Xj is {pi) = Dj {pi). continuous, by (13), there Ui {uj {Dj {pi)) + e) > Ui{w — Dj (p^)) . and Uj {Dj [p')) = + e. Now, Uj {Dj (p,)) + payoff Ui {uj {Dj {pi)) e), ^ stationarity, Xj (p,) deviation for Proof. Case i, Reject, Xj (p,) i.e., two Assmne that xi (p2) ^ N , offer is we have Ui {w f/j {Uj {Dj for t, any p_,, and demand Di price Pj be accepted, yielding higher = Dj ^ X2{p\). < (p,)) = Vj Thus, offering {p,). Then, Uj {Dj {pi)). a profitable p^ is cases. Reject — Dj = (p,)) i {Dj t/, {xlj Lemma Then, by Since Xj {pi))). at the beginning of any date i L2, for each (p,) ^ Reject, + at which he is accepted, 1 This has two implications. First, since pj {pi))). «, Second, at will a contradiction. follows that the continuation value of makes an it Reject and Uj {Dj 2] There are 6 distinct i,j ^ (p,) [Lemma 1: offers p', i contradiction. a. (Part 3) Suppose that Xj by if (A > iPj)) (A S,U, {u, (15) {Pj))) (A (p^)) > 6iUi {Uj {Dj (p,))), player i must accept the (see Lemma LI). Since j offers pj it must be true that u^ if {pj ) , Uj{u,{Di{pj)))>Uj{v,) each for Ui (A with > Vi > (P,)) Vi > 6,U, {u, (£>_, (A Now, assume that (P;))). Hence, by (16), {?,))) > SiUi {ui {Di {pj))). Since Ui {Di {pj)) has a local Cose S^Ut {uj maximum at u^ Assume that Xj ,2: Reject, agents (A (Pj))- {pi) = (i) {u, f/, (16) (A > {?:))) Uj Then, by {v,) for some G N. i,j would never reach an agreement, thus 2, u^ (A (Pj)) we also If = their continuation values Therefore, Xi {pj) 6^Ui {Di (pj)) = = i.e., Vi S'^Ui {Di (Pj)). Proof. . ^ Reject Since j offers pj, Ui {Di As in On {pj)). Case [Lemma 1, if = Ui {Di {pj)) Proof. Vi. Since Ui = the other hand, 0, 3]Assume there him only Vi. {vi) = Vi. Di v, < > would be would must accept who makes > > 0; Ui {Di {pj)) > offers Pi, it will be «, (A Uj (0) for each 0, = {Pj)) (jpj) if then Vi m G P. Then, if i Then, at the previous date, i should not m [Lemma 4] By Assumption 3,ior 6i = is = Ui {Di {pj)) if exists such pi T'l/Si. Xi {pj) then Uj this yields Ui {Di {pj)) accepted, yielding a payoff higher than accept pj, which gives Then, Xj {pi). x, (pj) 1), this the Wahasian price p*, providing a profitable deviation (p*) for the agent offer. each '^'t- had yield a contradiction: In that case, in a stationary equilibrium each agent an (15), 6iUi {ui {Di {pj))), this implies that Uj Thus, by Assmnption Reject for not true. is Since the Walrasian payoffs are strictly positive (by Assumption zero. it continuous, this imphes the 62 Lemma. 18 = l,6iUi {6jUj {vi)) > Ui {w - Dj {pi)) > References [1] Aumann, R. A Palgrave, [2] The New Binmore and Dasgupta (edi- Theory," in Jolin Eatwell et Dictionary of Economics, Stockton Press, III," in New al. (editors): York, 1987. The Economics of Bargaining, Blackwell. Binmore in [4] "Game Binmore, K. (1987): "Nash bargaining theory tors): [3] (1987): K., A. Rubinstein and A. WoUnsky (1986): "The Nash bargaining solution economic modelling," Rand Journal of Economics, 17, 176-188. Coase, R. (1972): "Dmrabihty and monopoly," Journal of Law and Economics, 15, 143-149. [5] Edgeworth, F. (1881): Mathematical Pschics: An Essay on the Application of Math- ematics to the Moral Sciences, Harvard University Press. [6] Gale (1986): "Bargaining and Competition Part [7] Gale (1987): "Limit theorems Economic Theory, [8] for I," Econometrica, 54, 785-806. markets with sequential bargaining," Journal of 43, 20-54. Fudenberg, D., D. Levine, and J. Tirole (1985): models of bar- "Infinite-horizon gaining with one-sided incomplete information," in Roth (editor): Game- Theoretic Models of Bargaining, Cambridge University Press. [9] Gul, H. Sonnenschein, F., monopoly and the Coase [10] Harsanyi, J. (1986): conjecture," Journal of (1977): Rational Behaviour Social Situations, [11] and R. Wilson Cambridge University "Foundations of dynamic Economic Theory, 39; 155-190. and Bargaining Equilibria in Games and Press, Cambridge. Hurwicz, L. (1979): "Outcome functions yielding Wahasian and Lindahl allocations at Nash equilibrium points for two or more agents," Review of Economic Studies, 46, 217-225. [12] Nash, J. [13] Perry, M. and cally F. (1950): timed P. "The bargaining problem," Econometrica, Reny offers," (1993): 18, 155-162. "A non-cooperative bargaining model with Journal of Economic Theory, 59, 50-77. 19 strategi- [14] Osborne, M. and A. Rubinstein (1990): Bargaining and Markets, Academic Press. [15] Rubinstein, A. (1982): "Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model," Econometrica, 50-1, 97-110. [16] Rubinstein, A. and A. Wolinsky (1990): "Decentralized trading, strategic behavior, and the Walrasian outcome," The Review of Economic [17] Studies, 57-1, 63-78. Schmeidler, D. (1980): "Walrasian analysis via strategic outcome functions," Econometrica, 48-7, 1585-1593. [18] Sertel, M. and M. Yildiz (1994): solution," forthcoming in Koray, S. "The impossibility of a Wah-asian bargaining and M. Sertel (editors): Advances in Economic Design, Springer, Heidelberg, 2001, [19] Smith, L. and E. Stacchetti (2001): "Aspirational Bargaining," University of Michigan, mimeo. / 20 Date Due |^<i|bJ MIT LIBRARIES 3 9080 02527 8869