Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/onirrelevanceoftOOsmit DEWEY HB31 .M415 working paper department of economics ON THE IRRELEVANCE OF TRADE TIMING Lones Smith 96-6 Feb. 1996 massachusetts institute of technology 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass. 02139 ON THE IRRELEVANCE OF TRADE TIMING Lones Smith 96-6 Feb. 1996 13 1996 96-6 On the Irrelevance of Trade Timing* Lones Smith^ Department of Economics Massachusetts Institute of Technology MA 02139 Cambridge, February 1996 4, Abstract Given standard, transparent assumptions, Street adage that 'timing is everything'. I this paper questions the Wall show that for a 'small' risk-neutral trader with private information that dependent of the public information is an Arrow is security, conditionally in- exactly indifferent about the timing of his trade: His expected return per dollar invested is a martingale. This is true despite the fact that he expects the asset price itself to rise given favorable information and I fall given unfavorable information. demonstrate the result in generality and point out that the Arrow security assumption cannot be relaxed: With compound securities paying on two there is states, a (generically strict) preference to trade immediately, while for more general assets, the result is ambivalent — one may even wish to delay trading! *I owe special thanks to Massimiliano Amarantefor proving a key inequality (A). I am also grateful to Glenn Ellison for inquiring of an economic interpretation of the 'conditional martingale' used in an early version of Smith and S0rensen (1996), and to Angel Serrat Tubert for helping me clarify my thoughts. I have likewise profited from comments on the Usenet group sci. math. research including Dan Cass (S.J.F.C. in Rochester), and especially Drazen Pantic (University of Belgrade) for extending the proof of the timing irrelevance proposition to nondiscrete measures. Finally, I thank Peter DeMarzo, Thomas Piketty, Paul Samuelson, Peter Sorensen, Jiang Wiang, and Richard Zeckhauser for helpful feedback. I acknowledge the NSF for financial support. Any errors and opinions expressed are mine alone. ^e-mail address: lonesQlones.mit.edu — 1. 'Timing is everything' has remarkably little is to say INTRODUCTION a popular refrain on Wall Street. Yet the finance literature about a topic that is deemed of supreme importance among This paper attempts to redress this anomaly, by inquiring of the applied practitioners. As purely informational motives for trade timing. such, I When trader with no strategic reasons to time his trade. consider the problem of a small his 'informational edge' over is the market maximized? To fix ideas, consider the following hypothetical scenario. A corporate insider of a biotech firm has gotten wind of an announcement next Friday of the unexpected The approval of his firm's soon-to-be major drug. this information. 1 Of insider naturally wishes to profit FDA from course, in theory there are obscenely large arbitrage opportunities: Indeed, by buying on slim enough margins, the insider can expect to reap tremendous So suppose profits. that will ring truer amount of for whatever reason that he cannot buy on margin when I consider only imperfect information. 2 Let money with which to invest, that his purchases do not affect the price. restriction him have a given by buying stocks, and assume he When —a is poor enough should he purchase? Typical gut instincts argue in favor of buying immediately. Indeed, at one obvious level, delay only sees the depreciation of his informational advantage, as he expects the price to start rising. But that is not the issue here, as the trader cares not so much about the asset price as its reciprocal, the return (or his 'bang per buck'). By this yardstick, I now wish to make the ent assumptions, so long as his timing completely irrelevant^. To is in advance of the public announcement, 'low' states Discounting is H, initial asset price. 1. He wishes buy ^his example that 2 it L, respectively, ignored, is The asset pays off 1 or zero in the 'high' = 1 - T(L) € (0, 1) is given. so that po = 7(H) is also the and the prior chance 7(H) and traders are assumed risk neutral, Let the insider discover his private information that the payoff will be as many shares as his wealth will permit, and being 'small', this activity for illustrative purposes only, and neither endorses such trading activity, nor suggests actually occurs. More it is illustrate this hopefully striking proposition, let's consider the following simple two-period, two-state model. and point that under standard and transpar- generally, with unfavorable information, assume he likewise faces a short sale constraint. will not affect the price. If he purchases immediately, his return per dollar will be 1/po- he waits until the next period's public information of a public signal a H whose outcome or L, then the expect price the insider's expected return 4 next price p\, namely In this paper, timing is I ' . . . , higher: E\p\ is is in {cri, an } \ revealed, namely the announcement correlated with the state of the world is H] unchanged! For is = ££=1 7{o k H)7(H | it If | ok ) >p 3 But . equals the expected reciprocal of the 5 wish to explore the generality of this observation. Obviously, trade not always moot. For one, the insider here has perfect information. The paper formulates and proves the timing irrelevance proposition for any partially informed trader — so long as his information is conditionally the true state of the world. assumption in the It independent of the public information given must be underscored that literature. It so happens that the this is the standard regularity on the asset being a pure result turns 'Arrow security', paying a dividend of $1 in one state of the world, and one ventures outside this domain, In fact, with compound bundles I can show that timing irrelevance no longer prevails. of two Arrow a (generically securities, there is preference to trade immediately on any private information, while the result for more general Let me securities: I briefly explore the show by example that one may even wish economics of expectation, even though the price is is my main expected to rise result. benefits price is Why is is strict) ambivalent to delay trading! the return constant in (with favorable information)? There a simple perhaps well-known intuition that at least more favorable than the justifies price process: Since the return why is strictly the return process convex in the from the riskiness of the stochastic price movements. For instance, if price, tomorrow, while the expected return is flat But why then does the at 3. 3 This intuitive result follows from the Cauchy-Schwartz inequality (J2 a kb k ) 2 put a k = 7{H n a k )ly/7{^) and b k = The identity sums 5 One might hazard ^). over all 'possible' it > 1/3 benefit exactly < (£ a fc)C>*)» ^ we public signals a k namely those with with 7((J k , is the current 1/3, an equal chance of moving to 1/2 or 1/4 leaves the expected price at 3/8 4 Once elsewhere. D H) > 0. that with a longer time horizon, the trader could learn from early public signals to better time his trade; but this conjecture is false, for the basic two-period logic can just as well be iterated into the future. cancel out the expected rise in the price? Here, is I have not found any deeper intuition than suggested by a close reading of the above example: the vector of possible prices next period is proportional to the vector of quotients of conditional and unconditional signal — the dot product probabilities, or 7(H\o}.) oc 7{ak\H)/7{ok)- Thus, the expected return — and the vector of conditional signal chances of the return vector signal distribution; since the expected return is unchanged independent of the is for signals that are pure noise, the result follows. This intuition extends to the case of partial information in the paper. The finance literature has been very focused in First, there is American call what it has to say about trade timing. 6 a large and well-established literature on option pricing, especially for the and put options. The exercise date of such an instrument and one may optimally wish to exercise this is relevant only insofar as it it before is expiration date. its a choice variable, For my purposes, represents a single-person decision problem dealing with timing a discrete trade. But in two absolutely crucial respects, the option pricing problem is a different beast: It is concerned not with returns but with prices, and more crucially, the interaction between private and public information is a non-issue for option pricing. For this reason, timing work in Ross (1989) on the phenomenon of 'uncertainty resolution irrelevancy', is also not relevant here Second, there — and my resolution date is assumed known, anyway. a large and growing literature on the optimal timing of trades when is faced with strategic considerations. See, for instance, Kyle (1985) and (1989), Pfleiderer (1989), to my and more thrust here recently, Smith (1995). This — which concerns a 'small trader' line of work is clearly orthogonal effect. Third, there has been work on market timing based on returns, but at a heuristic level than here. which uses it is CAPM The best paper of this genre The next I have seen here (APT) rather than the arbitrage pricing theory enlightening to read that literature knowing section describes a plain vanilla my main model in Admati and as I is much more Merton (1981), have. If anything, result. which I can state and prove both the timing irrelevance proposition for Arrow securities and a timing impatience proposition for compound securities on two states. trading for a three state security! 6 I An example follows with a strict preference to delay close with a conclusion and a mathematical appendix. See Duffie (1992) or Merton (1990) for references, a discussion of this point, and a glimpse at attention the mainstream finance literature has paid to issues of timing. little how THE FORMAL MODEL AND RESULTS 2. To be • Information Structure. build on the state space now standard Q, is assumed analysis (unlike sigma algebra on space variables a : —) later is done by treating E also as admit general signal spaces. tedious, so I I shall instead discrete, shall therefore define S, the all 'signal events'. u = Let G {0,cr) The 17. simply think of the signals as stochastic 8 mapping the payoff-relevant state space into the signal events 7 be the common prior probability trader with the starring role in this paper and observes r, a public signal an G SG Beyond the primary in particular that r . . . is initially G S about the state of the world All signals r, o\, 02, (I) as the my inferences about 6. Finally, let informative signal x E. Think of (or, Bayesian traders observing a realization of a will be able to make signal outcomes). The small = fl The will also somewhat Q, is components — namely, the space of S shall as the space of payoff irrelevant signals realizations. While no harm finite. MS) £ I model of Milgrom and Stokey (MS) and partition the (1982) into two statistically-related payoff relevant states, and set deliberately uncontroversial at this stage, T G S. In endowed with a private periods n realized. Crucially, is are independent, conditional assertion that the private measure on fL on each = I 1, 2, is . . , N, assume that G state 6k and public information . conditionally independent, this also precludes any distracting incentives the trader might have to try to learn from early public signal realizations be the sigma-field generated by the within §„ is S, or equivalently also first and make inferences about future ones. Let §„ n signals (<Xi,. . . , <x„). Thus, (S„) a progressively refined sub-sigma-field of S. is a filtration (So every event in an event in S n+ i, for instance.) • Payoffs and Prices. Let the payoff function of the asset be n : 1-4 E, realized and observed in period iV (a known date), with no discounting until then. So the price of the asset at the is end of period n is the expected asset payoff, or the standard assumption that the asset As usual, the random is efficiently pn = £[7r|S n ]. Embedded priced given risk neutral traders. must be price process (p n ) corresponding to the filtration (S n ) a martingale (when adapted to (§„)). That is, pm here = £[p n |§m] for all n > m. This implies that there are no arbitrage opportunities on the basis of public information alone. But given one's private information, one anticipates a period by period erosion in one's informational edge. Indeed, the following result Lemma Under assumption I, prices (Prices) not surprising (and is are expected to move its proof omitted). in the direction of private information: £(7r|S n ,T)|£[£(7r|S n+1 ,T)|S n ,r] as the private information r G T is favorable or unfavorable, or £(7r|S n ,T) ^ £(7r|S n ). So on price considerations alone, the individual ought to trade right away on his private information, regardless of the informational structure. than the market, then he the purchase price is is always expected to * Timing Irrelevance. is If the trader is ever more optimistic by the conditional independence of the so, so rise, As noted now is earlier, signals. But the anticipated cheapest time to buy. the preceding logic is not relevant if one simply trying to invest a given amount. Rather, one cares about the return per dollar. This say, is true even for short-selling and — namely, buying negative units of the share worth $1 by buying the shares back later netting out In this general setting, the after the asset value is realized. most far-reaching timing irrelevance claim would hold that the return of an investment of $1 in period n equals the expected payoff from deferring this investment one period, namely £[7r|S n This conjecture is false. I = ,T]/p n shall n is simply too — namely, one in rich. which n = What l 6o , securities are linear combinations of The reason must do I — 1 if Arrow Proposition 1 (Timing Irrelevance) amount \S n ,T] ] is its failure, restrict focus to is 9 = O, and securities. some will point out a pure Arrow security state 8 £ ©• Such a otherwise. General With this motivation, Under assumption I, a to invest is indifferent about and that the range of the space of payoff the 'indicator function' on simple security awards a payoff n(0) with a fixed ,T]/pn+1 soon explore the nature of that the inequality can go either way. functions £[£[7r|S n+1 how he times compound we have partially informed trader his trades of an Arrow security: (P(0o|Sn,T)/(P(0o|Sn) = £[y(0o|§n + i,T)/:P(0o|S„ + i) |S„,T]. (1) The proposition proved in the appendix, but right here is space E, where the argument is less general but certainly assume a discrete signal more transparent. = about the multiple periods, and simply denote S forget shall I {Si, 52, . . . , In particular, Sm }• Thus, S and mutually exclusive partition of S, one of whose elements totally exhaustive Then given information t E T, publicly observed next period. period for an Arrow security Iff coincides with its will a be the expected return next current return, since = Y,V{Sm\T)V{H\Sm ,T)/7{H\Sm E[P{H\Sm ,T)/y(H\Sn )\T\ is ) m = VPK m y{Sm \H,T)?{H\T)l'S>{S \H)9(H)/nS ^ = V9K ^ ml { { nSm ' ° ml{T)] rn \T) m) nSm\H)?(H\T)/nSm \T) 9(Sm \H)1>(H)/nsm ) = ?(H\T)/7(H)Y 7(Sm) / m = 9(H\T)/7{H) where all steps are simplifications except the middle equality, which conditional independence, namely The of T given of state state H Sm Sm )/7(H\Sm . The ) is now more next period T H, or T(5rn H',T)/y(5m |T) J involved. really a is vector of such premia given information is proportional to the signal likelihood ratio • y(Sm )/J>(Sm \H). So = 7(Sm \H), the dot product of the informational premium vector and this time, provided conditional this reduces to T(5m )/0 (5m |T) 5 — and the conditional likelihood vector independent of the signal distribution, as in the introduction. • Trading Impatience with Two-State Securities. conditional independence assumption 'clearly' drives the result. showing that the Arrow security restriction is Proposition 2 (Trading Impatience) securities, one has a One might argue I now that the refute such logic, by absolutely crucial. For two state securities, the natural intuition that traders prefer to trade at once Arrow public signal-dependent measure of an informational premium independence holds, or 7(Sm \H,T) is The divided by the unconditional signal likelihood ratio of | (7(Sm \T)) the statement of 7(Sm \H,T) = 7(Sm \H). intuition in the introduction return 7(H\T, is is valid. For (generic) assets that bundle together two (strict) incentive to trade immediately on any information. Proof: Let the compound For simplicity, security let's restrict pay out 7r(^) in state 0(, with tt(8i) ^ n(6 2 )7 Rephrasing the desired focus to discrete signal spaces. highest immediately. we wish to show that This statement is simultaneously captured for both favorable information (stock purchase) result, the per dollar return exceeds one, if and unfavorable information by the twin (short sale) it is inequalities, £[7r|r]/pog£MT,8]M|l These initial and = final returns are (resp.) £[tt\T]/ Pq c[v\T,S]/pi = 2^-y{Sm\T) ^ . J2e ?(0e\T)n(6e ) / J^t r— . (2) W) ^) and 7 . ( T,inSm\ei)y(dt )ir(et )/7{sm ) ^ ^ With only yt = M = it suffices to {p m } and {qm } that each + - 2/2 Zl+ Z2 Z/i nsrn\0iWt\TM9t)3: t nsm\6iWt) = pm = show that for sum we have , to ft (1 1, - \ ar)g any x 6 \Pmyi m) PmZ\ 771 (0, 1), y,, Z{ = (1 0, / is , s - x)(y2 /z2 ) . ,, (1 / is irrelevant exactly '7 '(h) = two Arrow securities have the same • the two Arrow securities are informationally indistinguishable: 7(B m \8i) timing is irrelevant, initial return: 3>(0i|T)/ more general compound securities, the result example showing that with three 7 Compound and with two-state states, Otherwise, the states can be merged. one securities, may go may = \r - x)(y 2 /z 2 • the securities, = 1. ?{0i), So to r t.\ \ ) (A) thus established in the appendix. proof of (a) also shows that timing * Timing Ambivalence with General x tP(S m |^ 2 ), and nonnegative weights + qm y2 > ^ *(yiM) + + qm Z2 § This nifty dual inequality happens to be new, and Remark. The ' + > (3) [ e) 9(& m \8i), Qm 7(9e )n(8e ). Notice that x(yi/zi) s >v + | 2^{xPm *—* / nSm \eeP(Ge)n(e J2 e 2 states, simply define 7{6e \T)Tr(ee ), and ze establish (2), ?: e either way. in fact I now either: 7(0 2 \T)/7{6 2 ) Securities. impatience when <C> is = 7(§m\8 2 ) With Arrow the rule. With provide a minimal wish to delay trading, pending 8 observation of the public information. Let the payoffs instates 6\, 6 2 and #3 be n(8\) , n(9 2 ) = 7(6 = X ) trader = = 1/48, 7(8 2 \T) The £[tt] = = 40/96, 7(8 3 ) = (1/96)96 + = 96/11 = = 25/48, 7(9 3 \T) 55/96 are chosen to yield a neat (40/96)9.6 [(1/48)96 + = + + public signal realization between the two periods public beliefs towards state 6 2 and * it is A Arrow securities, the away from 845/768 which very hood A„ n > m. A ratios, if closely related and ir: then A m = is is = | So, state. 9 all n For instance, > m. 8 The 9 See, for instance, this . a £[p„ \p m ] for law of iterated expectations , Sn ] then £[II n if qn = T(H | Il m = ] II m \ So, , Sn and ) this the conditional martingale one plus the likelihood ratio is the return on this latter martingale is formally identical to the timing irrel- paper was indeed inspired by this conditional martingale. nature of the numbers reflects the difficulty Chow, Robbins and Siegmund (1971). slightly exotic . = pm in In a theoretical exploration of herd- (ir) the unconditional martingale. Since And . i.e. by APT by lineage to the a martingale, £[7r role played Samuelson (1965). Namely, in it and evance proposition. (3) revealed before buying. is also related Smith and S0rensen (1996) have suggestively dubbed H, assumed So observing S\ tips Beyond the key ing, the asset paying $1 in state 1/2). 11/10 classic martingale stochastic process is the set of likeli- £[A n X m ,H] for | n„ (it) If one conditions on the true = (l—qn )/Qn either So or S\ with is APT is a consequence of the applied to the ultimate asset payoff for all = slightly exceeds the initial return of 1.1, timing irrelevance proposition stylized level, the + 5 + 4)/10 = . Ross (1976) or the primal version of n > m. At a 10 and 8 3 Plugging the above data into 8\ risk-neutral economy, the sequence (p n ) of prices all initial asset price +4+5= 1 (2 and (1/2,3/4, Link to the Arbitrage Theory of Pricing. — either in = optimal to wait until the public information strictly prior beliefs in posterior beliefs T(9i \T) (ll/24)(96/ll)]/10 respective state-dependent chances (1/2, 1/4, 1/2) and so = (55/96)(96/ll) 96, 11/24. This yields the neat expected return per dollar (25/48)9.6 yields an expected return of Common 8.73, respectively. assumed to have information r G T, resulting is £[7r|T]/po and n(8 3 ) 9.6, 1/96, 7(8 2 ) Po The = 48/5 = of constructing the example. CONCLUDING REMARKS 3. • Apologetics. Almost as firm as the new skepticism of simple this proposition is disbelief; (ii) 'of course it nontrivially true, but the question posed paper has addressed the fails (i) no first and very natural (the lunch exists, is must be my claim is most natural, is economists' true'; or (Hi) yes, the not relevant. I believe that the response by proof, and the second by showing absent the Arrow security restriction. At any rate, For the third reaction, free appear surprising. Reactions to earlier versions of results that paper have thus been belief that I I feel how the result the question itself is novel. humble: This paper merely explores a transparent feel) thought experiment in financial timing. Are there purely informational reasons that private information rationally be traded upon without haste, or for otherwise timing one's trade? As with any economic model, role played this paper is meant to sharpen our understanding of the by the driving assumptions. Previous work on endogenous timing of trades has either focused on models of pure public information, or confounded strategic effects with pure timing considerations. 'small trader'. The key rather than prices, is finite I have sidestepped strategic effects by focusing on a wealth assumption, which suggested the focus on returns only a natural corollary of 'smallness'. But surely any timing model ought to be robust to the simple calculus of when best to invest a dollar. Since a small trader's information is not impacted in the price, this also precludes applying insights from Radner (1979), that the equilibrium will be fully revealing the Arrow-Debreu securities are traded. 10 This is concerning the states for which reasonable as I am simply studying the single-person decision problem. * Lessons of the Paper. This paper has been a simple economic exploration of how the interaction of private with public information affects the timing of trades. Within the maintained small trader world, the conditionally independent. This is timing papers but also in classics alternative is critical assumption is that private and public signals are almost universally posited, not only in most strategic like Grossman and that private and public information is Stiglitz (1980). The tautological conditionally correlated. While by no means technically appealing, many plausible information structures produce just 10 But see Geanakoplos (1990) for further discussion. this result. For instance, if distinct traders learn of different profitability of the firm is the sum components of a firm, and if the of the profitability of the separate parts, then given the value of the firm, the separate signals are 'conditionally correlated'. A curious application of the paper One may wish is in the problem of optimal design of a security: noncompound Arrow to choose a security simply because it assures there are no perverse incentives for the delay of informational revelation. Smith (1995) has recently studied endogenous trading One lesson of this paper is that 'frenzies' in a a strategic setting. — correlated information or compound securities aside — strategic considerations (or other large trader effects) are the only rational explanations attempts to 'time one's trade'. for Finally, I feel the inviting mathematical similarity between the arbitrage pricing theory and the timing irrelevance proposition and the pivotal role of Arrow securities in each may speak to a deeper underlying connection, and merits further investigation. A. APPENDIX • General Proof of Proposition addresses concerns that my This proof 1. is for completeness, but also application of conditional independence may take special ad- vantage of a discrete public signal space. Let SjT be the sigma-algebra y(SnT|0 o ,SnW0o|Sn) = S£ S n +i, we have SDT6 / JsnT {Tn5|5 G S fc }. Assumption ?(T\8 ,S n )9{S\6 ,& n )V(8 \& n ) = I justifies y(SnTndo\S n = ) 7{T\8 Q ,S n )?(S n 6 S„+i, and thus O>(0o|Cu).<& = [ h>dJ> JsnT = y(Snrn0o |S») = y(T\e ,s n )?{sne = y(T\eo ,s n \B n ) o \s n )dy )J'?(0 = ?(T\6Q ,S n ) 10 o \8 n+1 )dV, J 7(0 \8 n ). For since SE S n +i- Hence / As 5 G S n +i is y{&o\Bl+1 )i T dy = arbitrary and 35 (^ |Sn+i) y{T\e Q s„) , is ?(e J \s n+1 ) d?. an S„+i -measurable function, this is equivalent to WolCi) n T|S»+i] = 3Wo,S„M0 o |S B+ i). by definition of a conditional expectation. Dividing both sides by 7(8o\S n+ i) yields 11 «, , mfl , P(«+ e.[7(e \sl+1 )i T \B n ] __ i)Ir Sn+i T(^o|S n +i) since (P(#o|Sn+i) a S n+ i-measurable function. Taking expectations, is I have ^•j-XSfef* Bayes rule to the LHS, and use the definition of a conditional expectation Finally, apply on the RHS, to get 7{6 \S n ,T)/?(e \S n ) • Proof of Inequality ( A) holds. Assume Next, set ^= E PrnVl p* l PmZl first step is to prove a=y,p< we \i rather illustrative, as f°r otherwise it shows when equality double equality must hold in (A). define + gm3/2 + qm Z2 5 = VJ qv and gmj/l X PmZ\ + Qm V2 +qm Z2 + y2) / (zi + Z2) ^ xA + (l — x)B ^ x(yi/zi) + (1 — x) (1/2/^2)that B > A, with B > A generically. Too see this, write then we wish to show that The If E.[9(6 \SZ+1 )/9(6 \S n+1 ) |S„,T], as required. The proof is . WLOG that 3/2/^2 > IJil z A = j/2/^2 — 2/i/^i- = (yi + gmj/gCj/l/fl + Pm2l + 9m ^2 PmiVl/ Zl)Z! A)z2 = 2/iM +A E Pmgm*2 PmZ\ and likewise 2 B= 11 Note that CP(^o|S^+1 ) > since y /z l l is finite + A^2 QmZ2 PmZ\ + qm z2 and includes no zero chance 11 states. + qm Z2 Hence, S-A=A (qm > m -Pm)qmZ2 A V"^/ =A > 9m - Pm) PmZl+qm Z2 (qm 2 -Pm) x __ ^ final equality ' Z2 + \Z\+Z2 - p m )z\Z2 z 2 )(p Tn Zi+qTn z2 (qm {zi+ ) ZlZ 2 (zi+z2 )(p m zi+qm z2 where the " ( ) holds since Y^ m P™ = ^m Q™- So B> A, unless pm = qm for all m. Simple calculation reveals that the critical = threshold x x = z2 /(z\ equality in (a). There are two immediate consequences: First, since that B> + z2 ) yields double we have just shown A, we have y±±yi^ xA+ {i-x)B < zi+z2 as x ^ yi/zi x. Second, because B > A, and and y2 /z2 we must have y2 /z2 , A >B > and B are clearly each weighted averages of A> y\jz\. It is then intuitive, and also easily verified, that xA + for x ^ - x)B | x{ yi / Zl ) + (1 - x)(y2 /z2 ) x. Finally, in (A) (1 x = x corresponds can only hold if A = 7{e 2 \T)iy{e 2 ) or y{S m \0i) = to 7r(#i) or pm 7(S m \e 2 ) = n(6 2 ), which has been ruled out. Thus, equality = qm for all for all 12 m, as m. This reduces to 7(6i\T)/7(6i) required. = MIT LIBRARIES 3 9080 00939 9517 References Admati, Anat and Paul Pfleiderer, "A Theory of Intraday Patterns: Price Stability," Review of Financial Studies, 1989, 1, Volume and 3-40. Herbert Robbins, and David Siegmund, Great Expectations: The Theory of Optimal Stopping, Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1971. Duffle, Darrell, Dynamic Asset Pricing Theory, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Chow, Y. S., Press, 1992. Geanakoplos, John, "An Introduction to General Equilibrium with Incomplete Markets," Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1990, 19, 1-38. Grossman, Sanford J. and Joseph E. Stiglitz, "On the Impossibility of Informationally Efficient Markets," American Economic Review, 1980, 70, 393-408. Kyle, Albert S., "Continuous Auctions and Insider Trading," Econometrica, 1985, 53, 1315-1335. — "Informed Speculation with Imperfect Competition," Review of Economic Studies, 1989, 56, 317-356. , Merton, Robert — C., "On Market Timing and Investment Performance, I. An Equilibrium Theory of Value for Market Forecasts," 1981, 54, 363-406. Continuous-time Finance, 2nd ed., Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1990. , Milgrom, Paul and Nancy Stokey, "Information, Trade, and Common Knowledge," Journal of Economic Theory, 1982, 26, 17-27. Equilibrium: Generic Existence and the Information Revealed by Prices," Econometrica, 1979, ^7, 655-678. Radner, Roy, "Rational Expectations Ross, Stephen A., "The Arbitrage Theory of Capital Asset Pricing," Journal of Economic Theory, 1976, 3, 343-362. — "Information and Volatility: The No- Arbitrage Martingale Approach to Timing and , Resolution Irrelevancy," 1989, 44, 1-17. Samuelson, Paul A., "Proof that Properly Anticipated Prices Fluctuate Randomly," 1965, 6, 41-63. Smith, Lones, "Do Rational Traders Frenzy?," 1995. MIT mimeo. — and Peter S0rensen, "Pathological Outcomes of Observational Learning," 1996. MIT Working Paper. 13 Date Due AWL 8 M996 Lib-26-67