Investment Busts, Reputation, and the Temptation to Blend in with the Crowd∗ Steven R. Grenadier Andrey Malenko Ilya A. Strebulaev Stanford GSB MIT Sloan Stanford GSB September 2011 PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE COMMENTS WELCOME We thank seminar participants at Stanford University for their helpful comments. We are responsible for all remaining errors. Address for correspondence: Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, 518 Memorial Way, Stanford, CA, 94305. Grenadier: sgren@stanford.edu; Malenko: amalenko@mit.edu; Strebulaev: istrebulaev@stanford.edu. ∗ 1 Abstract Real investment decisions can be substantially affected by the temptation of managers to blend in with the crowd and delay liquidation of unsuccessful projects. As we show, this could have a far-reaching repercussions for the dynamics of whole industries and conceivably for the economy at large. The underlying mechanism is the link between managerial reputation based on the available information about the current project outcome and managerial payoffs from attracting future funding recourses and future project cash flows. If liquidation of a current project reveals negative information about ability, the manager will optimally delay abandonment decisions to make it more difficult for the market to judge managerial ability correctly. In a dynamic model, we show how this simple intuition can lead to amplification of modest negative shocks and explain such phenomenon as industry-specific investment busts. 2 1 Introduction None love the messenger who brings bad news. Love can be even harder to find if the bad news speaks ill of the messenger’s abilities. When corporate managers face the unappealing task of revealing unsuccessful outcomes that impact their reputations, delay may be their first instinct.1 Delay becomes even more enticing if they can wait for industry-wide downturns in order to hide individual failings and instead “blend in with the crowd”. In this paper we argue that real investment decisions can be substantially affected by the temptation to blend in with the crowd. More importantly, this could have a far-reaching repercussions for the dynamics of whole industries and conceivably for the economy at large. To appreciate the simplicity and generality of our intuition, consider an example from the venture-capital industry. Entrepreneurs care not just about the payoffs on current projects, but also about their reputations, which is critical in attracting future funding sources. Thus, perception of one’s ability by outsiders links the payoff on a current project with future payoffs. Now suppose an entrepreneur realizes that a project is likely to never pay off, and thus should be scrapped. However, if liquidation reveals negative information about her ability, she will reconsider the decision to scrap the project. First, she may delay her liquidation decision simply hoping for some potential resurrection of the project’s fortunes. Second, and more importantly, by delaying she may hope to time her decision so that it would be more difficult for the market to judge her low ability correctly. She may strategically attempt to blend in with the crowd at a time when higher-ability managers have to liquidate their projects as well, either during a recession or a negative industry-wide shock. In such a case she can successfully hide the negative information, avoiding truthful revelation altogether. Such behavior leads to inefficiently low liquidation and the continued survival of projects which, on the basis of economics alone, should long ago have been liquidated. This intuition is not constrained to entrepreneurial firms. General partners of private equity funds get up to 50% of their compensation from future funds they 1 See e.g. Miller (2002) and Kothari, Shu, and Wysocki (2009). 3 will run (Chung, Sensoy, Stern, and Weisbach (2010)). If they realize that their current fund is not doing well, they may want to delay liquidating their unsuccessful investments until the time when other funds have to liquidate as well. Bank loan officers may have substantial private information about the performance of the loans they authorized in the first place and they may delay foreclosing on a bad loan for fear of losing their reputation and job until the time recession hits and loan’s poor performance could be attributed to systematic factors rather than their screening and monitoring abilities. Strategic delay decisions of individual managers, who attempt to blend in with the crowd, may have far-reaching consequences for their industries. In particular, even relatively small negative market-wide shocks could launch an avalanche of liquidations and lead to investment busts. While one may view a sudden and severe economic downturn as causing massive failures, it may in fact be mostly revealing past failures that were waiting for an opportune time to be revealed. Thus, this economic mechanism can explain the magnitude of cyclicality of investment activity which we observe in many industries, such as VC, banking, and real estate. In order to explore this economic mechanism in detail, we build a continuous-time dynamic signaling model that formalizes the blending in with the crowd intuition and investigate whether relatively small shocks can lead to disproportionately large liquidations. Because our goal is to understand the efficiency of investment liquidation, our starting point is the cross-section of projects that have already been funded and running. A project’s expected payoff consists of an idiosyncratic project-specific component (some projects are inherently less likely to be successful) as well as a component that depends on the ability of managers who run them. We assume that projects are either successful (with a random arrival of payoff) or unsuccessful (payoff never arrives). Neither the manager nor outside investors know the type of the project, and gradually adjust their beliefs about the project’s type in a Bayesian manner. Only managers, however, know their abilities. Outsiders are initially aware only about the distribution of ability in the total pool of projects and subsequently either observe managerial ability at the time of the project’s successful payoff or learn about it by observing managerial liquidation decisions (or lack of them). 4 By operating projects managers incur running costs, which proxy not only for the direct financing costs but also for indirect costs, such as lost opportunities elsewhere. If these costs are the same across projects, then we should expect low ability managers to liquidate their projects first. Consider the trade-off that a low-ability manager faces. By liquidating the project now she saves on the running costs of the project but at the same time she reveals her low quality which adversely impacts her reputation and thus future returns. This trade-off naturally leads to a single-jamming equilibrium, in which managers strategically delay liquidation, but are in fact not able to hide their true ability from the market upon liquidation (Grenadier and Malenko, 2011). Now consider what happens in the presence of negative market-wide shocks which cause a liquidation of a fraction of all projects, irrespective of their characteristics. A low ability manager has an additional incentive to delay because now she has an opportunity to hide her true quality by liquidating at the same time as other managers and blaming the market-wide shock. We find that the presence of systematic shocks has two effects on industry dynamics. First, strategic delays caused by the temptation to blend in may cause a substantial increase in inefficient liquidation. Second, at the time of the market-wide shock, the liquidation rate can be disproportionately large relative to the size of the shock. This mechanism can thus explain commonly observed dynamics in such different industries as venture capital, real estate, and banking. Over a long period of time, the incidence of negative outcomes and “news” can be unusually low. This period is then followed by an investment bust with a very high rate of mortality among projects. A typical explanation of this phenomena involves either markets’ unreasonable optimism (say, about the prospects of a particular industry or technology), followed by the participants “waking up” to more sorrow prospects, or the availability of “cheap” credit which feeds bad projects until a large macroeconomic downturn limits the availability of capital dramatically. Our simple and intuitively clear mechanism can explain such a phenomenon when the markets are rational and when the market-wide shocks are relatively small. An important implication of our results is that the temptation of individual man5 agers to blend in can serve as a multiplier effect in industry- and economy-wide movements. For practical purposes, it could therefore be important to consider what contractual and institutional mechanisms could limit the opportunity of managers to blend in. Our paper relates to several strands in the literature. Psychological research has demonstrated that people tend to overinvest suboptimally in loss-making situations, a trait called escalation of commitment or sunk cost fallacy (Arkes and Blumer (1985), Staw and Hoang (1995)). Escalation of commitment has been shown to be particularly pervasive is scenarios when additional investment can lead to the return of the original investment (known as “gamble for resurrection”). Our mechanism provides a rational interpretation of the escalation of commitment when managers find it optimal to overinvest by attempting to blend in with the crowd later on. Rajan (1994) builds a 2-period banking model with an inefficient delay of loan liquidations in normal times. In his model, in the adverse economy all loans are the same (bad) quality and the private information of banks drives loans liquidations. In our mechanism, differential ability of managers and loans and the belief of the market play the crucial role. A recent literature on dynamic lemons markets (e.g. Kurlat (2010)) consider the case of buyers and sellers who choose to trade in the market when there are many liquidity traders and the adverse selection problem is not as severe. In this literature, high liquidity is good in the sense that entrepreneurs can sell their projects to raise capital for the new ones. Thus, high liquidity is associated with economic expansions and low liquidity is associated with economic contractions. In our paper, negative economic shocks are associated with forced liquidations. Acharya, DeMarzo, and Kremer (forthcoming) consider a model of dynamic disclosure. In their model, a public shock reduces the value of the option to delay disclosure and thereby leads to a wave in disclosures of bad information. There is no blending in with the crowd effect because disclosure is assumed to be truthful (as in the standard disclosure models). 6 2 Model Setup In this section, we discuss the main ingredients of the model and the economic rationale behind our setup. Our goal is to explore the economic mechanism of “blending in” by building a simple model that intuitively relates to a number of features observed in the real world. Consider an entrepreneur (or manager) operating an investment project. The manager is characterized by her ability, represented by θ, which is private information of the manager. The manager’s investment project can be successful (with probability p0 ) or unsuccessful (with probability 1 − p0 ). A successful project provides a payoff of θ > 0 at a Poisson event which arrives with intensity λ > 0. Outsiders do not know θ except for its prior distribution, which is common knowledge. It is given by p.d.f. f (θ) and c.d.f. F (θ) with full support on θ, θ̄ . By contrast, an unsuccessful project never pays off. Waiting for a project to pay off requires a cash outflow of c per unit time. The manager learns about the quality of her investment project over time and decides on the optimal timing of liquidation. The discount rate is equal to r ∈ (0, λ). The model of an individual entrepreneurial project thus contains four main ingredients: ability level θ, success probability p0 , success intensity λ, and waiting cost c. All these ingredients have close equivalents in the business world. As an example, consider financing entrepreneurial start-ups. As entrepreneurs typically know more about their abilities and project’s potential is driven in large part by the quality of start-up teams,2 we assume that θ is both the ability level and the payoff upon successful realization and that it is private to the founders. At the same time, most start–ups fail, often for reasons unrelated to entrepreneurial ability. The likelihood of success or failure is becoming apparent over time to both managers and financiers. For example, both the managers and investors of a solar energy firm observe the 2 There is substantial literature on venture capital and entrepreneurial firms showing that quality of management teams determines in large part the outcome of the project and that VCs and angels pay a great deal of attention to the characteristics of the founders. E.g., see Busenitz and Barney (1997), Maxwell, Jeffrey, and Levesque (2011), Petty and Gruber (2011), Sudek (2006), and Zacharakis and Meyer (2000). 7 trends in the industry, but the managers are better positioned to know how large the payoff will be in the case of a particular technology or wider industry success. Start-ups also incur (frequently substantial) costs while waiting for the resolution of uncertainty. Such costs are not necessarily exclusively financial and often include the opportunity cost of the manager. The project may be liquidated at any time for two reasons. First, the project may be liquidated because the manager chooses to do so. Liquidating the project allows the manager to stop paying out the flow of c at the cost of foregoing any potential payoff of θ. Second, the project may be liquidated exogenously because it gets exposed to a market-wide (or an industry-wide) shock that impacts many firms at once. In such an event, the manager has no choice but to liquidate. The market-wide shock arrives as a Poisson event with intensity µ > 0 and is publicly observable. A given project is exposed to the market-wide shock with probability q. Whether the project is in fact exposed to the shock or not is learned by the manager, but not by the market, at the time of arrival of the shock. To illustrate an industry-wide shock, consider again the example of the solar energy industry. Although the physical outcome, electricity generation, is common across myriad of solar energy projects, technologies differ widely, and often subtle changes in technologies can produce large variation in payoff structure. A substantial reduction in the production cost of solar panels – a negative industry-wide shock – pushes some producers out of business. The propensity to fail often depends on subtle variation in technology that is difficult for outsiders to decipher. The managers are thus better equipped to learn whether such a shock negatively affects their technology. Assume that the entrepreneur cares about her reputation in the eyes of the outsiders. When a successful project pays off, all parties observe θ. For simplicity, we assume that the reputation payoff upon the project payoff is γθ, where γ > 0 is the parameter measuring the degree with which reputation-building incentives are important. However, in the event of liquidation, outsiders do not directly observe θ. Instead, at any time t prior to the payoff on an investment or a liquidation, outsiders hold the conditional expectation E [θ|It ], where It is the past history that outsiders 8 know at time t. The reputation payoff upon liquidation at time t is therefore γE [θ|It ]. The reputation payoff is the reduced-form specification of the manager’s interactions with outsiders after the given project. For example, entrepreneurs interact repeatedly with investors and, once their low ability is established, are less likely to get new funding or have access to top VCs. Of course, more sophisticated specifications of reputation-building incentives are also possible but the simple specification we employ captures succinctly the main idea behind reputation importance. Before proceeding to find optimal decisions and equilibrium solution of our model, let us identify the main economic mechanism we want to capture. Consider a manager with a relatively low θ and suppose that the market-wide shock has not arrived yet. She thinks about the following trade-off. If she exercises the liquidation option immediately, she will save on cash outflows. However, the exercise decision will reveal θ to the market which will lead to a drop in the reputation component of the manager’s utility function. If there were no market-wide shock, this would simply lead to a separating equilibrium with the single-jamming property (as in Grenadier and Malenko (2011): every type delays the liquidation decision in the hope of fooling the market into believing that her type is higher, but in equilibrium the outsiders learn θ with certainty. However, with the market-wide shock the equilibrium will be more interesting. Specifically, the entrepreneur may choose to delay optimally the exercise decision until the market-wide shock arrives and liquidate at the arrival of the shock. By doing this, she pools (blends in) with all types that liquidate at the arrival of the market-wide shock including types with high θ. We later explore how this blending in can yield a number of interesting stylized facts such as frequently observed industry-wide investment busts. 2.1 Learning Process As the success of the project is uncertain, an important state variable is the belief that the project is successful. Let p (t) denote the posterior probability at time t that the project is successful, given that the project has not paid off until time t. Over a short period between t and t + dt, the project pays off with probability λdt, conditional 9 on being successful. Hence, the posterior probability p (t + dt) conditional on not getting a payoff during [t, t + dt] is equal to: p (t + dt) = (1 − λdt) p (t) . (1 − λdt) p (t) + 1 − p (t) (1) Rewriting (1) and taking the limit dt → 0, we obtain the following differential equation: dp (t) = −λp (t) (1 − p (t)) dt, (2) with the boundary condition p (0) = p0 . (3) p0 . (1 − p0 ) eλt + p0 (4) The solution to (2) – (3) is: p (t) = The dynamics of the belief process is intuitive. As long as the project does not pay off, the belief that the project is successful decreases continuously over time. The speed of adjustment is proportional to λ, the intensity with which the successful project pays off. Once the project pays off, the belief that the project is successful jumps up to one. Note that because the private information of the manager does not enter the belief evolution process (4), the manager and outsiders always share the same belief about the success of the project. 2.2 Benchmark Case As a benchmark, consider the case of symmetric information in which outsiders also know θ. We break up the value function into two regions depending upon whether or not the market shock has yet occured. Let Vb∗ (p) and Va∗ (p) denote the value to the manager before and after the arrival of the market-wide shock, respectively, where p is the current belief that the project is successful. Working backwards in time, consider first the liquidation problem after the market-wide shock has occured. By Itô’s lemma for jump processes (see, e.g., Shreve (2004b), in the range in which 10 liquidation is not optimal the evolution of Va∗ (p) is given by dVa∗ (p) = −cdt − λp (1 − p) Va∗′ (p) dt + (θ + γθ − Va∗ (p)) dN (t) , (5) where N (t) is a point process describing the arrival of the project payoff. In (5), the first component reflects the cash outflow due to keeping the project afloat, the second component reflects the change in expected value due to learning about potential success of the project, and the last component reflects the change in expected value if the project pays off (the manager receives the project payoff θ, reputation payoff γθ, and foregoes the expected value of the project). Dividing (5) by dt, taking the expectation, and equating it with rVa∗ (p), we obtain the following differential equation: (r + λp) Va∗ (p) = −c − λp (1 − p) Va∗′ (p) + λp (1 + γ) θ. (6) Let p̂a denote the threshold at which type θ finds it optimal to liquidate the project. Equation (6) is solved subject to the following boundary conditions: Va∗ (p̂a ) = γθ, (7) Va∗′ (p̂a ) = 0. (8) The value-matching condition (7) says that at the liquidation trigger point, the manager receives her reputation payoff. The boundary condition (8 is a standard smooth-pasting condition. Evaluating (6) at the point p̂a gives us p̂a = c + rγθ . λθ (9) The comparative statics of the liquidation trigger is intuitive: the liquidation occurs earlier when the waiting cost is higher, the success intensity of the project is lower, the interest rate is higher (i.e., the opportunity cost of waiting is higher), and the reputation is more important (i.e., a higher utility from liquidating sooner and getting on with other opportunities). Before discussing the comparative statics with respect to ability, consider first 11 the problem of optimal liquidation before the arrival of the market-wide shock. The evolution of Vb∗ (p) is given by: dVb∗ (p) = −cdt − λp (1 − p) Vb∗′ (p) dt + (θ + γθ − Vb∗ (p)) dN (t) (10) + [q (γθ − Vb∗ (p)) + (1 − q) (Va∗ (p) − Vb∗ (p))] dM (t) , where M (t) is a point process describing the arrival of the market-wide shock. Compared to (5), equation (10) includes an additional term reflecting the change in expected value due to the potential arrival of the market-wide shock. Upon arrival of the market-wide shock, the project is exposed to it with probability q, in which case forced liquidation takes place, so the change in expected value is γθ − Vb∗ (p) . With probability 1 − q, the project is not exposed to the shock, in which case the change in expected value is Va∗ (p) − Vb∗ (p). Dividing (10) by dt, taking the expectation, and equating it with rVb∗ (p), we obtain the following differential equation: (r + λp + µ) Vb∗ (p) = −c−λp (1 − p) Vb∗′ (p)+λp (1 + γ) θ+µ (qγθ + (1 − q) Va∗ (p)) . (11) Let p̂b denote the threshold at which type θ finds it optimal to liquidate the project, prior to the arrival of the market shock. By analogy with (7) – (8), equation (11) is solved subject to boundary conditions Vb∗ (p̂b ) = γθ and Vb∗′ (p̂b ) = 0. Evaluating (11) at point p̂b and rearranging the terms gives us: rγθ + c = λθp̂b + µ (1 − q) (Va∗ (p̂b ) − γθ) . (12) It is easy to see that p̂b = p̂a satisfies (12). It is also the unique solution, because the right-hand side of (12) is strictly increasing in p̂b . Thus, the liquidation trigger is the same both before and after the arrival of the market-wide shock. We can denote this full-information trigger as p∗ (θ) = p̂a = p̂b . Intuitively, without information frictions between the manager and outsiders, blending in is impossible and the only consequence of the market-wide shock is to introduce noise in the liquidation process by forcing the manager to liquidate the project excessively early if her project gets 12 exposed to the shock. Although the liquidation thresholds are the same before and after the arrival of the shock, the value functions are not. Because the market-wide shock may trigger liquidation at a sub-optimal time, Vb∗ (p) < Va∗ (p) for any p above the liquidation threshold. Assuming that the starting point p0 is such that no type wants to liquidate immediately (p0 > p∗ (θ)), the optimal liquidation strategy in the benchmark case can be summarized in Proposition 1: Proposition 1. Suppose that θ is known both to the manager and outsiders. Then, the optimal trategy of the manager is to liquidate the project when p (t) decreases to trigger p∗ (θ). When the market-wide shock arrives, the project is liquidated if and only if it is exposed to the shock. Let us see how p∗ (θ) depends on θ: c d ∗ p (θ) = − 2 < 0. dθ λθ (13) We can see that the liquidation decision under symmetric information satisfies three properties. First, the equilibrium liquidation strategy is optimal in the sense that there is no other liquidation strategy that yields a higher expected payoff to the manager. Second, higher types liquidate the project later. Intuitively, if the potential payoff from the project is higher, then the manager optimally waits for a longer period before scrapping it. Finally, the market-wide shock affects liquidation if and only if the project is exposed to the shock. If the project is not exposed to the shock, then the manager never liquidates it at the time when the shock arrives. 3 Private Information Case In this section we provide the solution of the main case, in which there is asymmetric information between the manager and outsiders. Even though there is no revelation 13 of θ when the project is liquidated, outsiders will try to infer θ from observing the timing of liquidation. In turn, the manager will attempt to manipulate her liquidation decision in order to shape the belief of outsiders. Because we assume only one market-wide shock, we solve the model by backward induction. First, we consider the optimal timing of liquidation after the market-wide shock has already arrived. In this case, no future market-wide shock is possible, so the solution is quite standard and follows Grenadier and Malenko (2011). Second, we move a step back and consider the problem of liquidating the project at the time of the market-wide shock. It turns out that many types will choose to liquidate projects together with the market-wide shock, even when their projects are not exposed to the shock. We call this property “blending in.” Finally, we consider the problem of liquidating the project prior to the arrival of the market-wide shock. In the first and third stages of the problem, our focus is on the separating equilibrium. Note, however, that there can also be pooling or semi-pooling equilibria. In these equilibria, several types liquidate the project at the same instant even without the market-wide shock due to self-fulfilling beliefs. There are two reasons for our focus on the separating equilibrium. First, because we are mostly interested in how market-wide shocks trigger waves of strategic liquidations, it is natural to abstract from possible waves of liquidations in other periods. Second, even though pooling and semi-pooling equilibria exist, they typically do not survive the D1 equilibrium refinement.3 In this respect, focusing on separating equilibria is without loss of generality. 3.1 Liquidation Decision after the Shock Consider the decision of type θ to liquidate the project after the market-wide shock has already arrived at some point in the past. In this case, no more market-wide shocks can arrive, so the problem is relatively simple. Conjecture that the distribution of types after the market-wide shock is truncated at type θ̂ from below. This 3 See Cho and Sobel (1990) and Romey (1996) for the proof of this result for signaling models with discrete types and a continuum of types, respectively. 14 conjecture is verified the posterior h iniSection 3.2. Then, belief of outsiders is that θ is distributed over θ̂, θ̄ with p.d.f. f (θ) / 1 − F θ̂ . Following Grenadier and Malenko (2011) we first solve for the manager’s liquidation strategy for a given inference function of outsiders, and then apply the rational expectations condition that the liquidation strategy and the inference function must be consistent with each other. Specifically, suppose that outsiders believe that type θ liquidates the project at threshold p̄a (θ), which is a monotonic and differentiable function of θ. Thus, if the manager liquidates the project at threshold p̂, outsiders infer that the manager’s type is θ̃ = p̄−1 a (p̂). Let Va p, θ̃, θ denote the value to the manager for a fixed belief of outsiders about the manager’s type θ̃, where p is probability that the project is successful and θ is the true type of the manager. By the standard valuationarguments (e.g., Dixit and Pindyck (1994) ), in the region prior to liquidation Va p, θ̃, θ must satisfy: (r + λp) Va = −c − λp (1 − p) ∂Va + λp (θ + γθ) . ∂p (14) Suppose that the manager decides to liquidate the project at trigger p̂. Upon liquidation, the payoff to the manager is γ θ̂, implying the boundary condition Va p̂, θ̃, θ = γ θ̃. (15) Solving (14) subject to boundary condition (15) yields the value to the manager for a given liquidation threshold and the belief of the outsiders: λr +1 1 Va p, θ̃, θ, p̂ = p −1 U θ̃, θ, p̂ p i c λp h c − + + θ + γθ , r r+λ r where − λr −1 1 1 c λp̂ c U θ̃, θ, p̂ = −1 + γ θ̃ − + θ + γθ . p̂ p̂ r r+λ r (16) (17) Given the hypothesized inference function p̄a , we can substitute p̄−1 a (p̂) for θ̃ in (16) 15 – (17) and take the first-order condition with respect to p̂: dp̄−1 (p̂) c + γ θ̃ (p̂) r − λp̂ θ + γθ − γ θ̃ (p̂) + λ (1 − p̂) p̂γ a = 0. dp̂ (18) Equation (18) reflects the costs and benefits of postponing the liquidation. The first two terms reflect the costs of waiting an additional instant: paying a cost c and delaying the reputation payoff. The third term reflects the benefits of waiting an additional instant: possibility that the project will pay off. Finally, the last term reflects the effect of waiting an instant on the outsiders’ inference of the manager’s type. Applying the rational expectations condition that the liquidation strategy of the manager must be perfectly revealing, we get the equilibrium differential equation: h i λγ p̄a (1 − p̄a ) dp̄a =− , θ ∈ θ̂, θ̄ . dθ c + rγθ − λp̄a θ (19) This equation must be solved subject to the initial value condition that the lowest type liquidates at the symmetric information threshold. Intuitively, if the lowest type did not liquidate at the symmetric information threshold, she would find it optimal to deviate to the symmetric information threshold. This deviation not only would improve the direct payoff from exercise but also could improve the reputation payoff, since the current belief is already as bad as possible. Depending on the time at which the market-wide shock arrives, there can be one of two cases: 1. If the shock occurs early relative to the unconstrained optimal liquidation threshold of type θ̂, then the initial value condition is c + rγ θ̂ p̄a θ̂ = p∗ θ̂ = . λθ̂ (20) This is the case if the market-wide shock arrives at time t such that p (t) > ∗ p θ̂ . 2. If the shock occurs late relative to the unconstrained optimal liquidation thresh16 old of type θ̂, then the initial value condition is pa θ̂ = p (t). This is the case if the market-wide shock arrives at time t such that p (t) ≤ p∗ θ̂ . In the appendix we show that this argument indeed yields a unique separating equilibrium threshold p̄a (θ) by verifying that U θ̃, θ, p satisfies regularity conditions in Mailath (1987). This result is summarized in Proposition 2 below: Proposition 2. Let pa (θ) be the decreasing function that solves n differential o equation (19) subject to the initial value condition p̄a θ̂ = min p∗ θ̂ , p (t) . Then, pa (θ) is the liquidation threshold of type θ in the unique separating equilibrium. It immediately follows that the equilibrium liquidation threshold after the arrival of the shock depends on the lowest type in this region, θ̂, and the posterior probability of the project being successful right after the shock, p. Thus, we denote the equilibrium liquidation threshold in this section by p̄a θ, θ̂, p . We denote the equilibrium value function, Va p, θ, θ, p̄a θ, θ̂, p , by V̄a p, θ, θ̂ . 3.2 Liquidation Decision Upon the Arrival of the Shock Consider the decision of type θ to liquidate the project upon the arrival of the marketwide shock. Analogously to the previous section, conjecture that the manager’s timing of liquidation before the arrival of the market-wide shock is given by threshold p̄b (θ), which is decreasing in θ. This conjecture is verified in Section 3.3. Then, the posterior belief of outsiders upon the arrival of the market-wide shock is that θ is distributed over θ̌, θ̄ with p.d.f. f (θ) / 1 − F θ̌ . Let p ≤ p∗ θ̌ denote the posterior probability of the project being successful upon the arrival of the shock. The conjecture that at the time of the shock p never exceeds p∗ θ̌ is also verified in Section 3.3. When the market-wide shock arrives, the project may be exposed to the shock (with probability q) or not exposed to the shock (with probability 1 − q). In the former case the manager has no choice but to liquidate the project. In the latter 17 case the manager may decide to liquidate the project strategically. If the manager chooses to liquidate the project, she gets a reputation payoff that is independent of her true type. If the manager chooses to postpone the liquidation decision, her expected payoff is increasing in her true type. Hence, there exists type θ̂ ∈ θ̌, θ̄ such that the non-exposed project is liquidated if θ < θ̂ and not liquidated if θ > θ̂. Provided that θ̂ < θ̄, there can be two scenarios depending on when type that is marginally higher than θ̂ liquidates her project: Scenario 1: Type θ̂ + ε, where ε is an infinitesimal positive value, liquidates the project immediately after the market-wide shock. This happens if and only if: p ≤ p θ̂ , ∗ ´ θ̂ ´ θ̄ θf (θ) dθ + q θ̂ θf (θ) dθ θ̌ = θ̂. F θ̂ − F θ̌ + q 1 − F θ̂ (21) (22) Condition (21) states that the optimal liquidation time of type θ̂ is at the market-wide shock or immediately after. Condition (22) states that type θ̂ is exactly indifferent between pooling and liquidating at the time of the market-wide shock (the left-hand side of (22)) and separating and liquidating immediately after the market-wide shock. Scenario 2: Type θ̂ + ε, where ε is an infinitesimal positive value, liquidates at ∗ the symmetric information threshold p θ̂ + ε . This happens if and only if: p > p θ̂ , ∗ ´ θ̂ ´ θ̄ θf (θ) dθ + q θ̂ θf (θ) dθ 1 ∗ θ̌ = V p, θ̂ , γ a F θ̂ − F θ̌ + q 1 − F θ̂ (23) (24) where p, θ̂ is the value of the project to type θ in the symmetric information framework, when the belief that the project is successful is p. Condition (23) states Va∗ 18 that the optimal liquidation time of type θ̂ is given by threshold p θ̂ . Condition ∗ (24) states that type θ̂ is indifferent between liquidating at the time of the market- wide shock and waiting to liquidate at her optimal separating threshold. Note that because Va∗ p, θ̂ = γ θ̂ for all p ≤ p∗ θ̂ , condition (22) is a special case of condition (24).4 Scenarios 1 and 2 imply that the equilibrium can have one of two forms. In the first case, liquidation happens continuously with positive probability, while in the second case, a wave of liquidations triggered by the market-wide shock is followed by a period of no liquidation. The next proposition shows that there exists a unique equilibrium threshold θ̂, it can be easily computed, and it is always strictly between θ̌ and θ̄: Proposition 3. There exists a unique equilibrium threshold θ̂, and θ̂ ∈ θ̌, θ̄ . It is computed in the following way. Letθ̂m denote the unique solution to ( 22). If ∗ p ≤ p θ̂m , then θ̂ = θ̂m . If p > p∗ θ̂m , then θ is determined as the unique solution to ( 24). The results of this section have two interesting implications. First, because θ̂ > θ̌, the market-wide shock leads to liquidation of more projects than are affected by the shock directly. Intuitively, the manager of a bad project has incentives to time the liquidation decision in order to pool with better types, who have to liquidate because of exposure to the market-wide shock. In other words, the manager liquidates strategically at times when the liquidation decision is not very informative of the manager’s ability. Second, depending on whether the equilibrium belongs to scenario 1 or scenario 2, there can be different time-series properties of liquidation decisions. In the former case, the market-wide shock triggers a wave of liquidations, but after the shock is over the liquidation rate does not change compared to normal times. By contrast, in the latter case, the market-wide shock triggers a wave of liquidations, which is 4 Conditions (24) and (22) implicitly assume that θ̌ < θ̂ < θ̄. If θ̂ = θ̌ or θ̂ = θ̄, then (24) and (22) may hold as strict inequalities. In the proof of Proposition 3, we establish that indeed θ̂ ∈ θ̌, θ̄ . 19 followed by a quiet period of no liquidations. We discuss these implications in more detail in Section 4. Let V̄s p, θ, θ̌ denote the value of type θ when the shock arrives and before the manager learns if her project is exposed to the shock. Then, n o V̄s p, θ, θ̌ = qγ θ̂ θ̌ + (1 − q) max γ θ̂ θ̌ , V̄a p, θ, θ̂ θ̌ . 3.3 (25) Liquidation Decision Before the Arrival of the Shock To complete the solution of the model, consider the decision of type θ to liquidate the project before the arrival of the market-wide shock. Similar to Section 3.1, we solve for the separating equilibrium in two steps. First, we solve for the manager’s liquidation strategy for a given inference function of outsiders. Second, we apply the rational expectations condition that the inference function of outsiders must be consistent with the liquidation strategy of the manager. Suppose that outsiders believe that type θ liquidates the project at lower threshold p̄b (θ), which is a decreasing and differentiable function of θ. Hence, if the manager liquidates the project at threshold p̂, outsiders update their belief about the man−1 ager’s type to θ̃ (p̂) = p̄b (p̂). Let Vb p, θ̃, θ denote the value to the manager for a fixed belief of outsiders θ, where p is the probability that the project is successful and θ is the manager’s true type. Using the standard argument, in the region prior to liquidation, Vb p, θ̃, θ satisfies the following differential equation: ∂Vb (r + λp + µ) Vb = −c − λp (1 − p) + λp (θ + γθ) ∂p +µV̄s p, θ, θ̃ (p) . (26) Suppose that the manager decides to liquidate the project at threshold p̂. Upon liquidation, the payoff to the manager is γ θ̃ (p̂), implying the boundary condition Vb p̂, θ, θ̃ = γ θ̃ (p̂) . 20 (27) Equations (26) – (27) yield the value to the manager for a given liquidation threshold p̂. The liquidation threshold that the manager chooses must satisfy the smoothpasting condition: ∂Vb = γ θ̃′ (p̂) . (28) ∂ p̂ Plugging (27) and (28) into (26) yields the following equation for the manager’s liquidation threshold for a given outsiders’ inference function: (r + λp̂ + µ) γ θ̃ (p̂) = −c − λγ p̂ (1 − p̂) θ̃′ (p̂) + µV̄s p̂, θ, θ̃ (p̂) . (29) Then, we can apply the rational expectations condition that the manager’s liquidation strategy must be consistent with outsiders’ inference function. Similar to Section 3.1, this condition implies θ̃ (p̂) = θ, and hence, p̂ = p̄b (θ) and θ̃′ (p̂) = 1/p̄b (θ). Hence, the equilibrium liquidation threshold must satisfy (r + λp̄b (θ) + µ) γθ = −c − λγ p̄b (θ) (1 − p̄b (θ)) + µV̄s (p̄b (θ) , θ, θ) . p̄′b (θ) (30) Note that V̄s (p̄b (θ),θ,θ) is the value that type θ gets from the arrival of the market wide shock, when she is the lowest type remaining. Because θ̂ θ̌ > θ̌, as established in the previous section, when the market-wide shock arrives in this case, type θ will always choose to liquidate the project, whether the project is exposed to the shock or not. Therefore, V̄s (p̄b (θ),θ,θ) = γ θ̂ (θ), so we can write (30) as the following equilibrium differential equation: dp̄b λγpb (1 − pb ) , θ ∈ θ, θ̄ . =− dθ c + rγθ − λp̄ θ − µγ θ̂ (θ) − θ (31) b Equation (31) is similar to Equation (19), but its denominator includes an additional term −µγ θ̂ (θ) − θ . It reflects an additional incentive to delay liquidating due to a potential arrival of the market-wide shock, which will allow the manager to blend in with higher types. Equation (31) is solved subject to the appropriate initial value condition. Anal21 ogous to Section 3.1, the appropriate initial value condition is that the lowest type θ liquidates the project as if her liquidation decision did not reveal information to outsiders: c + rγθ − µγ θ̂ (θ) − θ p̄b (θ) = . (32) λθ Note that the right-hand side of (32) is the most preferred threshold of type θ in the symmetric information framework, taking payoff upon arrival of the market-wide shock as given. The intuition behind (32) is simple. If the lowest type did not liquidate at this threshold, she would find it optimal to deviate to it. Such deviation not only would increase the direct payoff from liquidation but also could increase the reputation payoff, because the current outsiders’ inference is already as low as possible. Assuming that the prior on the project being successful p0 is such that even the lowest type θ does not find it optimal to liquidate the project immediately, we can summarize the results of this section 4. In the appendix we in Proposition prove the proposition by verifying that Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ satisfies regularity conditions in Mailath (1987). Proposition 4. Let pb (θ) be the decreasing function that solves differential equation (31) subject to the initial value condition (32). Then, pb (θ) is the liquidation threshold of type θ in the unique separating equilibrium in the range before the arrival of the market-wide shock. Taken together, Propositions 2 – 4 imply that there exists a unique equilibrium, in which different types separate via different liquidation strategies. At most times the market-wide shock does not arrive, so different types liquidate projects at different instances. However, on rare occasions when an external shock triggers liquidations for an exogenous reason, a wave of liquidations occurs. Importantly, the wave exceeds the fraction of firms affected by the shock: firms with bad enough projects choose to blend in with the crowd and liquidate together with firms affected by the shock, even though they are themselves not affected by the shock directly. 22 4 Model Implications This section is to be completed. In this section we analyze the economic implications of the model. 4.1 How Significant is Blending in with the Crowd? The previous section implies that when liquidation decisions are informative and the managers care about their reputation, there exists the blending with the crowd effect: the managers have incentives to time their liquidation decisions to periods when good projects are liquidated for an exogenous reason, such as the marketwide shock. It is interesting to see how significant the magnitude of this effect is. Suppose that a fraction q of firms is exposed to the shock.Out of firms that are not exposed to the shock, fraction 1 − F θ̂ / F θ̂ − F θ̃ liquidates. To study the importance of strategic liquidation, we introduce the magnification multiplier, defined as the ratio of the probability that the project is liquidated at the time when the market-wide shock arrives to the probability that the project is exposed to the market-wide shock M = q + (1 − q) F 1−F (θ̂ ) (θ̂)−F (θ̃) q (33) (1 − q) 1 − F θ̂ . = 1+ q F θ̂ − F θ̃ If there is no blending with the crowd effect, as in the benchmark case in Section 2.2, then the magnification multiplier is equal to one. Otherwise, M > 1. Figure 1 quantifies the magnification multiplier for different values of the fraction of firms exposed to the shock, q, for the case of uniform distribution of types. It appears that the magnification multiplier is very significant. For example, when the project is exposed to the market-wide shock with probability 1%, the magnification multiplier is around M = 10, meaning that for every exposed firm that liquidates 23 Figure 1: Plot M as a function of q there are 9 firms that are not exposed to the shock but choose to liquidate for strategic reasons. The magnification effect is even higher for smaller shocks. For example, if the shock hits the firm with probability 0.1% (q = 0.001), then the magnification multiplier is around M = 30. In general, the higher the size of the shock, the lower the magnification effect. Plot the magnification effect for scenario 1 vs. scenario 2. Intuition: in scenario 2 the firm has a valuable option to liquidate at the unconstrained optimal threshold, which is likely to reduce the magnification effect. Thus, if the shock arrives early, then the magnification effect is less significant. 4.2 Time-Series Patterns of Liquidations Three distinct time-series effects that arise in our model: Result 1: For any θ, p̄b (θ) < p̄a (θ, θ, p0 ). As a consequence, the probability of a future market-wide shock incentivizes bad types to delay their liquidation decisions (“the living dead”). Result 2: However, it can be that pa (θ, θ, p) < pa θ, θ̂, p for some types. This is always the case for types that are close to θ̂ under scenario 2 (when p > p∗ θ̂ , i.e. if the market-wide shock arrives early). Intuitively, the worst type always liquidates at the symmetric information threshold. Because the market-wide shock changes the identity of the worst type, it increases the liquidation threshold (at least) for types that are close to the new worst type. Thus, market-wide shocks have a positive effect: without them, some types would delay their liquidation decisions even longer. Result 3: in scenario 2 (when p > p∗ (θ)), some types speed up liquidation decisions compared to the case of no market-wide shock. Without pooling, they would wait longer. 24 4.3 Welfare Effects of Market-Wide Shocks Although it may seem that market-wide shocks are always detrimental because they force liquidation of good projects and reduce information revelation due to the blending with the crowd effect, they actually have a positive effect of reducing the delay in liquidation of some other projects. Without the economy-wide shock, costly liquidation delay could be even higher. 5 Conclusion Real investment decisions can be substantially affected by the temptation of managers to blend in with the crowd and delay liquidation of unsuccessful projects. As we show, this could have a far-reaching repercussions for the dynamics of whole industries and conceivably for the economy at large. The underlying mechanism is the link between managerial reputation based on the available information about the current project outcome and managerial payoffs from attracting future funding recourses and future project cash flows. If liquidation of a current project reveals negative information about ability, the manager will optimally delay abandonment decisions to make it more difficult for the market to judge managerial ability correctly. In a dynamic model, we show how this simple intuition can lead to amplification of modest negative shocks and explain such phenomenon as industry-specific investment busts. 6 References Cho, In-Koo, and Joel Sobel, 1990, Strategic stability and uniqueness in signaling games, Journal of Economic Theory 50, 381–413. Chung, Ji-Woong, Berk A. Sensoy, Lea H. Stern, and Michael S. Weisbach, 2010, Pay for Performance from Future Fund Flows: The Case of Private Equity, Working Paper, Ohio State University. 25 Dixit, Avinash K., and Robert S. Pindyck, 1994, Investment under Uncertainty (Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ). Grenadier, Steven, and Andrey Malenko, 2011, Real Options Signaling Games with Applications to Corporate Finance, Review of Financial Studies forthcoming. Kothari, S., S. Shu, and P. Wysocki, 2009, Do managers withhold bad news?, Journal of Accounting Research 47, 241–276. Mailath, George J., 1987, Incentive compatibility in signaling games with a continuum of types, Econometrica 55, 1349–1365. Miller, Gregory S., 2002, Earnings Performance and Discretionary Disclosure, Journal of Accounting Research 40, 173–204. Morellec, Erwan, and Norman Schurhoff, 2011, Corporate investment and financing under asymmetric information, Journal of Financial Economics 99, 262– 288. Ramey, Garey, 1996, D1 signaling equilibria with multiple signals and a continuum of types, Journal of Economic Theory 69, 508–531. Shreve, Steven E., 2004, Stochastic Calculus for Finance II: Continuous-Time Models (Springer-Verlag: New York, NY) 26 Appendix: Proofs Proof of Proposition 2 We prove the proposition by applying Theorems 1 - 3 from Mailath (1987). To do this, we show that U θ̃, θ, p̂ satisfies regularity conditions from Mailath (1987). h i2 2 Condition 1 (Smoothness): U θ̃, θ, p̂ is C on θ̂, θ̄ × (0, 1). It is straightforward to see that the condition is satisfied. Condition 2 (Belief monotonicity): Uθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ never equals zero, and so is either positive or negative. Differentiating (17) with respect to θ̃, − λr −1 γ 1 −1 > 0. Uθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ = p̂ p̂ (34) Hence, the belief monotonicity condition is satisfied. Condition 3 (Type monotonicity): Uθp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ never equals zero, and so is either positive or negative. Differentiating (17) with respect to θ, − λr −1 1 λ (1 + γ) Uθ θ̃, θ, p̂ = − −1 . p̂ r+λ (35) Differentiating (35) with respect to p̂, Uθp̂ − λr −2 1+γ 1 θ̃, θ, p̂ = − 2 −1 < 0. p̂ p̂ (36) Hence, the type monotonicity condition is satisfied. Condition 4 (“Strict” quasiconcavity): Up̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ = 0 has a unique solution in p̂, which maximizes U θ̃, θ, p̂ , and Up̂p̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ < 0 at this solution. Consider the 27 derivative of (17) with respect to p̂ when θ̃ = θ hc i r λp̂ c r r −1 − −1 p̂ λ (1 − p̂) λ + γθ − + θ + γθ Up̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = λ r r+λ r r r hc i r λp̂ c − −2 + + 1 p̂ λ (1 − p̂) λ + γθ − + θ + γθ (37) λ r r+λ r i r r λ hc −p̂ λ (1 − p̂)− λ −1 + θ + γθ . r+λ r Equation Up̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = 0 has a unique solution in p̂, given by p∗ (θ), determined in Section 2.2. The second derivative is r r Up̂p̂ (θ, θ, p∗ (θ)) = −p∗ (θ) λ −1 (1 − p∗ (θ))− λ −2 θ < 0. (38) Hence, the “strict” quasiconcavity condition is satisfied. Condition 5 (Boundedness): There exists δ > 0 such that for all (θ, p̂) ∈ θ, θ̄ × (0, 1) Up̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0 implies |Up̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| > δ. Differentiating Up̂ (θ, θ, p̂) with respect to p̂, r hr c i r − 1 p̂ λ −2 (1 − p̂)− λ −2 + γθ − p̂θ λ λh r r i r r r c −3 − + + 2 p̂ λ −1 (1 − p̂) λ + γθ − p̂θ (39) λ λ r r r −p̂ λ −1 (1 − p̂)− λ −2 θ r c i h r r r − 1 + 3p̂ + γθ − p̂θ − p̂ (1 − p̂) θ . = p̂ λ −2 (1 − p̂)− λ −3 λ λ r Up̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = r Condition Up̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0 is equivalent to r λ − 1 + 3p̂ r c + γθ − p̂θ − p̂θ ≥ 0. 1 − p̂ λ r (40) If p̂ → 0, the left-hand side of (40) approaches λr − 1 λr rc + γθ < 0. If p̂ → 1, the left-hand side of (40) approaches −∞ (this is because λr rc + γθ − θ < 0, since p∗ (θ) < p0 < 1). Finally, if p̂ → p∗ (θ), the left-hand side of (40) approaches 28 −p∗ (θ) θ < 0. Therefore, (40) implies that r r |Up̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| = p̂ λ −1 (1 − p̂)− λ −2 θ |p∗ (θ) − p̂| (41) >δ for a low enough δ > 0. Thus, the boundedness condition is satisfied. By Theorems 1 and 2 from Mailath (1987), any separating equilibrium liquidation threshold p̄a (θ) is continuous, differentiable, satisfies Equation (19), and dp̄a (θ) /dθ has the same sign as Uθp̂ . Because Uθp̂ < 0, the liquidation threshold p̄a (θ) is decreasing in θ. To ensure that the decreasing solution to Equation (19) subject to the initial value condition (20) is indeed the unique separating equilibrium, we check the single-crossing condition: Single-crossing condition: Up̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ /Uθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ is a strictly monotonic function of θ. The ratio of the two derivatives is equal to: h i r r −λ −2 r c −1 λ p̂ (1 − p̂) + γ θ̃ − p̂ θ − γ θ̃ − θ Up̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ λ r = r r p̂ λ (1 − p̂)− λ −1 γ Uθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ r c + γ θ̃ − p̂ θ − γ θ̃ − θ λ r = . γ p̂ (1 − p̂) (42) Consider the derivative of Up̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ /Uθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ with respect to θ: − p̂ (1 + γ) 1+γ =− < 0. γ p̂ (1 − p̂) γ (1 − p̂) (43) Hence, the single-crossing condition is verified. By Theorem 3 in Mailath (1987), the unique solution to (19) - (20) is indeed the separating equilibrium. 29 Proof of Proposition 3 h i Let φ θ̂ denote the left-hand side of (22) and (24). Note that φ θ̂ , θ̃, θ̄ is h i a continuous function that takes values in θ̃, θ̄ . Hence, by Brower fixed point theorem, it has a fixed point. Taking the derivative of f θ̂ , ´ ´ (1 − q) f θ̂ θ̂ q + (1 − q) F θ̂ − F θ̃ − θ̃θ̂ θf (θ) dθ − q θ̂θ̄ θf (θ) dθ . φ′ θ̂ = 2 q + (1 − q) F θ̂ − F θ̃ (44) Hence, φ′ θ̂ has the same sign as θ̂ − φ θ̂ . Thus, at any fixed point φ′ θ̂ = 0. ′ The fixed point is unique, because any point at which φ θ̂ = 0 must be a lo cal minimum. To see this, note that according to (44) we can write φ′ θ̂ = ψ θ̂ θ̂ − f θ̂ for some strictly positive and differentiable function ψ θ̂ . Hence, φ′′ θ̂ = ψ ′ θ̂ θ̂ − φ θ̂ + ψ θ̂ 1 − φ′ θ̂ . ′′ ′ Around point θ̂ : φ θ̂ = 0, φ θ̂ = ψ θ̂ > 0. Hence, any point φ θ̂ = 0 must ′ be a local minimum. Therefore, the fixed point is unique. In particular, this result implies that equation (21) has a unique solution in θ̂, which is also a point at which φ θ̂ reaches its minimum. 1 Next, consider any p. It must be the case that γ Va p, θ̂ ≥ θ̂ with the strict equality if and only if p ≤ p∗ θ̂ . To the left of θ̂m : φ′ θ̂m = 0, φ θ̂ is a monotonically decreasing function of θ̂. Because Va p, θ̂ is a strictly increasing function for any p taking values from V p, θ̃ to V p, θ̂m ≥ θ̂m , equation (24) has a h i unique solution on θ̂ ∈ θ̃, θ̂m , provided that Va p, θ̃ ≤ Eθ̃ [θ]. If p > p∗ θ̂m , this ∗ solution is θ̂ < θ̂m . If p ≤ p θ̂m , this solution is θ̂ = θ̂m . The case Va p, θ̃ > Eθ̃ [θ] corresponds to the case when no type wants to blend in with the crowd, because the option to wait is too valuable to liquidate immediately even for the most optimistic 30 belief possible. i Finally, it remains to show that equation (24) has no root in the range θ̂ ∈ θ̂m , θ̄ . Note that because φ′ θ̂ > 0 for any θ̂ > θ̂m , θ̂ > φ θ̂ for any θ̂ > θ̂m . However, 1 V p, θ̂ ≥ θ̂ by definition of the option. Hence, equation (24) has no root in the a γ i range θ̂ ∈ θ̂m , θ̄ . Proof of Proposition 4 We check that the value function in the pre-shock region satisfies regularity conditions 1 - 5 in Mailath (1987). Then, we apply Theorems 1 and 2 from Mailath (1987). The general solution to (26) is c λp c + + (1 + γ) θ Vb (p) = C (1 − p) p − r+µ r+λ+µ r+µ −1 ˆ p x r+µ λ V̄s x, θ, θ̃ (x) r+µ+λ r+µ µ + (1 − p) λ p− λ dx. (45) r+µ λ 0 (1 − x) λ +2 r+µ+λ λ − r+µ λ To pin down constant C, we use boundary condition (27). This gives us the following value to the manager for a given liquidation threshold and inference function: Vb p, θ̃, θ, p̂ r+µ +1 λ 1 = p −1 Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ p c λp c + + (1 + γ) θ − r+µ r+λ+µ r+µ −1 ˆ x x r+µ λ V̄s x, θ, θ̃ (x) r+µ+λ r+µ µ + (1 − p) λ p− λ dx, r+µ λ 0 (1 − x) λ +2 31 (46) where − r+µ ˆ −1 1 1 λ c λp̂ c µ p̂ x Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ = −1 + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ − p̂ p̂ r+µ r+λ+µ r+µ λ 0 (47) Note that Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ is analogous to U θ̃, θ, p̂ except for two differences: (i) r + µ instead of r; (ii) there is an additional term. The last term integrates over values of θ̃ (p) , taking the functional form as given, while γ θ̃ denotes a specific value of θ̃ ∈ θ, θ̄ . Now we can check that Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ satisfies conditions from Mailath (1987): h i2 2 Condition 1 (Smoothness): Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ is C on θ̂, θ̄ × (0, 1). The condition is satisfied provided that the integral in the is smooth. last term Condition 2 (Belief monotonicity): Ubθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ never equals zero, and so is either positive or negative. Differentiating Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ with respect to θ̃: − r+µ −1 γ 1 λ −1 > 0. Ubθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ = p̂ p̂ (48) Hence, the belief monotonicity condition is satisfied. Condition 3 (Type monotonicity): Ubθp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ never equals zero, and so is either positive or negative. Differentiating Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ with respect to θ, − r+µ −1 λ λ (1 + γ) 1 −1 Ubθ θ̃, θ, p̂ = − p̂ r+µ+λ r+µ ˆ p̂ x λ −1 V̄sθ x, θ, θ̃ (x) µ − dx. r+µ λ 0 (1 − x) λ +2 (49) Differentiating (49) with respect to p̂, r+µ µ − r+µ −2 1 + γ + V̄sθ p̂, θ, θ̃ Ubθp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ = −p̂ λ (1 − p̂) λ . λp̂ 32 (50) r+µ −1 λ V̄s x, θ, (1 − x) r+µ λ Because V̄s p̂, θ, θ̃ is non-decreasing in θ, Ubθp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ < 0. Therefore, the type monotonicity condition is satisfied. Condition 4 (“Strict” quasiconcavity): Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = 0 has a unique solution in p̂, which maximizes Ub(θ, θ, p̂), and Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) < 0 at this solution. Consider the derivative of Ub θ̃, θ, p̂ with respect to p̂: − r+µ −1 λ λp̂ c 1 1 c Ubp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ = − 2 −1 + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ p̂ p̂ r+µ r+λ+µ r+µ − r+µ −2 λ r+µ 1 1 c λp̂ c + +1 −1 + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ λ p̂ p̂3 r + µ r+λ+µ r+µ − r+µ −1 λ λ 1 1 c −1 + (1 + γ) θ (51) − p̂ p̂ r+λ+µ r+µ r+µ −1 ¯ λ Vs p̂, θ, θ̃ µ p̂ . − +2 λ (1 − p̂) r+µ λ We can rewrite this as r+µ − r+µ −1 −1 λ λ Ubp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ = −p̂ (1 − p̂) λp̂ c c + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ r+µ r+λ+µ r+µ r + µ + λ r+µ −1 c λp̂ c −2 − r+µ λ + p̂ λ (1 − p̂) + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ λ r+µ r+λ+µ r+µ (52) r+µ r+µ r+µ λ c µ r+µ + (1 + γ) θ − p̂ λ −1 (1 − p̂)− λ −2 V̄s p̂, θ, θ̃ (p̂) . −p̂ λ (1 − p̂)− λ −1 r+λ+µ r+µ λ When θ̃ = θ, Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = p̂ where A= r+µ −1 λ (1 − p̂)− r+µ −2 λ × A, c + rγθ µ − p̂θ − V̄s (p̂, θ, θ) − γθ . λ λ (53) (54) Note that V̄s (p̂, θ, θ) is weakly increasing in p̂. Therefore, the right-hand side of (54) 33 is strictly decreasing in p̂. Hence, equation Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = 0 has the unique solution p∗2 (θ) = c + rγθ − µγ θ̂ (θ) − θ λθ (55) . The second derivative of Ub (θ, θ, p̂)with respect to p̂ at p∗2 (θ) is equal to Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p∗2 (θ)) = −p∗2 (θ) r+µ −1 λ (1 − p∗2 (θ))− r+µ −2 λ µ θ + V̄sp̂ (p∗2 (θ) , θ, θ) . λ (56) Because θ̂ (θ) > θ, as established in Section 3.2, in the neighborhood of p∗2 (θ) V̄s (p̂, θ, θ) is equal to θ̂ (θ). Therefore, V̄sp̂ (p∗2 (θ) , θ, θ) = 0. Hence, Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p∗2 (θ)) = −p∗2 (θ) r+µ −1 λ (1 − p∗2 (θ))− r+µ −2 λ (57) θ < 0. Therefore, the “strict” quasiconcavity condition is satisfied. Condition 5 (Boundedness): There exists δ > 0 such that for all (θ, p̂) ∈ θ, θ̄ × (0, 1) Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0 implies |Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| > δ. Differentiating (53) with respect to p̂, Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) = p̂ r+µ −1 λ (1 − p̂) −2 − r+µ λ r + µ − λ r + µ + 2λ + λp̂ λ (1 − p̂) µ × A − θ − V̄sp̂ (p̂, θ, θ) . λ (58) Condition Up̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0 is equivalent to r + µ − λ r + µ + 2λ + λp̂ λ (1 − p̂) ×A−θ− µ V̄sp̂ (p̂, θ, θ) ≥ 0. λ If p̂ → 1, the left-hand side of (59) approaches −∞. This is because r λ (59) c r + γθ − θ < 0, since p∗ (θ) < p0 < 1. If p̂ → p∗2 (θ), the left-hand side of (59) approaches −θ < 0. Finally, if p̂ → 0, the left-hand side of (59) approaches −∞, if r + µ > λ, ∞, if r + µ < λ, and −θ − µγ θ̂ (θ) < 0, if r + µ = λ. λ First, consider the case r +µ ≥ λ. By the argument above, there exists a constant ∆ > 0 such that any p̂ at which Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0 must satisfy p̂ > ∆, p̂ < 1 − ∆, and 34 |p̂ − p∗2 (θ)| > ∆. Therefore, for any p̂ at which Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0: |Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| = p̂ r+µ −1 λ (1 − p̂)− r+µ −2 λ θ |p∗2 (θ) − p̂| (60) >δ for a low enough δ > 0. Therefore, the boundedness condition is satisfied in this case. Second, consider the case r + µ < λ. Analogously to the case r + µ ≥ λ, any p̂ bounded away from zero at which Ubp̂p̂ (θ, θ, p̂) ≥ 0 must satisfy |Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| > δ for sufficiently low positive δ. Therefore, to verify the boundedness condition in this case it is sufficient to check that |Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| > δ if p̂ is arbitrarily close to zero. When p̂ → 0, |Ubp̂ (θ, θ, p̂)| converges to lim p̂→∞ θp∗2 (θ) p̂ λ−r−µ λ = ∞. (61) Therefore, the boundedness condition is satisfied in the case r + µ < λ too. By Theorems 1 and 2 from Mailath (1987), any separating equilibrium liquidation threshold p̄b (θ) is continuous, differentiable, satisfies Equation (31), and dp̄b (θ) /dθ has the same sign as Ubθp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ . Because Ubθp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ < 0, the liquidation threshold p̄b (θ) is decreasing in θ. To ensure that the decreasing solution to Equation (31) subject to the initial value condition (32) is indeed the unique separating equilibrium, we check the single-crossing condition: Single-crossing condition: Ubp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ /Ubθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ is a strictly monotonic function of θ. The ratio of the two derivatives is equal to: Ubp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ 1 c λp̂ c =− + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ γ p̂ r + µ r+λ+µ r+µ Ubθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ r+µ+λ 1 c λp̂ c + + γ θ̃ − + (1 + γ) θ γλ p̂ (1 − p̂) r + µ r+λ+µ r+µ (62) λ c µ 1 − + (1 + γ) θ − V̄s p̂, θ, θ̃ (p̂) . γ (r + λ + µ) r + µ γλ p̂ (1 − p̂) 35 Consider the derivative of Ubp̂ θ̃, θ, p̂ /Ubθ̃ θ̃, θ, p̂ with respect to θ: 1 − γ (1 − p̂) µ 1 + γ + V̄sθ p̂, θ, θ̃ (p̂) < 0. λp̂ (63) Hence, the single-crossing condition is verified. By Theorem 3 in Mailath (1987) the unique solution to (31) - (32) is indeed the separating equilibrium. Proof of Results from Section 4.2 Proof of Result 1. Noting that µ > 0 and θ̂ (θ) > θ, initial value conditions (20) and (32) imply that p̄b (θ) < p̄a (θ, θ, p0 ). Consider any point θ at which p̄b (θ) = p̄a (θ, θ, p0 ). Equations (19) and (31) imply that p̄aθ (θ, θ, p0 ) > p̄′b (θ), that is, p̄b (θ) decreases faster than p̄a (θ, θ, p0 ). Hence, p̄b (θ) < p̄a (θ, θ, p0 ). n o Proof of Result 2. Initial value condition (20) implies that p̄a θ̂, θ̂, p = min p∗ θ̂ , p . ∗ ∗ In particular, if p ≥ p θ̂ , then p̄a θ̂, θ̂, p = p θ̂ . However, equation (19) im plies that p̄a θ̂, θ, p < p∗ θ̂ for all θ̂ > θ: whenever p̄a (θ, θ, p) approaches p∗ (θ), p̄aθ (θ, θ, p) approaches −∞. Therefore, if p ≥ p∗ θ̂ , there exists type θ̂′ > θ̂ , such h i ′ that p̄a θ̂, θ̂, p > p̄a θ̂, θ, p for all θ ∈ θ̂, θ̂ . Proof of Result 3. Without the market-wide shock, the liquidation threshold of any type θ > θ, denoted p̄n (θ) would be below p∗ (θ). However, if p ≥ p∗ θ̂ , then ∗ type θ̂ (θ) liquidates at the symmetric information threshold: p̄a θ̂, θ̂, p = p θ̂ . h i By continuity, there exists type θ̂′′ , such that p̄a θ, θ̂, p > p̄n (θ) for all θ ∈ θ̂, θ̂′ . 36