GRS LX 700 Language Acquisition and Linguistic Theory Week 2. The emergence of syntax Syntax Recall the basic structure of adult sentences. IP (a.k.a. TP, INFLP, …) is the position of modals and auxiliaries, also assumed to be home of tense and agreement. CP is where wh-words move and where I moves in subject-aux-inversion Splitting the INFL Syntax since 1986 has been more or less driven by the principle “every separable functional element belongs in its own phrase.” Various syntactic tests support these moves as well (cf. CAS LX 523). Splitting the INFL Distinct syntactic functions assigned to distinct functional heads. T: tense/modality AgrO: object agreement, accusative case AgrS: subject agreement, nominative case Neg: negation Origins: Pollock (1989) (split INFL into Agr and T), Chomsky (1993) (split INFL into AgrS, T, AgrO). Functional heads The DP, CP, and VP all suffered a similar fate. DP was split into DP and NumP Origin: Ritter 1991 and related work Functional heads VP was split into two parts, vP where the agent starts, and VP where the patient starts. V and v combine by head movement. Origins: Larson (1988) proposed a similar structure for double-object verbs, Hale & Keyser (1993) proposed something like this structure, which was adopted by Chomsky (1993). Functional heads CP was split into several “discourserelated” functional heads as well (topic, focus, force, and “finiteness”). Origins: Rizzi (1997) Functional structure Often, the “fine structure” of the functional heads does not matter, so people will still refer to “IP” (with the understanding that under a microscope it is probably AgrSP, TP, AgrOP, or even more complex), “CP”, “DP”, etc. The heart of “syntax” is really in the functional heads, on this view. Verbs and nouns give us the lexical content, but functional heads (TP, AgrSP, etc.) give us the syntactic structure. How do kids get there? Given the structure of adult sentences, the question we’re concerned about here will be in large part: how do kids (consistently) arrive at this structure (when they become adults)? Kids learn it (patterns of input). Chickens and eggs, and creoles, and so forth. Option 1: Kids start out assuming the entire adult structure, learning just the details (Does the verb move? How is tense pronounced?) Option 2: Kids start out assuming some subpart of the adult structure, complexity increasing with (predetermined?) development. Testing for functional structure Trying to answer this question involves trying to determine what evidence we have for these functional structures in child syntax. It’s not very easy. It’s hard to ask judgments of kids, and they often do unhelpful things like repeat (or garble) things they just heard (probably telling us nothing about what their grammar actually is). Testing for functional structure We do know what various functional projections are supposed to be responsible for, and so we can look for evidence of their effects in child language. This isn’t foolproof. If a child fails to pronounce the past tense suffix on a verb that was clearly intended to be in the past, does this mean there’s no TP? Does it mean they simply made a speech error (as adults sometimes do)? Does it mean they haven’t figured out how to pronounce the past tense affix yet? Helpful clues kids give us Null subjects Kids seem to drop the subject off of their sentences a lot. More than adults would. There’s a certain crosslinguistic systematicity to it as well, from which we might take hints about kids’ functional structure. Root infinitives Kids seem to use nonfinite forms of main (root) clause verbs where adults wouldn’t. Again, there’s a certain crosslinguistic systematicity to it that can provide clues as to what’s going on. Radford (1990, 1995) A proposal about Early Child English. Kids’ syntax differs from adults’ syntax: kids use only lexical (not functional) elements structural sisters in kids’ trees always have a qrelation between them. VP NP q V’ man V q chase “Small Clause Hypothesis” NP car adult syntax ≠ child syntax Adults: CP—IP—VP Kids: VP Evidence for absence of IP: No modals (repeating, kids drop them) No auxiliaries (Mommy doing dinner) No productive use of tense & agreement (Baby ride truck, Mommy go, Daddy sleep) Absence of CP No CP system: no complementizers (that, for, if) no preposed auxiliary (car go?) no wh-movement (imitating where does it go? yields go?; spontaneous: mouse doing?) kids bad at comprehending wh-object questions (out of canonical order). (—What are you doing? —No.) Absence of DP No DP system: no non-q elements no expletives (raining, outside cold) no of before noun complements of nouns (cup tea) Few determiners (Hayley draw boat, want duck, reading book) No possessive ’s, which may be a D. No pronouns, which are probably D. Small children’s small clauses The Small Clause Hypothesis is not prima facie crazy. Child English does seem to look something like what it would predict. On the other hand, when looking across languages, we find that the SCH doesn’t fare very well. In languages where tense/agreement is more visible, we find kids using infinitives, but only sometimes, other times using finite verbs. The case that kids do not represent tense weakens (but is not yet out of the running!). To T or not to T Focusing specifically on tense (and subject agreement), the fact that kids sometimes use tense and sometimes do not does not indicate that they know or represent T in their syntactic structure. The question is: When tense is there, does it act like tense would for an adult? Do kids differentiate between tensed and infinitive verbs, or are these just memorized Vs at this point? Full Competence Hypothesis Poeppel & Wexler (1993). Data: Andreas (2;1, from CHILDES). The morphosyntactic properties associated with finiteness and attributable to the availability of functional categories (notably head movement) are in place. The best model of the child data is the standard analysis of adult German (functional projections and all). The one exception: Grammatical Infinitive Hypothesis: Matrix sentences with (clause-final) infinitives are a legitimate structure in child German grammar. Adult German Phrase structure consists of CP, IP, VP. German is SOV, V2 The finite verb (or auxiliary or modal) is the second constituent in main clauses, following some constituent (subject, object, or adverbial). In embedded clauses, the finite verb is final. V2 comes about by moving the finite verb to (head-initial) C. German clause structure CP C DP C+I Hans kaufte IP I — — VP V DP den Ball — This “second position” is generally thought to be C, where something else (like the subject, or any other XP) needs to appear in SpecCP. This only happens with finite verbs. Nonfinite verbs remain at the end of the sentence (after the object). German clause structure CP DP den Ball C IP C+I hat DP I Hans VP V — V gekaufte Things other than subjects can appear in “first position”. When the tense appears on an auxiliary, the verb stays in place. In brief… Kids can choose a finite or a nonfinite verb. A finite (matrix) verb shows up in 2nd position A nonfinite verb appears clause-finally ich mach das nich I do that not du das haben you that have Results There is a strong contingency. Conclude: the finiteness distinction is made correctly at the earliest observable stage. +finite -finite V2, not final 197 6 V final, not V2 11 37 Do kids learn “this is a second position verb” for certain verbs? (Are some verbs used as auxiliaries?) Andreas used 33 finite verbs and 37 nonfinite verbs, 8 of which were in both categories— —and those 8 were finite in V2 position and nonfinite in final position. Remaining verbs show no clear semantic core that one might attribute the distribution to. Verb positioning = functional categories In adult German, V2 comes from V I C. If we can see non-subjects to the left of finite verbs, we FP know we have at least one functional projection (above Object F the subject, in whose Spec F+V VP the first position nonSubject V subject goes). — — When V is 2nd, what’s first? Usually subject, not a big surprise. But 19 objects before finite V2 (of 197 cases, 180 with overt subjects) And 31 adverbs before finite V2 Conclude: Kids basically seem to be acting like adults; their V2 is the same V2 that adults use. CP The Full Competence Hypothesis says not only that functional categories exist, but that the child has access to the same functional categories that the adult does. In particular, CP should be there too. Predicts what we’ve seen: finite verbs are in second position only (modulo topic drop leaving them in first position) nonfinite verbs are in final position only subjects, objects, adverbs may all precede a finite verb in second position. P&W’s predictions met—how did the other guys fare? Radford and related approaches (No functional categories for the young)? Well, we see V2 with finite verbs finite verb is second non-subjects can be first and you can’t do this except to move V out of VP and something else to its left… You need at least one functional category. Andreas uses agreement correctly when he uses it—adults use IP for that. P&W’s predictions met—how did the other guys fare? “No C hypothesis” (kids don’t use overt complementizers) Of course, kids don’t really use embedded clauses either (a chicken-egg problem?) Purported cases of embedded clauses without a complementizer aren’t numerous or convincing. Absence of evidence ≠ evidence of absence. P&W’s predictions met—how did the other guys fare? Can we get away with only one functional category? The word order seems to be generable this way so long as F is to the left of VP. subject can stay in SpecVP V moves to F non-subject could move to SpecFP. …though people tend to believe that IP in German is head-final (that is, German is headfinal except for CP). How do kids learn to put I on the right once they develop CP? P&W’s predictions met—how did the other guys fare? Empirical argument: negation and adverbs are standardly supposed to mark the left edge of VP. A subject in SpecVP (i.e. when a non-subject is topicalized) should occur to the right of such elements. 19 Object-initial sentences 31 adverb-initial sentences, 8 have an(other) adverb or negation, and all eight have the subject to the left of the adverb/negation. [CP Object C+I+V [IP Subject [VP neg/adv tSubj tV] tI ]] The Full Competence Hypothesis The idea: Kids have full knowledge of the principles and processes and constraints of grammar. Their representations are basically adult-like. What’s different is that kids optionally allow infinitives as matrix verbs (which kids grow out of). Harris & Wexler (1996) Child English bare stems as “OIs”? In the present, only morphology is 3sg -s. Bare stem isn’t unambiguously an infinitive form. No word order correlate to finiteness. OIs are clearer in better inflected languages. Does English do this too? Or is it different? Hypotheses: Kids don’t “get” inflection yet; go and goes are basically homonyms. These are OIs, the -s is correlated with something systematic about the child syntax. Harris & Wexler (1996) Exploring a consequence of having T in the structure: do support. Rationale: Main verbs do not move in English. Without a modal or auxiliary, T is stranded: The verb -ed not move. Do is inserted to save T. Predicts: No T, no do insertion. Harris & Wexler (1996) Empirically, we expect: She go She goes She not go (no T no do) She doesn’t go (adult, T and do) but never She not goes (evidence of T, yet no do). Note: All basically options if kids don’t “get” inflection. Harris & Wexler (1996) Looked at 10 kids from 1;6 to 4;1 Adam, Eve, Sara (Brown), Nina (Suppes), Abe (Kuczaj), Naomi (Sachs), Shem (Clark), April (Higginson), Nathaniel (Snow). Counted sentences… with no or not before the verb without a modal/auxiliary with unambiguous 3sg subjects with either -s or -ed as inflected. Harris & Wexler (1996) Affirmative: 43% inflected 782 47 < 10% inflected -inflec neg Negative: aff It not works Mom no N. has a microphone no goes in there but the horse not stand ups no goes here! +inflec 594 5 Harris & Wexler (1996) Small numbers, but in the right direction. Generalization: Considering cases with no auxiliary, kids inflect about half the time normally, but almost never (up to performance errors) inflect in the negative. If do is an indicator of T in the negative, we might expect to see that do appears in negatives about as often as inflection appears in affirmatives. Also, basically true: 37% vs. 34% in the pre-2;6 group, 73% vs. 61% in the post-2;6 group. Harris & Wexler (1996) Also, made an attempt to ascertain how the form correlated with the intended meaning in terms of tense. (Note: a nontrivial margin of error…) Inflected verbs overwhelmingly in the right context. present bare stem 771 -s 418 -ed 10 past 128 14 168 future 39 5 0 Harris & Wexler (1996) Last, an elicitation experiment contrasting affirmative, never (no T dependence for adults), and not. Does the cow always go in the barn, or does she never go? Does the cow go in the barn or does she not go in the barn? Do you think he always goes or do you think he never goes? Do you think that he goes, or don’t you think that he goes? Processing load? Extra load of not alleviated by leaving off the -s? If that’s the case, we’d expect never and not to behave the same way—in fact, never might be harder, just because it’s longer (and trigger more -s drops). Harris & Wexler (1996) Affirmatives inflected often, not inflected rarely, never sort of inbetween. Looking at the results in terms of whether the question was inflected: Kids overall tended to use inflection when there was inflection in the question. When the stimulus contained an -s: affirmative: 15 vs. 7 (68% had an -s) never: 14 vs. 16 (48%) not: 4 vs. 12 (25%) —quite a bit lower. Some alternatives… Root infinitives due to “modal drop”? Idea: I want to eat pizza. RI? I want to eat pizza. First question: why modals? Second, they don’t (always) seem to mean what they should if there is a null modal. 20/37 seem to be clearly non-modal. Thorsten Ball haben (T already has the ball) Modal drop Adult modals are in position 2, regardless of what is in position 1. If kids are dropping modals, we should expect a certain proportion of the dropped modals to appear with a nonsubject in position 1. But none occur—nonfinite verbs also seem to come with initial subjects. Modal drop On the other hand, if nonfinite final V indicates failure to raise to I and C, we don’t expect CP to be available for “topicalization” (the assumption is that V2 involves both movement of V to C and movement of something else to SpecCP; but no need to move something to SpecCP unless V is in C). Modal drop Just to be sure (since the numbers are small), P&W check to make sure they would have expected non-subjects in position 1 with nonfinite verbs if the modal drop hypothesis were true. 17% of the verbs are infinitives 20% of the (finite) time we had non-subject topicalization So 3% of the time (20% of 17%) we would expect non-subject topicalization in nonfinite contexts. Of 251 sentences, we would have expected 8. We saw none. Subject case errors Various people have observed that kids learning English sometimes will use accusative subjects. It turns out that there’s a sort of a correlation with the finiteness of the verb as well. Finite verbs go with nominative case, while nonfinite verbs seem to go with either nominative or accusative case. Finiteness vs. case errors subject Schütze & Wexler (1996) Nina 1;11-2;6 Finite Nonfinite Loeb & Leonard (1991) 7 representative kids 2;11-3;4 Finite Nonfinite he+she 255 139 436 75 him+her 14 120 4 28 % non-Nom 5% 46% 0.9% 27% EPP and missing INFL If there were just an IP, responsible for both NOM and tense, then they should go together (cf. “IP grammar” vs. “VP grammar”) Yet, there are many cases of root infinitives with NOM subjects And, even ACC subjects seem to raise out of the VP over negation (me not go). We can understand this once we consider IP to be split into TP and AgrP; tense and case are separated, but even one will still pull the subject up out of VP. (ATOM:+Agr –Tns) What to make of the case errors? Case is assumed to be the jurisdiction of AgrSP and AgrOP. So, nominative case can serve as an unambiguous signal that there is an AgrSP. Accusative case, conversely, may signal a missing AgrSP. Why are non-AgrSP subjects accusatives? Probably a default case in English: Who’s driving? Me. Me too. It’s me. Other languages seem not to show this “accusative subject” error but also seem to have a nominative default (making an error undetectable). “ATOM” Schütze & Wexler propose a model of this in which the case errors are a result of being able to either omit AgrSP or Tense. For a subject to be in nominative case, AgrSP must be there (TP’s presence is irrelevant). For a finite verb, both TP and AgrSP must be there. English inflection (3sg present –s) relies on both. If one or the other is missing, we’ll see an infinitive (i.e. bare stem). Thus, predicted: finite (AgrSP+TP) verbs show Nom (AgrSP), but only half of the nonfinite verbs (not both AgrSP and TP) show Nom (AgrSP). We should not see finite+Acc. Agr/T Omission Model (ATOM) Adult clause structure: AgrP NOMi Agr Agr TP T ti T VP ATOM Kiddie clause, missing TP (—TNS): AgrP NOMi Agr Agr VP ATOM Kiddie clause, missing AgrP (—AGR): TP ACC defaulti T T VP Pronunciation of English T+AgrS(+V) is pronounced like: /s/ if we have features [3, sg, present] /ed/ if we have the feature [past] Ø otherwise Layers of “default”, most specific first, followed by next most specific (“Distributed Morphology”, Halle & Marantz 1993). Notice: 3sg present –s requires both TP and AgrSP, but past –ed requires only TP (AgrSP might be missing, so we might expect some accusative subjects of past tense verbs). One prediction of ATOM +AGR+TNS: NOM with inflected verb (-s) +AGR–TNS: NOM with bare verb –AGR+TNS: default (ACC) with bare verb –AGR–TNS: GEN with bare verb (the GEN case was not discussed by Wexler 1998, but see Schütze & Wexler 1996) Nothing predicts Acc with inflected verb. Finite pretty much always goes with a nominative subject. subject Schütze & Wexler (1996) Nina 1;11-2;6 Finite Nonfinite Loeb & Leonard (1991) 7 representative kids 2;11-3;4 Finite Nonfinite he+she 255 139 436 75 him+her 14 20 4 28 % non-Nom 5% 46% 0.9% 27% ATOM and morphology [+3sg +pres] = -s [+past] = -ed —=Ø [+masc +3sg +nom] play+[3sg+pres] [+2sg +nom] play+[2sg +past] he plays. you play. But is this knowledge built-in? Hint: no. [+masc, +3sg, +nom] = he [+masc, +3sg, +gen] = his [+masc, +3sg] = him [+fem, +3sg, +nom] = she [+fem, +3sg] = her [+1sg, +nom] = I [+1sg, +gen] = my [+1sg] = me [+2, +gen] = your [+2] = you ATOM and morphology What if the child produces a lot of utterances like and even her sleeping her play her sleeps her goes to school but never uses the word she? ATOM predicts that agreement and nominative case should correlate. Her goes to school is predicted never to occur. So does this child’s use of her goes to school mean ATOM is wrong? Schütze (2001, inter alia) No. Her goes to school is not necessarily a counterexample to ATOM (although it is a candidate). Morphology must be learned and is crosslinguistically variable. She is known to emerge rather late compared to other pronouns. If the kid thinks her is the nominative feminine 3sg pronoun, her goes to school is perfectly consistent with ATOM. Hence, we should really only count her+agr correlations from kids who have demonstrated that they know she. ATOM and morphology Morphology (under “Distributed Morphology”) is a system of defaults. The most specified form possible is used. Adult English specifies her as a feminine 3sg pronoun, and she as a nominative feminine 3sg pronoun. If the kid doesn’t know she, the result will be that all feminine 3sg pronouns will come out as her. That’s just how you pronounce nominative 3sg feminine, if you’re the kid. Just like adult you. [+masc, +3sg, +nom] = he [+masc, +3sg, +gen] = his [+masc, +3sg] = him [+fem, +3sg, +nom] = she [+fem, +3sg] = her [+1sg, +nom] = I [+1sg, +gen] = my [+1sg] = me [+2, +gen] = your [+2] = you Rispoli (2002, inter alia) Rispoli has his own theory of her-errors. Pronoun morphology is organized into “tables” (paradigms) basically, where each form has a certain weight. When a kid is trying to pronounce a pronoun, s/he attempts to find the entry in the table and pronounce it. The kid’s success in finding the form is affected by “gravity”. “Heavier” forms are more likely to be picked when accessing the table, even if it’s not quite the right form. If it’s close and it’s heavy, it’ll win out a lot of the time. Her by virtue of being both acc and gen is extraheavy, and pulls the kid in fairly often. Her plays ATOM and Rispoli make different predictions with respect to her plays. ATOM says it should never happen (up to simple performance error) Rispoli says case errors are independent of agreement, her plays is perfectly possible, even expected. Rispoli’s complaints about Schütze’s studies: Excluding kids who happen not to produce she in the transcript under evaluation is not good enough. The assumption is that this learning is monotonic, so if the kid ever used she (productively) in the past, the her errors should not be excluded. Monotonicity Schütze assumes that use of she is a matter of knowledge of she. Once the kid knows it, and given that the adult version of the kid will know it, it’s there, for good. Rispoli claims that the “weight” of she can fluctuate, so that it could be “known” but misretrieved later if her becomes too heavy. Rispoli (2002) set out to show that there is a certain amount of “yoyo’ing” in the production of she. We’ll focus on Nina, for whom we can get the data. Nina she vs. her Rispoli’s counts show Nina using she from basically the outset of her use of pronouns, and also shows a decrease of use of she at 2;5. 2;2 1315 2;3 1619 2;4 2023 2;5 she her 2 4% 43 96% 1 8% 12 92% 1 14% 6 86% 7 73 Checking Rispoli’s counts 2;2 *CHI: she have hug a lady . *CHI: she have jamas@f on . These are the times when Nina used she (twice at 2;2, once at 2;3, once at 2;4). Rispoli found 7 at 2;5, we’ll deal with them later. 2;3 *MOT: does she like it ? *CHI: she drink apple juice . *CHI: her like apple juice . 2;4 *MOT: he's up there ? *CHI: no # she's not up there . *CHI: he's up there . Checking 2;2 *CHI: helping her have a yellow blanket . *MOT: she has a yellow blanket ? *CHI: yeah [= yes] . *CHI: her's ok . *CHI: her ok . *MOT: she's ok ? *CHI: ok . *CHI: her's ok . *CHI: her ok . *CHI: her's ok . *MOT: she's ok . These three and one other time Nina said her’s ok are the only candidate counterexamples at 2;2. At 2;2, 45 her+bare verb. At 2;3, no candidate counterexamples, 14 her+bare verbs. (R got 43, possibly including her’s ok) (R got 12) At 2;4 none, 7 her+bare. (R got 6) Checking *MOT: what happened when I shampooed Miriam yesterday ? *CHI: her was cried . 2;5: *MOT: oh # there's the dolly's bottle . *CHI: her's not going to drink it . *MOT: I'll start washing it . *MOT: see how clean it comes ? *MOT: you want to use the pot ? *CHI: a little bit . *CHI: her don't . *CHI: her's not dirty . *CHI: not dirty . I found about 76 her+bare/past verbs. I found 3 potential counterexamples. Bottom line? It doesn’t seem like anything was particularly affected, even if Nina’s early files were fully included. The number of possible counterexamples seems well within the “performance error” range. The point about variation in usage of she is valid, worth being aware of the assumptions and being sure we’re testing the right things. Rispoli was trying to make the point that if we’d accidentally missed a she in the early files, we might have excluded counterexamples there. Yet, even including everything, the asymmetry is strong. Two hypotheses about learning VEPS (very early parameter setting) Basic parameters are set correctly at the earliest observable stages, that is, at least from the time that the child enters the twoword stage around 18 months of age. VEKI (very early knowledge of inflection) At the earliest observable stage (two-word stage), the child knows the grammatical and phonological properties of many important inflectional elements of their language. Two-word stage? The reason both VEPS and VEKI mention the two-word stage is just because this is the first stage where we have evidence of utterance composition. Very Early Parameter Setting As soon as you can see it, kids have: VO vs. OV order set (Swedish vs. German) V>I [yes/no] (French vs. English) V2 [yes/no] (German vs. French/English) Null subject [yes/no] (Italian vs. Fr./E.) So, at least by the 2-word stage, they have the parameters set (maybe earlier) VEKI? Generally, when kids use inflection, they use it correctly. Mismatches are vanishingly rare. English (Harris & Wexler 1995) German (Poeppel & Wexler 1993) Again, this is kind of contrary to what the field had been assuming (which was: kids are slow at, bad at, learning inflection). Ok, but… So: Kids have the full functional structure available to them, and they set the parameters right away and know the inflection. What then do we make of the fact that kids make non-adult utterances in the face of evidence that they aren’t learning the parameters? KW: Certain (very specific, it turns out) properties of the grammar mature. Root infinitives vs. time The timing on root infinitives is pretty robust, ending around 3 years old. NS/OI But some languages appear not to undergo the “optional infinitive” stage. How can this be consistent with a maturational view? OI languages: Germanic languages studied to date (Danish, Dutch, English, Faroese, Icelandic, Norwegian, Swedish), Irish, Russian, Brazilian Portuguese, Czech Non-OI languages: Italian, Spanish, Catalan, Tamil, Polish NS/OI What differentiates the OI and non-OI languages? Agreement? Italian (non-OI) has rich agreement, but so does Icelandic (OI). Null subjects! Null Subject/OI Generalization: Children in a language go through an OI stage iff the language is not an INFL-licensed null subject language. NS/OI and Hebrew (Rhee & Wexler 1995) Hebrew is a NS language but only in 1st and 2nd person, non-present tense. Everywhere else (3rd past, future, present) subjects are obligatory. Hebrew-learning 2-year-olds showed optional infinitives except in 1/2-past, and allowed null subjects elsewhere, with infinitives. NS/OI and Hebrew (Rhee & Wexler 1995) % of RIs kids up to 1;11 null subjects overt subjects 1/2 past/fut (NS) 0 (of 21) 0 (of 6) else (non-NS) 32% (36/112) 0 (of 28) all OI kids 1/2 past/fut (NS) else (non-NS) null subjects 0.6% (1/171) 25% (85/337) overt subjects 1.4% (1/72) 0.6% (3/530) Implementing ATOM The basic idea: In adult clauses, the subject needs to move both to SpecTP and (then) to SpecAgrP. This needs to happen because T “needs” something in its specifier (≈EPP) and so does Agr. The subject DP can “solve the problem” for both T and for Agr—for an adult. Implementing ATOM Implementation: For adults: T needs a D feature. Agr needs a D feature. The subject, happily, has a D feature. The subject moves to SpecTP, takes care of T’s need for a D feature (the subject “checks” the D feature on T). The T feature loses its need for a D feature, but the subject still has its D feature (the subject is still a DP). The subject moves on, to take care of Agr. Implementing ATOM Implementation: For kids: Everything is the same except that the subject can only solve one problem before quitting. It “loses” its D feature after helping out either T or Agr. Kids are constrained by the Unique Checking Constraint that says subjects (or their D features) can only “check” another feature once. So the kids are in a bind. Implementing ATOM Kids in a pickle: The only options open to the kids are: Leave out TP (keep AgrP, the subject can solve Agr’s problem alone). Result: nonfinite verb, nom case. Leave out AgrP (keep TP, the subject can solve T’s problem alone). Result: nonfinite verb, default case. Violate the UCC (let the subject do both things anyway). Result: finite verb, nom case. No matter which way you slice it, the kids have to do something “wrong”. At that point, they choose randomly (but cf. Legendre et al.) Minimalist terminology Features come in two relevant kinds: interpretable and uninterpretable. Either kind of feature can be involved in a “checking”—only interpretable features survive. The game is to have no uninterpretable features left at the end. “T needs a D” means “T has an uninterpretable [D] feature” and the subject (with its normally interpretable [D] feature) comes along and the two features “check”, the interpretable one survives. UCC=D uninterpretable on subjects? Wait—how can you say kids are UG-constrained yet drop T/Agr? So, aren’t TP and AgrSP required by UG? Doesn’t this mean kids don’t have UGcompliant trees? Actually, perhaps no. UG requires that all features be checked, but it isn’t clear that there is a UG principle that requires a TP and an AgrP in every clause. Wait—how can you say kids are UG-constrained yet drop T/Agr? Perhaps what requires TP and AgrP are principles of (pragmatic) interpretation… You need TP so that your sentence is “anchored” in the discourse. You need AgrSP … why? Well, perhaps something parallel…? Wexler doesn’t really say… Regardless, kids can check all the uninterpretable features even without TP or AgrSP; hence, they can still be considered to be UG-constrained. NS/OI via UCC An old idea about NS languages is that they arise in languages where Infl is “rich” enough to identify the subject. Maybe in NS languages, AgrS does not need a D (it may in some sense be nouny enough to say that it is, or already has, D). If AgrS does not need a D, the subject is free to check off T’s D-feature and be done. Is there any way to see the effects of UCC even in NS languages? Italian: Mary has laughed. Suppose that auxiliaries (like have) also have a D-feature to be checked as the subject (in the adult language) passes through. Not crazy: (All) the students (all) have (all) left. UCC-constrained kids will have to drop something (the auxiliary or T), even in Italian. Lyons (1997) reports that a “substantial proportion of auxiliaries are omitted in OI-age Italian.” Ok, maybe. Consistent, anyway. One open question… The UCC says you can only use a D-feature on a DP to check against a functional category once. This explains why sometimes TP is omitted (keeping AgrSP) and sometimes AgrSP is omitted (keeping TP). but if GEN infin. comes from omitting both TP and AgrSP, what could ever cause that (particularly given Minimize Violations)? Theories of missing structure No functional projections. (Radford) Kids don’t have any functional projections (TP, CP, and so forth). This comes later. No TP, no tense distinction. Structure building. (Vainikka, Guilfoyle & Noonan) Kids start with no functional projections and gradually increase their functional structure. Theories of missing structure “ATOM” (Full competence). (Wexler, …) Kids have access to all of the functional structure and have a very specific problem with tense and agreement that sometimes causes them to leave one out. Truncation. (Rizzi) Like structure building but without the time course—kids have access to all of the functional structure but they don’t realize that sentences need to be CP’s, so they sometimes stop early. Rizzi and truncated trees The result (of not having CP=root) is that kids are allowed to have truncated structures—trees that look like adult trees with the tops chopped off. Importantly: The kids don’t just leave stuff out—they just stop the tree “early.” So, if the kid leaves out a functional projection, s/he leaves out all higher XPs as well. Truncation If kid selects anything lower than TP as the root, the result is a root infinitive—which can be as big as any kind of XP below TP in the structure. Note in particular, though, it can’t be a CP. So: we expect that evidence of CP will correlate with finite verbs. Truncation Pierce (1989) looking at French observed that there are almost no root infinitives with subject clitics—this is predicted if these clitics are instances of subject agreement in AgrS; if there is no TP, there can be no AgrSP. Truncation There is some dispute in the syntax literature as to whether the position of NegP (the projection responsible for the negative morpheme) is higher or lower than TP in the tree. If NegP is higher than TP, we would expect not to find negative root infinitives. Truncation and NegP But we do find negative Root Infinitives— (Pierce 1989): in the acquisition of French, negation follows finite verbs and preceds nonfinite verbs (that is—French kids know the movement properties of finiteness, and thus they have the concept of finiteness). Truncation and NegP So, is TP higher than NegP? Hard to say conclusively from the existing French data because there are not many negative root infinitives—but further study could lead to a theoretical result of this sort about the adult languages. S O Vfin? Usually (Poeppel & Wexler 1993) German kids put finite verbs in second position, and leave nonfinite verbs at the end. Occasionally one finds a finite verb at the end. Rizzi suggests we could look at this as an instance of a kid choosing AgrSP as root, where CP is necessary to trigger V2. Legendre et al. (2000) Wexler: During OI stage, kids sometimes omit T, and sometimes omit Agr. Based on a choice of which to violate, the requirement to have T, to have Agr, to have only one. (cf. “Kids in a pickle” slide) Legendre et al.: Looking at development (of French), it appears that the choice of what to omit is systematic; we propose a system to account for (predict) the proportion of the time kids omit T, Agr, both, neither, in progressive stages of development. Optimality Theory Legendre et al. (2000) is set in the Optimality Theory framework (often seen in phonology, less often seen applied to syntax). “Grammar is a system of ranked and violable constraints” Optimality Theory In our analysis, one constraint is Parse-T, which says that tense must be realized in a clause. A structure without tense (where TP has been omitted, say) will violate this constraint. Another constraint is *F (“Don’t have a functional category”). A structure with TP will violate this constraint. Optimality Theory Parse-T and *F are in conflict—it is impossible to satisfy both at the same time. When constraints conflict, the choice made (on a language-particular basis) of which constraint is considered to be “more important” (more highly ranked) determines which constraint is satisfied and which must be violated. Optimality Theory So if *F >> Parse-T, TP will be omitted. and if Parse-T >> *F, TP will be included. Optimality Theory Grammar involves constraints on the representations (e.g., SS, LF, PF, or perhaps a combined representation). The constraints exist in all languages. Where languages differ is in how important each constraint is with respect to each other constraint. Optimality Theory: big picture Universal Grammar is the constraints that languages must obey. Languages differ only in how those constraints are ranked relative to one another. (So, “parameter” = “ranking”) The kid’s job is to re-rank constraints until they match the order which generated the input that s/he hears. Legendre et al. (2000) Proposes a system to predict the proportions of the time kids choose the different options among: Omit TP Omit AgrSP Omit both TP and AgrSP Include both TP and AgrSP (violating UCC) French v. English English: T+Agr is pronounced like /s/ if we have features [3, sg, present] /ed/ if we have the feature [past] /Ø/ otherwise French: T+Agr is pronounced like: danser a dansé je danse j’ai dansé NRF (3sg) past 1sg (present) 1sg past The idea Kids are subject to conflicting constraints: Parse-T Parse-Agr *F *F2 Include a projection for tense Include a project for agreement Don’t complicate your tree with functional projections Don’t complicate your tree so much as to have two functional projections. The idea Sometimes Parse-T beats out *F, and then there’s a TP. Or Parse-Agr beats out *F, and then there’s an AgrP. Or both Parse-T and Parse-Agr beat out *F2, and so there’s both a TP and an AgrP. But what does sometimes mean? Floating constraints The innovation in Legendre et al. (2000) that gets us off the ground is the idea that as kids re-rank constraints, the position of the constraint in the hierarchy can get somewhat fuzzy, such that two positions can overlap. *F Parse-T Floating constraints *F Parse-T When the kid evaluates a form in the constraint system, the position of ParseT is fixed somewhere in the range—and winds up sometimes outranking, and sometimes outranked by, *F. Floating constraints *F Parse-T (Under certain assumptions) this predicts that we would see TP in the structure 50% of the time, and see structures without TP the other 50% of the time. French kid data Looked at 3 French kids from CHILDES Broke development into stages based on a modified MLU-type measure based on how long most of their utterances were (2 words, more than 2 words) and how many of the utterances contain verbs. Looked at tense and agreement in each of the three stages represented in the data. French kid data Kids start out using 3sg agreement and present tense for practically everything (correct or not). We took this to be a “default” (No agreement? Pronounce it as 3sg. No tense? pronounce it as present. Neither? Pronounce it as an infinitive.). French kid data This means if a kid uses 3sg or present tense, we can’t tell if they are really using 3sg (they might be) or if they are not using agreement at all and just pronouncing the default. So, we looked at non-present tense forms and non-3sg forms only to avoid the question of the defaults. French kids data We found that tense and agreement develop differently—specifically, in the first stage we looked at, kids were using tense fine, but then in the next stage, they got worse as the agreement improved. Middle stage: looks like competition between T and Agr for a single node. A detail about counting We counted non-3sg and non-present verbs. In order to see how close kids’ utterances were to adult’s utterances, we need to know how often adults use non3sg and non-present, and then see how close the kids are to matching that level. So, adults use non-present tense around 31% of the time—so when a kid uses 31% non-present tense, we take that to be “100% success” In the last stage we looked at, kids were basically right at the “100% success” level for both tense and agreement. Proportion of non-present and non-3sg verbs 40% 35% 30% 25% non-present non-3sg adult non-pres adult non-3sg 20% 15% 10% 5% 0% 3b 4b 4c Proportion of non-finite root forms 35% 30% 25% 20% NRFs 15% 10% 5% 0% 3b 4b 4c A model to predict the percentages Stage 3b (first stage) no agreement about 1/3 NRFs, 2/3 tensed forms *F2 ParseT ParseA *F A model to predict the percentages Stage 4b (second stage) non-3sg agreement and non-present tense each about 15% (=about 40% agreeing, 50% tensed) about 20% NRFs *F2 ParseT ParseA *F A model to predict the percentages Stage 4c (third stage) everything appears to have tense and agreement (adult-like levels) *F2 ParseT ParseA *F Predicted vs. observed— tense 40% 35% 30% 25% non-present predicted non-pres 20% 15% 10% 5% 0% 3b 4b 4c Predicted vs. observed—agr’t 40% 35% 30% 25% non-3sg predicted non-3sg 20% 15% 10% 5% 0% 3b 4b 4c Predicted vs. observed— NRFs 35% 30% 25% 20% NRFs predicted NRFs 15% 10% 5% 0% 3b 4b 4c