Bayesian models of inductive learning Josh Tenenbaum & Tom Griffiths MIT Computational Cognitive Science Group Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences Computer Science and AI Lab (CSAIL) What to expect • What you’ll get out of this tutorial: – Our view of what Bayesian models have to offer cognitive science. – In-depth examples of basic and advanced models: how the math works & what it buys you. – Some comparison to other approaches. – Opportunities to ask questions. • What you won’t get: – Detailed, hands-on how-to. – Where you can learn more: http://bayesiancognition.com Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Bayesian models in cognitive science • • • • • Vision Motor control Memory Language Inductive learning and reasoning…. Everyday inductive leaps • Learning concepts and words from examples “horse” “horse” “horse” Learning concepts and words “tufa” “tufa” “tufa” Can you pick out the tufas? Inductive reasoning Input: Cows can get Hick’s disease. Gorillas can get Hick’s disease. (premises) All mammals can get Hick’s disease. (conclusion) Task: Judge how likely conclusion is to be true, given that premises are true. Inferring causal relations Input: Day 1 Day 2 Day 3 Day 4 ... Took vitamin B23 Headache yes yes no yes ... no yes yes no ... Does vitamin B23 cause headaches? Task: Judge probability of a causal link given several joint observations. Everyday inductive leaps How can we learn so much about . . . – – – – – – Properties of natural kinds Meanings of words Future outcomes of a dynamic process Hidden causal properties of an object Causes of a person’s action (beliefs, goals) Causal laws governing a domain . . . from such limited data? The Challenge • How do we generalize successfully from very limited data? – Just one or a few examples – Often only positive examples • Philosophy: – Induction is a “problem”, a “riddle”, a “paradox”, a “scandal”, or a “myth”. • Machine learning and statistics: – Focus on generalization from many examples, both positive and negative. Rational statistical inference (Bayes, Laplace) Posterior probability Likelihood Prior probability p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH Sum over space of hypotheses Bayesian models of inductive learning: some recent history • Shepard (1987) – Analysis of one-shot stimulus generalization, to explain the universal exponential law. • Anderson (1990) – Models of categorization and causal induction. • Oaksford & Chater (1994) – Model of conditional reasoning (Wason selection task). • Heit (1998) – Framework for category-based inductive reasoning. Theory-Based Bayesian Models • Rational statistical inference (Bayes): p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH • Learners’ domain theories generate their hypothesis space H and prior p(h). – Well-matched to structure of the natural world. – Learnable from limited data. – Computationally tractable inference. What is a theory? • Working definition – An ontology and a system of abstract principles that generates a hypothesis space of candidate world structures along with their relative probabilities. • Analogy to grammar in language. • Example: Newton’s laws Structure and statistics • A framework for understanding how structured knowledge and statistical inference interact. – How structured knowledge guides statistical inference, and is itself acquired through higher-order statistical learning. – How simplicity trades off with fit to the data in evaluating structural hypotheses. – How increasingly complex structures may grow as required by new data, rather than being pre-specified in advance. Structure and statistics • A framework for understanding how structured knowledge and statistical inference interact. – How structured knowledge guides statistical inference, and is itself acquired through higher-order statistical learning. Hierarchical Bayes. – How simplicity trades off with fit to the data in evaluating structural hypotheses. Bayesian Occam’s Razor. – How increasingly complex structures may grow as required by new data, rather than being pre-specified in advance. Non-parametric Bayes. Alternative approaches to inductive generalization • • • • • • Associative learning Connectionist networks Similarity to examples Toolkit of simple heuristics Constraint satisfaction Analogical mapping Marr’s Three Levels of Analysis • Computation: “What is the goal of the computation, why is it appropriate, and what is the logic of the strategy by which it can be carried out?” • Representation and algorithm: Cognitive psychology • Implementation: Neurobiology Why Bayes? • A framework for explaining cognition. – How people can learn so much from such limited data. – Why process-level models work the way that they do. – Strong quantitative models with minimal ad hoc assumptions. • A framework for understanding how structured knowledge and statistical inference interact. – How structured knowledge guides statistical inference, and is itself acquired through higher-order statistical learning. – How simplicity trades off with fit to the data in evaluating structural hypotheses (Occam’s razor). – How increasingly complex structures may grow as required by new data, rather than being pre-specified in advance. Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Coin flipping Coin flipping HHTHT HHHHH What process produced these sequences? Bayes’ rule For data D and a hypothesis H, we have: P( H ) P( D | H ) P( H | D) P( D) • “Posterior probability”: P ( H | D ) • “Prior probability”: P(H ) • “Likelihood”: P ( D | H ) The origin of Bayes’ rule • A simple consequence of using probability to represent degrees of belief • For any two random variables: p ( A & B ) p ( A) p ( B | A) p( A & B) p( B) p( A | B) p( B) p( A | B) p( A) p( B | A) p( A) p( B | A) p( A | B) p( B) Why represent degrees of belief with probabilities? • Good statistics – consistency, and worst-case error bounds. • Cox Axioms – necessary to cohere with common sense • “Dutch Book” + Survival of the Fittest – if your beliefs do not accord with the laws of probability, then you can always be out-gambled by someone whose beliefs do so accord. • Provides a theory of learning – a common currency for combining prior knowledge and the lessons of experience. Bayes’ rule For data D and a hypothesis H, we have: P( H ) P( D | H ) P( H | D) P( D) • “Posterior probability”: P ( H | D ) • “Prior probability”: P(H ) • “Likelihood”: P ( D | H ) Hypotheses in Bayesian inference • Hypotheses H refer to processes that could have generated the data D • Bayesian inference provides a distribution over these hypotheses, given D • P(D|H) is the probability of D being generated by the process identified by H • Hypotheses H are mutually exclusive: only one process could have generated D Hypotheses in coin flipping Describe processes by which D could be generated D = HHTHT • Fair coin, P(H) = 0.5 • Coin with P(H) = p • Markov model • Hidden Markov model • ... statistical models Hypotheses in coin flipping Describe processes by which D could be generated D = HHTHT • Fair coin, P(H) = 0.5 • Coin with P(H) = p • Markov model • Hidden Markov model • ... generative models Representing generative models • Graphical model notation – Pearl (1988), Jordan (1998) • Variables are nodes, edges indicate dependency • Directed edges show causal process of data generation HHTHT d1 d2 d3 d4 d5 d1 d2 d3 d4 Fair coin, P(H) = 0.5 d1 d2 d3 d4 Markov model Models with latent structure • Not all nodes in a graphical model need to be observed • Some variables reflect latent structure, used in generating D but unobserved HHTHT d1 d2 d3 d4 d5 p d1 d2 d3 d4 P(H) = p s1 s2 s3 s4 d1 d2 d3 d4 Hidden Markov model Coin flipping • Comparing two simple hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Comparing simple and complex hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = p • Comparing infinitely many hypotheses – P(H) = p • Psychology: Representativeness Coin flipping • Comparing two simple hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Comparing simple and complex hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = p • Comparing infinitely many hypotheses – P(H) = p • Psychology: Representativeness Comparing two simple hypotheses • Contrast simple hypotheses: – H1: “fair coin”, P(H) = 0.5 – H2:“always heads”, P(H) = 1.0 • Bayes’ rule: P( H ) P( D | H ) P( H | D) P( D) • With two hypotheses, use odds form Bayes’ rule in odds form P(H1|D) P(H2|D) D: H1, H2: P(H1|D): P(D|H1): P(H1): = P(D|H1) x P(D|H2) P(H1) P(H2) data models posterior probability H1 generated the data likelihood of data under model H1 prior probability H1 generated the data Coin flipping HHTHT HHHHH What process produced these sequences? Comparing two simple hypotheses P(H1|D) P(H2|D) D: = P(D|H1) x P(D|H2) P(H1) P(H2) HHTHT H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/25 P(H1) = 999/1000 P(D|H2) = 0 P(H2) = 1/1000 P(H1|D) / P(H2|D) = infinity Comparing two simple hypotheses P(H1|D) P(H2|D) D: = P(D|H1) x P(D|H2) P(H1) P(H2) HHHHH H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/25 P(H1) = 999/1000 P(D|H2) = 1 P(H2) = 1/1000 P(H1|D) / P(H2|D) 30 Comparing two simple hypotheses P(H1|D) P(H2|D) D: = P(D|H1) x P(D|H2) P(H1) P(H2) HHHHHHHHHH H1, H2: “fair coin”, “always heads” P(D|H1) = 1/210 P(H1) = 999/1000 P(D|H2) = 1 P(H2) = 1/1000 P(H1|D) / P(H2|D) 1 Comparing two simple hypotheses • Bayes’ rule tells us how to combine prior beliefs with new data – top-down and bottom-up influences • As a model of human inference – predicts conclusions drawn from data – identifies point at which prior beliefs are overwhelmed by new experiences • But… more complex cases? Coin flipping • Comparing two simple hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Comparing simple and complex hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = p • Comparing infinitely many hypotheses – P(H) = p • Psychology: Representativeness Comparing simple and complex hypotheses p d1 d2 d3 d4 Fair coin, P(H) = 0.5 vs. d1 d2 d3 d4 P(H) = p • Which provides a better account of the data: the simple hypothesis of a fair coin, or the complex hypothesis that P(H) = p? Comparing simple and complex hypotheses • P(H) = p is more complex than P(H) = 0.5 in two ways: – P(H) = 0.5 is a special case of P(H) = p – for any observed sequence X, we can choose p such that X is more probable than if P(H) = 0.5 Probability Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Probability Comparing simple and complex hypotheses HHHHH p = 1.0 Probability Comparing simple and complex hypotheses HHTHT p = 0.6 Comparing simple and complex hypotheses • P(H) = p is more complex than P(H) = 0.5 in two ways: – P(H) = 0.5 is a special case of P(H) = p – for any observed sequence X, we can choose p such that X is more probable than if P(H) = 0.5 • How can we deal with this? – frequentist: hypothesis testing – information theorist: minimum description length – Bayesian: just use probability theory! Comparing simple and complex hypotheses P(H1|D) P(H2|D) P(D|H1) = P(D|H2) P(H1) x P(H2) Computing P(D|H1) is easy: P(D|H1) = 1/2N Compute P(D|H2) by averaging over p: Probability Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Distribution is an average over all values of p Probability Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Distribution is an average over all values of p Comparing simple and complex hypotheses • Simple and complex hypotheses can be compared directly using Bayes’ rule – requires summing over latent variables • Complex hypotheses are penalized for their greater flexibility: “Bayesian Occam’s razor” • This principle is used in model selection methods in psychology (e.g. Myung & Pitt, 1997) Coin flipping • Comparing two simple hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Comparing simple and complex hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = p • Comparing infinitely many hypotheses – P(H) = p • Psychology: Representativeness Comparing infinitely many hypotheses • Assume data are generated from a model: p d1 d2 d3 d4 P(H) = p • What is the value of p? – each value of p is a hypothesis H – requires inference over infinitely many hypotheses Comparing infinitely many hypotheses • Flip a coin 10 times and see 5 heads, 5 tails. • P(H) on next flip? 50% • Why? 50% = 5 / (5+5) = 5/10. • “Future will be like the past.” • Suppose we had seen 4 heads and 6 tails. • P(H) on next flip? Closer to 50% than to 40%. • Why? Prior knowledge. Integrating prior knowledge and data P( H ) P( D | H ) P( H | D) P( D) P(p | D) P(D | p) P(p) • Posterior distribution P(p | D) is a probability density over p = P(H) • Need to work out likelihood P(D | p) and specify prior distribution P(p) Likelihood and prior • Likelihood: P(D | p) = pNH (1-p)NT – NH: number of heads – NT: number of tails • Prior: P(p) pFH-1 (1-p)FT-1 ? A simple method of specifying priors • Imagine some fictitious trials, reflecting a set of previous experiences – strategy often used with neural networks • e.g., F ={1000 heads, 1000 tails} ~ strong expectation that any new coin will be fair • In fact, this is a sensible statistical idea... Likelihood and prior • Likelihood: P(D | p) = pNH (1-p)NT – NH: number of heads – NT: number of tails • Prior: P(p) pFH-1 (1-p)FT-1 Beta(FH,FT) – FH: fictitious observations of heads – FT: fictitious observations of tails Conjugate priors • Exist for many standard distributions – formula for exponential family conjugacy • Define prior in terms of fictitious observations • Beta is conjugate to Bernoulli (coin-flipping) FH = FT = 1 FH = FT = 3 FH = FT = 1000 Likelihood and prior • Likelihood: P(D | p) = pNH (1-p)NT – NH: number of heads – NT: number of tails • Prior: P(p) pFH-1 (1-p)FT-1 – FH: fictitious observations of heads – FT: fictitious observations of tails Comparing infinitely many hypotheses P(p | D) P(D | p) P(p) = pNH+FH-1 (1-p)NT+FT-1 • Posterior is Beta(NH+FH,NT+FT) – same form as conjugate prior • Posterior mean: • Posterior predictive distribution: Some examples • e.g., F ={1000 heads, 1000 tails} ~ strong expectation that any new coin will be fair • After seeing 4 heads, 6 tails, P(H) on next flip = 1004 / (1004+1006) = 49.95% • e.g., F ={3 heads, 3 tails} ~ weak expectation that any new coin will be fair • After seeing 4 heads, 6 tails, P(H) on next flip = 7 / (7+9) = 43.75% Prior knowledge too weak But… flipping thumbtacks • e.g., F ={4 heads, 3 tails} ~ weak expectation that tacks are slightly biased towards heads • After seeing 2 heads, 0 tails, P(H) on next flip = 6 / (6+3) = 67% • Some prior knowledge is always necessary to avoid jumping to hasty conclusions... • Suppose F = { }: After seeing 2 heads, 0 tails, P(H) on next flip = 2 / (2+0) = 100% Origin of prior knowledge • Tempting answer: prior experience • Suppose you have previously seen 2000 coin flips: 1000 heads, 1000 tails • By assuming all coins (and flips) are alike, these observations of other coins are as good as observations of the present coin Problems with simple empiricism • Haven’t really seen 2000 coin flips, or any flips of a thumbtack – Prior knowledge is stronger than raw experience justifies • Haven’t seen exactly equal number of heads and tails – Prior knowledge is smoother than raw experience justifies • Should be a difference between observing 2000 flips of a single coin versus observing 10 flips each for 200 coins, or 1 flip each for 2000 coins – Prior knowledge is more structured than raw experience A simple theory • “Coins are manufactured by a standardized procedure that is effective but not perfect.” – Justifies generalizing from previous coins to the present coin. – Justifies smoother and stronger prior than raw experience alone. – Explains why seeing 10 flips each for 200 coins is more valuable than seeing 2000 flips of one coin. • “Tacks are asymmetric, and manufactured to less exacting standards.” Limitations • Can all domain knowledge be represented so simply, in terms of an equivalent number of fictional observations? • Suppose you flip a coin 25 times and get all heads. Something funny is going on… • But with F ={1000 heads, 1000 tails}, P(H) on next flip = 1025 / (1025+1000) = 50.6%. Looks like nothing unusual Hierarchical priors • Higher-order hypothesis: is this coin fair or unfair? • Example probabilities: – P(fair) = 0.99 – P(p|fair) is Beta(1000,1000) – P(p|unfair) is Beta(1,1) • 25 heads in a row propagates up, affecting p and then P(fair|D) fair p d1 d2 d3 d4 P(fair|25 heads) P(25 heads|fair) P(fair) = 9 x 10-5 = P(unfair|25 heads) P(25 heads|unfair) P(unfair) More hierarchical priors • Latent structure can capture coin variability p ~ Beta(FH,FT) FH,FT Coin 1 d1 Coin 2 p d2 d3 d4 d1 d2 ... p d3 d4 p Coin 200 d1 d2 d3 • 10 flips from 200 coins is better than 2000 flips from a single coin: allows estimation of FH, FT d4 Yet more hierarchical priors physical knowledge FH,FT p d1 d2 p d3 d4 d1 d2 p d3 d4 d1 d2 d3 d4 • Discrete beliefs (e.g. symmetry) can influence estimation of continuous properties (e.g. FH, FT) Comparing infinitely many hypotheses • Apply Bayes’ rule to obtain posterior probability density • Requires prior over all hypotheses – computation simplified by conjugate priors – richer structure with hierarchical priors • Hierarchical priors indicate how simple theories can inform statistical inferences – one step towards structure and statistics Coin flipping • Comparing two simple hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = 1.0 • Comparing simple and complex hypotheses – P(H) = 0.5 vs. P(H) = p • Comparing infinitely many hypotheses – P(H) = p • Psychology: Representativeness Psychology: Representativeness Which sequence is more likely from a fair coin? HHTHT HHHHH more representative of a fair coin (Kahneman & Tversky, 1972) What might representativeness mean? Evidence for a random generating process P(H1|D) P(H2|D) P(D|H1) = P(D|H2) likelihood ratio H1: random process (fair coin) H2: alternative processes P(H1) x P(H2) A constrained hypothesis space Four hypotheses: h1 h2 h3 h4 fair coin “always alternates” “mostly heads” “always heads” HHTHTTTH HTHTHTHT HHTHTHHH HHHHHHHH Representativeness judgments Results • Good account of representativeness data, with three pseudo-free parameters, = 0.91 – “always alternates” means 99% of the time – “mostly heads” means P(H) = 0.85 – “always heads” means P(H) = 0.99 • With scaling parameter, r = 0.95 (Tenenbaum & Griffiths, 2001) The role of theories The fact that HHTHT looks representative of a fair coin and HHHHH does not reflects our implicit theories of how the world works. – Easy to imagine how a trick all-heads coin could work: high prior probability. – Hard to imagine how a trick “HHTHT” coin could work: low prior probability. Summary • Three kinds of Bayesian inference – comparing two simple hypotheses – comparing simple and complex hypotheses – comparing an infinite number of hypotheses • Critical notions: – generative models, graphical models – Bayesian Occam’s razor – priors: conjugate, hierarchical (theories) Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Rules and similarity Structure versus statistics Rules Logic Symbols Statistics Similarity Typicality A better metaphor A better metaphor Structure and statistics Statistics Similarity Typicality Rules Logic Symbols Structure and statistics • Basic case study #1: Flipping coins – Learning and reasoning with structured statistical models. • Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity – Statistical learning with structured representations. The number game • Program input: number between 1 and 100 • Program output: “yes” or “no” The number game • Learning task: – Observe one or more positive (“yes”) examples. – Judge whether other numbers are “yes” or “no”. The number game Examples of “yes” numbers Generalization judgments (N = 20) 60 Diffuse similarity The number game Examples of “yes” numbers Generalization judgments (n = 20) 60 Diffuse similarity 60 80 10 30 Rule: “multiples of 10” The number game Examples of “yes” numbers Generalization judgments (N = 20) 60 Diffuse similarity 60 80 10 30 Rule: “multiples of 10” 60 52 57 55 Focused similarity: numbers near 50-60 The number game Examples of “yes” numbers Generalization judgments (N = 20) 16 Diffuse similarity 16 8 2 64 Rule: “powers of 2” 16 23 19 20 Focused similarity: numbers near 20 The number game 60 Diffuse similarity 60 80 10 30 Rule: “multiples of 10” 60 52 57 55 Focused similarity: numbers near 50-60 Main phenomena to explain: – Generalization can appear either similaritybased (graded) or rule-based (all-or-none). – Learning from just a few positive examples. Rule/similarity hybrid models • Category learning – Nosofsky, Palmeri et al.: RULEX – Erickson & Kruschke: ATRIUM Divisions into “rule” and “similarity” subsystems • Category learning – Nosofsky, Palmeri et al.: RULEX – Erickson & Kruschke: ATRIUM • Language processing – Pinker, Marcus et al.: Past tense morphology • Reasoning – Sloman – Rips – Nisbett, Smith et al. Rule/similarity hybrid models • Why two modules? • Why do these modules work the way that they do, and interact as they do? • How do people infer a rule or similarity metric from just a few positive examples? Bayesian model • H: Hypothesis space of possible concepts: – – – – – h1 = {2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, …, 96, 98, 100} (“even numbers”) h2 = {10, 20, 30, 40, …, 90, 100} (“multiples of 10”) h3 = {2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64} (“powers of 2”) h4 = {50, 51, 52, …, 59, 60} (“numbers between 50 and 60”) ... Representational interpretations for H: – Candidate rules – Features for similarity – “Consequential subsets” (Shepard, 1987) Inferring hypotheses from similarity judgment Additive clustering (Shepard & Arabie, 1977): sij wk fik f jk k sij : similarity of stimuli i, j wk : weight of cluster k f ik : membership of stimulus i in cluster k (1 if stimulus i in cluster k, 0 otherwise) Equivalent to similarity as a weighted sum of common features (Tversky, 1977). Additive clustering for the integers 0-9: sij wk fik f jk k Rank Weight Stimuli in cluster Interpretation 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 1 .444 * * 2 .345 * * * 3 .331 4 .291 5 .255 6 .216 * 7 .214 * * * * 8 .172 * powers of two small numbers * * * * * * * * * * * * * * multiples of three large numbers middle numbers * * * * * * * odd numbers smallish numbers largish numbers Three hypothesis subspaces for number concepts • Mathematical properties (24 hypotheses): – Odd, even, square, cube, prime numbers – Multiples of small integers – Powers of small integers • Raw magnitude (5050 hypotheses): – All intervals of integers with endpoints between 1 and 100. • Approximate magnitude (10 hypotheses): – Decades (1-10, 10-20, 20-30, …) Hypothesis spaces and theories • Why a hypothesis space is like a domain theory: – Represents one particular way of classifying entities in a domain. – Not just an arbitrary collection of hypotheses, but a principled system. • What’s missing? – Explicit representation of the principles. • Hypothesis spaces (and priors) are generated by theories. Some analogies: – Grammars generate languages (and priors over structural descriptions) – Hierarchical Bayesian modeling Bayesian model • H: Hypothesis space of possible concepts: – Mathematical properties: even, odd, square, prime, . . . . – Approximate magnitude: {1-10}, {10-20}, {20-30}, . . . . – Raw magnitude: all intervals between 1 and 100. • X = {x1, . . . , xn}: n examples of a concept C. • Evaluate hypotheses given data: p ( X | h) p ( h) p(h | X ) p( X ) – p(h) [“prior”]: domain knowledge, pre-existing biases – p(X|h) [“likelihood”]: statistical information in examples. – p(h|X) [“posterior”]: degree of belief that h is the true extension of C. Bayesian model • H: Hypothesis space of possible concepts: – Mathematical properties: even, odd, square, prime, . . . . – Approximate magnitude: {1-10}, {10-20}, {20-30}, . . . . – Raw magnitude: all intervals between 1 and 100. • X = {x1, . . . , xn}: n examples of a concept C. • Evaluate hypotheses given data: p ( X | h) p ( h) p(h | X ) p( X | h) p(h) hH – p(h) [“prior”]: domain knowledge, pre-existing biases – p(X|h) [“likelihood”]: statistical information in examples. – p(h|X) [“posterior”]: degree of belief that h is the true extension of C. Likelihood: p(X|h) • Size principle: Smaller hypotheses receive greater likelihood, and exponentially more so as n increases. n 1 p ( X | h) if x1 , , xn h size( h) 0 if any xi h • Follows from assumption of randomly sampled examples. • Captures the intuition of a representative sample. Illustrating the size principle h1 2 12 22 32 42 52 62 72 82 92 4 14 24 34 44 54 64 74 84 94 6 16 26 36 46 56 66 76 86 96 8 10 18 20 28 30 38 40 48 50 58 60 68 70 78 80 88 90 98 100 h2 Illustrating the size principle h1 2 12 22 32 42 52 62 72 82 92 4 14 24 34 44 54 64 74 84 94 6 16 26 36 46 56 66 76 86 96 8 10 18 20 28 30 38 40 48 50 58 60 68 70 78 80 88 90 98 100 h2 Data slightly more of a coincidence under h1 Illustrating the size principle h1 2 12 22 32 42 52 62 72 82 92 4 14 24 34 44 54 64 74 84 94 6 16 26 36 46 56 66 76 86 96 8 10 18 20 28 30 38 40 48 50 58 60 68 70 78 80 88 90 98 100 h2 Data much more of a coincidence under h1 Bayesian Occam’s Razor p(D = d | M ) M1 Law of “Conservation of Belief” M2 All possible data sets d For any model M, all d D p(D d | M ) 1 Probability Comparing simple and complex hypotheses Distribution is an average over all values of p Prior: p(h) • Choice of hypothesis space embodies a strong prior: effectively, p(h) ~ 0 for many logically possible but conceptually unnatural hypotheses. • Prevents overfitting by highly specific but unnatural hypotheses, e.g. “multiples of 10 except 50 and 70”. Prior: p(h) • Choice of hypothesis space embodies a strong prior: effectively, p(h) ~ 0 for many logically possible but conceptually unnatural hypotheses. • Prevents overfitting by highly specific but unnatural hypotheses, e.g. “multiples of 10 except 50 and 70”. • p(h) encodes relative weights of alternative theories: H: Total hypothesis space p(H1) = 1/5 p(H2) = 3/5 p(H3) = 1/5 H1: Math properties (24) H2: Raw magnitude (5050) H3: Approx. magnitude (10) • even numbers • powers of two • multiples of three …. p(h) = p(H1) / 24 • 10-15 • 20-32 • 37-54 …. p(h) = p(H2) / 5050 • 10-20 • 20-30 • 30-40 …. p(h) = p(H3) / 10 A more complex approach to priors • Start with a base set of regularities R and combination operators C. • Hypothesis space = closure of R under C. – C = {and, or}: H = unions and intersections of regularities in R (e.g., “multiples of 10 between 30 and 70”). – C = {and-not}: H = regularities in R with exceptions (e.g., “multiples of 10 except 50 and 70”). • Two qualitatively similar priors: – Description length: number of combinations in C needed to generate hypothesis from R. – Bayesian Occam’s Razor, with model classes defined by number of combinations: more combinations more hypotheses lower prior Posterior: p ( X | h) p ( h) p(h | X ) p( X | h) p(h) hH • X = {60, 80, 10, 30} • Why prefer “multiples of 10” over “even numbers”? p(X|h). • Why prefer “multiples of 10” over “multiples of 10 except 50 and 20”? p(h). • Why does a good generalization need both high prior and high likelihood? p(h|X) ~ p(X|h) p(h) Bayesian Occam’s Razor Probabilities provide a common currency for balancing model complexity with fit to the data. Generalizing to new objects Given p(h|X), how do we compute p( y C | X ) , p( y the probability that C applies to some new hH stimulus y? Generalizing to new objects Hypothesis averaging: Compute the probability that C applies to some new object y by averaging the predictions of all hypotheses h, weighted by p(h|X): p( y C | X ) y C | h) p ( h | X ) p( hH 1 if yh 0 if yh h { y, X } p(h | X ) Examples: 16 Connection to feature-based similarity • Additive clustering model of similarity: sij wk fik f jk k • Bayesian hypothesis averaging: p( y C | X ) p( y Cp(| hX)| |Xph()hp| (Xh) h H{ y, X } h • Equivalent if we identify features fk with hypotheses h, and weights wk with p(h | X ) . Examples: 16 8 2 64 Examples: 16 23 19 20 Model fits Examples of “yes” numbers 60 60 80 10 30 60 52 57 55 Generalization judgments (N = 20) Bayesian Model (r = 0.96) Model fits Examples of “yes” numbers 16 16 8 2 64 16 23 19 20 Generalization judgments (N = 20) Bayesian Model (r = 0.93) Summary of the Bayesian model • How do the statistics of the examples interact with prior knowledge to guide generalization? posterior likelihood prior • Why does generalization appear rule-based or similarity-based? hypothesis averaging size principle broad p(h|X): similarity gradient narrow p(h|X): all-or-none rule Summary of the Bayesian model • How do the statistics of the examples interact with prior knowledge to guide generalization? posterior likelihood prior • Why does generalization appear rule-based or similarity-based? hypothesis averaging size principle Many h of similar size: broad p(h|X) One h much smaller: narrow p(h|X) Alternative models • Neural networks even 60 80 10 30 multiple of 10 multiple of 3 power of 2 Alternative models • Neural networks • Hypothesis ranking and elimination Hypothesis ranking: 60 80 10 30 1 2 3 4 …. even multiple of 10 multiple of 3 power of 2 …. Alternative models • Neural networks • Hypothesis ranking and elimination • Similarity to exemplars 1 sim ( y, x j ) – Average similarity: p( y C | X ) | X | x X j 60 60 80 10 30 60 52 57 55 Data Model (r = 0.80) Alternative models • Neural networks • Hypothesis ranking and elimination • Similarity to exemplars – Max similarity: p( y C | X ) max sim ( y, x j ) x j X 60 60 80 10 30 60 52 57 55 Data Model (r = 0.64) Alternative models • Neural networks • Hypothesis ranking and elimination • Similarity to exemplars – Average similarity – Max similarity – Flexible similarity? Bayes. Alternative models • • • • Neural networks Hypothesis ranking and elimination Similarity to exemplars Toolbox of simple heuristics – 60: “general” similarity – 60 80 10 30: most specific rule (“subset principle”). – 60 52 57 55: similarity in magnitude Why these heuristics? When to use which heuristic? Bayes. Summary • Generalization from limited data possible via the interaction of structured knowledge and statistics. – Structured knowledge: space of candidate rules, theories generate hypothesis space (c.f. hierarchical priors) – Statistics: Bayesian Occam’s razor. • Better understand the interactions between traditionally opposing concepts: – Rules and statistics – Rules and similarity – Rules and representativeness • Explains why central but notoriously slippery processing-level concepts work the way they do. – Similarity – Representativeness Why Bayes? • A framework for explaining cognition. – How people can learn so much from such limited data. – Why process-level models work the way that they do. – Strong quantitative models with minimal ad hoc assumptions. • A framework for understanding how structured knowledge and statistical inference interact. – How structured knowledge guides statistical inference, and is itself acquired through higher-order statistical learning. – How simplicity trades off with fit to the data in evaluating structural hypotheses (Occam’s razor). – How increasingly complex structures may grow as required by new data, rather than being pre-specified in advance. Theory-Based Bayesian Models • Rational statistical inference (Bayes): p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH • Learners’ domain theories generate their hypothesis space H and prior p(h). – Well-matched to structure of the natural world. – Learnable from limited data. – Computationally tractable inference. Looking towards the afternoon • How do we apply these ideas to more natural and complex aspects of cognition? • Where do the hypothesis spaces come from? • Can we formalize the contributions of domain theories? Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Marr’s Three Levels of Analysis • Computation: “What is the goal of the computation, why is it appropriate, and what is the logic of the strategy by which it can be carried out?” • Representation and algorithm: Cognitive psychology • Implementation: Neurobiology Working at the computational level statistical • What is the computational problem? – input: data – output: solution Working at the computational level statistical • What is the computational problem? – input: data – output: solution • What knowledge is available to the learner? • Where does that knowledge come from? Theory-Based Bayesian Models • Rational statistical inference (Bayes): p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH • Learners’ domain theories generate their hypothesis space H and prior p(h). – Well-matched to structure of the natural world. – Learnable from limited data. – Computationally tractable inference. Causality Bayes nets and beyond... • Increasingly popular approach to studying human causal inferences (e.g. Glymour, 2001; Gopnik et al., 2004) • Three reactions: – Bayes nets are the solution! – Bayes nets are missing the point, not sure why… – what is a Bayes net? Bayes nets and beyond... • What are Bayes nets? – graphical models – causal graphical models • An example: elemental causal induction • Beyond Bayes nets… – other knowledge in causal induction – formalizing causal theories Bayes nets and beyond... • What are Bayes nets? – graphical models – causal graphical models • An example: elemental causal induction • Beyond Bayes nets… – other knowledge in causal induction – formalizing causal theories Graphical models • Express the probabilistic dependency structure among a set of variables (Pearl, 1988) • Consist of – a set of nodes, corresponding to variables – a set of edges, indicating dependency – a set of functions defined on the graph that defines a probability distribution Undirected graphical models • Consist of X1 X3 X4 – a set of nodes X2 X5 – a set of edges – a potential for each clique, multiplied together to yield the distribution over variables • Examples – statistical physics: Ising model, spinglasses – early neural networks (e.g. Boltzmann machines) Directed graphical models • Consist of X1 X3 X4 – a set of nodes X2 X5 – a set of edges – a conditional probability distribution for each node, conditioned on its parents, multiplied together to yield the distribution over variables • Constrained to directed acyclic graphs (DAG) • AKA: Bayesian networks, Bayes nets Bayesian networks and Bayes • Two different problems – Bayesian statistics is a method of inference – Bayesian networks are a form of representation • There is no necessary connection – many users of Bayesian networks rely upon frequentist statistical methods (e.g. Glymour) – many Bayesian inferences cannot be easily represented using Bayesian networks Properties of Bayesian networks • Efficient representation and inference – exploiting dependency structure makes it easier to represent and compute with probabilities • Explaining away – pattern of probabilistic reasoning characteristic of Bayesian networks, especially early use in AI Efficient representation and inference • Three binary variables: Cavity, Toothache, Catch Efficient representation and inference • Three binary variables: Cavity, Toothache, Catch • Specifying P(Cavity, Toothache, Catch) requires 7 parameters (1 for each set of values, minus 1 because it’s a probability distribution) • With n variables, we need 2n -1 parameters • Here n=3. Realistically, many more: X-ray, diet, oral hygiene, personality, . . . . Conditional independence • All three variables are dependent, but Toothache and Catch are independent given the presence or absence of Cavity • In probabilistic terms: P(ache catch | cav) P(ache | cav) P(catch | cav) P(ache catch | cav) P(ache | cav) P(catch | cav) 1 P(ache | cav)P(catch | cav) • With n evidence variables, x1, …, xn, we need 2 n conditional probabilities: P( xi | cav), P( xi | cav) A simple Bayesian network • Graphical representation of relations between a set of random variables: Cavity Toothache Catch • Probabilistic interpretation: factorizing complex terms P( A, B, C ) P(V | parents [V ]) V { A, B,C} P( Ache, Catch, Cav) P( Ache, Catch | Cav) P(Cav) P( Ache | Cav) P(Catch | Cav) P(Cav) A more complex system Battery Radio Ignition Gas Starts On time to work • Joint distribution sufficient for any inference: P( B, R, I , G, S , O) P( B) P( R | B) P( I | B) P(G ) P( S | I , G ) P(O | S ) P( B) P( R | B) P( I | B) P(G) P(S | I , G) P(O | S ) P(O, G ) B, R, I , S P(O | G ) P(G ) P(G ) A more complex system Battery Radio Ignition Gas Starts On time to work • Joint distribution sufficient for any inference: P( B, R, I , G, S , O) P( B) P( R | B) P( I | B) P(G ) P( S | I , G ) P(O | S ) P(O, G ) P(O | G ) P( B) P( I | B) P( S | I , G ) P(O | S ) P(G ) S B, I A more complex system Battery Radio Ignition Gas Starts On time to work • Joint distribution sufficient for any inference: P( B, R, I , G, S , O) P( B) P( R | B) P( I | B) P(G ) P( S | I , G ) P(O | S ) • General inference algorithm: local message passing (belief propagation; Pearl, 1988) – efficiency depends on sparseness of graph structure Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) • Assume grass will be wet if and only if it rained last night, or if the sprinklers were left on: P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet: P(r | w) P( w | r ) P(r ) P( w) Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet: P( w | r ) P(r ) P(r | w) P(w | r, s) P(r, s) r , s Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet: P(r | w) P(r ) P(r , s) P(r , s) P(r , s) Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet: P(r ) P(r | w) P(r ) P(r , s) Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet: P(r | w) P(r ) P(r ) P(r ) P( s) Between 1 and P(s) P (r ) Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet and sprinklers were left on: P(r | w, s) P( w | r , s ) P(r | s ) P( w | s ) Both terms = 1 Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. Compute probability it rained last night, given that the grass is wet and sprinklers were left on: P(r | w, s ) P(r | s ) P (r ) Explaining away Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet P( R, S ,W ) P( R) P( S ) P(W | S , R) P(W w | S , R) 1 if S s or R r 0 if R r and S s. P(r ) P(r ) P(r ) P( s) P(r | w, s ) P(r | s ) P (r ) P(r | w) P (r ) “Discounting” to prior probability. Contrast w/ production system Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet • Formulate IF-THEN rules: – IF Rain THEN Wet – IF Wet THEN Rain IF Wet AND NOT Sprinkler THEN Rain • Rules do not distinguish directions of inference • Requires combinatorial explosion of rules Contrast w/ spreading activation Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet • Excitatory links: Rain Wet, Sprinkler Wet • Observing rain, Wet becomes more active. • Observing grass wet, Rain and Sprinkler become more active. • Observing grass wet and sprinkler, Rain cannot become less active. No explaining away! Contrast w/ spreading activation Rain Sprinkler Grass Wet • Excitatory links: Rain • Inhibitory link: Rain Wet, Sprinkler Sprinkler Wet • Observing grass wet, Rain and Sprinkler become more active. • Observing grass wet and sprinkler, Rain becomes less active: explaining away. Contrast w/ spreading activation Rain Burst pipe Sprinkler Grass Wet • Each new variable requires more inhibitory connections. • Interactions between variables are not causal. • Not modular. – Whether a connection exists depends on what other connections exist, in non-transparent ways. – Big holism problem. – Combinatorial explosion. Graphical models • Capture dependency structure in distributions • Provide an efficient means of representing and reasoning with probabilities • Allow kinds of inference that are problematic for other representations: explaining away – hard to capture in a production system – hard to capture with spreading activation Bayes nets and beyond... • What are Bayes nets? – graphical models – causal graphical models • An example: causal induction • Beyond Bayes nets… – other knowledge in causal induction – formalizing causal theories Causal graphical models • Graphical models represent statistical dependencies among variables (ie. correlations) – can answer questions about observations • Causal graphical models represent causal dependencies among variables – express underlying causal structure – can answer questions about both observations and interventions (actions upon a variable) Observation and intervention Battery Radio Ignition Gas Starts On time to work Graphical model: P(Radio|Ignition) Causal graphical model: P(Radio|do(Ignition)) Observation and intervention Battery Radio Ignition Gas Starts On time to work Graphical model: P(Radio|Ignition) Causal graphical model: P(Radio|do(Ignition)) “graph surgery” produces “mutilated graph” Assessing interventions • To compute P(Y|do(X=x)), delete all edges coming into X and reason with the resulting Bayesian network (“do calculus”; Pearl, 2000) • Allows a single structure to make predictions about both observations and interventions Causality simplifies inference • Using a representation in which the direction of causality is correct produces sparser graphs • Suppose we get the direction of causality wrong, thinking that “symptoms” causes “diseases”: Ache Catch Cavity • Does not capture the correlation between symptoms: falsely believe P(Ache, Catch) = P(Ache) P(Catch). Causality simplifies inference • Using a representation in which the direction of causality is correct produces sparser graphs • Suppose we get the direction of causality wrong, thinking that “symptoms” causes “diseases”: Ache Catch Cavity • Inserting a new arrow allows us to capture this correlation. • This model is too complex: do not believe that P( Ache, Catch | Cav) P( Ache | Cav) P(Catch | Cav) Causality simplifies inference • Using a representation in which the direction of causality is correct produces sparser graphs • Suppose we get the direction of causality wrong, thinking that “symptoms” causes “diseases”: Ache X-ray Catch Cavity • New symptoms require a combinatorial proliferation of new arrows. This reduces efficiency of inference. Learning causal graphical models C B E C B E • Strength: how strong is a relationship? • Structure: does a relationship exist? Causal structure vs. causal strength C B E C B E • Strength: how strong is a relationship? Causal structure vs. causal strength B C B w0 w1 w0 E C E • Strength: how strong is a relationship? – requires defining nature of relationship Parameterization • Structures: h1 = C B h0 = E E • Parameterization: C B 0 1 0 1 0 0 1 1 Generic h1: P(E = 1 | C, B) p00 p10 p01 p11 C B h0: P(E = 1| C, B) p0 p0 p1 p1 Parameterization • Structures: h1 = B C w0 w1 h0 = C B w0 E E w0, w1: strength parameters for B, C • Parameterization: C B 0 1 0 1 0 0 1 1 Linear h1: P(E = 1 | C, B) 0 w1 w0 w1+ w0 h0: P(E = 1| C, B) 0 0 w0 w0 Parameterization • Structures: h1 = B C w0 w1 h0 = C B w0 E E w0, w1: strength parameters for B, C • Parameterization: C B 0 1 0 1 0 0 1 1 “Noisy-OR” h1: P(E = 1 | C, B) 0 w1 w0 w1+ w0 – w1 w0 h0: P(E = 1| C, B) 0 0 w0 w0 Parameter estimation • Maximum likelihood estimation: maximize i P(bi,ci,ei; w0, w1) • Bayesian methods: as in the “Comparing infinitely many hypotheses” example… Causal structure vs. causal strength C B E C B E • Structure: does a relationship exist? Approaches to structure learning • Constraint-based C B – dependency from statistical tests (eg. 2) – deduce structure from dependencies E (Pearl, 2000; Spirtes et al., 1993) Approaches to structure learning • Constraint-based: C B – dependency from statistical tests (eg. 2) – deduce structure from dependencies E (Pearl, 2000; Spirtes et al., 1993) Approaches to structure learning • Constraint-based: C B – dependency from statistical tests (eg. 2) – deduce structure from dependencies E (Pearl, 2000; Spirtes et al., 1993) Approaches to structure learning • Constraint-based: C B – dependency from statistical tests (eg. 2) – deduce structure from dependencies E (Pearl, 2000; Spirtes et al., 1993) Attempts to reduce inductive problem to deductive problem Approaches to structure learning • Constraint-based: C B – dependency from statistical tests (eg. 2) – deduce structure from dependencies E (Pearl, 2000; Spirtes et al., 1993) • Bayesian: – compute posterior probability of structures, given observed data P(S|data) P(data|S) P(S) C B C B E E P(S1|data) P(S0|data) (Heckerman, 1998; Friedman, 1999) Causal graphical models • Extend graphical models to deal with interventions as well as observations • Respecting the direction of causality results in efficient representation and inference • Two steps in learning causal models – parameter estimation – structure learning Bayes nets and beyond... • What are Bayes nets? – graphical models – causal graphical models • An example: elemental causal induction • Beyond Bayes nets… – other knowledge in causal induction – formalizing causal theories Elemental causal induction C present C absent E present a c E absent b d “To what extent does C cause E?” Causal structure vs. causal strength B C B w0 w1 w0 E C E • Strength: how strong is a relationship? • Structure: does a relationship exist? Causal strength • Assume structure: B C w0 w1 E • Leading models (DP and causal power) are maximum likelihood estimates of the strength parameter w1, under different parameterizations for P(E|B,C): – linear DP, Noisy-OR causal power Causal structure • Hypotheses: h1 = C B E h0 = C B E • Bayesian causal inference: 1 1 support = P(data | h1 ) P(data | w0 , w1 ) p ( w0 , w1 | h1 01 0 P(data | h0 ) P(data | w0 ) p( w0 | h0 ) dw0 0 Buehner and Cheng (1997) People DP (r = 0.89) Power (r = 0.88) Support (r = 0.97) The importance of parameterization • Noisy-OR incorporates mechanism assumptions: – generativity: causes increase probability of effects – each cause is sufficient to produce the effect – causes act via independent mechanisms (Cheng, 1997) • Consider other models: – statistical dependence: 2 test – generic parameterization (Anderson, computer science) People Support (Noisy-OR) 2 Support (generic) Generativity is essential P(e+|c+) P(e+|c-) 100 50 0 8/8 8/8 6/8 6/8 4/8 4/8 2/8 2/8 0/8 0/8 Support • Predictions result from “ceiling effect” – ceiling effects only matter if you believe a cause increases the probability of an effect Bayes nets and beyond... • What are Bayes nets? – graphical models – causal graphical models • An example: elemental causal induction • Beyond Bayes nets… – other knowledge in causal induction – formalizing causal theories chemicals genes Clofibrate Wyeth 14,643 p450 2B1 Gemfibrozil Phenobarbital Carnitine Palmitoyl Transferase 1 Hamadeh et al. (2002) Toxicological sciences. chemicals genes X Clofibrate Wyeth 14,643 p450 2B1 Gemfibrozil Phenobarbital Carnitine Palmitoyl Transferase 1 Hamadeh et al. (2002) Toxicological sciences. Chemical X chemicals genes peroxisome proliferators Clofibrate Wyeth 14,643 + p450 2B1 + Gemfibrozil Phenobarbital + Carnitine Palmitoyl Transferase 1 Hamadeh et al. (2002) Toxicological sciences. Using causal graphical models • Three questions (usually solved by researcher) – what are the variables? – what structures are plausible? – how do variables interact? • How are these questions answered if causal graphical models are used in cognition? Bayes nets and beyond... • What are Bayes nets? – graphical models – causal graphical models • An example: elemental causal induction • Beyond Bayes nets… – other knowledge in causal induction – formalizing causal theories Theory-based causal induction Causal theory P(h|data) P(data|h) P(h) – Ontology – Plausible relations – Functional form Evaluated by statistical inference P(h1) = h1: Generates Y X B Z P(h0) =1 – h0: Y X B Z Hypothesis space of causal graphical models Both objects activate the detector Blicket detector Object A does not activate the detector by itself Chi each Then they maket (Gopnik, Sobel,Backward and colleagues) Blocking Condition Procedure used in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 e Condition See this? It’s a blicket machine. Blickets Blocking Condition make it go. s activate tector Object A does not activate the detector by itself s activate tector Object Aactivates the detector by itself Both objects activate the detector Children are asked if each is a blicket Thenare asked to they makethe machine go Let’s put this one on the machine. Children are asked if each is a blicket Thenare asked to they Object Aactivates the detector by itself Oooh, it’s a blicket! Chi each Then they maket Both objects activate the detector Object A does not activate the detector by itself Children are asked if each is a blicket Thenare asked to they makethe machine go “Blocking” Experiment edure used in2Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 Backward Blocking Condition dition e A – king Condition – – – – e B Both objects activate Children areObject asked ifA does not the detector each is a blicket activate the detector Thenare asked to they by itself makethe machine go Trial 1 Object Aactivates the detector Children by itself are asked if each is a blicket Thenare asked to they makethe machine go Trial 2 Children are asked if each is a blicket Thenare asked to they makethe machine go Both objects activate the detector Backward Blocking C Both objects 3, activate Trials 4 the detector Two objects: A and B Trial 1: A on detector – detector active Trial 2: B on detector – detector inactive Trials 3,4: A B on detector – detector active 3, 4-year-olds judge whether each object is a blicket Children are asked if Object Aactivates the each is a blicket detector by itself Thenare asked to they makethe machine go Children are asked if each is a blicket Thenare asked to they makethe machine go • A: a blicket • B: not a blicket A deductive inference? • Causal law: detector activates if and only if one or more objects on top of it are blickets. • Premises: – Trial 1: A on detector – detector active – Trial 2: B on detector – detector inactive – Trials 3,4: A B on detector – detector active • Conclusions deduced from premises and causal law: – A: a blicket – B: not a blicket Both objects activate the detector Object A does not activate the detector by itself “Backwards blocking” el et al. (2002), Experiment 2Figure 13: Procedure used in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 Backward Blocking Condition One-Cause Condition (Sobel, Tenenbaum & Gopnik, 2004) A t A does not e the detector by itself Aactivates the tor by itself Children are a each is a blicke Thenare asked t they makethe machin B Children are asked if objects activate Both each is a blicket the detector Thenare asked to they makethe machine go – – – – Trial 1 Both objects activate Object A does not the detector activate the detector by itself Trial 2 Object Aactivates the Children are asked if detector by itself each is a blicket Thenare asked to they makethe machine go Two objects: A and B Backward Blocking Condition Trial 1: A B on detector – detector active Trial 2: A on detector – detector active 4-year-olds judge whether each object is a blicket Both objects activate Object Aactivates the Children are asked if is a a blicket • each A: blicket (100% of judgments) each is a blicket the detector detector by itself Thenare asked to they Thenare asked to they makethe machine go makethe machine go • B: probably not a blicket (66% of judgments) Children are asked if Children are a each is a blicke Thenare asked t they makethe machin Theory • Ontology – Types: Block, Detector, Trial – Predicates: Contact(Block, Detector, Trial) Active(Detector, Trial) • Constraints on causal relations – For any Block b and Detector d, with prior probability q : Cause(Contact(b,d,t), Active(d,t)) • Functional form of causal relations – Causes of Active(d,t) are independent mechanisms, with causal strengths wi. A background cause has strength w0. Assume a near-deterministic mechanism: wi ~ 1, w0 ~ 0. Theory • Ontology – Types: Block, Detector, Trial – Predicates: Contact(Block, Detector, Trial) Active(Detector, Trial) B A E Theory • Ontology – Types: Block, Detector, Trial – Predicates: Contact(Block, Detector, Trial) Active(Detector, Trial) B A E A = 1 if Contact(block A, detector, trial), else 0 B = 1 if Contact(block B, detector, trial), else 0 E = 1 if Active(detector, trial), else 0 Theory • Constraints on causal relations – For any Block b and Detector d, with prior probability q : Cause(Contact(b,d,t), Active(d,t)) P(h00) = (1 – q)2 No hypotheses with E B, E A, A B, etc. h00 : B A P(h10) = q(1 – q) h10 : E E P(h01) = (1 – q) q A = “A is a blicket” E h01 : B A E B A P(h11) = q2 h11 : B A E Theory • Functional form of causal relations – Causes of Active(d,t) are independent mechanisms, with causal strengths wb. A background cause has strength w0. Assume a near-deterministic mechanism: wb ~ 1, w0 ~ 0. P(h00) = (1 – q)2 A P(E=1 | A=0, B=0): P(E=1 | A=1, B=0): P(E=1 | A=0, B=1): P(E=1 | A=1, B=1): B P(h01) = (1 – q) q A B P(h10) = q(1 – q) A B P(h11) = q2 A B E E E E 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 “Activation law”: E=1 if and only if A=1 or B=1. Bayesian inference • Evaluating causal models in light of data: P (d | hi ) P (hi ) P(hi | d ) P(d | h j ) P(h j ) h H j • Inferring a particular causal relation: P( A E | d ) P( A E | h j ) P(h j | d ) h H j Modeling backwards blocking P(h00) = (1 – q)2 A P(E=1 | A=0, B=0): P(E=1 | A=1, B=0): P(E=1 | A=0, B=1): P(E=1 | A=1, B=1): B P(h01) = (1 – q) q A B P(h10) = q(1 – q) A B P(h11) = q2 A B E E E E 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 P( B E | d ) P(h01 ) P(h11 ) q P( B E | d ) P(h00 ) P(h10 ) 1 q Modeling backwards blocking P(h00) = (1 – q)2 A P(E=1 | A=1, B=1): B P(h01) = (1 – q) q A B P(h10) = q(1 – q) A B P(h11) = q2 A B E E E E 0 1 1 1 P( B E | d ) P(h01 ) P(h11 ) 1 P( B E | d) P(h10 ) 1 q Modeling backwards blocking P(h01) = (1 – q) q A B P(h10) = q(1 – q) A B P(h11) = q2 A B E E E P(E=1 | A=1, B=0): 0 1 1 P(E=1 | A=1, B=1): 1 1 1 P( B E | d ) P(h11 ) q P( B E | d ) P(h10 ) 1 q Both objects activate the detector Object A does not activate the detector by itself Children are asked if Manipulating the prior eachused is a blicket Figure 13: Procedure in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 Thenare asked to they makethe machine go One-Cause Condition Figure 13:2Procedure Figure used 13:2inProcedure Sobel Figure et al. used 13: (2002), in Procedure Sobel Experiment et used al. (2002), in2Sobel Experiment et al. (2002), 2 esed 13:inProcedure Sobel et al. used (2002), in Sobel Experiment et al. (2002), Experiment Backward Blocking Condition One-Cause Condition One-Cause Condition One-Cause Condition Cause Condition I. Pre-training phase: Blickets are rare . . . . Both objects activate the detector Object A does not Children are a each is a blicke activate the detector Thenare asked t they by itself Both Both objects Object Both not objectsare activate Object not are asked ObjectifA doesChildren not ask Both Object the Children asked if A doesChildren h objects activate Object A does notobjects activate Object A does Children notobjects areactivate asked ifAactivates Children areactivate asked if A does makethe are machin each is a blicket each is a blicket eachthe is detector a blicket thea detector thea detector activate the detector activate the detector each is blicket detector byeach blicketactivate the detector the detector itselfis the detector activate the detector activate the detector Thenare asked to by itselfthey Thenare asked to Thenare asked to Thenare asked to Thenare asked to they they by itself by itself they they by itself by itself makethe machine go makethe machine g makethe machine go makethe machine go makethe machine go Figure 13: Procedure used in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 sed et al. (2002), Experiment 2 el et in al.Sobel (2002), Experiment 2 Figure 13: Procedure used in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 One-Cause Condition Backward Blocking Condition One-Cause Condition Backward Blocking Backward Condition Blocking Backward Condition Blocking Condition ward ondition Blocking Condition II. Backwards blocking phase: Both objects activate the detector A does not t A does notObject Object A does not Children are asked if each is a blicket activate the detector Both objects activate Object Aactivates the Children are a are asked if Children are askedChildren if Then they are asked to by itself each Both objects activate Object A does not Children are asked if is a blicke the detector detector by itself each is a blicket activate the detector each is a blicket e the detector make t he machine go Then each is a blicket the detector activate the detector they are asked t Then Thenare asked to they are asked to by itself they by itself Both objects activate Both objects activate Object Aactivates Both objects the activate Object Aactivates Children the are Object asked Aactivates if Children the ask Then h objects activate Object Aactivates the make Object Aactivates Children the are asked if Children are asked if make they are asked to by itself t he are machin makethe machine go the machine go each is a blicket each each is blicket each is blicket detector by itself thea detector thea detector the detector detector by itself detector by itself the detector detector by itself detector by itself make the machine go is a blicket Thenare asked to Thenare asked to Thenare asked to Thenare asked to they they they they makethe machine go makethe machine g makethe machine go makethe machine go A B Trial 1 Trial 2 After each trial, adults judge the probability that each Backward Blocking Condition ndition object is a blicket. Backward Blocking Condition • “Rare” condition: First observe 12 objects on detector, of which 2 set it off. • “Common” condition: First observe 12 objects on detector, of which 10 set it off. Both objects activate the detector Object A does not Children are asked if Figure 13: Procedure used2in Sobel a blicket et Figure Procedure usedeach in isSobel al. (2002), Experiment activate the13: detector Inferences from ambiguous data Thenare asked to they makethe machine go by itself One-Cause Condition One-Cause Condition Figure 13:2Procedure Figure used 13:2inProcedure Sobel Figure et al. used 13: (2002), in Procedure Sobel Experiment et used al. (2002), in2Sobel Experiment et al. (2002), 2 esed 13:inProcedure Sobel et al. used (2002), in Sobel Experiment et al. (2002), Experiment Backward Blocking Condition One-Cause Condition One-Cause Condition One-Cause Condition Cause Condition I. Pre-training phase: Blickets are rare . . . . Object A doesBoth not objects activate Children are askedObject if each is a blicket activate activate the detector the detector Thenare asked to by they by itself Both Both objects Object Both not objectsare activate Object not are asked Object ifAthe does Children not goare ask Both Object the Children asked if A doesChildren h objects activate Object A does notobjects activate Object A does Children notobjects areactivate asked ifAactivates Children areactivate asked if A does make machine each is a blicket each is a blicket eachthe is detector a blicket thea detector thea detector activate the detector activate the detector each is blicket detector byeach blicketactivate the detector the detector itselfis the detector activate the detector activate the detector Then Thenare asked to Then Then Then they are asked to by itselfthey by itself by itself they are asked to they are asked to they are asked to by itself by itself make make makethe machine go makethe machine go makethe machine go the machine go the machine g Both objects activate the detector Figure 13: Procedure used2in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2 e 13: Procedure used in Sobel et al. (2002), Experiment 2), Experiment 2 al. obel (2002), et al. (2002), Experiment Experiment 2 2 Figureused 13: Procedure in Sobel et al. (2002), Cause Condition Figure 13: Procedure inOne-Cause Sobel etused al.Condition (2002), Experiment 2 Experiment 2 Backward Blocking Condition Backward Blocking Condition One-Cause Condition One-Cause Condition Backward Blocking Backward Condition Blocking Backward Condition Blocking Condition ward ondition Blocking Condition II. Two trials: A B detector, B C detector A does not Children are asked if h objects activate Object A doesBoth not objects activate Children are askedObject if each is a blicket Children are asked the detector activate the detector each is a blicket the detector activate the detector Object Children areChildren asked if areChildren Both objects activate Object AactivatesBoth the objects activate if Aa Object es not A does not asked if are asked if Then Then they are by itself they are asked to by itself each is activate a blicket theifdetector asked toeach is a blicket detecto the detector byare itself each isBoth a blicket each is activate a blicket ctivate etector theBoth detector objects Object A does not Children asked objects Object A does not Children are asked if detector makethe machine they maketthe go are asked to he machine Then Then Then Then they are asked to are asked they they to are asked to f by itself the each is a blicket the detector activate detector eachgo is a blicket detector activate the detector Both objects activate Both objects activate Object Aactivates Both objects the activate Object Aactivates Children the are Object asked Aactivates if the machine Children the goare ask h objects activate Object Aactivates thetgo Object Aactivates Children the are asked if Children asked make make make maketgo the machine Thenare asked to he machine he machine goby itself they by itselfarethey Then areifasked to each is a blicket each is a blicket the detector the detector detector by itself the detector detector by itself detector by itself each is a blicket each is a blicket the detector detector by itself detector by itself makethe machine go makethe machine go Then Then Then Then they are asked to they are asked to they are asked to they are asked to make make makethe machine go makethe machine go the machine go the machine g A B C Trial 1 Trial 2 After each trial, adults Backward Blockingjudge Conditionthe probability that each Backward Condition Backward Blocking Condition object isBlocking a blicket. ward Blocking Condition Same domain theory generates hypothesis space for 3 objects: A • Hypotheses: h000 = B C h100 = E A h010 = B C B A C h110 = C B C E A B C h011 = E h101 = B E h001 = E A A A B E C h111 = A E • Likelihoods: P(E=1| A, B, C; h) = 1 if A = 1 and A or B = 1 and B or C = 1 and C else 0. B C E E exists, E exists, E exists, • “Rare” condition: First observe 12 objects on detector, of which 2 set it off. The role of causal mechanism knowledge • Is mechanism knowledge necessary? – Constraint-based learning using 2 tests of conditional independence. • How important is the deterministic functional form of causal relations? – Bayes with “noisy sufficient causes” theory (c.f., Cheng’s causal power theory). Bayes with correct theory: Bayes with “noisy sufficient causes” theory: Theory-based causal induction • Explains one-shot causal inferences about physical systems: blicket detectors • Captures a spectrum of inferences: – unambiguous data: adults and children make allor-none inferences – ambiguous data: adults and children make more graded inferences • Extends to more complex cases with hidden variables, dynamic systems: come to my talk! Summary • Causal graphical models provide a language for asking questions about causality • Key issues in modeling causal induction: – what do we mean by causal induction? – how do knowledge and statistics interact? • Bayesian approach allows exploration of different answers to these questions Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Property induction Collaborators Charles Kemp Lauren Schmidt Fei Xu Pat Shafto Neville Sanjana Amy Perfors Liz Baraff The Big Question • How can we generalize new concepts reliably from just one or a few examples? – Learning word meanings “horse” “horse” “horse” The Big Question • How can we generalize new concepts reliably from just one or a few examples? – Learning word meanings, causal relations, social rules, …. – Property induction Gorillas have T4 cells. Squirrels have T4 cells. All mammals have T4 cells. How probable is the the conclusion (target) given the premises (examples)? The Big Question • How can we generalize new concepts reliably from just one or a few examples? – Learning word meanings, causal relations, social rules, …. – Property induction Gorillas have T4 cells. Squirrels have T4 cells. Gorillas have T4 cells. Chimps have T4 cells. All mammals have T4 cells. All mammals have T4 cells. More diverse examples stronger generalization Is rational inference the answer? • Everyday induction often appears to follow principles of rational scientific inference. – Could that explain its success? • Goal of this work: a rational computational model of human inductive generalization. – Explain people’s judgments as approximations to optimal inference in natural environments. – Close quantitative fits to people’s judgments with a minimum of free parameters or assumptions. Theory-Based Bayesian Models • Rational statistical inference (Bayes): p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH • Learners’ domain theories generate their hypothesis space H and prior p(h). – Well-matched to structure of the natural world. – Learnable from limited data. – Computationally tractable inference. The plan • Similarity-based models • Theory-based model • Bayesian models – “Empiricist” Bayes – Theory-based Bayes, with different theories • Connectionist (PDP) models • Advanced Theory-based Bayes – Learning with multiple domain theories – Learning domain theories The plan • Similarity-based models • Theory-based model • Bayesian models – “Empiricist” Bayes – Theory-based Bayes, with different theories • Connectionist (PDP) models • Advanced Theory-based Bayes – Learning with multiple domain theories – Learning domain theories An experiment (Osherson et al., 1990) • 20 subjects rated the strength of 45 arguments: X1 have property P. X2 have property P. X3 have property P. All mammals have property P. • 40 different subjects rated the similarity of all pairs of 10 mammals. Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals • Sum-Similarity: sim( i, X ) sim( i, j ) x x jX x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals • Max-Similarity: sim( i, X ) max sim( i, j ) jX x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals • Max-Similarity: sim( i, X ) max sim( i, j ) jX x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals • Max-Similarity: sim( i, X ) max sim( i, j ) jX x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals • Max-Similarity: sim( i, X ) max sim( i, j ) jX x x x Mammals: Examples: x Similarity-based models (Osherson et al.) strength(“all mammals” | X ) sim( i, X ) imammals • Max-Similarity: sim( i, X ) max sim( i, j ) jX x x x Mammals: Examples: x Sum-sim versus Max-sim • Two models appear functionally similar: – Both increase monotonically as new examples are observed. • Reasons to prefer Sum-sim: – Standard form of exemplar models of categorization, memory, and object recognition. – Analogous to kernel density estimation techniques in statistical pattern recognition. • Reasons to prefer Max-sim: – Fit to generalization judgments . . . . Data Data vs. models Model . Each “ ” represents one argument: X1 have property P. X2 have property P. X3 have property P. All mammals have property P. Three data sets Max-sim Sum-sim Conclusion kind: “all mammals” “horses” “horses” Number of examples: 3 2 1, 2, or 3 Feature rating data (Osherson and Wilkie) • People were given 48 animals, 85 features, and asked to rate whether each animal had each feature. • E.g., elephant: 'gray' 'hairless' 'toughskin' 'big' 'bulbous' 'longleg' 'tail' 'chewteeth' 'tusks' 'smelly' 'walks' 'slow' 'strong' 'muscle’ 'quadrapedal' 'inactive' 'vegetation' 'grazer' 'oldworld' 'bush' 'jungle' 'ground' 'timid' 'smart' 'group' ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features New property • Compute similarity based on Hamming distance, A B A B or cosine. • Generalize based on Max-sim or Sum-sim. Three data sets r = 0.77 r = 0.75 r = 0.94 r = – 0.21 r = 0.63 r = 0.19 Max-Sim Sum-Sim Conclusion kind: “all mammals” “horses” “horses” Number of examples: 3 2 1, 2, or 3 Problems for sim-based approach • No principled explanation for why Max-Sim works so well on this task, and Sum-Sim so poorly, when SumSim is the standard in other similarity-based models. • Free parameters mixing similarity and coverage terms, and possibly Max-Sim and Sum-Sim terms. • Does not extend to induction with other kinds of properties, e.g., from Smith et al., 1993: Dobermanns can bite through wire. German shepherds can bite through wire. Poodles can bite through wire. German shepherds can bite through wire. Marr’s Three Levels of Analysis • Computation: “What is the goal of the computation, why is it appropriate, and what is the logic of the strategy by which it can be carried out?” • Representation and algorithm: Max-sim, Sum-sim • Implementation: Neurobiology The plan • Similarity-based models • Theory-based model • Bayesian models – “Empiricist” Bayes – Theory-based Bayes, with different theories • Connectionist (PDP) models • Advanced Theory-based Bayes – Learning with multiple domain theories – Learning domain theories Theory-based induction • Scientific biology: species generated by an evolutionary branching process. – A tree-structured taxonomy of species. • Taxonomy also central in folkbiology (Atran). Theory-based induction Begin by reconstructing intuitive taxonomy from similarity judgments: clustering How taxonomy constrains induction • Atran (1998): “Fundamental principle of systematic induction” (Warburton 1967, Bock 1973) – Given a property found among members of any two species, the best initial hypothesis is that the property is also present among all species that are included in the smallest higher-order taxon containing the original pair of species. “all mammals” Cows have property P. Dolphins have property P. Squirrels have property P. All mammals have property P. Strong (0.76 [max = 0.82]) “large herbivores” Cows have property P. Dolphins have property P. Squirrels have property P. Cows have property P. Horses have property P. Rhinos have property P. All mammals have property P. All mammals have property P. Strong: 0.76 [max = 0.82]) Weak: 0.17 [min = 0.14] “all mammals” Cows have property P. Dolphins have property P. Squirrels have property P. Seals have property P. Dolphins have property P. Squirrels have property P. All mammals have property P. All mammals have property P. Strong: 0.76 [max = 0.82] Weak: 0.30 [min = 0.14] Taxonomic distance Max-sim Sum-sim Conclusion kind: “all mammals” “horses” “horses” Number of examples: 3 2 1, 2, or 3 The challenge • Can we build models with the best of both traditional approaches? – Quantitatively accurate predictions. – Strong rational basis. • Will require novel ways of integrating structured knowledge with statistical inference. The plan • Similarity-based models • Theory-based model • Bayesian models – “Empiricist” Bayes – Theory-based Bayes, with different theories • Connectionist (PDP) models • Advanced Theory-based Bayes – Learning with multiple domain theories – Learning domain theories The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features New property The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The Bayesian approach ? Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The Bayesian approach p(h) h p(d |h) Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Bayes’ rule: p ( d | h) p ( h) p(h | d ) p(d | h) p(h) hH p(h) h p(d |h) Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Probability that property Q holds for species x: p(Q( x) | d ) p(h | d ) h consistent with Q ( x ) p(h) h p(d |h) Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property “Size principle”: |h| = # of positive instances of h 1 p(d | h) h 0 if d is consistent with h otherwise p(h) h p(d |h) Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The size principle h1 “even numbers” 2 12 22 32 42 52 62 72 82 92 4 14 24 34 44 54 64 74 84 94 6 16 26 36 46 56 66 76 86 96 8 10 18 20 28 30 38 40 48 50 58 60 68 70 78 80 88 90 98 100 h2 “multiples of 10” The size principle h1 “even numbers” 2 12 22 32 42 52 62 72 82 92 4 14 24 34 44 54 64 74 84 94 6 16 26 36 46 56 66 76 86 96 8 10 18 20 28 30 38 40 48 50 58 60 68 70 78 80 88 90 98 100 h2 “multiples of 10” Data slightly more of a coincidence under h1 The size principle h1 “even numbers” 2 12 22 32 42 52 62 72 82 92 4 14 24 34 44 54 64 74 84 94 6 16 26 36 46 56 66 76 86 96 8 10 18 20 28 30 38 40 48 50 58 60 68 70 78 80 88 90 98 100 h2 “multiples of 10” Data much more of a coincidence under h1 Illustrating the size principle Which argument is stronger? Grizzly bears have property P. All mammals have property P. “Non-monotonicity” Grizzly bears have property P. Brown bears have property P. Polar bears have property P. All mammals have property P. Probability that property Q holds for species x: p(Q( x) | d ) p(h) / h h consistent with Q ( x ), d p ( h) / h h consistent with d p(h) p(Q(x)|d) Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 h p(d |h) d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ... ? Generalization Hypotheses New property Probability that property Q holds for species x: p(Q( x) | d ) p(h) / h h consistent with Q ( x ), d p ( h) / h h consistent with d p(h) h p(d |h) Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Specifying the prior p(h) • A good prior must focus on a small subset of all 2n possible hypotheses, in order to: – Match the distribution of properties in the world. – Be learnable from limited data. – Be efficiently computationally. • We consider two approaches: – “Empiricist” Bayes: unstructured prior based directly on known features. – “Theory-based” Bayes: structured prior based on rational domain theory, tuned to known features. “Empiricist” Bayes: (Heit, 1998) h1 h2 h3 h4 h5 h6 h7 h8 h9 h10 h11 h12 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 p(h) = 1 15 1 2 15 15 1 3 15 15 1 1 1 15 15 15 1 1 15 15 1 15 1 15 h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Results r = 0.38 r = 0.16 r = 0.79 r = 0.77 r = 0.75 r = 0.94 “Empiricist” Bayes Max-Sim Why doesn’t “Empiricist” Bayes work? • With no structural bias, requires too many features to estimate the prior reliably. • An analogy: Estimating a smooth probability density function by local interpolation. N=5 N = 100 N = 500 Why doesn’t “Empiricist” Bayes work? • With no structural bias, requires too many features to estimate the prior reliably. • An analogy: Estimating a smooth probability density function by local interpolation. Assuming an appropriately structured form for density (e.g., Gaussian) leads to better generalization from sparse data. N=5 N=5 “Theory-based” Bayes Theory: Two principles based on the structure of species and properties in the natural world. 1. Species generated by an evolutionary branching process. – A tree-structured taxonomy of species (Atran, 1998). 2. Features generated by stochastic mutation process and passed on to descendants. – Novel features can appear anywhere in tree, but some distributions are more likely than others. Mutation process generates p(h|T): – Choose label for root. – Probability that label mutates along branch b : 1 e 2 l b l = mutation rate |b| = length of branch b s1 s2 s3 s4 s5 s6 s7 s8 s9 s10 2 T p(h|T) h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Mutation process generates p(h|T): – Choose label for root. – Probability that label mutates along branch b : 1 e 2 l b l = mutation rate |b| = length of branch b x x x 2 T p(h|T) h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Samples from the prior • Labelings that cut the data along fewer branches are more probable: > “monophyletic” “polyphyletic” Samples from the prior • Labelings that cut the data along longer branches are more probable: > “more distinctive” “less distinctive” • Mutation process over tree T generates p(h|T). • Message passing over tree T efficiently sums over all h. • How do we know which tree T to use? s1 s2 s3 s4 s5 s6 s7 s8 s9 s10 T p(h|T) h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property The same mutation process generates p(Features|T): – Assume each feature generated independently over the tree. – Use MCMC to infer most likely tree T and mutation rate l given observed features. – No free parameters! s1 s2 s3 s4 s5 s6 s7 s8 s9 s10 T p(h|T) h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Results r = 0.91 r = 0.95 r = 0.91 r = 0.38 r = 0.16 r = 0.79 r = 0.77 r = 0.75 r = 0.94 “Theory-based” Bayes “Empiricist” Bayes Max-Sim Grounding in similarity Reconstruct intuitive taxonomy from similarity judgments: clustering Theory-based Bayes Max-sim Sum-sim Conclusion kind: “all mammals” “horses” “horses” Number of examples: 3 2 1, 2, or 3 Explaining similarity • Why does Max-sim fit so well? – An efficient and accurate approximation to this Theory-Based Bayesian model. – Correlation with Bayes on threepremise general arguments, over 100 simulated trees: Mean r = 0.94 Correlation (r) – Theorem. Nearest neighbor classification approximates evolutionary Bayes in the limit of high mutation rate, if domain is tree-structured. Alternative feature-based models • Taxonomic Bayes (strictly taxonomic hypotheses, with no mutation process) > “monophyletic” “polyphyletic” Alternative feature-based models • Taxonomic Bayes (strictly taxonomic hypotheses, with no mutation process) • PDP network (Rogers and McClelland) Species Features Results r = 0.91 r = 0.95 r = 0.91 Bias is just right! Theory-based Bayes r = 0.51 r = 0.53 r = 0.85 Bias is too strong Taxonomic Bayes r = 0.41 PDP network r = 0.62 r = 0.71 Bias is too weak Mutation principle versus pure Occam’s Razor • Mutation principle provides a version of Occam’s Razor, by favoring hypotheses that span fewer disjoint clusters. • Could we use a more generic Bayesian Occam’s Razor, without the biological motivation of mutation? Mutation process generates p(h|T): – Choose label for root. – Probability that label mutates along branch b : 1 e 2 l b l = mutation rate |b| = length of branch b s1 s2 s3 s4 s5 s6 s7 s8 s9 s10 2 T p(h|T) h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Mutation process generates p(h|T): – Choose label for root. – Probability that label mutates along branch b : l l = mutation rate |b| = length of branch b s1 s2 s3 s4 s5 s6 s7 s8 s9 s10 T p(h|T) h Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 d ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Features Generalization Hypothesis New property Bayes (taxonomy+ mutation) Premise typicality effect (Rips, 1975; Osherson et al., 1990): Strong: Bayes (taxonomy+ Occam) Horses have property P. All mammals have property P. Max-sim Weak: Seals have property P. Conclusion kind: “all mammals” Number of examples: 1 All mammals have property P. Typicality meets hierarchies • Collins and Quillian: semantic memory structured hierarchically • Traditional story: Simple hierarchical structure uncomfortable with typicality effects & exceptions. • New story: Typicality & exceptions compatible with rational statistical inference over hierarchy. Intuitive versus scientific theories of biology • Same structure for how species are related. – Tree-structured taxonomy. • Same probabilistic model for traits – Small probability of occurring along any branch at any time, plus inheritance. • Different features – Scientist: genes – People: coarse anatomy and behavior Induction in Biology: summary • Theory-based Bayesian inference explains taxonomic inductive reasoning in folk biology. • Insight into processing-level accounts. – Why Max-sim over Sum-sim in this domain? – How is hierarchical representation compatible with typicality effects & exceptions? • Reveals essential principles of domain theory. – Category structure: taxonomic tree. – Feature distribution: stochastic mutation process + inheritance. The plan • Similarity-based models • Theory-based model • Bayesian models – “Empiricist” Bayes – Theory-based Bayes, with different theories • Connectionist (PDP) models • Advanced Theory-based Bayes – Learning with multiple domain theories – Learning domain theories Property type Generic “essence” Theory Structure Taxonomic Tree Lion Cheetah Hyena Giraffe Gazelle Gorilla Monkey Lion Cheetah Hyena Giraffe Gazelle Gorilla Monkey ... Property type Generic “essence” Size-related Food-carried Theory Structure Taxonomic Tree Dimensional Directed Acyclic Network Giraffe Lion Giraffe Cheetah Hyena Lion Gorilla Giraffe Hyena Gazelle Gazelle Cheetah Monkey Monkey Gorilla Gorilla Monkey Lion Cheetah Hyena Giraffe Gazelle Gorilla Monkey ... Lion Gazelle Hyena ... Cheetah ... One-dimensional predicates • Q = “Have skins that are more resistant to penetration than most synthetic fibers”. – Unknown relevant property: skin toughness – Model influence of known properties via judged prior probability that each species has Q. threshold for Q Skin toughness House cat Camel Elephant Rhino One-dimensional predicates Bayes (taxonomy+ mutation) Max-sim Bayes (1D model) Disease Food web model fits (Shafto et al.) r = 0.82 r = -0.35 r = -0.05 Property r = 0.77 Mammals Island Disease Taxonomic tree model fits (Shafto et al.) r = 0.16 r = 0.81 r = 0.62 Property r = -0.12 Mammals Island The plan • Similarity-based models • Theory-based model • Bayesian models – “Empiricist” Bayes – Theory-based Bayes, with different theories • Connectionist (PDP) models • Advanced Theory-based Bayes – Learning with multiple domain theories – Learning domain theories Theory • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure • Feature i generated by mutation process with rate li p(S|T) F9 F8 Domain Structure F7 F11 F14 F13 F6 F12 F3 F1 F10 F14 F2 F4 F10 F10 F5 S3 S4 S1 S2 S9 S10 S5 S6 S7 S8 p(D|S) Data Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 l10 high ~ weight low Theory • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure • Feature i generated by mutation process with rate li p(S|T) F9 F8 Domain Structure F7 F11 F14 F13 F6 F12 F3 F1 F10 F14 F2 F10 F4 F10 F5 S3 S4 S1 S2 S9 S10 S5 S6 S7 S8 p(D|S) Data Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Species X ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? ? Theory • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure • Feature i generated by mutation process with rate li p(S|T) F9 F8 Domain Structure F7 F11 F14 F13 F6 F12 F3 F1 F10 F14 F2 F4 F10 F10 F5 S3 S4 S1 S2 S9 S10 S5 S6 S7 S8 p(D|S) Data Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Species X SX Where does the domain theory come from? • Innate. – Atran (1998): The tendency to group living kinds into hierarchies reflects an “innately determined cognitive structure”. • Emerges (only approximately) through learning in unstructured connectionist networks. – McClelland and Rogers (2003). Bayesian inference to theories • Challenge to the nativist-empiricist dichotomy. – We really do have structured domain theories. – We really do learn them. • Bayesian framework applies over multiple levels: – Given hypothesis space + data, infer concepts. – Given theory + data, infer hypothesis space. – Given X + data, infer theory. Bayesian inference to theories • Candidate theories for biological species and their features: – T0: Features generated independently for each species. (c.f. naive Bayes, Anderson’s rational model.) – T1: Features generated by mutation in tree-structured taxonomy of species. – T2: Features generated by mutation in a one-dimensional chain of species. • Score theories by likelihood on object-feature matrix: p( D | T ) p( D | S , T ) p(S | T ) S max p( D | S , T ) p( S | T ) S T0: • No organizational structure for species. • Features distributed independently over species. F1 F2 F5 F8 F9 F1 F2 F3 F2 F5 F2 F4 F7 F4 F1 F6 F8 F7 F5 F7 F10 F9 F7 F9 F12 F12 F13 F14 F13 F14 F14 S1 S2 S3 S4 Data F1 F2 F6 F2 F4 F7 F4 F2 F1 F8 F8 F5 F3 F6 F9 F9 F12 F6 F8 F10 F10 F13 F11 F9 F11 F13 F14 F13 F12 F14 S5 S6 S7 S8 S9 S10 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Features T0: • No organizational structure for species. • Features distributed independently over species. F1 F6 F7 F8 F9 F11 F1 F3 F3 F6 F7 F7 F7 F8 F8 F8 F9 F9 F9 F11 F11 F4 F10 F12 F12 F8 F11 F14 F14 F9 S1 S2 S3 S4 Data F4 F8 F9 S5 S6 F2 F5 F5 F6 F9 F9 F7 F10 F10 F8 F13 F13 F9 F14 F14 F11 S7 F2 F6 F7 F8 F9 F11 S8 S9 S10 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Features T0: • No organizational structure for species. • Features distributed independently over species. T1: • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure. • Features distributed via stochastic mutation process. F9 F1 F6 F7 F8 F9 F11 F1 F3 F3 F6 F7 F7 F7 F8 F8 F8 F9 F9 F9 F11 F11 F4 F10 F12 F12 F8 F11 F14 F14 F9 S1 S2 S3 S4 Data F8 F4 F8 F9 S5 S6 F2 F5 F5 F6 F9 F9 F7 F10 F10 F8 F13 F13 F9 F14 F14 F11 S7 F7 F11 F2 F6 F7 F8 F9 F11 F14 F13 F12 F3 S8 S9 S10 F6 F1 F10 F2 F14 F10 F4 F5 S3 S4 S1 S2 S9 S10 S5 S6 S7 S8 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Features T0: p(Data|T1) ~ 1.83 x 10-41 • No organizational structure for species. • Features distributed independently over species. T1: p(Data|T2) ~ 2.42 x 10-32 • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure. • Features distributed via stochastic mutation process. F9 F1 F6 F7 F8 F9 F11 F1 F3 F3 F6 F7 F7 F7 F8 F8 F8 F9 F9 F9 F11 F11 F4 F10 F12 F12 F8 F11 F14 F14 F9 S1 S2 S3 S4 Data F8 F4 F8 F9 S5 S6 F2 F5 F5 F6 F9 F9 F7 F10 F10 F8 F13 F13 F9 F14 F14 F11 S7 F7 F11 F2 F6 F7 F8 F9 F11 F14 F13 F12 F3 S8 S9 S10 F6 F1 F10 F2 F14 F10 F4 F5 S3 S4 S1 S2 S9 S10 S5 S6 S7 S8 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Features T0: • No organizational structure for species. • Features distributed independently over species. F1 F2 F5 F8 F9 F1 F2 F3 F2 F5 F2 F4 F7 F4 F1 F6 F8 F7 F5 F7 F10 F9 F7 F9 F12 F12 F13 F14 F13 F14 F14 S1 S2 S3 S4 Data F4 F14 F1 F2 F6 F2 F4 F7 F4 F2 F1 F8 F8 F5 F3 F6 F9 F9 F12 F6 F8 F10 F10 F13 F11 F9 F11 F13 F14 F13 F12 F14 S5 S6 S7 T1: • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure. • Features distributed via stochastic mutation process. F9 F7 F1 F5 F7 F13 F12 F13 F10 F8 F9 F11 F13 F13 F10 F11 F12 F12 F6 F5 S8 S9 S10 F2 F9 F6 F8 F3 F10 F8 F12 F7 F5 F2 F6 F6 F3 F2 F14 S2 S4 S7 S10 S8 S1 S9 S6 S3 S5 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Features T0: p(Data|T1) ~ 2.29 x 10-42 • No organizational structure for species. • Features distributed independently over species. F1 F2 F5 F8 F9 F1 F2 F3 F2 F5 F2 F4 F7 F4 F1 F6 F8 F7 F5 F7 F10 F9 F7 F9 F12 F12 F13 F14 F13 F14 F14 S1 S2 S3 S4 Data F4 F14 F1 F2 F6 F2 F4 F7 F4 F2 F1 F8 F8 F5 F3 F6 F9 F9 F12 F6 F8 F10 F10 F13 F11 F9 F11 F13 F14 F13 F12 F14 S5 S6 S7 T1: p(Data|T2) ~ 4.38 x 10-53 • Species organized in taxonomic tree structure. • Features distributed via stochastic mutation process. F9 F7 F1 F5 F7 F13 F12 F13 F10 F8 F9 F11 F13 F13 F10 F11 F12 F12 F6 F5 S8 S9 S10 F2 F9 F6 F8 F3 F10 F8 F12 F7 F5 F2 F6 F6 F3 F2 F14 S2 S4 S7 S10 S8 S1 S9 S6 S3 S5 Species 1 Species 2 Species 3 Species 4 Species 5 Species 6 Species 7 Species 8 Species 9 Species 10 Features Empirical tests • Synthetic data: 32 objects, 120 features – tree-structured generative model – linear chain generative model – unconstrained (independent features). • Real data – Animal feature judgments: 48 species, 85 features. – US Supreme Court decisions, 1981-1985: 9 people, 637 cases. Results Preferred Model Null Tree Linear Tree Linear Theory acquisition: summary • So far, just a computational proof of concept. • Future work: – Experimental studies of theory acquisition in the lab, with adult and child subjects. – Modeling developmental or historical trajectories of theory change. • Sources of hypotheses for candidate theories: – What is innate? – Role of analogy? Outline • Morning – Introduction (Josh) – Basic case study #1: Flipping coins (Tom) – Basic case study #2: Rules and similarity (Josh) • Afternoon – Advanced case study #1: Causal induction (Tom) – Advanced case study #2: Property induction (Josh) – Quick tour of more advanced topics (Tom) Advanced topics Structure and statistics • Statistical language modeling – topic models • Relational categorization – attributes and relations Structure and statistics • Statistical language modeling – topic models • Relational categorization – attributes and relations Statistical language modeling • A variety of approaches to statistical language modeling are used in cognitive science – e.g. LSA (Landauer & Dumais, 1997) – distributional clustering (Redington, Chater, & Finch, 1998) • Generative models have unique advantages – identify assumed causal structure of language – make use of standard tools of Bayesian statistics – easily extended to capture more complex structure Generative models for language latent structure observed data Generative models for language meaning sentences Topic models • Each document a mixture of topics • Each word chosen from a single topic • Introduced by Blei, Ng, and Jordan (2001), reinterpretation of PLSI (Hofmann, 1999) • Idea of probabilistic topics widely used (eg. Bigi et al., 1997; Iyer & Ostendorf, 1996; Ueda & Saito, 2003) Generating a document q distribution over topics z z z topic assignments w w w observed words w P(w|z = 1) = f (1) HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS topic 1 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.0 0.0 0.0 0.0 0.0 w P(w|z = 2) = f (2) HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS topic 2 0.0 0.0 0.0 0.0 0.0 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 Choose mixture weights for each document, generate “bag of words” q = {P(z = 1), P(z = 2)} {0, 1} {0.25, 0.75} MATHEMATICS KNOWLEDGE RESEARCH WORK MATHEMATICS RESEARCH WORK SCIENTIFIC MATHEMATICS WORK SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE MATHEMATICS SCIENTIFIC HEART LOVE TEARS KNOWLEDGE HEART {0.5, 0.5} MATHEMATICS HEART RESEARCH LOVE MATHEMATICS WORK TEARS SOUL KNOWLEDGE HEART {0.75, 0.25} WORK JOY SOUL TEARS MATHEMATICS TEARS LOVE LOVE LOVE SOUL {1, 0} TEARS LOVE JOY SOUL LOVE TEARS SOUL SOUL TEARS JOY A selection of topics (from 500) THEORY SCIENTISTS EXPERIMENT OBSERVATIONS SCIENTIFIC EXPERIMENTS HYPOTHESIS EXPLAIN SCIENTIST OBSERVED EXPLANATION BASED OBSERVATION IDEA EVIDENCE THEORIES BELIEVED DISCOVERED OBSERVE FACTS SPACE EARTH MOON PLANET ROCKET MARS ORBIT ASTRONAUTS FIRST SPACECRAFT JUPITER SATELLITE SATELLITES ATMOSPHERE SPACESHIP SURFACE SCIENTISTS ASTRONAUT SATURN MILES ART STUDENTS PAINT TEACHER ARTIST STUDENT PAINTING TEACHERS PAINTED TEACHING ARTISTS CLASS MUSEUM CLASSROOM WORK SCHOOL PAINTINGS LEARNING STYLE PUPILS PICTURES CONTENT WORKS INSTRUCTION OWN TAUGHT SCULPTURE GROUP PAINTER GRADE ARTS SHOULD BEAUTIFUL GRADES DESIGNS CLASSES PORTRAIT PUPIL PAINTERS GIVEN BRAIN NERVE SENSE SENSES ARE NERVOUS NERVES BODY SMELL TASTE TOUCH MESSAGES IMPULSES CORD ORGANS SPINAL FIBERS SENSORY PAIN IS CURRENT ELECTRICITY ELECTRIC CIRCUIT IS ELECTRICAL VOLTAGE FLOW BATTERY WIRE WIRES SWITCH CONNECTED ELECTRONS RESISTANCE POWER CONDUCTORS CIRCUITS TUBE NEGATIVE NATURE WORLD HUMAN PHILOSOPHY MORAL KNOWLEDGE THOUGHT REASON SENSE OUR TRUTH NATURAL EXISTENCE BEING LIFE MIND ARISTOTLE BELIEVED EXPERIENCE REALITY THIRD FIRST SECOND THREE FOURTH FOUR GRADE TWO FIFTH SEVENTH SIXTH EIGHTH HALF SEVEN SIX SINGLE NINTH END TENTH ANOTHER A selection of topics (from 500) JOB SCIENCE BALL FIELD STORY MIND DISEASE WATER WORK STUDY GAME MAGNETIC STORIES WORLD BACTERIA FISH JOBS SCIENTISTS TEAM MAGNET TELL DREAM DISEASES SEA CAREER SCIENTIFIC FOOTBALL WIRE CHARACTER DREAMS GERMS SWIM KNOWLEDGE BASEBALL EXPERIENCE NEEDLE THOUGHT CHARACTERS FEVER SWIMMING WORK PLAYERS EMPLOYMENT CURRENT AUTHOR IMAGINATION CAUSE POOL OPPORTUNITIES RESEARCH PLAY COIL READ MOMENT CAUSED LIKE WORKING CHEMISTRY FIELD POLES TOLD THOUGHTS SPREAD SHELL TRAINING TECHNOLOGY PLAYER IRON SETTING OWN VIRUSES SHARK SKILLS MANY BASKETBALL COMPASS TALES REAL INFECTION TANK CAREERS MATHEMATICS COACH LINES PLOT LIFE VIRUS SHELLS POSITIONS BIOLOGY PLAYED CORE TELLING IMAGINE MICROORGANISMS SHARKS FIND FIELD PLAYING ELECTRIC SHORT SENSE PERSON DIVING POSITION PHYSICS HIT DIRECTION INFECTIOUS DOLPHINS CONSCIOUSNESS FICTION FIELD LABORATORY TENNIS FORCE ACTION STRANGE COMMON SWAM OCCUPATIONS STUDIES TEAMS MAGNETS TRUE FEELING CAUSING LONG REQUIRE WORLD GAMES BE EVENTS WHOLE SMALLPOX SEAL OPPORTUNITY SPORTS MAGNETISM SCIENTIST TELLS BEING BODY DIVE EARN STUDYING BAT POLE TALE MIGHT INFECTIONS DOLPHIN ABLE SCIENCES TERRY INDUCED NOVEL HOPE CERTAIN UNDERWATER A selection of topics (from 500) JOB SCIENCE BALL FIELD STORY MIND DISEASE WATER WORK STUDY GAME MAGNETIC STORIES WORLD BACTERIA FISH JOBS SCIENTISTS TEAM MAGNET TELL DREAM DISEASES SEA CAREER SCIENTIFIC FOOTBALL WIRE CHARACTER DREAMS GERMS SWIM KNOWLEDGE BASEBALL EXPERIENCE NEEDLE THOUGHT CHARACTERS FEVER SWIMMING WORK PLAYERS EMPLOYMENT CURRENT AUTHOR IMAGINATION CAUSE POOL OPPORTUNITIES RESEARCH PLAY COIL READ MOMENT CAUSED LIKE WORKING CHEMISTRY FIELD POLES TOLD THOUGHTS SPREAD SHELL TRAINING TECHNOLOGY PLAYER IRON SETTING OWN VIRUSES SHARK SKILLS MANY BASKETBALL COMPASS TALES REAL INFECTION TANK CAREERS MATHEMATICS COACH LINES PLOT LIFE VIRUS SHELLS POSITIONS BIOLOGY PLAYED CORE TELLING IMAGINE MICROORGANISMS SHARKS FIND FIELD PLAYING ELECTRIC SHORT SENSE PERSON DIVING POSITION PHYSICS HIT DIRECTION INFECTIOUS DOLPHINS CONSCIOUSNESS FICTION FIELD LABORATORY TENNIS FORCE ACTION STRANGE COMMON SWAM OCCUPATIONS STUDIES TEAMS MAGNETS TRUE FEELING CAUSING LONG REQUIRE WORLD GAMES BE EVENTS WHOLE SMALLPOX SEAL OPPORTUNITY SPORTS MAGNETISM SCIENTIST TELLS BEING BODY DIVE EARN STUDYING BAT POLE TALE MIGHT INFECTIONS DOLPHIN ABLE SCIENCES TERRY INDUCED NOVEL HOPE CERTAIN UNDERWATER Learning topic hiearchies (Blei, Griffiths, Jordan, & Tenenbaum, 2004) Syntax and semantics from statistics Factorization of language based on statistical dependency patterns: long-range, document specific, dependencies short-range dependencies constant across all documents semantics: probabilistic topics q z z z w w w x x x syntax: probabilistic regular grammar (Griffiths, Steyvers, Blei, & Tenenbaum, submitted) x=2 x=1 z = 1 0.4 HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 OF 0.6 FOR 0.3 BETWEEN 0.1 0.8 z = 2 0.6 SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.7 0.1 0.3 0.2 0.9 x=3 THE 0.6 A 0.3 MANY 0.1 x=2 x=1 z = 1 0.4 HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 OF 0.6 FOR 0.3 BETWEEN 0.1 0.8 z = 2 0.6 SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.7 0.1 0.3 0.2 0.9 THE ……………………………… x=3 THE 0.6 A 0.3 MANY 0.1 x=2 x=1 z = 1 0.4 HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 OF 0.6 FOR 0.3 BETWEEN 0.1 0.8 z = 2 0.6 SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.7 0.1 0.3 0.2 0.9 THE LOVE…………………… x=3 THE 0.6 A 0.3 MANY 0.1 x=2 x=1 z = 1 0.4 HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 OF 0.6 FOR 0.3 BETWEEN 0.1 0.8 z = 2 0.6 SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.7 0.1 0.3 0.2 0.9 THE LOVE OF……………… x=3 THE 0.6 A 0.3 MANY 0.1 x=2 x=1 z = 1 0.4 HEART LOVE SOUL TEARS JOY 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 OF 0.6 FOR 0.3 BETWEEN 0.1 0.8 z = 2 0.6 SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE WORK RESEARCH MATHEMATICS 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.7 0.1 0.3 0.2 0.9 THE LOVE OF RESEARCH …… x=3 THE 0.6 A 0.3 MANY 0.1 Semantic categories MAP FOOD NORTH FOODS EARTH BODY SOUTH NUTRIENTS POLE DIET MAPS FAT EQUATOR SUGAR WEST ENERGY LINES MILK EAST EATING AUSTRALIA FRUITS GLOBE VEGETABLES POLES WEIGHT HEMISPHERE FATS LATITUDE NEEDS CARBOHYDRATES PLACES LAND VITAMINS WORLD CALORIES COMPASS PROTEIN CONTINENTS MINERALS GOLD CELLS BEHAVIOR DOCTOR BOOK IRON CELL SELF PATIENT BOOKS SILVER ORGANISMS INDIVIDUAL HEALTH READING ALGAE PERSONALITY HOSPITAL INFORMATION COPPER METAL BACTERIA RESPONSE MEDICAL LIBRARY METALS MICROSCOPE SOCIAL CARE REPORT STEEL MEMBRANE EMOTIONAL PATIENTS PAGE CLAY ORGANISM LEARNING NURSE TITLE LEAD FOOD FEELINGS DOCTORS SUBJECT ADAM LIVING PSYCHOLOGISTS MEDICINE PAGES ORE FUNGI INDIVIDUALS NURSING GUIDE ALUMINUM PSYCHOLOGICAL MOLD TREATMENT WORDS MINERAL EXPERIENCES MATERIALS NURSES MATERIAL MINE NUCLEUS ENVIRONMENT PHYSICIAN ARTICLE STONE CELLED HUMAN HOSPITALS ARTICLES MINERALS STRUCTURES RESPONSES DR WORD POT MATERIAL BEHAVIORS SICK FACTS MINING STRUCTURE ATTITUDES ASSISTANT AUTHOR MINERS GREEN PSYCHOLOGY EMERGENCY REFERENCE TIN MOLDS PERSON PRACTICE NOTE PLANTS PLANT LEAVES SEEDS SOIL ROOTS FLOWERS WATER FOOD GREEN SEED STEMS FLOWER STEM LEAF ANIMALS ROOT POLLEN GROWING GROW Syntactic categories SAID ASKED THOUGHT TOLD SAYS MEANS CALLED CRIED SHOWS ANSWERED TELLS REPLIED SHOUTED EXPLAINED LAUGHED MEANT WROTE SHOWED BELIEVED WHISPERED THE HIS THEIR YOUR HER ITS MY OUR THIS THESE A AN THAT NEW THOSE EACH MR ANY MRS ALL MORE SUCH LESS MUCH KNOWN JUST BETTER RATHER GREATER HIGHER LARGER LONGER FASTER EXACTLY SMALLER SOMETHING BIGGER FEWER LOWER ALMOST ON AT INTO FROM WITH THROUGH OVER AROUND AGAINST ACROSS UPON TOWARD UNDER ALONG NEAR BEHIND OFF ABOVE DOWN BEFORE GOOD SMALL NEW IMPORTANT GREAT LITTLE LARGE * BIG LONG HIGH DIFFERENT SPECIAL OLD STRONG YOUNG COMMON WHITE SINGLE CERTAIN ONE SOME MANY TWO EACH ALL MOST ANY THREE THIS EVERY SEVERAL FOUR FIVE BOTH TEN SIX MUCH TWENTY EIGHT HE YOU THEY I SHE WE IT PEOPLE EVERYONE OTHERS SCIENTISTS SOMEONE WHO NOBODY ONE SOMETHING ANYONE EVERYBODY SOME THEN BE MAKE GET HAVE GO TAKE DO FIND USE SEE HELP KEEP GIVE LOOK COME WORK MOVE LIVE EAT BECOME Statistical language modeling • Generative models provide – transparent assumptions about causal process – opportunities to combine and extend models • Richer generative models... – probabilistic context-free grammars – paragraph or sentence-level dependencies – more complex semantics Structure and statistics • Statistical language modeling – topic models • Relational categorization – attributes and relations Relational categorization • Most approaches to categorization in psychology and machine learning focus on attributes - properties of objects – words in titles of CogSci posters • But… a significant portion of knowledge is organized in terms of relations – co-authors on posters – who talks to whom (Kemp, Griffiths, & Tenenbaum, 2004) Attributes and relations Data Model attributes objects X P(X) = ik z P(xik|zi) i P(zi) mixture model (c.f. Anderson, 1990) objects objects Y P(Y) = ij z P(yij|zi) i P(zi) stochastic blockmodel Stochastic blockmodels • For any pair of objects, (i,j), probability of relation is determined by classes, (zi, zj) To type j From type i l11 l12 l13 l21 l22 l23 l31 l32 l33 Each entity has a type = Z L P(Z,L|Y) P(Y|Z,LP(Z)P(L • Allows types of objects and class probabilities to be learned from data Stochastic blockmodels A B C A B C A B D C A B C A A B B C C D D Categorizing words • Relational data: word association norms (Nelson, McEvoy, & Schreiber, 1998) • 5018 x 5018 matrix of associations – symmetrized – all words with < 50 and > 10 associates – 2513 nodes, 34716 links Categorizing words BAND INSTRUMENT BLOW HORN FLUTE BRASS GUITAR PIANO TUBA TRUMPET TIE COAT SHOES ROPE LEATHER SHOE HAT PANTS WEDDING STRING SEW MATERIAL WOOL YARN WEAR TEAR FRAY JEANS COTTON CARPET WASH LIQUID BATHROOM SINK CLEANER STAIN DRAIN DISHES TUB SCRUB Categorizing actors • Internet Movie Database (IMDB) data, from the start of cinema to 1960 (Jeremy Kubica) • Relational data: collaboration • 5000 x 5000 matrix of most prolific actors – all actors with < 400 and > 1 collaborators – 2275 nodes, 204761 links Categorizing actors Albert Lieven Karel Stepanek Walter Rilla Anton Walbrook Germany UK Moore Marriott Laurence Hanray Gus McNaughton Gordon Harker Helen Haye Alfred Goddard Morland Graham Margaret Lockwood Hal Gordon Bromley Davenport British comedy Gino Cervi Nadia Gray Enrico Glori Paolo Stoppa Bernardi Nerio Amedeo Nazzari Gina Lollobrigida Aldo Silvani Franco Interlenghi Guido Celano Archie Ricks Helen Gibson Oscar Gahan Buck Moulton Buck Connors Clyde McClary Barney Beasley Buck Morgan Tex Phelps George Sowards Italian US Westerns Structure and statistics • Bayesian approach allows us to specify structured probabilistic models • Explore novel representations and domains – topics for semantic representation – relational categorization • Use powerful methods for inference, developed in statistics and machine learning Other methods and tools... • Inference algorithms – – – – belief propagation dynamic programming the EM algorithm and variational methods Markov chain Monte Carlo • More complex models – Dirichlet processes and Bayesian non-parametrics – Gaussian processes and kernel methods Reading list at http://www.bayesiancognition.com Taking stock Bayesian models of inductive learning • Inductive leaps can be explained with hierarchical Theory-based Bayesian models: Domain Theory Probabilistic Generative Model Structural Hypotheses Data Bayesian inference Bayesian models of inductive learning • Inductive leaps can be explained with hierarchical Theory-based Bayesian models: T S S D D D D D D S D D ... D ... Bayesian models of inductive learning • Inductive leaps can be explained with hierarchical Theory-based Bayesian models. • What the approach offers: – Strong quantitative models of generalization behavior. – Flexibility to model different patterns of reasoning that in different tasks and domains, using differently structured theories, but the same general-purpose Bayesian engine. – Framework for explaining why inductive generalization works, where knowledge comes from as well as how it is used. Bayesian models of inductive learning • Inductive leaps can be explained with hierarchical Theory-based Bayesian models. • Challenges: – Theories are hard. Bayesian models of inductive learning • Inductive leaps can be explained with hierarchical Theory-based Bayesian models: • The interaction between structure and statistics is crucial. – How structured knowledge supports statistical learning, by constraining hypothesis spaces. – How statistics supports reasoning with and learning structured knowledge. – How complex structures can grow from data, rather than being fully specified in advance.