An argument consists of a conclusion (the claim that the speaker or writer is arguing for) and premises (the claims that he or she offers in support of the conclusion). Here is an example of an argument: • – [Premise] Every officer on the force has been certified, and [premise] nobody can be certified without scoring above 70 percent on the firing range. Therefore [conclusion] every officer on the force must have scored above 70 percent on the firing range. The Structure of Argument: Conclusions and Premises When we analyze an argument, we need to first separate the conclusion from the grounds for the conclusion which are called premises. Stating it another way, in arguments we need to distinguish the claim that is being made from the warrants that are offered for it. The claim is the position that is maintained, while the warrants are the reasons given to justify the claim. It is sometimes difficult to make this distinction, but it is important to see the difference between a conclusion and a premise, a claim and its warrant, differentiating between what is claimed and the basis for claiming it. We might make a claim in a formal argument. For example, we might claim that teenage pregnancy can be reduced through sex education in the schools. To justify our claim we might try to show the number of pregnancies in a school before and after sex education classes. In writing an argumentative essay we must decide on the point we want to make and the reasons we will offer to prove it, the conclusion and the premises. The same distinction must be made in reading argumentative essays, namely, what is the writer claiming and the warrant is offered for the claim, what is being asserted and why. Take the following complete argument: ◦ Television presents a continuous display of violence in graphically explicit and extreme forms. It also depicts sexuality not as a physical expression of internal love but in its most lewd and obscene manifestations. We must conclude, therefore, that television contributes to the moral corruption of individuals exposed to it. Whether we agree with this position or not, we must first identify the logic of the argument to test its soundness. In this example the conclusion is “television contributes to the moral corruption of individuals exposed to it.” The premises appear in the beginning sentences: “Television presents a continuous display of violence in graphic and extreme forms,” and “(television) depicts sexuality…in its most lewd and obscene manifestations.” Once we have separated the premises and the claim then we need to evaluate whether the case has been made for the conclusion. Has the writer shown that television does corrupt society? Has a causal link been shown between the depiction of lewd and obscene sex and the moral corruption of society? Does TV reflect violence in our society or does it promote it? •Since dissection is sometimes difficult because we cannot always see the skeleton of the argument. In such cases we can find help by looking for “indicator” words. When the words in the following list are used in arguments, they usually indicate a premise has just been offered and that a conclusion is about to be presented. Consequently Therefore Thus So Hence accordingly We can conclude that It follows that We may infer that This means that It leads us to believe that This bears out the point that Example: ◦ Sarah drives a Dodge Viper. This means that either she is rich or her parents are. The conclusion is: ◦ Either she is rich or her parents are. The premise is: ◦ Sarah drives a Dodge Viper. When the words in the following list are used in arguments, they generally introduce premises. They often occur just after a conclusion has been given. Since Because For whereas In as much as For the reasons that In view of the fact As evidenced by Example: ◦ Either Sarah is rich or her parents are, since she drives a Dodge Viper. The premise is the claim that Sarah drives a Dodge Viper; the conclusion is the claim that either Sarah is rich or her parents are. Indicator words can tell us when the theses and the supports appear, even in complex arguments that are embedded in paragraphs. We can see whether the person has good reasons for making the claim, or whether the argument is weak. We should keep this in mind when presenting our own case. An argument that presents a clear structure of premises and conclusions, without narrative digressions, metaphorical flights, or other embellishments, is much easier for people to follow. To help us make sense of our experience, we humans constantly group things into classes or categories. These classifications are reflected in our everyday language. In formal reasoning the statements that contain our premises and conclusions have to be rendered in a strict form so that we know exactly what is being claimed. These logical forms were first formulated by Aristotle (384-322 B.C.). They are four in number, carrying the designations A, E, I, O, as follows: ◦ All S is P (A). ◦ No S is P (E). ◦ Some S is P (I). ◦ Some S is not P (O). The letter "S" stands for the class designated by the subject term of the proposition. The letter "P" stands for the class designated by the predicate term. Substituting any class-defining words for S and P generates actual categorical propositions. In classical theory, the four standard-form categorical propositions were thought to be the building blocks of all deductive arguments. Each of the four has a conventional designation: A for universal affirmative propositions; E for universal negative propositions; I for particular affirmative propositions; and O for particular negative propositions. These various relationships between classes are affirmed or denied by categorical propositions. The result is that there can be just four different standard forms of categorical propositions. They are illustrated by the four following propositions: 1. 2. 3. 4. All politicians are liars. No politicians are liars. Some politicians are liars. Some politicians are not liars. The first is a universal affirmative proposition. It is about two classes, the class of all politicians and the class of all liars, saying that the first class is included or contained in the second class. A universal affirmative proposition says that every member of the first class is also a member of the second class. In the present example, the subject term “politicians” designates the class of all politicians, and the predicate term “liars” designates the class of all liars. Any universal affirmative proposition may be written schematically as All S is P. where the terms S and P represent the subject and predicate terms, respectively. The name “universal affirmative” is appropriate because the position affirms that the relationship of class inclusion holds between the two classes and says that the inclusion is complete or universal: All members of S are said to be members of P also. The second example ◦ No politicians are liars. Is a universal negative proposition. It denies of politicians universally that they are liars. Concerned with two classes, a universal negative proposition says that the first class is wholly excluded from the second, which is to say that there is no member of the first class that is also a member of the second. Any universal proposition may be written schematically as No S is P Where, again, the letters S and P represent the subject and predicate terms. The name “universal negative” is appropriate because the proposition denies that the relation of class inclusion holds between the two classes – and denies it universally: No members at all of S are members of P. The third example ◦ Some Politicians are liars. is a particular affirmative proposition. Clearly, what the present example affirms is that some members of the class of all politicians are (also) members of the class of all liars. But it does not affirm this of politicians universally: Not all politicians universally, but, rather, some particular politician or politicians, are said to be liars. This proposition neither affirms nor denies that all politicians are liars; it makes no pronouncement on the matter. The word “some” is indefinite. Does it mean “at least one,” or “at least two,” or “at least one hundred?” In this type of proposition, it is customary to regard the word “some” as meaning “at least one.” Thus a particular affirmative proposition, written schematically as ◦ Some S is P. says that at least one member of the class designated by the subject term S is also a member of the class designated by the predicate term P. The name “particular affirmative” is appropriate because the proposition affirms that the relationship of class inclusion holds, but does not affirm it of the first class universally, but only partially, of some particular member or members of the first class. The fourth example ◦ Some politicians are not liars is a particular negative proposition. This example, like the one preceding it, does not refer to politicians universally but only to some member or members of that class; it is particular. But unlike the third example, it does not affirm that the particular members of the first class referred to are included in the second class; this is precisely what is denied. A particular negative proposition, schematically written as Some S is not P. says that at least one member of the class designated by the subject term S is excluded from the whole of the class designated by the predicate term P. Every categorical proposition has a quality, either affirmative or negative. It is affirmative if the proposition asserts some kind of class inclusion, either complete or partial. It is negative if the proposition denies any kind of class inclusion, either complete or partial. Every categorical proposition also has a quantity, either universal or particular. It is universal if the proposition refers to all members of the class designated by its subject term. It is particular if the proposition refers only to some members of the class designated by its subject term. Standard-form categorical propositions consist of four parts, as follows: Quantifer (subject term) copula (predicate term) The three standard-form quantifiers are "all," "no" (universal), and "some" (particular). The copula is a form of the verb "to be." Sentence Standard Form Attribute All apples are delicious. A All S is P. Universal affirmative No apples are delicious. E No S is P. Universal negative Some apples are delicious. I Some S is P. Particular affirmative Some apples are not delicious. O Some S is not P. Particular negative Distribution is an attribute of the terms (subject and predicate) of propositions. A term is said to be distributed if the proposition makes an assertion about every member of the class denoted by the term; otherwise, it is undistributed. In other words, a term is distributed if and only if the statement assigns (or distributes) an attribute to every member of the class denoted by the term. Thus, if a statement asserts something about every member of the S class, then S is distributed; otherwise S and P are undistributed. ◦ Here is another way to look at All S are P. The S circle is contained in the P circle, which represents the fact that every member of S is a member of P. Through reference to this diagram, it is clear that every member of S is in the P class. But the statement does not make a claim about every member of the P class, since there may be some members of the P class that are outside of S. Translate the following sentences into standard form categorical statements: Each insect is an animal. Not every sheep is white. A few holidays fall on Saturday. There are a few right – handed first basemen. Politicians Liars Anything in area 1 is a politician, but not a liar. Anything in area 2 is both a politician and a liar. Anything in area 3 is a liar but not a politician. And anything in area 4, the area outside the two circles is neither a politician or a liar. Politicians Liars The shading means that the part of the politicians circle that does not overlap with the liars circle is empty; that is, it contains no members. The diagram thus asserts that there are no politicians who are are not liars. All politicians are liars. Politicians Liars To say that no politicians are liars is to say that no members of the class of politicians are members of the class of liars – that is, that there is no overlap between the two classes. To represent this claim, we shade the portion of the two circles that overlaps as shown above. No politicians are liars. Politicians Liars In logic, the statement “Some politicians are lairs” means “There exists at least one politician and that politician is a liar.” To diagram this statement, we place an X in that part of the politicians circle that overlaps with the liars circle. Politicians Liars A similar strategy is used with statements of the form “Some S are not P.” In logic, the statement “Some politicians are not liars” means “At least one politician is not a liar.” To diagram this statement we place an X in that part of the politicians circle that lies outside the liars circle. Claims about single individuals, such as “Aristotle is a logician,” can be tricky to translate into standard form. It’s clear that this claim specifies a class, “logicians,” and places Aristotle as a member of that class. The problem is that categorical claims are always about two classes, and Aristotle isn’t a class. (We couldn’t talk about some of Aristotle being a logician.) What we want to do is treat such claims as if they were about classes with exactly one member. One way to do this is to use the term “people who are identical with Aristotle,” which of course has only Aristotle as a member. Claims about single individuals should be treated as A-claims or E-claims. “Aristotle is a logician” can be translated into “All people identical with Aristotle are logicians.” Individual claims do not only involve people. For example, “Fort Wayne is in Indiana” is “All cities identical with Fort Wayne are cities in Indiana.” 1. 2. In categorical logic, “some” always means “at least one.” “Some” statements are understood to assert that something actually exists. Thus, “some mammals are cats” is understood to assert that at least one mammal exists and that that mammal is a cat. By contrast, “all” or “no” statements are not interpreted as asserting the existence of anything. Instead, they are treated as purely conditional statements. Thus, “All snakes are reptiles” asserts that if anything is a snake, then it is a reptile, not that there are snakes and that all of them are reptiles. Draw Venn diagrams of the following statements. In some cases, you may need to rephrase the statements slightly to put them in one of the four standard forms. No apples are fruits. Some apples are not fruits. All fruits are apples. Some apples are fruits. Do people really go around saying things like “some fruits are not apples”? Not very often. But although relatively few of our everyday statements are explicitly in standard categorical form, a surprisingly large number of those statements can be translated into standard categorical form. Every S is P. Whoever is an S is a P. Any S is a P. Each S is a P. Only P are S. Only if something is a P is it an S. The only S are P. Example: Every dog is an animal. Whoever is a bachelor is a male. Any triangle is a geometrical figure. Each eagle is a bird. Only Catholics are popes. Only if something is a dog is it a cocker spaniel. The only tickets available are tickets for cheap seats. Pay special attention to the phrases containing the word “only” in that list. (“Only” is one of the trickiest words in the English language.) Note, in particular, that as a rule the subject and the predicate terms must be reversed if the statement begins with the words “only” or “only if.” Thus, “Only citizens are voters” must be rewritten as “All voters are citizens,” not “All citizens are voters.” And, “Only if a thing is an insect is it a bee” must be rewritten as “All bees are insects,” not “All insects are bees.” No S are P. S are not P. Nothing that is an S known is a P. No one who is an S Republican is a P. All S are non-P. Example: No cows are reptiles. Cows are not reptiles. Nothing that is a fact is a mere opinion. No one who is a is a Democrat. If anything is a plant, then it is not a mineral. Example: Some P are S. Some students are men. A few S are P. A few mathematicians are poets. There are S that are P.There are monkeys that are carnivores. Several S are P. Several planets in the solar system are gas giants. Many S are P. Many students are hard workers. Most S are P. Most Americans are carnivores. Example: Not all S are P. Not all politicians are liars. Not everyone who is Not everyone who is a an S is a P. politician is a liar. Some S are non-P. Some philosophers are non Aristotelians. Most S are not P. Most students are not binge drinkers. Nearly all S are Nearly all students are not not P. cheaters. The process of casting sentences that we find in at ext into one of these four forms is technically called paraphrasing, and the ability to paraphrase must be acquired in order to deal with statements logically. In the processing of paraphrasing we designate the affirmative or negative quality of a statement principally by using the words “no” or “not.” We indicate quantity, meaning whether we are referring to the entire class or only a portion of it, by using words “all” or “some.” In addition, we must render the subject and the predicate as classes of objects with the verb “is” or “are” as the copula joining the halves. We must pay attention to the grammar, diagramming the sentences if need be, to determine the parts of the sentence, the group that is meant, and even what noun is being modified. The kind of thing a claim directly concerns is not always obvious. For example, if you think for a moment about the claim “I always get nervous when I take logic exams,” you’ll see it’s a claim about times. It’s about getting nervous and about logic exams indirectly,of course, but it pertains directly to times or occasions. The proper translation of the example is “All times I take logic exams are times that I get nervous.” Once our statement is translated into proper form, we can see it implications to other forms of the statement. For example, if we claim “All scientists are gifted writers,” that certainly implies that “Some scientists are gifted writers,” but we cannot logically transpose the proposition to “All gifted writers are scientists.” In other words, some statements would follow, others would not. To help determine when we can infer one statement from another and when there is disagreement, logicians have devised tables that we can refer to if we get confused. Thus, by the definition of “distributed term”, S is distributed and P is not. In other words for any (A) proposition, the subject term, whatever it may be, is distributed and the predicate term is undistributed. “No S are P” states that the S and P class are separate, which may be represented as follows: This statement makes a claim about every member of S and every member of P. It asserts that every member of S is separate from every member of P, and also that every member of P is separate from every member of S. Both the subject and the predicate terms of universal negative (E) propositions are distributed. The particular affirmative (I) proposition states that at least one member of S is a member of P. If we represent this one member of S that we are certain about by an asterisk, the resulting diagram looks like this: Since the asterisk is inside the P class, it represents something that is simultaneously an S and a P; in other words, it represents a member of the S class that is also a member of the P class. Thus, the statement “Some S are P” makes a claim about one member (at least) of S and also one member (at least) of P, but not about all members of either class. Thus, neither S or P is distributed. The particular negative (O) proposition asserts that at least one member of S is not a member of P. If we once again represent this one member of S by an asterisk, the resulting diagram is as follows: Since the other members of S may or may not be outside of P, it is clear that the statement “Some S are not P” does not make a claim about every member of S, so S is not distributed. But, as may be seen from the diagram, the statement does assert that the entire P class is separated from this one member of the S that is outside; that is, it does make a claim about every member of P. Thus, in the particular negative (O) proposition, P is distributed and S is undistributed. “Unprepared Students Never Pass” Universals distribute Subjects. Negatives distribute Predicates. “Any Student Earning B’s Is Not On Probation” ◦ ◦ ◦ ◦ A distributes Subject. E distributes Both. I distributes Neither. O distributes Predicate. Quality, quantity, and distribution tell us what standard-form categorical propositions assert about their subject and predicate terms, not whether those assertions are true. Taken together, however, A, E, I, and O propositions with the same subject and predicate terms have relationships of opposition that do permit conclusions about truth and falsity. In other words, if we know whether or not a proposition in one form is true or false, we can draw certain valid conclusions about the truth or falsity of propositions with the same terms in other forms. There are four ways in which propositions may be opposed-as contradictories, contraries, subcontraries, and subalterns. Two propositions are contradictories if one is the denial or negation of the other; that is, if they cannot both be true and cannot both be false at the same time. If one is true, the other must be false. If one is false, the other must be true. A propositions (All S is P) and O propositions (Some S is not P), which differ in both quantity and quality, are contradictories. All logic books are interesting books. Some logic books are not interesting books. Here we have two categorical propositions with the same subject and predicate terms that differ in quantity and quality. One is an A proposition (universal and affirmative). The second is an O proposition (particular and negative). Can both of these propositions be true at the same time? The answer is "no." If all logic books are interesting, than it can't be true that some of them are not. Likewise, if some of them are not interesting, then it can't be true that all of them are. Can both propositions be false at the same time? Again, the answer is "no". If it's false that all logic books are interesting, then it must be true that some of them are not interesting. Likewise if it's false that some of them are not interesting, then all of them must be interesting. Like this pair, all A and O propositions with the same subject and predicate terms are contradictories. One is the denial of the other. They can't both be true or false at the same time. E propositions (No S is P) and I propositions (Some S is P) likewise differ in quantity and quality and are contradictories. Example: No presidential elections are contested elections. Some presidential elections are contested elections. Here again we have two categorical propositions with the same subject and predicate terms that differ in both quantity and quality. In this case, the first is an E proposition—universal and negative— and the second is an I proposition—particular and positive. Can both be true at the same time? The answer is "no." If no presidential elections are contested, then it can't be true that some are. Likewise is some are contested, then it can't be true that none are. Can both be false at the same time? Again the answer is "no." If it's false that no presidential elections are contested, then it must be true that some of them are. Likewise if it's false that some are contested, then it must be the case that none are. Like this pair, all E and I propositions with the same subject and predicate terms are contradictories. One is the denial of the other. They can't both be true or false at the same time. Two propositions are contraries if they cannot both be true; that is, if the truth of one entails the falsity of the other. If one is true, the other must be false. But if one is false, it does not follow that the other has to be true. Both might be false. A (All S is P) and E (No S is P) propositions-which are both universal but differ in quality-are contraries unless one is necessarily (logically or mathematically) true. For example: All books are written by Stephen King. No books are written by Stephen King. Both are false. Two propositions are subcontraries if they cannot both be false, although they both may be true. I (Some S is P) and O (Some S is not P) propositions-which are both particular but differ in quality-are subcontraries unless one is necessarily false. For example: Some dogs are cocker spaniels. Some dogs are not cocker spaniels. Subalternation is the relationship between a universal proposition (the superaltern) and its corresponding particular proposition (the subaltern). According to Aristotelian logic, whenever a universal proposition is true, its corresponding particular must be true. Thus if an A proposition (All S is P) is true, the corresponding I proposition (Some S is P) is also true. Likewise if an E proposition (No S is P) is true, so too is its corresponding particular (Some S is not P). The reverse, however, does not hold. That is, if a particular proposition is true, its corresponding universal might be true or it might be false. For example: All bananas are fruit. Therefore, some bananas are fruit. Or, no humans are reptiles. Therefore, some humans are not reptiles. However, we can’t go in reverse. We can’t say some animals are not dogs. Therefore, no animals are dogs. Or, some guitar players are famous rock musicians. Therefore, all guitar players are famous rock musicians. The first kind of immediate inference, called conversion, proceeds by simply interchanging the subject and predicate terms of the proposition. Conversion is valid in the case of E and I propositions. “No women are American Presidents,” can be validly converted to “No American Presidents are women.” An example of an I conversion: “Some politicians are liars,” and “Some liars are politicians” are logically equivalent, so by conversion either can be validly inferred from the other. One standard-form proposition is said to be the converse of another when it is formed by simply interchanging the subject and predicate terms of that other proposition. Thus, “No idealists are politicians” is the converse of “No politicians are idealists,” and each can validly be inferred from the other by conversion. The term convertend is used to refer to the premise of an immediate inference by conversion, and the conclusion of the inference is called the converse. Note that the converse of an A proposition is not generally valid form that A proposition. For example: “All bananas are fruit,” does not imply the converse, “All fruit are bananas.” A combination of subalternation and conversion does, however, yield a valid immediate inference for A propositions. If we know that "All S is P," then by subalternation we can conclude that the corresponding I proposition, "Some S is P," is true, and by conversion (valid for I propositions) that some P is S. This process is called conversion by limitation. Convertend A proposition: All IBM computers are things that use electricity. Converse A proposition: All things that use electricity are IBM computers. Convertend A proposition: All IBM computers are things that use electricity. Corresponding particular: I proposition: Some IBM computers are things that use electricity. Converse (by limitation) I proposition: Some things that use electricity are IBM computers. The first part of this example indicates why conversion applied directly to A propositions does not yield valid immediate inferences. It is certainly true that all IBM computers use electricity, but it is certainly false that all things that use electricity are IBM computers. Conversion by limitation, however, does yield a valid immediate inference for A propositions according to Aristotelian logic. From "All IBM computers are things that use electricity" we get, by subalternation, the I proposition "Some IBM computers are things that use electricity." And because conversion is valid for I propositions, we can conclude, finally, that "Some things that use electricity are IBM computers." The converse of“Some S is not P,” does not yield an valid immediate inference. Convertend O proposition: Some dogs are not cocker spaniels. Converse O proposition: Some cocker spaniels are not dogs. This example indicates why conversion of O prepositions does not yield a valid immediate inference. The first proposition is true, but its converse is false. Does not convert to A A All men are wicked creatures. All wicked creatures are men. Does convert to E E No men are wicked creatures. No wicked creatures are men. Does convert to I I Some wicked men are creatures. Some wicked creatures are men. Does not convert to O O Some men are not wicked creatures. Some wicked creatures are not men. Obversion - A valid form of immediate inference for every standard-form categorical proposition. To obvert a proposition we change its quality (from affirmative to negative, or from negative to affirmative) and replace the predicate term with its complement. Thus, applied to the proposition "All cocker spaniels are dogs," obversion yields "No cockerspaniels are nondogs," which is called its "obverse." The proposition obverted is called the "obvertend." The obverse is logically equivalent to the obvertend. Obversion is thus a valid immediate inference when applied to any standard-form categorical proposition. The obverse of the A proposition "All S is P" is the E proposition "No S is non-P." The obverse of the E proposition "No S is P" is the A proposition "All S is non-P." The obverse of the I proposition "Some S is P" is the O proposition "Some S is not non-P." The obverse of the O proposition "Some S is not P" is the I proposition "Some S is non-P." Obvertend A-proposition: All cartoon characters are fictional characters. Obverse E-proposition: No cartoon characters are non-fictional characters. Obvertend E-proposition: No current sitcoms are funny shows. Obverse A-proposition: All current sitcoms are non-funny shows. Obvertend I-proposition: Some rap songs are lullabies. Obverse O-proposition: Some rap songs are not nonlullabies. Obvertend O-proposition: Some movie stars are not geniuses. Obverse I-proposition: Some movie stars are nongeniuses. As these examples indicate, obversion always yields a valid immediate inference. If every cartoon character is a fictional If no current sitcoms are funny, then all of them If some rap songs are lullabies, then those If some movie stars are not geniuses, than they character, then it must be true that no cartoon character is a non-fictional character. must be something other than funny. particular rap songs at least must not be things that aren't lullabies. must be something other than geniuses. Contraposition is a process that involves replacing the subject term of a categorical proposition with the complement of its predicate term and its predicate term with the complement of its subject term. Contraposition yields a valid immediate inference for A propositions and O propositions. That is, if the proposition All S is P is true, then its contrapositive All non-P is non-S is also true. For example: Premise A proposition: All logic books are interesting things to read. Contrapositive A proposition: All non interesting things to read are non logic books. The contrapositive of an A proposition is a valid immediate inference from its premise. If the first proposition is true it places every logic book in the class of interesting things to read. The contrapositive claims that any noninteresting things to read are also nonlogic books—something other than a logic book—and surely this must be correct. Premise: I-proposition: Some humans are non-logic teachers. Contrapositive I-proposition: Some logic teachers are not human. As this example suggests, contraposition does not yield valid immediate inferences for I propositions. The first proposition is true, but the second is clearly false. E premise: No dentists are non-graduates. The contrapositive is: No graduates are non-dentists. Obviously this is not true. The contrapositive of an E proposition does not yield a valid immediate inference. This is because the propositions "No S is P" and "Some non-P is non-S" can both be true. But in that case "No non-P is nonS," the contrapositive of "No S is P," would have to be false. A combination of subalternation and contraposition does, however, yield a valid immediate inference for E propositions. If we know that "No S is P" is true, then by subalternation we can conclude that the corresponding O proposition, "Some S is not P," is true, and by contraposition (valid for O propositions) that "Some non-P is not non-S" is also true. This process is called contraposition by limitation. Premise: E-proposition: No Game Show Hosts are Brain Surgeons. Contrapositive E proposition: No non-Brain Surgeons are non-Game show hosts. Premise: E proposition: No game show hosts are brain surgeons. Corresponding particular O proposition: Some game show hosts are not brain surgeons. Contrapositive O proposition: Some non-brain surgeons are not non-game show hosts. The first part of this example indicates why contraposition applied directly to E propositions does not yield valid immediate inferences. Even if the first proposition is true then the second can still be false. This may be hard to see at first, but if we take it apart slowly we can understand why. The first proposition, if true, clearly separates the class of game show hosts from the class of brain surgeons, allowing no overlap between them. It does not, however, tell us anything specific about what is outside those classes. But the second proposition does refer to the areas outside the classes and what it says might be false. It claims that there is not even one thing outside the class of brain surgeons that is, at the same time, a non-game show host. But wait a minute. Most of us are neither brain surgeons nor game show hosts. Clearly the contrapositive is false. Contraposition by limitation, however, does yield a valid immediate inference for E propositions according to Aristotelian logic. By subalternation from the first proposition we get the O proposition "Some game show hosts are not brain surgeons." And then by contraposition, which is valid for O propositions, we get the valid, if tonguetwisting O proposition, "Some non-brain surgeons are not non-game show hosts." O proposition. Premise: Some flowers are not roses. Some non-roses are not non-flowers. This is valid. Thus we can see that contraposition is a valid form of inference only when applied to A and O propositions. Contraposition is not valid at all for I propositions and is valid for E propositions only by limitation. Table of Contraposition Premise Contrapositive A: All S is P. A: All non-P is non-S. E: No S is P. O: Some non-P is not non-S. (by limitation) I: Some S is P. Contraposition not valid. Some non-P is not non-S. O: Some S is not P. Aristotelian logic suffers from a dilemma that undermines the validity of many relationships in the traditional Square of Opposition. Mathematician and logician George Boole proposed a resolution to this dilemma in the late nineteenth century. This Boolean interpretation of categorical propositions has displaced the Aristotelian interpretation in modern logic. The source of the dilemma is the problem of existential import. A proposition is said to have existential import if it asserts the existence of objects of some kind. I and O propositions have existential import; they assert that the classes designated by their subject terms are not empty. But in Aristotelian logic, I and O propositions follow validly from A and E propositions by subalternation. As a result, Aristotelian logic requires A and E propositions to have existential import, because a proposition with existential import cannot be derived from a proposition without existential import. A and O propositions with the same subject and predicate terms are contradictories, and so cannot both be false at the same time. But if A propositions have existential import, then an A proposition and its contradictory O proposition would both be false when their subject class was empty. For example: ◦ Unicorns have horns. If there are no unicorns, then it is false that all unicorns have horns and it is also false that some unicorns have horns. The Boolean interpretation of categorical propositions solves this dilemma by denying that universal propositions have existential import. This has the following consequences: I propositions and O propositions have existential import. A-O and E-I pairs with the same subject and predicate terms retain their relationship as contradictories. Because A and E propositions have no existential import, subalternation is generally not valid. Contraries are eliminated because A and E propositions can now both be true when the subject class is empty. Similarly, subcontraries are eliminated because I and O propositions can now both be false when the subject class is empty. Some immediate inferences are preserved: conversion for E and I propositions, contraposition for A and O propositions, and obversion for any proposition. But conversion by limitation and contraposition by limitation are no longer generally valid. Any argument that relies on the mistaken assumption of existence commits the existential fallacy. The result is to undo the relations along the sides of the traditional Square of Opposition but to leave the diagonal, contradictory relations in force. The relationships among classes in the Boolean interpretation of categorical propositions can be represented in symbolic notation. We represent a class by a circle labeled with the term that designates the class. Thus the class S is diagrammed as shown below: To diagram the proposition that S has no members, or that there are no S’s, we shade all of the interior of the circle representing S, indicating in this way that it contains nothing and is empty. To diagram the proposition that there are S’s, which we interpret as saying that there is at least one member of S, we place an x anywhere in the interior of the circle representing S, indicating in this way that there is something inside it, that it is not empty. To diagram a standard-form categorical proposition, not one but two circles are required. The framework for diagramming any standard-form proposition whose subject and predicate terms are abbreviated by S and P is constructed by drawing two intersecting circles: Claims about single individuals, such as “Aristotle is a logician,” can be tricky to translate into standard form. It’s clear that this claim specifies a class, “logicians,” and places Aristotle as a member of that class. The problem is that categorical claims are always about two classes, and Aristotle isn’t a class. (We couldn’t talk about some of Aristotle being a logician.) What we want to do is treat such claims as if they were about classes with exactly one member. One way to do this is to use the term “people who are identical with Aristotle,” which of course has only Aristotle as a member. Claims about single individuals should be treated as A-claims or E-claims. “Aristotle is a logician” can be translated into “All people identical with Aristotle are logicians.” Individual claims do not only involve people. For example, “Fort Wayne is in Indiana” is “All cities identical with Fort Wayne are cities in Indiana.” 1. 2. In categorical logic, “some” always means “at least one.” “Some” statements are understood to assert that something actually exists. Thus, “some mammals are cats” is understood to assert that at least one mammal exists and that that mammal is a cat. By contrast, “all” or “no” statements are not interpreted as asserting the existence of anything. Instead, they are treated as purely conditional statements. Thus, “All snakes are reptiles” asserts that if anything is a snake, then it is a reptile, not that there are snakes and that all of them are reptiles. Draw Venn diagrams of the following statements. In some cases, you may need to rephrase the statements slightly to put them in one of the four standard forms. No apples are fruits. Some apples are not fruits. All fruits are apples. Some apples are fruits. Do people really go around saying things like “some fruits are not apples”? Not very often. But although relatively few of our everyday statements are explicitly in standard categorical form, a surprisingly large number of those statements can be translated into standard categorical form. Every S is P. Whoever is an S is a P. Any S is a P. Each S is a P. Only P are S. Only if something is a P is it an S. The only S are P. Example: Every dog is an animal. Whoever is a bachelor is a male. Any triangle is a geometrical figure. Each eagle is a bird. Only Catholics are popes. Only if something is a dog is it a cocker spaniel. The only tickets available are tickets for cheap seats. Pay special attention to the phrases containing the word “only” in that list. (“Only” is one of the trickiest words in the English language.) Note, in particular, that as a rule the subject and the predicate terms must be reversed if the statement begins with the words “only” or “only if.” Thus, “Only citizens are voters” must be rewritten as “All voters are citizens,” not “All citizens are voters.” And, “Only if a thing is an insect is it a bee” must be rewritten as “All bees are insects,” not “All insects are bees.” No S are P. S are not P. Nothing that is an S known is a P. No one who is an S Republican is a P. All S are non-P. Example: No cows are reptiles. Cows are not reptiles. Nothing that is a fact is a mere opinion. No one who is a is a Democrat. If anything is a plant, then it is not a mineral. Some P are S. A few S are P. There are S that are P. Several S are P. Many S are P. Most S are P. Not all S are P. Not everyone who is an S is a P. Some S are non-P. Most S are not P. Nearly all S are not P. The process of casting sentences that we find in at ext into one of these four forms is technically called paraphrasing, and the ability to paraphrase must be acquired in order to deal with statements logically. In the processing of paraphrasing we designate the affirmative or negative quality of a statement principally by using the words “no” or “not.” We indicate quantity, meaning whether we are referring to the entire class or only a portion of it, by using words “all” or “some.” In addition, we must render the subject and the predicate as classes of objects with the verb “is” or “are” as the copula joining the halves. We must pay attention to the grammar, diagramming the sentences if need be, to determine the parts of the sentence, the group that is meant, and even what noun is being modified. The kind of thing a claim directly concerns is not always obvious. For example, if you think for a moment about the claim “I always get nervous when I take logic exams,” you’ll see it’s a claim about times. It’s about getting nervous and about logic exams indirectly,of course, but it pertains directly to times or occasions. The proper translation of the example is “All times I take logic exams are times that I get nervous.” Once our statement is translated into proper form, we can see it implications to other forms of the statement. For example, if we claim “All scientists are gifted writers,” that certainly implies that “Some scientists are gifted writers,” but we cannot logically transpose the proposition to “All gifted writers are scientists.” In other words, some statements would follow, others would not. To help determine when we can infer one statement from another and when there is disagreement, logicians have devised tables that we can refer to if we get confused. Does not convert to A A All men are wicked creatures. All wicked creatures are men. Does convert to E E No men are wicked creatures. No wicked creatures are men. Does convert to I I Some wicked men are creatures. Some wicked creatures are men. Does not convert to O O Some men are not wicked creatures. Some wicked creatures are not men. Syllogism – a deductive argument in which a conclusion is inferred from two premises. In a syllogism we lay out our train of reasoning in an explicit way, identifying the major premise of the argument, the minor premise, and the conclusion. The major premise consists of the chief reason for the conclusion, or more technically, it is the premise that contains the term in the predicate of the conclusion. The minor premise supports the conclusion in an auxiliary way, or more precisely, it contains the term that appears in the subject of the conclusion. The conclusion is the point of the argument, the outcome, or necessary consequence of the premise. Example in an argumentative essay: ◦ In determining who has committed war crimes we must ask ourselves who has slaughtered unarmed civilians, whether as reprisal, “ethnic cleansing,” terrorism”, or outright genocide. For along with pillaging, rape, and other atrocities, this is what war crimes consist of . In the civil war in the former Yugoslavia, soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army committed hundreds of murders of this kind. They must therefore be judged guilty of war crimes along with the other awful groups in our century, most notably the Nazis. The conclusion to this argument is that soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army are guilty of war crimes. The premises supporting the conclusion are that slaughtering unarmed civilians is a war crime, and soldiers in the Bosnian Serb army have slaughtered unarmed civilians. The following syllogism will diagram this argument. All soldiers who slaughter unarmed civilians are guilty of war crimes. Some Bosnian Serb soldiers are soldiers who slaughter unarmed civilians Some Bosnian Serb soldiers are guilty of war crimes. Enthymeme - An argument that is stated incompletely, the unstated part of it being taken for granted. An enthymeme may be the first, second, or third order, depending on whether the unstated proposition is the major premise, the minor premise, or the conclusion of the argument. Enthymemes traditionally have been divided into different orders, according to which part of the syllogism is left unexpressed. A first order enthymeme is one in which the syllogism’s major premise is not stated. For example, suppose someone said, “We must expect to find needles on all pine trees; they are conifers after all.” Once we recognize this as an enthymeme we must provide the unstated (major) premise, namely, “All conifers have needles.” Then we need to paraphrase the statements and arrange them in a syllogism, indicating by parentheses which one we added was not in the text: (All conifers are trees that have needles.) All pine trees are conifers. All pine trees are trees that have needles. A second - order enthymeme is one in which only the major premise and the conclusion are stated, the minor premise being suppressed. For example, “Of course tennis players aren’t weak, in fact, no athletes are weak.” Obviously, the missing premise is “Tennis players are athletes,” so the syllogism would appear this way. No athletes are weak. (All tennis players are athletes.) No tennis players are weak. A third – order enthymeme is one in which both premises are sated, but the conclusion is left unexpressed. For example, “All true democrats believe in freedom of speech, but there are some Americans who would impose censorship on free expression.” The reader is left to draw the conclusion that some Americans are not true democrats. The syllogism: All true democrats are people who believe in freedom of speech. Some Americans are not people who believe in freedom of speech. (Some Americans are not true democrats.) No certainty should be rejected. So, no selfevident propositions should be rejected. Some beliefs about aliens are not rational, for all rational beliefs are proportional to the available evidence. John is a member of the police force and all policemen carry guns. No matter how diligent we are in constructing our argument in proper form, our conclusion can still be mistaken if the conclusion does not strictly follow from the premises, that is, if the logic is not sound. For example, All fish are gilled creatures. All tuna are fish. All tuna are gilled creatures. This seems correct. But suppose we want to claim that all tuna are fish for the simple reason that they have gills and all fish have gills. Our syllogism would then appear in the following form: All fish are gilled creatures. All tuna are gilled creatures. All tuna are fish. Of course, this syllogism is problematic. The mistake seems to lie in the structure itself. From the fact that tuna have gills we cannot conclude that tuna must be fish, because we do not know that only fish have gills. Another example: John is pro-choice, therefore John is a Democrat. Some Republicans or Libertarians are pro-choice. Just because John is pro-choice does not mean that he is necessarily a Democrat. An argument of this kind, where the conclusion fails to follow from the premises, is considered invalid. That is, the form of the argument is flawed so that the reasons that are given do not support the claim that is made. Suppose we were to argue the following: All trees are reptiles. All rocks are trees. All rocks are reptiles. It is true that if all trees are reptiles, and all rocks are trees, then it logically follows that all rocks are reptiles. The obvious problem is that trees are not reptiles and rocks are not trees. The logical structure of an argument can be sound. Given the premises, the conclusion follows necessarily from them, but the premises are untrue. Truth is correspondence with reality. A statement is true if it describes things as they are. Validity, on the other hand, applies to the structure of an argument, not to the statements that make up its content. As we have seen, an argument is valid if, given the premises, the conclusion is unavoidable.