Today’s Lecture • Some administrative stuff (based on the course outline) • Why do we study philosophy? • Why should we study philosophy? • An introduction to philosophical method: Reading philosophy, engaging in philosophy, writing a philosophy paper. Some administrative stuff:Due dates and texts • Two important things to note in the course outline: The dates for the in-class quizzes and the due dates for your assignments. • You have a course text and a course pack. We will be using both. The exam will presuppose a knowledge of the readings taken from both sources. Some administrative stuff:Inclass quizzes • Each in-class quiz will consist of one short answer question. • It will not be essay question. • It will ask about a term covered in class or a basic position advocated by a philosopher already covered in class. Some administrative stuff:Six days of grace • You have six days of grace to use against any of your assignment due dates. This will, I hope, eliminate the need to ask for an extension. • You can use these days of grace all at once or pace them out through the term. They are yours to use and lose. • I will keep a record of each of your days of grace if you need to see what you have left at any point in the term. Some administrative stuff:Email policy • I will reply within four days to your emails. • I will NOT accept email submissions of your assignments, except in exceptional circumstances (and you need to get my permission to so submit your assignment). Some administrative stuff:Course web site • I will post the lecture notes on the web. These may be posted before the lecture and they may not. I ask for your patience with the web site. It is my gift to you, not something I am required to provide for this course. • Do check out the online resources I have provided for the class. You will find them useful. Some administrative stuff: Office hours • I have two office hours a week. If you cannot make it to my office during these times we can set up an appointment. • My office is TC 306 • My phone number is 661-2111, ext. 85798. • My email is afenton2@uwo.ca. Some administrative stuff: Assignment topics • I will be providing possible topics for your assignments. Choose one, and only one, when writing the relevant assignment. • You have the topics for your first assignment. • Be sure to follow the instructions on the back of your assignment handout. I will be using this list as a grade your assignments. Some administrative stuff • Any questions about the course outline? Why do we study philosophy? • Note: the distinction between ‘Why do we study philosophy?’ and ‘Why should we study philosophy?’ is a distinction between the descriptive and normative. • Philosophical practice typically involves conceptual analysis and normative judgments. • ‘What do we mean by ‘good’?’ is a conceptual question. • ‘Is abortion always wrong?’ is a normative question. • ‘Are my beliefs about the external world justified?’ is a normative question. Why do we study philosophy? • • • • • 1. We want to take an arts course but we can’t stand poetry. 2. It’s cool. 3. It’s better than studying math. 4. We get to call ourselves philosophers. 5. We get to astound our friends with jargon they would otherwise never hear. • 6. Philosophy is an excellent conversation stopper at the family table. • 7. You want to know if we have good enough reasons for believing x, where x is a subject of some importance to you. Why should we study philosophy? • 1. Our values and beliefs can cause us, and others, harm. As we should minimize the harm we do to ourselves and others (or avoid unnecessary harm to ourselves and others), we should ensure that our values or beliefs are justified. Philosophical inquiry can aid us in evaluating our values and beliefs. Why should we study philosophy? • 2. It is better to be moral than immoral. What’s more, it is better to be nonaccidentally moral than accidentally moral. Philosophical inquiry can aid in our search for the moral life. Why should we study philosophy? • 3. According to many (though not all) religious traditions, our belief choices in this life will inform the quality of our life after death. But these traditions offer competing (i.e. incompatible) claims about what our belief choices should be. Since it may be in our long-term interest to be circumspect in our belief choices, philosophical inquiry can aid our inquiry into the verisimilitude of the claims made by the relevant traditions, and of our own beliefs. Why should we study philosophy? • 4. Our belief choices and preferences often inform our path in life. As these beliefs and preferences help us narrow our options or inform our decisions, we should ensure they conform to those standards that, when obeyed, maximize our best interests. Philosophical inquiry can aid in the clarification of what is in our best interest, what standards will maximize this interest, and what beliefs or preferences conform to these standards. What is philosophy? • This is a hard question to answer. Part of the problem is that this question has no one right answer. • We can distinguish between philosophy and other disciplines on the basis of its general method, subject matter or the attitude of those who engage in it. What is philosophy? Some remarks about method. • As I have already said philosophy is primarily concerned with conceptual analysis and normative judgments. • Conceptual analysis is one of the first steps in doing philosophy. Before you can properly answer a question you need to ensure that you understand what is being asked. What is philosophy? Some remarks about method. • Conceptual analysis can also save a lot of later confusion. It may be that what appears to be a pressing metaphysical problem (e.g. a problem about what really exists independently of how we represent reality) is really due to a confusion in the way we have formulated the issue. • Must we belief that there are moral facts in order to make sense of the idea of justified moral statements? What is it for a statement to be justified? What is philosophy? Some remarks about method. • In philosophical discussion or inquiries both conceptual analyses and normative judgments require adequate defense. • If we are providing an analysis of justification, we need to defend the analysis we proffer. What is philosophy? Some remarks about method. • If we are making a judgment about whether a given belief about the external world is justified or unjustified, we need to defend that judgment. • Philosophical defense of analyses or judgments takes the form of arguments in favor of the analyses or judgments we are proffering. • A defense is adequate if the argument offered is a strong one. • A philosophical position is good or bad relative to how well it is defended. What is philosophy? Some remarks about philosophy’s subject matter. • Three general questions provide the common foci of philosophical inquiry: • (1) What do we know? The relevant area is known as epistemology. • (2) What (really) exists? The relevant area is known as metaphysics. • (3) How should we act? This area involves the development and defense of theories of value. What is philosophy? Some remarks about philosophy’s subject matter. • Epistemology concerns such questions as ‘What is knowledge?’, ‘What is the extent of our knowledge?’, and ‘How do we know that we know?’. • Metaphysics concerns such questions as ‘What exists independently of our minds?’, ‘What is the mind?’, ‘Does God exist?’, and ‘Do we have souls?’. • Theories of value will, in all likelihood, touch on questions that are either epistemological or metaphysical in nature. What is philosophy? Some remarks about ‘the’ philosophical attitude. • Philosophical inquiry is often marked by a degree of skepticism regarding received traditions, beliefs, or viewpoints. • Philosophical inquiry is often motivated by a desire to know the truth of the matter, or to form justified beliefs about whatever it is that is being investigated. • Philosophers often exhibit a dissatisfaction with limiting their views to mere opinions. Reading philosophy • There are certain questions you should ask yourself when reading philosophy. • 1. What is the central thesis the philosopher is defending? • 2. What minor theses is the philosopher defending in the course of defending her overall (or central) thesis? Reading philosophy • 3. What does the philosopher offer in defense of her central thesis? • 4. What does the philosopher offer in defense of her minor theses? • 5. Does the philosopher provide an adequate defense of her central thesis? • 6. Does the philosopher provide an adequate defense of her minor theses? Engaging in philosophy • In questions 5 and 6 from the previous slide the concept of adequate defense is used to assess the strength of a philosopher’s position. • By what do we mean ‘adequate defense’? • What is it to defend a thesis anyway? Engaging in philosophy • In philosophy, a defense of a thesis consists of offering reasons for believing that the thesis is true or probably true. • A defense of a thesis is adequate if it succeeds in providing reasons for believing that the thesis is true or probably true. Engaging in philosophy • Adequate defense presupposes, then, that the reasons given in defense of a thesis are (1) relevant to the defense of the thesis in question, (2) extensive enough to warrant the conclusion drawn in the thesis, and (3) are themselves true or likely to be true. Engaging in philosophy • If you are attempting to show that a thesis is true, or certainly true, you will probably want to use a deductive argument. • An argument is deductive if its premises (the reasons given in the defense of a given thesis) entail, or are intended to entail, the conclusion (the thesis which is being defended). • A premise, or set of premises, entail a conclusion if it impossible for the premise, or set of premises, to be true and the conclusion to be false. Engaging in philosophy • Consider the premises: • (1) If Everybody Loves Raymond is a comedy, then it is badly written. • (2) Everybody Loves Raymond is a comedy. • These premises entail what conclusion? • (3) So, Everybody Loves Raymond is badly written. • Why? IF (1) and (2) are TRUE, then (3) MUST ALSO BE TRUE. Engaging in philosophy • Do note that you cannot argue that because (1) and (2) entail (3), (3) must be true. • Why? It could be the case that (1) or (2) is false. Engaging in philosophy • In logical jargon, this argument is valid (the conclusion is entailed by the premises) but it may not be sound. • A deductive argument is sound if it is valid AND the premises are, in fact, true. • You can only contend that (3) must be true on the basis of the above argument if it is sound. Engaging in philosophy • If you are attempting to show that a thesis is probably, or possibly, true, you will probably want to use an inductive argument. • An argument is inductive if its premises (non-conclusively) support, or are intended to support (albeit non-conclusively), the conclusion. Engaging in philosophy • A premise, or set of premises, (nonconclusively) support a conclusion if it increases the likelihood that the conclusion is true to something between zero and one (where one is absolute certitude). • If it only slightly increases such a likelihood, then the argument is weak. If it greatly increases such a likelihood then the argument is strong. If it doesn’t increase the likelihood of the conclusion’s truth at all, it really sucks. Engaging in philosophy • (1) Chimpanzees probably think. • (2) After all, chimpanzees have brains that are relevantly similar to our own, • (3) and brains are the material substrate of human thought. Engaging in philosophy • (4) What’s more, if a human possesses a properly functioning brain, it is reasonable to conclude that she thinks. • (5) So if a chimpanzee possesses a properly functioning brain, it is reasonable to conclude that she thinks. • (6) Finally, most chimpanzees possess properly functioning brains. Engaging in philosophy • Is this argument strong, weak or does it really suck? Engaging in philosophy • Fallacies (forms of argument) to avoid: • (1) Do not beg the question. You beg the question in an argument when you (implicitly or explicitly) assume in your premises the (truth of the) very thesis that you are defending. • I know that God exists. After all, the Bible assumes that God exists, and the Bible is infallible (on these matters). We know that the Bible is infallible (on these matters) because it is God’s Word. Engaging in philosophy • (2) Do not appeal to red herrings (nonsequiturs). You appeal to a red herring if you treat an irrelevant fact or observation as relevant to the truth of the thesis that you are defending. • I know that abortion is wrong. After all, the current US administration is intent on seeing Roe vs. Wade struck down and many legal experts agree that the grounds for the decision in Roe vs. Wade are too weak to withstand legal scrutiny. Engaging in philosophy • (3) Do not equivocate. You equivocate if your argument’s apparent success depends on the use of more than one meaning for a term central to the argument. • I know that abortion is wrong. Killing humans is always wrong. Human fetuses are human. Abortion kills human fetuses. So, abortion kills humans. So, abortion is wrong. Engaging in philosophy • (4) Avoid arguments from ignorance. Arguments from ignorance conclude that something is true on the ground that there is an absence of counterevidence, or that something is false on the ground that there is an absence of confirming evidence. • I know that no extra-terrestrials have visited the planet. No UFO, or alien, sighting has turned out to be true and we have no evidence in the historical records that any of our ancestors encountered such beings. Engaging in philosophy • (5) Avoid appeals to (questionable) authority. Arguments contain appeals to (questionable) authority if they contain appeals to an individual who is not an expert in the relevant area of knowledge, the area in which they are an expert is not a legitimate area of knowledge, or there is no consensus among those who are experts in the relevant area of knowledge. Engaging in philosophy • I know that biological evolution didn’t occur on Earth. After all, the Reverend Billy Graham believes that the theory of evolution is false. Engaging in philosophy • (6) Avoid appeals to popularity (i.e. ad populum arguments). An argument contains an appeal to popularity if the defense for the argument’s conclusion consists of an appeal to something commonly, or widely, believed. • It’s obvious that homosexuality is immoral. After all, most moral theologians, many moral philosophers and most religious traditions have condemned homosexuality. Engaging in philosophy • (7) Avoid false dilemmas. An argument contains a false dilemma if there are more choices (available) than those offered in the argument, and the argument portrays the choices it offers as exhaustive (of those available). • Of course, Yassar is a terrorist. He opened fire on an American army patrol, and you only shoot at American soldiers if you are mad or a terrorist. We all know that Yassar is not mad.