Chapter 9 Law and the End of Life We come at last to that part of life about which few of us like to think. Though the therapist may encourage us to “face up to it,” and the financial analyst may warn us to “plan for it,” most of us prefer to push it to the deep recesses of our consciousness. After all, to “face up to” or to “plan for” death is to acknowledge its inevitably, something few of us are willing to dwell on – and the younger we are the less apt we are to do so. Not so the web of law; indeed, as we shall see, issues surrounding the very inevitable end of life make up a large and, with the greying of the baby boom generation, a growing segment of the web.1 Like Shelley’s “traveler,” the law moves with us from “cradle to grave”(Shelley 1820). In this chapter, we explore law at the end of life. We begin by reviewing law’s modern role in making the last days, months, years of life’s journey more comfortable. Next, we contemplate the nexus between law and life’s physical end, including technologies that try to keep life going longer and longer and the legal ability (or inability) we have to end life when pain or despair make continuation unbearable. Finally, we briefly describe law’s very ancient concern with the end in questions surrounding the distribution of property, debts and taxes. LAW IN THE GOLDEN YEARS: MODERN CONCERNS OF OLD AGE While the treatment of the aged in this Nation has not been wholly free of discrimination, such persons, unlike, say, those who have been discriminated against on the basis of race or national origin, have not experienced a "history of purposeful unequal treatment" or been subjected to unique disabilities on the basis of stereotyped characteristics not truly indicative of their abilities. [O]ld age does not define a "discrete and insular" group in need of "extraordinary protection from the majoritarian political process." Instead, it marks a stage that each of us will reach if we live out our normal span. Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307, at 313-314, 1976 (per curiam) (citations deleted from original). The Murgia Court came about as close to defining “old age” as one will find in American case law. It is simply the inevitable end game of life that “each of us will reach if we live out our normal span.” As we discussed in Chapter 6 within the context of early life and childhood, age demarcations are inherently subjective and arbitrary. This is equally true with regard to the other end of life’s continuum. For legal purposes, age is both quite determinate (one can calculate in years, months, days, even seconds) and indeterminate. It is not clear when a child is no longer appropriately considered a child; nor is it any more clear when a person crosses the threshold to become elderly. In Murgia, the Court addressed a 14th Amendment equal protection challenge to a Massachusetts law that set that threshold for uniformed police offers at age 50, mandating retirement from the force for all who reached that milestone. Significantly, the Justices determined that age, unlike race, is not a “suspect classification,” and that the state need only demonstrate a rational basis for making age-related distinctions. The Court reasoned: “Through mandatory retirement at age 50, the legislature seeks to protect the public by assuring physical preparedness of its uniformed police. Since physical ability generally declines with age, mandatory retirement at 50 serves to remove from police service those whose fitness for uniformed work presumptively has diminished with age. This clearly is rationally related to the State's objective” (Murgia, at 314-315). (Only Justice Marshall dissented from this view, finding instead that the state’s argument was entirely irrational). Some 15 years later, the Court considered a similar challenge to a Missouri constitutional provision mandating retirement of all judges at age 70.2 Although a bit more divided, a majority reached a similar conclusion: The Missouri mandatory retirement provision, like all legal classifications, is founded on a generalization. It is far from true that all judges suffer significant deterioration in performance at age 70. It is probably not true that most do. It may not be true at all. But a State `does not violate the Equal Protection Clause merely because the classifications made by its laws are imperfect'.... The people of Missouri rationally could conclude that the threat of deterioration at age 70 is sufficiently great, and the alternatives for removal sufficiently inadequate, that they will require all judges to step aside at age 70. This classification does not violate the Equal Protection Clause” (Gregory v. Ashcroft, 501 U.S. 452, 473, 1991) (quoting Murgia at 316). The Court reiterated this logic in one of the set of opinions delivered at the turn of the 21st century. In Kimel v. Florida Board of Regents, Justice O’Connor, writing for a 5-4 majority, stated: “Our Constitution permits States to draw lines on the basis of age when they have a rational basis for doing so at a class-based level, even if it ‘is probably not true that those reasons are valid in the majority of cases” ((120 S. Ct. 631, 647 (2000)).3 What Is Old Age? While age is generally measured in years, it is more than objective chronological fact. To be classified as young or old is in part an individualized subjective perception, a set of expectations about the collective future, and a function of the contemporary socioeconomic milieu. Thus, what is understood as old age is a changing phenomenon and social reality. For example, upon his visit in the 1830s, Tocqueville observed, among many other things, that the short life expectancy of the period, about 35 years, produced a population that was restless, full of bravado and willing to take high risks for the thrill of the moment. Their taste for physical gratifications must be regarded as the original source of that secret disquietude which the actions of the Americans betray and of that inconstancy of which they daily ford fresh examples. He who has set his heart exclusively upon the pursuit of worldly welfare is always in a hurry, for he has but a limited time at his disposal to reach, to grasp, and to enjoy it. The recollection of the shortness of life is a constant spur to him. Besides the good things that he possesses, he every instant fancies a thousand others that death will prevent him from trying if he does not try them soon. This thought fills him with anxiety, fear, and regret and keeps his mind in ceaseless trepidation, which leads him perpetually to change his plans and his abode. (Tocqueville 1835, Book II, Chapter 13) Indeed, there was no reason to delay gratification, because death was a constant threat to all who survived birth. The threat of death, of course, haunts us all, but the time horizon for those who lived in the early 1800s was short by today’s standard, and most people had little reason to conjure up a long-term life strategy. No doubt, it was precisely that kind of perspective and expectation that led Alexander Hamilton and Vice President Aaron Burr to a fateful dueling field in 1804. Left dead at the ripe old age of 49, Hamilton had long surpassed the expected life span of his birth cohort. In fact, he outlived his own son who had also been killed in a duel three years earlier. By the turn of the twentieth century, the average American citizen could expect to live about 47 years. This was a statistically significant improvement, but socially not a profound one for the vast majority of the population. Life was hard. Childbirth was risky; childhood was short; adolescence was nonexistent. Tuberculosis, scarlet fever, small pox, polio, influenza, and other infectious diseases swept through the population in waves, and only the very strong, the very lucky, and the very wealthy survived into what today we would consider old age. The census of 1900 indicates that a rather small minority, four percent (or, about 3.1 million people), of the American population was 65 or older. The first half of the 20th century saw general conditions improve with advances in sanitation, housing, and overall economic well-being. Moreover, treatment of infectious diseases became much more effective. As a result, people were living longer. In 1940 the ranks of the 65 and older population had swelled to 9 million, and by 1950 life expectancy had increased to 68 years. Quality of life continued to improve during the latter half of the 20th century, with growing economic prosperity, great strides in nutritional and medical research, more successful treatment of chronic diseases (such as cancer and heart disease), and the like. As a consequence, life expectancy has risen steadily to about 77 years in 2000. On the other end of the spectrum, the infant mortality rate has decreased dramatically. Indeed, since 1950, the infant mortality rate has dropped from 29.2 (per 1000 live births) to just over seven. This means that more people survive the first year of life, and a higher percentage of each birth cohort live to middle age and beyond together. By the year 2000, the 65 and older contingent of the population had climbed to 34.7 million and is projected to bulge to 53.2 million by 2020 as the baby boom generation of the 1950s reach that milestone. Considering the issue from a slightly different perspective, during the 20th century, the number of persons in the United States under age 65 tripled; while the number aged 65 or over increased by a magnitude of 11, from 4% to about 16% of the total population. Meanwhile, the greyest of the grey, those 85 years old or more, now represent the fastest growing group among the nation’s elderly. Suffice it to say that old age was not the issue in the 19th century that it has become – socially, economically, politically, and legally. As the Murgia Court noted, “physical ability generally declines with age,” and later in Gregory, the Court observed that we can expect to “suffer significant deterioration in performance” as we advance towards life’s end. Thus, the 20th century Court, unlike its predecessors, could work from the assumption that “if we live out our normal span,” we can all expect to experience significant deterioration in abilities and performance. As we recounted above, the number of people for whom that assumption became a reality was increasing considerably by the 1920s, and as that happened, the elderly and their unique problems began to appear on the radar screens of policy makers. The social and economic convulsions produced by the Great Depression of the 1930s brought the elderly clearly into focus. Until then, people who lived into their 60s and beyond and who had left the workforce and hence were no longer earning an income, relied upon a patchwork support system that included their friends and families, voluntary pension programs by some employers (for a select number of employees), and private charities, to provide a sufficient level of sustenance to survive until their ultimate death. During the Depression, private pension systems were wiped out by the stock market crash, massive unemployment placed most families under extreme economic stress and unable to care for their elders, and charities were completely swamped. With no cash reserve and no reliable source of support, older workers fortunate enough to have jobs had no incentive to quit. Franklin Roosevelt was elected in a landslide in the presidential election of 1932 with a promise to address the mounting economic morass with quick and decisive action. On January 8, 1934 President Roosevelt announced his intention to provide for Social Security. The first step was to create, by executive order, a Committee on Economic Security, empowered to study the problems and devise a concrete set of legislative proposals. The Committee's recommendations were presented to Congress in January of 1935, and the Social Security Act (SSA) of 1935 was signed into law on August 14.4 The SSA created a trust from which disbursements would be made to older citizens (65 years and over), funded by a payroll tax and employer contributions. The act was a major piece of the New Deal package, guaranteeing a security benefit to the nation’s oldest citizens. It was designed also to produce an economic stimulus. Older workers would retire from their jobs, making room for younger, presumably more productive ones who desperately needed employment, and they would spend their social security checks, thus injecting new cash into the struggling economy. Roosevelt’s plan was not without its detractors, however, and the legislative enactment immediately triggered litigation. The Act’s opponents argued, among many other points, that Congress had violated its Constitutional authority to create policy that would enhance the “general welfare” by extending benefits only to one segment of the population, old people, and that it had breached the Tenth Amendment power of the states to address social policy of this kind (see e.g., Wolfskill 1962).5 Justice Cardozo, writing for the majority upholding the Act’s constitutionality, stated: The purge of nation-wide calamity that began in 1929 has taught us many lessons. Not the least is the solidarity of interests that may once have seemed to be divided....Spreading from State to State, unemployment is an ill not particular but general, which may be checked, if Congress so determines, by the resources of the Nation....The hope behind this statute is to save men and women from the rigors of the poor house as well as from the haunting fear that such a lot awaits them when journey's end is near. Congress did not improvise a judgment when it found that the award of old age benefits would be conducive to the general welfare....Among the relevant facts are these: The number of persons in the United States 65 years of age or over is increasing proportionately as well as absolutely. What is even more important the number of such persons unable to take care of themselves is growing at a threatening pace. More and more our population is becoming urban and industrial instead of rural and agricultural. The evidence is impressive that among industrial workers the younger men and women are preferred over the older. In times of retrenchment the older are commonly the first to go, and even if retained, their wages are likely to be lowered....With the loss of savings inevitable in periods of idleness, the fate of workers over 65, when thrown out of work, is little less than desperate.... The problem is plainly national in area and dimensions. Moreover, laws of the separate states cannot deal with it effectively. Congress, at least, had a basis for that belief. States and local governments are often lacking in the resources that are necessary to finance an adequate program of security for the aged.... (Helvering v. Davis, 301 US 619, 641-644, 1937).(notes deleted from original). Thus, the SSA passed constitutional muster, and in 1940 the first benefits were paid to workers, 65 and older, who had retired. Although it has been amended a number of times since, usually to expand benefits, the legislation has proven to be among the most politically popular and resilient policies of the 20th century. By mid-century, the 65+ segment of the population, whose ranks had swelled to about 15 million, began to organize for the first time to promote their interests through the legislative process and through the courts.6 In 1958, for example, the American Association of Retired Persons (AARP) was founded, and by the end of 1999, the organization could boast a membership of over 30 million.7 The SSA of 1935 is a significant landmark. First, it legally defined old age as beginning at 65 years. Thus, we were given a fixed legal definition of old age at a time when length of life has substantially increased, and when, from a range of other perspectives, the threshold marking senior status is clearly not fixed. Moreover, as Friedman (1984: 9) has argued, by mandating retirement from the active workforce at age 65 in order to receive benefits, it was “an act of age discrimination,” a matter that has been debated since the SSA was enacted and become increasingly heated as life-expectancy has grown longer and people wish to keep working longer. Thus, one of the primary targets of the AARP and affiliated organizations was age discrimination in employment, and their lobbying efforts soon began to bear fruit. By 1961 New York and California had added age discrimination to civil rights legislation prohibiting discriminatory hiring and firing practices with regard to race.8 And in 1964, the U.S. Congress enacted the Older Americans Act (OAA) as part of President Lyndon Johnson’s Great Society program, one stated objective of which was to promote “opportunity for employment with no discriminatory personnel practices because of age.”9 The Age Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA) of 1967 made it illegal for private sector employers (with 25 or more employees) to refuse to hire, or to fire, a worker because of age.10 In 1994, Congress amended the ADEA, extending coverage to all state and local governments (29 U. S. C. §§621 et seq. (1994 ed. and Supp. III), which, as we observed above, the Supreme Court invalidated in Kimel, finding that state agencies need only demonstrate a rational basis for discriminating according to age. Litigation claiming workplace age discrimination has been robust under ADEA; however, providing convincing evidence and demonstrating clear animus is inherently difficult (see e.g., Crawshaw-Lewis 1996). For example, a company might legitimately choose not to promote or refuse to hire an older employee for salary reasons. To the employee, the result is discriminatory and the cost-saving rationale a mere pretext. Under the law it is not, unless there is evidence that the decision was predicated by intentional discrimination. The Supreme Court held salary and discrimination to be analytically distinct in Hazen Paper Co. v. Biggins (507 U.S. 604, 1993), with the result being that executive employment decisions have been easier to defend. The Court also held that decisions based upon stereotyped characterization and expectation that disparage older workers are invalid under ADEA provisions. Again, however, clear evidence that employment decisions hinged upon discriminatory stereotypes is necessary. Age-related comments by a supervisor, referring to an employee as an “old fart,” for example, are not of themselves sufficient to prove age discrimination.11 A second issue targeted by the AARP and other grey lobby organizations is medical care. As people live longer, the likelihood that they will require extended medical care and hospitalization increases substantially. Indeed, the growing ranks of the elderly translates into a considerable increase in the number of potentially infirm citizens with significant medical needs (see e.g., Crimmins and Ingegneri 1993). In addition, the second half of the 20th century witnessed a boom in the nursing home and hospice care industries. As the Supreme Court aptly noted in Murgia, “physical ability generally declines with age” (427 US 307, 315), and in Gregory, “the threat of deterioration at age 70 is ... great” (501 US 452, 473). Congress responded in 1965 with legislation establishing the Medicare (42 U.S.C. 1395 et seq.) and the Medicaid (42 U.S.C. 1396 et seq.) programs as Title XVIII and Title XIX of the Social Security Act.12 The Medicare program (Title XVIII) was established with two parts, each with its own trust fund. One part was the Hospital Insurance (HI) program to cover hospital costs, and the Supplementary Medical Insurance (SMI) program covers expenses not covered by HI. Benefits under each program are extended to all who have participated in the Social Security system. Medicaid (Title XIX) was established as a Federal-State matching entitlement program in response to the widely perceived inadequacy of "welfare medical care" under public assistance. Medicaid was designed to ensure that low income individuals and families would be provided with adequate care, and the program immediately became the largest source of funding for medical and health-related services for the nation’s “have nots,” many of whom are elderly. In 1996, for example, more than 36 million people received Medicaid benefits, at a cost of $160 billion dollars.13 Because each state sets its own standards and contingencies in order to administer the program under broad Federal guidelines, the system has become a complex web of varying eligibility and benefit regulations.14 Needless to say, the legislative extensions to the Social Security Act, intended to address the special health and medical needs that accompany advancing age have made “eldercare” advocacy (both political and legal) a growth industry. Indeed, since 1965, a plethora of new lobbying organizations has become active across the state legislatures to promote expansion of the programs’ coverage. Moreover, the federal and state courts have been kept busy addressing a wide range of issues that have been produced by the programs’ administration. Once the state has decided to institute a policy extending benefits, questions of eligibility quickly become nontrivial, and the state may not arbitrarily reduce or terminate benefits to those receiving them. These have been heavily litigated issues.15 In addition, the government assumes some responsibility for guaranteeing an acceptable quality of medical and health care services and facilities, and each state has implemented an elaborate system of regulations. Finally, criminal law has come into play in response to serious incidents of fraud, false claims, reports and the like. In short, the decision to extend medical benefits to the nation’s elderly through the Medicare and Medicaid programs gave rise to a virtual cottage industry of lawmaking, litigation, and enforcement. LAW AND THE END OF LIFE: DEATH AND DYING Just as the present technological revolution is jumbling our way of thinking about birth and life’s inception, it is confusing our ideas about death. Where, as we suggested above, an average American in 1915 could expect to die at around age 50, he may now expect to live until he is 76.16 These impressive gains in life expectancy result from a number of factors including better and more plentiful foodstuffs,17 increased knowledge in the areas of nutrition,18 health,19 and exercise,20 and much less dangerous living21 and working22 conditions than our forebear faced -- all the result of law. They also result, of course, from stunning advances in medical technologies – technologies that can truly be double-edged swords. For while many are kept alive longer, many of those are not necessarily kept alive better. And just as the law is struggling to catch up with technologies that are redefining the beginning of life, it is scrambling to keep pace with technologies that are redefining the end of life. This section explores law’s attempt to stake out territory in the “brave new world” of death. Here, we see very clearly, as much, if not more than in any area we have investigated, the difficult role of law in maintaining the delicate balance between individual liberty and social order. For here, the question becomes do I or does society define the end of my life? What Is Death? As the law records your birth, so does it define your death -- and has, for a long time. For over 200 years, the common law definition of death was the “cessation of life, [the] permanent [irreversible] cessation of all vital signs.”23 Generally referred to as the cardiopulminary definition of death, one’s demise was legalized upon “the absence of pulse, heartbeat, and breathing” (Kibble-Smith 1985). By the 1980s, medical developments had raced ahead of law sufficiently to make the mere lack of breath, pulse, and beating heart inadequate as a legal definition and prompting widespread adoption of a “whole brain death” delineation. Today, every state but New Jersey and New York employs some variation on the so-called “whole brain death” standard. Thus, for example, in addition to the “cessation of circulatory and respiratory functions,” Maryland law adds the “[i]rreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem” (Md. Health-General Code Ann. § 5-202 (1999)). But, who makes the “cessation” call? And under what circumstances is it made? Clearly, medical technology can keep the heart beating, the lungs respirating, the body feeding long after the person has ceased being able to do so on her own. Moreover, and notwithstanding the natural termination of life-sustaining functions, is life lived in excruciating pain or progressive loss of control life worth living? To whom does this decision fall? Over the past several decades, judges have often had to make these difficult calls. Law & the Individual’s Decision to Die In many ways, law’s modern brush with such quality of death issues began “[o]n the night of April 15, 1975, [when,] for reasons still unclear, Karen Quinlan ceased breathing for at least two 15 minute periods” (In the Matter of Karen Quinlan, 70 N.J. 10, 23 (Supreme Court of New Jersey, 1976). The lapses were critical and tragic, leaving Karen comatose and “in a chronic and persistent ‘vegetative’ state, having no awareness of anything or anyone around her and existing at a primitive reflex level” (Id.). According to expert medical witnesses, she had lost the “more highly developed [part of the] brain which is uniquely human which controls our relation to the outside world, our capacity to talk, to see, to feel, to sing, to think” (Id., 24). Moreover, throughout a long hospital stay in intensive care, Karen was fed by way of a nasal- gastro tube and her breathing was assisted by way of a respirator, without which experts agreed she probably would not live long. Despite her condition and despite the fact that no form of treatment could cure or even improve her status, Karen’s physicians and numerous medical experts contended that “removal from the respirator would not conform to medical practices, standards and traditions” (Id., 25). In purely biological terms, Karen was not “brain dead.” What experts, whether legal or medical, divine based on complex statutory criteria or scientific standards, may be quite different from the layperson’s simple emotional or sensory reaction. And, to Joseph Quinlan the perpetually vegetative being whose life hung on the function of a respirator was no longer the daughter he had loved so much. His daughter was dead, and he wanted the wasted the body that once housed her spirit and higher brain dead, too. Thus, Mr. Quinlan asked to be appointed his daughter’s guardian. In addition, he requested that the grant of guardianship give him an express power to authorize the discontinuance of all extraordinary medical procedures that sustained Karen's vital processes. Mr. Quinlan argued that his daughter had a right, grounded in privacy interests, to refuse bodily intrusions such as the supposedly life-sustaining respirator. Further, he contended, that in the absence of her own competency, her guardian, carrying out her pre-coma wishes, should be able to assert the right on her behalf. A unanimous New Jersey Supreme Court agreed with Karen’s father. “We have no hesitancy,” the Court asserted, “in deciding . . . that no external compelling interest of the State could compel Karen to endure the unendurable, only to vegetate a few measurable months with no realistic possibility of returning to any semblance of cognitive or sapient life” (Quinlan, 39). Relying particularly on Griswold v. Connecticut24 and Roe v. Wade,25 the New Jersey Court asserted an “unwritten constitutional right of privacy” in the U.S. Constitution, “[p]resumably . . . broad enough to encompass a patient's decision to decline medical treatment under certain circumstances, in much the same way as it is broad enough to encompass a woman's decision to terminate pregnancy under certain conditions” (Quinlan, 40). The state’s interest in “the preservation and sanctity of human life,” according to the Court, “weakens and the individual's right to privacy grows as the degree of bodily invasion increases and the prognosis dims. Ultimately there comes a point at which the individual's rights overcome the State interest” (Quinlan, 40-41). Karen’s case, in the opinion of the Court, had clearly passed that point. Indeed, so clearly had it passed the point that Karen herself could no longer assert her interests. Thus, If a putative decision by Karen to permit this non-cognitive, vegetative existence to terminate by natural forces is regarded as a valuable incident of her right of privacy, as we believe it to be, then it should not be discarded solely on the basis that her condition prevents her conscious exercise of the choice. The only practical way to prevent destruction of the right is to permit the guardian and family of Karen to render their best judgment, subject to the qualifications hereinafter stated, as to whether she would exercise it in these circumstances. If their conclusion is in the affirmative this decision should be accepted by a society the overwhelming majority of whose members would, we think, in similar circumstances, exercise such a choice in the same way for themselves or for those closest to them. It is for this reason that we determine that Karen's right of privacy may be asserted in her behalf, in this respect, by her guardian and family under the particular circumstances presented by this record (at 40-41).26 In spite of an increasing number of so-called “right to die” cases arising in the years following the Quinlan decision,27 the U.S. Supreme Court avoided the issue for more than a decade until confronted in its 1989-90 Term with the case of a young Missouri woman, Nancy Cruzan. Though the circumstances of her incompetency were less mysterious than those of Karen Quinlan’s, Nancy Cruzan faced a very similar situation. In 1983, Cruzan lost control of her car, the ultimate result being a “persistent vegetative state” of life (Cruzan v. Missouri Department of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 266 (1989)). Thereafter, Cruzan was kept alive by means of artificial nutrition and hydration. After concluding that their daughter would never regain her mental faculties, Nancy’s parents sought court authorization for termination of the artificial procedures. Their request was granted by a Missouri State trial court which found that Nancy “had a fundamental right under the State and Federal Constitutions to refuse or direct the withdrawal of ‘death prolonging procedures.’”28 Moreover, the trial court concluded that Nancy’s conversations with a housemate some years earlier, established her wish to terminate the procedures. The Missouri Supreme Court, however, disagreed, refusing to read a substantial right to privacy into either the federal or Missouri Constitutions, finding a strong state policy in favor of preservation of life embodied in the Missouri Living Will statute, and dismissing as “unreliable” Nancy’s wishes as expressed to her former roommate (Cruzan, 268). The U.S. Supreme Court granted cert to consider the question whether an individual, suffering circumstances such as those of Cruzan, has a right under the United States Constitution which would require hospitals to withdraw life-sustaining treatment. Writing for a bare majority,29 Chief Justice Rehnquist upheld the Missouri Supreme Court decision, reasoning that the state has a general interest in “the protection and preservation of human life,” as well as more particular interests in safeguarding incompetents from potential abuses by surrogates. The “United States Constitution [does not] forbid . . . the establishment of [such] procedural requirement[s] by . . . State[s]”(Cruzan, 280). In short, the Court deferred to states’ determinations about the appropriateness of terminating treatment for incompetent patients. Moreover, it indirectly encouraged the use of “living will” documents as more determinative of patients’ ultimate wishes than the sort of thoughtless conversations Ms. Cruzan had had with her housemate before the accident. Nevertheless, the Court did recognize a longstanding common law right to refuse medical treatment (Cruzan, 270). The Court, in addition, explicitly recognized a constitutionally protected “liberty interest” to refuse life saving procedures. Indeed, according to the Chief Justice, had the case involved a competent individual, “we assume that the United States Constitution would grant [her] a constitutionally protected right to refuse lifesaving hydration and nutrition” (Cruzan, 229). The question remained, however, does the right to refuse infer a right to die? Just twenty-one days before the Supreme Court issued its Cruzan decision, in Michigan, 54-year old Janet Adkins “died of an injection of potassium chloride in the back of a 1968 Volkswagen camper van.”30 Ms. Adkins had been diagnosed with Alzheimer's disease and, according to her husband, wanted to die. She was assisted in her efforts by then little known medical pathologist, Dr. Jack Kevorkian. Of course, Dr. Kevorkian would become very well-known – indeed, a full-blown national celebrity – during the 1990s, as the country’s foremost crusader and activist for legalizing assisted suicide. Through public appearances, writings (see esp. Kevorkian 1991), and, most especially, through often openly assisting in or presiding at more than 100 deaths,31 Kevorkian, to a large degree, single-handedly framed the “right-to-die” debate during the last decade of the twentieth century. Despite his crucial public role, however, Kevorkian’s actual legal influence was locally limited to Michigan, where he kept state prosecutors, judges, juries, and legislators extremely busy throughout decade arresting, trying, and aiming legislation at him until finally managing to convict him of second-degree murder in 1999.32 While Kevorkian’s exploits grabbed the public limelight, the campaign for a legal “right to die” proceeded on several fronts, leading, in 1997, to the U.S. Supreme Court. Two fact scenarios, two separate constitutional claims, and two Circuit Court opinions a continent apart led to the Court’s first – and to date, only set of rulings on physician-assisted suicide. In Washington, four doctors and their gravely ill patients filed suit against the State, claiming that its ban on assisted suicide violated the Due Process Clause by inhibiting the personal choices of mentally competent, terminally ill adults to commit physician-assisted suicide. The Washington plaintiffs won favorable rulings from a U.S. District Court (Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 850 F. Supp. 1454 (WD Wash. 1994)) and the Ninth Circuit (Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 79 F.3d 790, 798 (1996), en banc). Meanwhile, in New York, a group of physicians and their patients challenged that state’s ban on Equal Protection grounds, claiming that New York’s practice allowing one class of patients to hasten their deaths by directing the removal of life-support systems, while disallowing others wishing to hasten their deaths by self-administering prescribed drugs accorded different treatment not rationally related to any legitimate state interests. There, a trial court ruled against the plaintiffs (Quill v. Koppell, 870 F. Supp. 78 (SDNY 1994)), but the Second U.S. Circuit agreed with their claim (Quill v. Koppell, 80 F.3d 716 (1996)). The Supreme Court reversed both Circuits. Thus, in the Washington case – arguably, the more important of the two – Chief Justice Rehnquist, writing for the Court, emphatically asserted that [t]he history of the law's treatment of assisted suicide in this country has been and continues to be one of the rejection of nearly all efforts to permit it. That being the case, our decisions lead us to conclude that the asserted “right” to assistance in committing suicide is not a fundamental liberty interest protected by the Due Process Clause. (Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 728 (1997)). The High Court having found no fundamental liberty interest, the state needed to demonstrate only that its ban was rationally related to legitimate government interests. According to the Chief Justice, the state had numerous such stakes, including: an “unqualified interest in the preservation of human life.”. . . [A]n interest in preventing suicide, and in studying, identifying, and treating its causes. . . .[A]n interest in protecting the integrity and ethics of the medical profession. . . . [A]n interest in protecting vulnerable groups--including the poor, the elderly, and disabled persons--from abuse, neglect, and mistakes. . . . [And, an interest in avoiding] the path to voluntary and perhaps even involuntary euthanasia. (Glucksberg, at 728-31). In the New York case, too, the Court upheld the state bar on physician-assisted suicide, easily dismissing the Equal Protection claim. Again, the Chief Justice: On their faces, neither New York's ban on assisting suicide nor its statutes permitting patients to refuse medical treatment treat anyone differently than anyone else or draw any distinctions between persons. Everyone, regardless of physical condition, is entitled, if competent, to refuse unwanted lifesaving medical treatment; no one is permitted to assist a suicide. . . . [W]e think the distinction between assisting suicide and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment, a distinction widely recognized and endorsed in the medical profession and in our legal traditions, is both important and logical; it is certainly rational (Vacco v. Quill, 521 U.S.793, 800 (1997)). The effect of the Court’s 1997 rulings was to leave in the hands of the individual states the decision to allow or ban assisted suicide. To date, states overwhelmingly have chosen to err on the conservative side of banning the practice. Hence, 38 states explicitly criminalize assisted suicide by means of statute. Six other states and the District Columbia may prosecute assisted suicides as common law crimes. In five states the law is unclear (Pratt 1999). Only in Oregon is physician-assisted suicide a clearly legal option. The Oregon Death with Dignity Act33 began in 1994 as a citizen initiative, passed by voters on a slim 51% majority. Implementation was delayed by court injunction until 1997 when a legislative referendum asking voters to repeal the Act was rejected by Oregonians. The Act allows terminally ill Oregon residents to use prescriptions obtained from their physicians for self-administered, lethal medications. Ending one's life in accordance with the law does not constitute illegal suicide. While legalizing physician assistance, the Act specifically prohibits euthanasia, where a physician or other person directly administers a medication to end another's life.34 In the first full year of its operation, 23 people received legal prescriptions for lethal medications, of which 15 died after taking their lethal medications, six died from their underlying illness, and two remained alive.35 In reaction specifically to the Oregon legislation, in 1999, the U.S. House of Representatives passed The Pain Relief Promotion Act of 1999(H. R. 2260, 106th Cong., 1st sess.). The bill, on which the Senate had not acted as of January 2000, would effectively overturn the Oregon Death with Dignity law by barring “doctors from using federally controlled drugs such as morphine to cause death” (Koch 1999). Law & the State’s Decision to End Life Overwhelmingly, then, governments in the United States have constructed high legal barriers to willful death. At the same time, however, governments across the country have not been adverse to imposing death on the unwilling through capital punishment. Indeed, the vast majority of jurisdictions --38 states and the federal government – currently authorize the death penalty as punishment for certain crimes. (See Tables 1 and 2) TABLE 1 CAPITAL OFFENSES, BY STATE Alabama. Capital murder with a finding of at least 1 of 9 aggravating circumstances (Ala. Code §13A-5-40 and §13A-5-49). Arizona. First-degree murder accompanied by at least 1 of 10 aggravating factors. Arkansas. Capital murder (Ark. Code Ann. 5-10-101) with a finding of at least 1 of 10 aggravating circumstances; treason. California. Firstdegree murder with special circumstances; train wrecking; treason; perjury causing execution. Colorado. Firstdegree murder with at least 1 of 13 aggravating factors; treason. Capital sentencing excludes persons determined to be mentally retarded. Connecticut. Capital felony with 9 categories of aggravated homicide (C.G.S. 53a-54b). Delaware. Firstdegree murder with aggravating Kansas. Capital murder with 7 aggravating circumstances (KSA 21-3439). Capital sentencing excludes persons determined to be mentally retarded. New York. Firstdegree murder with 1 of 12 aggravating factors. Capital sentencing excludes persons determined to be mentally retarded. Kentucky. Murder with aggravating factors; kidnaping with aggravating factors. North Carolina. First-degree murder (N.C.G.S. 14-17). Louisiana. Firstdegree murder; aggravated rape of victim under age 12; treason (La. R.S. 14:30, 14:42, and 14:113). Maryland. Firstdegree murder, either premeditated or during the commission of a felony, provided that certain death eligibility requirements are satisfied. Ohio. Aggravated murder with at least 1 of 8 aggravating circumstances. (O.R.C. secs. 2903.01, 2929.01, and 2929.04). Oklahoma. Firstdegree murder in conjunction with a finding of at least 1 of 8 statutorily defined aggravating circumstances. Oregon. Aggravated murder (ORS 163.095). Mississippi. Capital murder (97-3-19(2) MCA); aircraft piracy (97-25-55(1) MCA). Pennsylvania. Firstdegree murder with 18 aggravating circumstances. Missouri. First-degree murder (565.020 RSMO). South Carolina. Murder with 1 of 10 aggravating circumstances (§ 163-20(C)(a)). Mental retardation is a mitigating factor. Montana. Capital murder with 1 of 9 aggravating circumstances (46-18- circumstances. Florida. First-degree murder; felony murder; capital drug trafficking. Georgia. Murder; kidnaping with bodily injury or ransom where the victim dies; aircraft hijacking; treason. Idaho. First-degree murder; aggravated kidnaping. Illinois. First-degree murder with 1 of 15 aggravating circumstances. Indiana. Murder with 16 aggravating circumstances (IC 3550-2-9). Capital sentencing excludes persons determined to be mentally retarded. 303 MCA); capital sexual assault (45-5503 MCA). Nebraska. Firstdegree murder with a finding of at least 1 statutorily-defined aggravating circumstance. Nevada. First-degree murder with 13 aggravating circumstances. New Hampshire. Six categories of capital murder (RSA 630:1 and RSA 630:5). New Jersey. Purposeful or knowing murder by one's own conduct; contract murder; solicitation by command or threat in further-ance of a narcotics conspiracy (NJSA 2C:11-3C). New Mexico. Firstdegree murder in conjunction with a finding of at least 1 of 7 aggravating circumstances (Section 30-2-1A, NMSA). South Dakota. Firstdegree murder with 1 of 10 aggravating circumstances; aggravated kidnaping. Tennessee. Firstdegree murder. Texas. Criminal homicide with 1 of 8 aggravating circumstances (TX Penal Code 19.03). Utah. Aggravated murder (76-5-202, Utah Code annotated). Virginia. First-degree murder with 1 of 12 aggravating circumstances (VA Code § 18.2-31). Washington. Aggravated firstdegree murder. Wyoming. Firstdegree murder. Table 2 FEDERAL LAWS PROVIDING FOR THE DEATH PENALTY 8 U.S.C. 1342 — Murder related to the smuggling of aliens. 18 U.S.C. 32-34 — Destruction of aircraft, motor vehicles, or related facilities resulting in death. 18 U.S.C. 36 — Murder committed during a drug-related drive-by shooting. 18 U.S.C. 37 — Murder committed at an airport serving international civil aviation. 18 U.S.C. 115(b)(3) [by cross-reference to 18 U.S.C. 1111] — Retaliatory murder of a member of the immediate family of law enforcement officials. 18 U.S.C. 241, 242, 245, 247 — Civil rights offenses resulting in death. 18 U.S.C. 351 [by cross-reference to 18 U.S.C. 1111] — Murder of a member of Congress, an 18 U.S.C. 1114 — Murder of a Federal judge or law enforcement official. 18 U.S.C. 1958 — Murder for hire. 18 U.S.C. 1116 — Murder of a foreign official. 18 U.S.C. 1992 — Willful wrecking of a train resulting in death. 18 U.S.C. 1118 — Murder by a Federal prisoner. 18 U.S.C. 1119 — Murder of a U.S. national in a foreign country. 18 U.S.C. 1120 — Murder by an escaped Federal prisoner already sentenced to life imprisonment. 18 U.S.C. 1121 — Murder of a State or local law enforcement official or other person aiding in a Federal investigation; murder of a State correctional officer. 18 U.S.C. 1201 — Murder during a kidnaping. 18 U.S.C. 1203 — Murder during a 18 U.S.C. 1959 — Murder involved in a racketeering offense. 18 U.S.C. 2113 — Bank-robbery-related murder or kidnaping. 18 U.S.C. 2119 — Murder related to a carjacking. 18 U.S.C. 2245 — Murder related to rape or child molestation. 18 U.S.C. 2251 — Murder related to sexual exploitation of children. 18 U.S.C. 2280 — Murder committed during an offense against maritime navigation. 18 U.S.C. 2281 — Murder committed during an offense against a maritime fixed platform. important executive official, or a Supreme Court Justice. 18 U.S.C. 794 — Espionage. 18 U.S.C. 844(d), (f), (i) — Death resulting from offenses involving transportation of explosives, destruction of government property, or destruction of property related to foreign or interstate commerce. 18 U.S.C. 924(i) — Murder committed by the use of a firearm during a crime of violence or a drugtrafficking crime. 18 U.S.C. 930 — Murder committed in a Federal Government facility. hostage taking. 18 U.S.C. 1503 — Murder of a court officer or juror. 18 U.S.C. 1512 — Murder with the intent of preventing testimony by a witness, victim, or informant. 18 U.S.C. 2332 — Terrorist murder of a U.S. national in another country. 18 U.S.C. 2332a — Murder by the use of a weapon of mass destruction. 18 U.S.C. 2340 — Murder involving torture. 18 U.S.C. 1513 — Retaliatory murder of a witness, victim, or informant. 18 U.S.C. 2381 — Treason. 18 U.S.C. 1716 — Mailing of injurious articles with intent to kill or resulting in death. 21 U.S.C. 848(e) — Murder related to a continuing criminal enterprise or related murder of a Federal, State, or local law enforcement officer. 18 U.S.C. 1751 [by cross-reference to 18 U.S.C. 1111] — Assassination or kidnaping resulting in the death of the President or Vice President. 49 U.S.C. 1472-1473 — Death resulting from aircraft hijacking. 18 U.S.C. 1091 — Genocide. 18 U.S.C. 1111 — First-degree murder. _________________________________________________________________ Though a widespread statutory option throughout the nation, actual imposition of the death penalty is highly concentrated in five, primarily southern, states. Thus, throughout the 21year period from January 1, 1977--the year following the Supreme Court’s reimposition of the death penalty (Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976))36 after a four year hiatus (Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972))37-- to December 31, 1998, 500 convicts in 18 states were put to death. However, nearly two-thirds of those executions occurred in Texas, Virginia, Florida, Missouri, and Louisiana (Snell 1999). American laws’ contemporary entanglement with state-sponsored death began in 1972 when the Supreme Court considered the cases of three indigent African-American convicts sentenced to death in the states of Georgia and Texas. (Furman) Two of the men had been convicted of rape; one was a murderer. At issue before the Court was whether the imposition and execution of the death penalty constituted “cruel and unusual punishment” within the meaning of the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments. In a decision featuring five concurrences and four dissents, the Court judged that in these cases it did, effectively vacating death sentences nationwide. Although Justices Brennan and Marshall argued that capital punishment was per se unconstitutional, the prevailing view – that of Justices Douglas, White, and Stewart – hinged on the basically standardless manner in which the penalty was imposed. According to Justice Stewart: These death sentences are cruel and unusual in the same way that being struck by lightning is cruel and unusual. For, of all the people convicted of rapes and murders in 1967 and 1968, many just as reprehensible as these, the petitioners are among a capriciously selected random handful upon whom the sentence of death has in fact been imposed. My concurring Brothers have demonstrated that, if any basis can be discerned for the selection of these few to be sentenced to die, it is the constitutionally impermissible basis of race. But racial discrimination has not been proved, and I put it to one side. I simply conclude that the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments cannot tolerate the infliction of a sentence of death under legal systems that permit this unique penalty to be so wantonly and so freakishly imposed. (Stewart, J., concurring, at (Citations omitted)). Over the course of the next several years, the death penalty came to a halt in the United States, as individual jurisdictions attempted to fashion legislation that would meet constitutional muster. Then, in 1976, five cases, consolidated for review, and covering death penalty statutes in Georgia, Florida, Texas, Louisiana, and North Carolina, were presented to the Court. At issue in the primary case, Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976). was the imposition of the death penalty for murder resulting from an armed robbery. The penalty, sentenced to Troy Gregg, was applied following a set of procedures mandated by the Georgia legislature following Furman. And, the question before the Court was whether the imposition of the sentence of death for the crime of murder under the revised laws of the five states violated the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments. The Court ruled that in the cases of Georgia, Florida, and Texas it did not, thus effectively reinstituting capital punishment. Again, the Court was divided both on reasoning and on judgment. However, Justices Stewart, Powell, and Stevens, announcing the judgment of the Court upholding the law in three states, concluded that “[t]he punishment of death for the crime of murder does not, under all circumstances, violate the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments”(Gregg). According to Justice Stewart, the judiciary has a limited role to play in criminal sentencing: [I]n assessing a punishment selected by a democratically elected legislature against the constitutional measure, we presume its validity. We may not require the legislature to select the least severe penalty possible so long as the penalty selected is not cruelly inhumane or disproportionate to the crime involved. And a heavy burden rests on those who would attack the judgment of the representatives of the people.(Gregg, at 175)38 Since Gregg, the Supreme Court’s death penalty docket has largely sought to clarify procedural bounds to capital punishment.39 Thus, the Court has held that the imposition of the death penalty for rape alone is “grossly disproportionate” and thus unconstitutional (Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. 584 (1977)). In addition, the Court has ruled that the death penalty is age-limited, setting a threshold of 18 years on executions (Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551 (2005). And, it has held that executing the mentally retarded is unconstitutional (Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002)). In favor of capital defendants, the Court has ruled that sentencing juries must be informed of mitigating circumstances (Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.S. 586 (1978)). But, to the presumed detriment of those facing the death penalty, it has upheld the use of “victim impact statements” at the sentencing phase of trial (Payne v. Tennessee, 501 U.S. 808 (1991)). The Poverty Connection. Among death penalty controversies, the most troublesome are those revolving around the disproportionate application of the sanction to certain groups – notably, the poor and minorities. According to the American Civil Liberties Union, “[n]inety percent of criminal defendants in this country who are charged with a capital crime are indigent when arrested, and virtually all are penniless by the time their case reaches the appeals stage. In California, the state with the largest death row population, less than 2 percent were represented at trial by retained counsel.”42 For the vast majority of poor capital defendants the problem, more often than not, is one of counsel. Though guaranteed legal representation through the first appeal,43 by most assessments, indigent capital defendants tend to receive “grossly unqualified” assistance (Coyle, Lavelle, and Strasser1990).44 Stephen Bright, Director of the Southern Center for Human Rights, provides the following tragic example: After years in which she and her children were physically abused by her adulterous husband, a woman in Talladega County, Alabama, arranged to have him killed. Tragically, murders of abusive spouses are not rare in our violent society, but seldom are they punished by the death penalty. Yet this woman was sentenced to death. Why? It may have been in part because one of her court-appointed lawyers was so drunk that the trial had to be delayed for a day after he was held in contempt and sent to jail. The next morning, he and his client were both produced from jail, the trial resumed, and the death penalty was imposed a few days later. It may also have been in part because this lawyer failed to find hospital records documenting injuries received by the woman and her daughter, which would have corroborated their testimony about abuse. And it may also have been because her lawyers did not bring their expert witness on domestic abuse to see the defendant until 8 p.m. on the night before he testified at trial (Bright 1994: 1835-1836).45 In fact, the majority of high-rate death penalty states do not have public defender systems, relying instead on court-appointed lawyers, underpaid and with no particular experience in the very special realm of capital punishment. According the American Bar Association: Jurisdictions that employ the death penalty have proven unwilling to establish the kind of legal services system that is necessary to ensure that defendants charged with capital offenses receive the defense they require. Many death penalty states have no working public defender programs, relying instead upon scattershot methods for selecting and supporting defense counsel in capital cases. For example, some states simply assign lawyers at random from a general list - a scheme destined to identify attorneys who lack the necessary qualifications and, worse still, regard their assignments as a burden. Other jurisdictions employ "contract" systems, which typically channel indigent defense business to attorneys who offer the lowest bids. Other states use public defender schemes that appear on the surface to be more promising, but prove in practice to be just as ineffective. (ABA 1998: 224) Nor, is the problem limited to the states. Even lawyers appointed in the federal system receive inadequate compensation to ensure competent defense. Indeed, no less than the Chief Justice has noted the problem, requesting additional monies from Congress and asserting that “[a]dequate pay for appointed counsel is important to ensure that a defendant's constitutional right to counsel is fulfilled.”46 The Race Connection. In addition to the poverty problem, race persists as a disturbing and complicating element in capital punishment. Of the 3,404 prisoners under sentence of death nationwide at the end of 1998, 43% were black, a figure hugely disproportionate to the percentage of African-Americans in the total population (Snell 1998). Indeed, according to one observer, “[r]ace is more likely to affect death sentencing than smoking affects the likelihood of dying from heart disease. [Yet, t]he latter evidence has produced enormous changes in law and societal practice, while racism in the death penalty has been largely ignored” (Dieter 1998). The problem, of course, is nothing new – nor, is its recognition. Atticus Finch, the lawyer-hero of Harper Lee’s 1960 novel, To Kill A Mockingbird, clearly recognized it in his defense of Tom Robinson, accused, in a capital case, of raping a white girl (Lee 1960). Before that, in 1940, the great novelist Richard Wright provided the tragic portrait of Bigger Thomas, sentenced to death for the accidental killing of a white woman, while his intentional murder of a black woman went largely ignored (Wright 1947/1993). In real life, the so-called “Scottsboro Boys,” seven black youth, were convicted in Alabama in 1931 for the crime of sexually assaulting two white girls. The jury had, within its discretion, the authority to sentence the young men to as few as 10 years imprisonment; it chose, instead, the death penalty (Powell v. Alabama, 287 U.S. 45 (1932)). Few doubted that the key element in the jury’s decision was the race of the defendants and victims. As Justice Marshall pointed out in his 1972 Furman concurrence: [A] look at the bare statistics regarding executions is enough to betray much of the discrimination. A total of 3,859 persons [were executed between 1930 and 1972]. . . . Of the executions, 3,334 were for murder; 1,664 of the executed murderers were white and 1,630 were Negro; 455 persons, including 48 whites and 405 Negroes, were executed for rape. It is immediately apparent that Negroes were executed far more often than whites in proportion to their percentage of the population. Furman v. Georgia, at 364 (Marshall, J., concurring) (Citations omitted). In recent years, the statistical analyses have become far more sophisticated and, to many, far more convincing. At the same time, the problem has remained peculiarly intractable. Take, for example, the case of Warren McCleskey. In 1978, McCleskey a black Georgian, was convicted of killing a white police officer during the course of a robbery, and he was sentenced to death. As part of his habeas petition, McCleskey claimed that the Georgia capital sentencing process was administered in a racially discriminatory manner. His case, which reached the Supreme Court in 1987 (McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279 (1987)), centered around the “Baldus Study,” a statistical examination of the death sentence in Georgia which demonstrated a disparity in the imposition of capital punishment based on the race of the murder victim and, to a lesser extent, the race of the defendant, with black defendants who killed white victims having the greatest likelihood of receiving death.47 The study, McCleskey claimed, established that application of the death penalty was irrational, arbitrary, capricious, and, thus, unconstitutional, violating the Eighth Amendment and both the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth. In a 5-4 decision rendered by Justice Powell, the High Court rejected his claim on all counts.48 Beginning with McCleskey’s Equal Protection argument, Powell maintained that in order to prevail, the defendant “must prove that the decisionmakers in his case acted with discriminatory purpose” (McCleskey, at 292) (emphasis added). This, he had not done, relying instead on the generalized findings of the “Baldus Study.” Although the Court has accepted statistical patterns as proof of discrimination in other Equal Protection cases, the nature of the capital sentencing decision, and the relationship of the statistics to that decision, are fundamentally different from the corresponding elements in the venire-selection or Title VII [of the Civil Rights Act] cases. Most importantly, each particular decision to impose the death penalty is made by a petit jury selected from a properly constituted venire. Each jury is unique in its composition, and the Constitution requires that its decision rest on consideration of innumerable factors that vary according to the characteristics of the individual defendant and the facts of the particular capital offense. (McCleskey, at 295) In short, for purposes of applying statistical findings to Equal Protection analyses, the criminal justice system in general and the death penalty in particular are unique: McCleskey's statistical proffer must be viewed in the context of his challenge. [He] challenges decisions at the heart of the State's criminal justice system. “One of society's most basic tasks is that of protecting the lives of its citizens and one of the most basic ways in which it achieves the task is through criminal laws against murder.” Implementation of these laws necessarily requires discretionary judgments. Because discretion is essential to the criminal justice process, we would demand exceptionally clear proof before we would infer that the discretion has been abused. (McCleskey, at 297) (citations omitted) Nor was the Court sympathetic to McCleskey’s Eighth Amendment-Due Process claim. There is, asserted Powell, “a constitutionally permissible range of discretion in imposing the death penalty” – a range met by the State of Georgia and within which McCleskey’s sentence was not disproportionate to his crime by any traditional indicia (McCleskey, at 305-306). Writing in dissent, Justice Brennan admitted that under his view “the death penalty is in all circumstances cruel and unusual punishment forbidden by the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments” (McCleskey, at 320, Brennan, J., dissenting).49 Nevertheless, he took particular umbrage at the circumstances surrounding McCleskey’s sentence: At some point in this case, Warren McCleskey doubtless asked his lawyer whether a jury was likely to sentence him to die. A candid reply to this question would have been disturbing. First, counsel would have to tell McCleskey that few of the details of the crime or of McCleskey's past criminal conduct were more important than the fact that his victim was white. Furthermore, counsel would feel bound to tell McCleskey that defendants charged with killing white victims in Georgia are 4.3 times as likely to be sentenced to death as defendants charged with killing blacks. In addition, frankness would compel the disclosure that it was more likely than not that the race of McCleskey's victim would determine whether he received a death sentence: 6 of every 11 defendants convicted of killing a white person would not have received the death penalty if their victims had been black, while, among defendants with aggravating and mitigating factors comparable to McCleskey's, 20 of every 34 would not have been sentenced to die if their victims had been black. Finally, the assessment would not be complete without the information that cases involving black defendants and white victims are more likely to result in a death sentence than cases featuring any other racial combination of defendant and victim. The story could be told in a variety of ways, but McCleskey could not fail to grasp its essential narrative line: there was a significant chance that race would play a prominent role in determining if he lived or died. (McCleskey, at 321) (citations omitted) Since McCleskey, statistics continue to demonstrate race disparity in capital sentencing. For example, the most recent “Baldus Study,” an examination of the death penalty in Philadelphia, found continuing patterns of “arbitrariness and discrimination in the administration of the death penalty . . . [and] not [merely] confined to southern jurisdictions” (Baldus, et al 1998: 1738). At the same time, since the retirements of Justices Brennan, Marshall, and Blackmun, there is no longer a single Justice on the Supreme Court who is fundamentally opposed to the principle or current application of the death penalty; while among core death penalty decision makers – district attorneys in capital punishment states – almost 98% are white (Pokorak 1998). And What of Innocence? Finally, regardless of race or economic status, with the growing sophistication of DNA analysis, there has been an increasing trend – one which should give pause to even the most die-hard advocates of the death penalty – toward the exoneration of death row inmates. According to the Death Penalty Information Center, “since 1973, over 80 people have been released from death row with evidence of their innocence” (Dieter 1997). Indeed, in Illinois, the problem has become so acute – since the death penalty was reinstated there “23 years ago, 13 death row inmates have been cleared of murder charges, compared to 12 who have been put to death” (Claiborne 2000: 4) – that Governor George Ryan (R) has imposed a moratorium on executions, pending an extensive study of a system deemed “‘fraught with errors’ and ‘broken’.”50 Throughout most of the nation, however, the increasing possibility of criminal exoneration is being met with stiff resistance toward the goal of ever-quicker executions, as states shorten and streamline death appeals and as Congress limits the scope of habeas,51 all sanctioned by the Supreme Court.52 The End In the end (literally), no matter which way we go, something must be done with our remains. Here too, there is the law. In many ways, the modern legal brush with the post-mortem began in the late-1800s when artisans and entrepreneurs specializing in death – undertakers, embalmers, and funeral directors – sought increased status and economic fortune via the state’s imprimatur, professional licensing (Friedman 1973: 398-399). At the time, [t]hey had many rivals. Doctors embalmed the dead. Clergymen controlled funerals. Many undertakers were part-time funeral directors, who sold coffins and caskets as the mainstay of their business. In the late 1800s, Hudson Samson, president of the Funeral Directors National Association of the United States, prepared a model legislative act for licensing embalmers. At the same time, Samson tried to uplift the artifacts of professional funerals. (In 1889, he designed a “special eight poster, oval-decked funeral car”; in 1989, a magnificent wooden drape hearse.) It was all part of one general movement, to give tone and economic strength to the occupation, in short, to “professionalize” these doctors of the dead. Samson wanted a law to regulate “the care and burial of the dead the same as there is for the practice of medicine.” In 1894, Virginia passed the first licensing law. . . . Thereafter, only registered embalmers could practice the “science of embalming.” By 1900, some twenty-four states had passed similar legislation. (Friedman 1973: 398) Today, the provision of funeral services is governed largely by a tangled web of religious ritual, individual state law, and some federal consumer protection law. At the state level, the disposal of our “remains” is regulated in part by insurance law (overseeing the honest disbursement of death benefits), by transportation law (licensing hearses), and by a variety of zoning laws and cemetery oversight rules (regulating burial sites). The heart of most state funeral law, however, remains in occupational licensing oversight. Maryland law is instructive. Thus, in Maryland, a State Board of Morticians, appointed by the Governor with the advice and consent of the Senate, sets standards and oversees the licensing, advertising, and inspection of morticians, mortician apprentices, funeral directors, and funeral homes.53 Although funeral regulation is traditionally a function of state law, a substantial proportion of the funeral industry traverses the route of interstate commerce and thus implicates federal law as well. Of particular importance here is regulation and consumer protection undertaken by the Federal Trade Commission (FTC).54 Hence, the FTC monitors and sanctions unfair or deceptive acts or practices in selling or offering to sell funeral goods or funeral services to the public (16 CFR 453.2). The so-called “Funeral Rule,” administered by the FTC, requires “funeral providers to provide consumers with information regarding funeral products and services and ensures consumers pay for only the products and services they want and need” (FTC 1998). While violators may be subject to litigation, a recently developed “Funeral Rule Offenders Program” -- a venture generated jointly by the FTC and the National Funeral Directors Association (NFDA) – offers funeral homes found to be in violation of the rule an opportunity to make voluntary payments and receive training rather than face possible enforcement action by the FTC and the state Attorneys General (FTC 1998). LAW AND THE AFTER-LIFE: ANCIENT CONCERNS OF SUCCESSION If at the death of a man who holds a lay `fee' of the Crown, a sheriff or royal official produces royal letters patent of summons for a debt due to the Crown, it shall be lawful for them to seize and list movable goods found in the lay `fee' of the dead man to the value of the debt, as assessed by worthy men. Nothing shall be removed until the whole debt is paid, when the residue shall be given over to the executors to carry out the dead man’s will. If no debt is due to the Crown, all the movable goods shall be regarded as the property of the dead man, except the reasonable shares of his wife and children. If a free man dies intestate, his movable goods are to be distributed by his next-of-kin and friends, under the supervision of the Church. The rights of his debtors are to be preserved. - Magna Carta, 121555 As the sections of Magna Carta quoted above suggest, law has long been concerned with the orderly transfer of that which we can’t take with us -- our heirs and, more importantly, our creditors should receive their fair shares of our lives’ work under a watchful legal eye. This section briefly reviews the ancient lineage of law in the transfer of property after death. Although the law has ever been involved in succession, the process of transferring a dead person’s property or rights, its involvement has not always been so legalistic or formal as it is today. According to Adam Hirsch (1996: 1060), [i]n colonial times, settlers were content to give effect to nuncupative (oral) wills or even to depositions by friends or family concerning the decedent's dispositive preferences as expressed to them casually. The court then ordered distribution “according to the minde (sic) of the deceased.” While such informality may have worked in a small-scale agricultural economy, “flexibility and individualized handling of estates,” according to Lawrence Friedman (1973: 219), “was a luxury that a mass society, with mass ownership of wealth, could not afford.” Thus, began the birth of a complex and sometimes daunting system of probate law. Wills, individuals’ declarations of how they want their property distributed after their deaths, are the basic form of succession. In general, wills are characterized by three customary requirements: they must be written, they must be signed, and they must be attested to -- that is, authenticated by witnesses. Of the three, the most formal -- some would say, archaically so -and the most likely to act as an impediment, is the attestation requirement. All states currently dictate that between two and three witnesses formally attest to the validity of a will in front of a third party, often a lawyer, an accountant, or notary public. At common law, the idea was to have several disinterested parties present to guard “the testator [will maker] against various nefarious acts, such as fraud or undue influence”(Mann 1994: 1042). Today, however, as Bruce Mann (1994: 1042) notes, “witnesses tend to be either family members, who are well-placed to commit the acts they are supposed to prevent, or comparative strangers in a lawyer's office or bank who sign when and where they are told and hardly see themselves as the testator's sentinels.” This complex law of succession may sometimes lead to very absurd results. Thus, in all states, if a will is formally typed, failure to abide by proper attestation will most likely invalidate the will in the eyes of the court. At the same time, a number of states do recognize so-called holographic wills, wills that are handwritten and signed with no witnesses. This leads, in many states to a kind of “schizophrenic” outcome in which either a will must be thoroughly formalized by virtue of witnesses and so on, or it must be thoroughly informalized by virtue of a statement wholly in handwriting. A will that is neither formal nor informal, but rather semi-formal--such as an estate plan typed and signed (but not witnessed) on a pre-printed will form--be it even an official statutory will form published with the state's imprimatur--is of no legal effect whatsoever. (Hirsch 1996: 1071) Regardless of the form of will, or, no will at all, when an individual dies, his or her estate is subject to probate. Probate is a court proceeding in which debts are settled, taxes paid, and whatever is left transferred to the deceased’s legal heirs. Like the rules surrounding wills themselves, probate varies according to individual state law. Thus, in some states, if an estate is relatively small and the will uncontested, the probate procedure may be quickly and fairly easily consummated; other states retain more formalized and complicated probate procedures. In general, probate involves four basic steps. First, the court will appoint someone to inventory and distribute the estate. Where the departed has left a valid will (in legal terms, where she has died testate), this person will be the executor named in the will. Where there is no will (where the deceased is intestate), the court itself will name an administrator. The executor or administrator is then responsible for collecting, itemizing and appraising all of the assets that are subject to probate. He or she then must pay outstanding debts and taxes, although most states permit a portion of the estate to be set-aside for survivors, out of the long reach of creditors. And, finally, what is left over is distributed to the estate’s heirs. Where there is no will, state law determines the legal heirs, most commonly, dividing the estate between the surviving spouse and the decedent’s closest blood relatives.56 Although probate is the most common form of succession, it is not the only form. Property that was placed in a living trust57 prior to death or property held in joint tenancy58 may pass to beneficiaries without court supervision. So too, may life insurance and retirement account benefits (Hames and Ekern 1998: 212 ). Of course, as the foregoing suggests, not only are death and taxes inevitable, they are inextricably intertwined. Indeed, “[o]ne of the oldest and most common forms of taxation is the taxation of property held by an individual at the time of his death.”59 Unlike the transfer of property to heirs which is governed by individual state law, the transfer of property to government (in other words, taxes) is a federal concern as well. This was not always the case. Early in American history, death taxes were primarily levied by state governments, with federal death taxes imposed only sporadically in times of war or threatened war. Thus, for example, “[t]he first Federal death tax was imposed from 1797 until 1802 as a stamp tax on inventories of deceased persons, receipts of legacies, shares of personal estate, probates of wills, and letters of administration to pay for the development of strong naval forces felt necessary because of strained trade relations with France” (Joint Committee on Taxation 1998). Thereafter, a sixty year hiatus ensued until a federal inheritance tax was imposed to offset the costs of the Civil War. In 1898, the federal government imposed its first estate tax to finance the SpanishAmerican War. Estate taxes as a permanent feature of the federal revenue system did not take hold until 1916 with the onset of World War I (Joint Committee on Taxation 1998). The current Federal Estate Tax (26 U.S.C. §2001) is a levy on decedents’ property before transfers to debtors or heirs take place. In addition, many states impose such taxes. Although more sophisticated estates may transfer many assets prior to death in the form of gifts, the Federal Gift Tax law (26 U.S.C. §2501) is “generally designed to prevent complete tax avoidance by this route” (26 U.S.C. §2501, LII, “Estate and Gift Tax”). Since 1976, federal estate and gift tax law has been unified, with a single graduated rate schedule applicable to transfers.60 Recently, federal death tax law has come under increasing criticism (e.g., Joint Economic Committee 1998). Numerous bills were introduced during the 106th Congress to reduce or eliminate the Estate Tax,61 though none currently has passed into law. CONCLUSION In this chapter, we explored law’s role at the end of life, from old age to death to burial to succession, the temporal parallel to celestial afterlife. The inevitability of death is well attended by the inevitability of law. In many ways, law’s ordering function is clearest here at the end. We structure law to make our grandparents’, parents’, and our own last years as neat and carefree as possible. We place law in the role of bulwark against the moral chaos we fear would arise should some (maybe many) of us seek to determine our own ends – or those of our loved ones. At the same time, we let law end the lives of those few whom we have determined most hideously breached society’s commandments. And we use law, after all is said and done, to transfer, in an orderly fashion, that which we “can’t take with us.” Yet, as the foregoing suggests, it is not without struggle that we give way at the end to the ordering proclivities of law. From age discrimination litigation to “right to die” claims, to the often long struggles of death row inmates trying to avoid execution, to the ongoing battle aimed at ending inheritance taxes, individuals employ law’s liberty motif to fight its ordering devices. The inherent battle, it seems, is inevitable – right down to the bitter end. . According to the Administration on Aging, Department of Health and Human Services: “The older population-persons 65 years or older-numbered 34.1 million in 1997. They represented 12.7% of the U.S. population, about one in every eight Americans. The number of older Americans increased by 2.8 million or 9.1% since 1990, compared to an increase of 7.0% for the under-65population. . . . Since 1900, the percentage of Americans 65+ has more than tripled (4.1% in 1900 to 12.7% in1997), and the number has increased eleven times (from 3.1 million to 34.1 million). The older population itself is getting older. In 1997 the 65-74 age 1 group (18.5 million) was eight times larger than in 1900, but the 75-84 group (11.7million) was 16 times larger and the 85+ group(3.9 million) was 31 times larger. . . . [T]he older population will burgeon between the years 2010 and2030 when the '"baby boom" generation reaches age 65. By 2030, there will be about 70 million older persons, more than twice their number in 1997. People 65+ are projected to represent 13% of population in the year 2000 but will be 20% by 2030.” “Profile of Older Americans: 1998,” http://www.aoa.dhhs.gov/aoa/stats/profile/#table1 (date visited: October 26, 1999). 2 . The Court had addressed the question of whether age distinctions violate the equal protection requirements of the 14th Amendment on one other occasion, reaching a similar conclusion. Vance v. Bradley, 440 U. S. 93 (1979) (upholding constitutionality of State Department regulation mandating retirement of Foreign Service employees at age 60).. 3 . At issue here was whether Congress, in extending age discrimination protection to state employees, had violated the states’ immunity from prosecution under the 11th Amendment. The 5-4 majority declared that Congress had overstepped its authority and restated its understanding that age is not a suspect classification. . 49 Stats. 623. For a thorough account of the Committee’s actions and the legislative history of the Social Security Act, see Witte (1962). Also see Weaver (1982); Altmeyer (1968); Nash, et al (1988). 4 5 . Helvering v. Davis, 301 US 619 (1937) represented a frontal assault on the general policy; while Steward Machine Company v. Davis, 301 US 548 (1937) challenged the taxation and employer contribution scheme. 6 . The depression era Townsend Movement in California, led by Dr. Francis E. Townsend, was actually the first effort to organize old people for the purpose of political action. The primary thrust of the movement was that every citizen should, at age 60, get $200 per month from the government with the requirement that it be spent, thereby both providing for old age and to stimulate the economy. Older folks would also be taken care of, and they would immediately put their stipends into circulation which would serve as an economic stimulus (Holtzman 1963). In addition, Abraham Epstein organized the American Association for Old Age Security in 1927 (which became the Association for Social Security in 1933) for the purpose of promoting old-age assistance laws (e.g., Lubove 1968). . See http://www.aarp.org for a full analysis of the organization’s lobbying and litigation efforts on behalf of senior citizens. (Visited January 13, 2000). 7 8 . NY Exec. Law, sec. 296 (1958); Laws Cal. 1961, ch. 1623. 9 . 79 Stat. 218, July 14, 1965. 0 10. 81 Stat. 602, December 15, 1967; 29 USC 621. The ADEA covered all individuals between the ages of 40 and 65, and was amended in 1978 to increase the upper age to 70 (92 Stat. 189, April 6, 1978). 1 1. There have been a number of such cases that have worked their way through the federal courts under ADEA. Waggoner v. City of Garland, 987 F2d 1160 (5th Cir. 1993) (finding supervisor’s stray remarks insufficient to prove age discrimination in employment) is an often-cited and pivotal case. Also see Bolton v. Scrivner, Inc., 36 F.3d 939, 944-45 (10th Cir. 1994), cert. denied, 115 S. Ct. 1104 (1995). 2 12. Medicare and Medicaid were parts of the Health Insurance for the Aged Act (79 Stat. 290, July 20, 1965. 3 13. For an extensive summary of both the Medicare and Medicaid programs, see Waid (1998). 4 14. Thus, a person who is eligible for Medicaid in one State might not be eligible in another State; and the services provided by one State may differ considerably in amount, duration, or scope from services provided in a similar or neighboring State. In addition, Medicaid eligibility and/or services within a State can change during the year. 5 15. See Goldberg v. Kelly, 405 U.S. 134 (1972) (holding that states cannot terminate benefits without a formal hearing on the recipient’s eligibility); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. 618 (1969) (invalidating residency requirements for receipt of benefits in light of the Constitutional “right to travel”). 6 16. It is estimated that by the year 2000 the average life expectancy will rise to 80 years of age. Indeed, if medical research into such technologies as stem cell replacement continue to progress, the Census Bureau predicts that within a century, more than 5,000,000 Americans will be living past 100! (Hall 2000). 7 17. Agriculture is heavily regulated and subsidized by law, both state and federal. Law covers a wide variety of loan programs, production assistance, disaster aid, crop insurance, pricing, trade agreements, and special labor regulations, to name a few. See, for more information, U.S., House of Representatives, Committee on Agriculture, http://agriculture.house.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999); U.S., Senate, Committee on Agriculture, Nutrition, and Forestry, http://www.senate.gov/~agriculture/ (date visited: October 26, 1999); and Farm Services Administration, U.S. Department of Agriculture, http://www.fsa.usda.gov/pas/default.asp (date visited: October 26, 1999). 8 18. See, U.S. Food and Drug Administration, Center for Food Safety and Applied Nutrition, http://vm.cfsan.fda.gov/list.html (date visited: October 26, 1999); and U.S.,”Food Safety” cite, http://www.foodsafety.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999). 9 19. See, for example, U.S. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, http://www.cdc.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999); U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, Health Resources and Services Administration, http://www.hrsa.dhhs.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999); and National Institutes of Health, http://www.nih.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999). 20. Yes, there’s even a President’s Council on Physical Fitness and Sports. See: http://www.indiana.edu/~preschal/council.html (date visited: October 26, 1999). 0 1 21. See for example, the U.S. Consumer Product Safety Commission, http://www.cpsc.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999). 2 2. See, U.S. Department of Labor, Occupational Health and Safety Administration, http://www.osha.gov/ (date visited: October 26, 1999). 3 23. Black's Law Dictionary (5th ed. 1979), p. 361, cited in Banks (1995). 4 24. 381 U.S. 479 (1965). For a discussion of Griswold, see Chapter 5. 5 25. 410 U.S. 113 (1973). For a discussion of Roe see Chapter 5. 26. Notably, the withdrawal of the life-sustaining apparatus did not bring on Karen’s death. She persisted in her vegetative coma for a full nine years before her death in 1985. See e.g., Malcolm (1985: 22). 6 7 27. From 1976 through 1988, at least 54 such cases were reported, marking a substantial increase over previous years. 760 S.W.2d at 412, n.4, cited in Cruzan v. Missouri Department of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 269 (1989). 8 28. App. to Pet. for Cert. A99, cited in Cruzan, 267. 29. The 5-4 decision included a majority consisting of the Chief Justice and Justices White, O’Connor, Scalia, and Kennedy (O’Connor and Scalia wrote concurrences). The dissent, led by Justice Brennan, included Justices Marshall, Blackmun and Stevens, with Stevens writing separately. 9 30. “Kevorkian’s Patients,” The Kevorkian File, http://www.rights.org/deathnet/Kfiles_details.html (Date visited: January 5, 2000). 0 1 31. On March 14, 1998, Kevorkian assisted in his 100th suicide. See Frontline (1998). 2 32. On April 13, 1999, Kevorkian was convicted of second-degree murder and delivery of a controlled substance in the death of Thomas Youk. Dr. Kevorkian was sentenced to 10-25 years in prison for delivery a lethal injection to Youk. Kevorkian had videotaped this particular death which was aired on the CBS show, 60 Minutes, the previous November. Prior to his conviction, Kevorkian had been tried and acquitted several times by Michigan juries and had been the impetus for two state laws outlawing assisted suicide, the first of which was declared unconstitutional by the Michigan Supreme Court. For a complete chronology of Kevorkian’s activities and the legal responses to those exploits, see Frontline (1998). See also, Lessenberry (1994). 3 3. Or. Rev. Stat.127.800 et seq. Although some states, like Maine, are considering measures similar to that of Oregon, the trend in recent years has been in the opposite direction, with more states acting to explicitly ban assisted suicide. See: “Legal Developments: Recent Legislation,” Choice in Dying, http://www.choices.org/legal.htm#Legislation (Date visited: January 6, 2000.) 34. Oregon Dept. of Human Resources, Health Division, “Oregon's Death with Dignity Act,” http://www.ohd.hr.state.or.us/cdpe/chs/pas/pas.htm (Date visited: January 6, 2000). 4 35. Oregon Dept. of Human Resources, Health Division, Annual Report: “Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act: The First Year's Experience,” http://www.ohd.hr.state.or.us/cdpe/chs/pas/arresult.htm (Date visited: January 6, 2000)> 5 6 36. For a discussion, see below. 7 37. For a discussion, see below. 8 38. Chief Justice Burger and Justices White and Rehnquist would have upheld, in addition, the Louisiana and North Carolina Laws. See, Roberts v. Louisiana, 428 U.S. 325, 337ff (1976), (White, J., dissenting). Justices Brennan and Marshall continued to maintain that the death penalty is always unconstitutional. See, Gregg, Brennan, J., dissenting at 227ff; Marshall, J., dissenting at 231ff. 9 39. Not a single member of the Court today views the death penalty as unconstitutional per se. 42. ACLU, “The Poverty Connection,” ACLU Execution Watch, http://www.aclu.org/executionwatch.html (Date visited: January 3, 2000) 2 3 43. See for example, Powell v. Alabama, 287 U.S. 45 (1932); Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963); Douglas v. California, 372 U.S. 535 (1963). 4 4. The term was quoted and accepted by the ABA in a 1997 report (ABA 1997: 224). 45. In spite of all the negligence, “both the Alabama Court of Criminal Appeals, Haney v. State, 603 So. 2d 368 (Ala. Crim. App. 1991), and the Alabama Supreme Court, Ex parte Haney, 603 So. 2d 412 (Ala. 1992), upheld the conviction and death sentence in the case” (Bright 1994: 1836, fn2). 5 46. Chief Justice William H. Rehnquist, “Panel Attorney Compensation,” The 1999 Year-End Report on the Federal Judiciary, accessed at: http://www.uscourts.gov/ttb/jan00ttb/jan2000.html (Date retrieved: May 5, 2000). 6 7 47. See: Baldus, Pulaski, Woodworth, and Kyle 1980; Baldus, Pulaski, Woodworth 1983; Baldus, Woodworth and Pulaski 1985; Baldus, Woodworth, and Pulaski 1986. 8 48. Justice Powell was joined by Chief Justice Rehnquist and by Justices White, O’Connor, and Scalia. 9 49. Justice Brennan was joined in full by Justice Marshall and in part by Justices Blackmun and Stevens. 0 50. Dennis Culloton, Press Secretary to Governor Ryan, quoted in Claiborne (2000: 1). 1 51. See Chapter 4. 2 52. See for example, Herrera v.Collins, 506 U.S. 390 (1993) (holding that a claim of actual innocence does not entitle a defendant to federal habeas relief where he has been afforded a fair trial and appeals) and Felker v. Turpin, 518 U.S. 651 (1996) (upholding congressional restrictions on habeas passed as part of the Antiterrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996.) 3 53. See generally, Md. HEALTH OCCUPATIONS Code Ann. § 7-101ff (1999). 54. The FTC attempts to be solicitous of state prerogatives here, exempting any state that “affords an overall level of protection to consumers which is as great as, or greater than, the protection afforded by [the FTC rule].” 16 CFR 453.9. 4 5 5. Magna Carta, Chapters 26 and 27 (1215 A.D.). The University of Oklahoma Law Center, http://www.law.ou.edu//hist/magna.html. (Date visited: August 4, 1998). 6 56. Generally, this would mean that the spouse gets some portion of the estate, while the children get the remainder. However, if there are no children, the spouse may have to split the estate with her dearly departed’s parents or siblings. 57. “A Trust is a creature of the law in which one party - the Trustee - has legal ownership of any form of property that has been transferred to him/her or "it" (e.g., a bank) by the person establishing the Trust. That "establishing" person is called the Grantor (or Settlor, or Trustor). The property is known as the Trust "principal," or "corpus." These Trust assets are invested and/or managed for the benefit of one or more beneficiaries. Sometimes, the Grantor also wears the hats of Trustee and beneficiary. Generally, however, if the Grantor is the Trustee, he/she cannot be the only beneficiary. . . . [A] "living" [trust is one] established during the Grantor's lifetime (Palermo). 7 8 58. Joint tenancy is the legal term for joint ownership of property. For example, most husbands and wives jointly hold title to the couple’s house. 59. Cornell Law School, Legal Information Institute (LLI), “Estate and Gift Tax: an Overview,” http://www.law.cornell.edu/topics/estate_gift_tax.html (Date Visited: September 30, 1999). 9 60. “A gift tax is imposed on lifetime transfers and an estate tax is imposed on transfers at death. Since1976, the gift tax and the estate tax have been unified so that a single graduated rate schedule applies to cumulative taxable transfers made by a taxpayer during his or her lifetime and at death. Under this rate schedule, the unified estate and gift tax rates begin at 18 percent on the first $10,000 in cumulative taxable transfers and reach 55 percent on cumulative taxable transfers over $3 million. In addition, a 5-percent surtax is imposed upon cumulative taxable transfers between $10 million and the amount necessary to phase out the benefits of the graduated rates and the unified credit. (Joint Committee on Taxation 1998) 0 1 61. See for example, the Estate and Gift Tax Rate Reduction Act, H.R.8 and the Family Heritage Preservation Act, H.R.86.