Framework Makes the Game Work Notes You are always right, do not let anyone change your mind (I.E. Sean Hilzendeger) Do not let people scare you away from going for it in the 2NR (I.E. Sean Hilzendeger) More definitions are in the T file You have to make your own blocks The people who defend the Game: Jake Lee, Will Bledsoe, Henry Ferolie (AKA Bobby), Jaime Romero 1NC 1NC Interpretation/Violation-- The affirmative has presented a plan text / advocacy statement that doesn’t advocate United States federal government action. Resolved means to express by formal vote Webster’s Revised Unabridged Dictionary, 1998 (dictionary.com) Resolved: 5. To express, as an opinion or determination, by resolution and vote; to declare or decide by a formal vote; -- followed by a clause; as, the house resolved (or, it was resolved by the house) that no money should be apropriated (or, to appropriate no money). “United States should” proscribes both a stable agent and mechanism Ericson 3—Jon M., Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., “The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition” 2003 http://hs.stdoms.org/ourpages/auto/2009/10/28/44705084/debaterguide.pdf p. 4) The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from the comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. An agent to do the acting—“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is usually the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges an action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action through governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose. Prefer our Interpretation First—Switch-side debate is good—it is the only way to foster tolerance— turns their claims of inclusion Muir 93—Star A, communication studies at George Mason University (“A Defense of the Ethics of Contemporary Debate” 1993 pg. 287-289 http://www.jstor.org/stable/40237780?seq=7#page_scan_tab_contents)//JLee The first response to the charge of relativism is that switch-side debate respects the existence of divergent beliefs, but focuses attention on assessing the validity of opposing belief systems. Scriven argues that the “confusion of pluralism, of the proper tolerance for diversity of ideas, with relativism – the doctrine that there are no right and wrong answers in ethics or religion – is perhaps the most serious ideological barrier to the implementation of moral education today.” The process of ethical inquiry is central to such moral education, but the allowance of just any position is not. Here is where cognitive-development diverges from the formal aims of values clarification. Where clarification ostensibly allows any value position, cognitive-development progresses from individualism to social conformity to social contract theory to universal ethical principles. A pluralistic pedagogy does not imply that all views are acceptable: It is morally and pedagogically correct to teach about ethics, and the skills of moral analysis rather than doctrine, and to set out the arguments for and against tolerance and pluralism. All of this is undone if you also imply that all the various incompatible views about abortion or pornography or war are equally right, or likely to be right, or deserving of respect. Pluralism requires respecting the right to hold divergent beliefs; it implies neither tolerance of actions based on those beliefs nor respecting the content of the beliefs. The role of switch-side debate is especially important in the oral defense of arguments that foster tolerance without accruing the moral complications of acting on such beliefs. The forum is therefore unique in providing debaters with attitudes of tolerance without committing them to active moral irresponsibility. As Freeley notes, debaters are indeed exposed to a multivalued world, both within and between the sides of a given topic. Yet this exposure hardly commits them to such "mistaken" values. In this view, the divorce of the game from the "real world" can be seen as a means of gaining perspective without obligating students to validate their hypothetical value structure through immoral actions. Values clarification, Stewart is correct in pointing out, does not mean that no values are developed. Two very important values—tolerance and fairness—inhere to a significant degree in the ethics of switch-side debate. A second point about the charge of relativism is that tolerance is related to the development of reasoned moral viewpoints. The willingness to recognize the existence of other views, and to grant alternative positions a degree of credibility, is a value fostered by switch-side debate: Alternately debating both sides of the same question ... inculcates a deep-seated attitude of tolerance toward differing points of view. To be forced to debate only one side leads to an ego-identification with that side. . . . The other side in contrast is seen only as something to be discredited. Arguing as persuasively as one can for completely opposing views is one way of giving recognition to the idea that a strong case can generally be made for the views of earnest and intelligent men, however such views may clash with one's own.... Promoting this kind of tolerance is perhaps one of the greatest benefits debating both sides has to offer. The activity should encourage debating both sides of a topic, reasons Thompson, because debaters are "more likely to realize that propositions are bilateral. It is those who fail to recognize this fact who become intolerant, dogmatic, and bigoted."40 While Theodore Roosevelt can hardly be said to be advocating bigotry, his efforts to turn out advocates convinced of their rightness is not a position imbued with tolerance. At a societal level, the value of tolerance is more conducive to a fair and open assessment of competing ideas. John Stuart Mill eloquently states the case this way: Complete liberty of contradicting and disproving our opinion is the very condition which justifies us in assuming its truth for purposes of action; and on no other terms can a being with human faculties have any rational assurance of being right.... the peculiar evil of silencing the expression of an opinion is, that it is robbing the human race. . . . If the opinion is right, they are deprived of the opportunity of exchanging error for truth: if wrong, they lose, what is almost as great a benefit, the clearer perception and livelier impression of the truth, produced by its collision with error. At an individual level, tolerance is related to moral identity via empathic and critical assessments of differing perspectives. Paul posits a strong relationship between tolerance, empathy, and critical thought. Discussing the function of argument in everyday life, he observes that in order to overcome natural tendencies to reason egocentrically and sociocentrically, individuals must gain the capacity to engage in self-reflective questioning, to reason dialogically and dialectically, and to "reconstruct alien and opposing belief systems empathically. Our system of beliefs is, by definition, irrational when we are incapable of abandoning a belief for rational reasons; that is, when we egocentrically associate our beliefs with our own integrity. Paul describes an intimate relationship between private inferential habits, moral practices, and the nature of argumentation. Critical thought and moral identity, he urges, must be predicated on discovering the insights of opposing views and the weaknesses of our own beliefs. Role playing, he reasons, is a central element of any effort to gain such insight. Second—Limits are key to a productive agonistic discussion Dryzek 6—Australian National University Professor of Social and Political Theory (John, Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals, American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 50, No. 3, July 2006; JRom) Mouffe is a radical pluralist: "By pluralism I mean the end of a substantive idea of the good life" (1996, 246). But neither Mouffe nor Young want to abolish communication in the name of pluralism and difference; much of their work advocates sustained attention to communication. Mouffe also cautions against uncritical celebration of difference, for some differences imply "subordination and should therefore be challenged by a radical democratic politics" (1996, 247). Mouffe raises the question of the terms in which engagement across difference might proceed. Participants should ideally accept that the positions of others are legitimate, though not as a result of being persuaded in argument. Instead, it is a matter of being open to conversion due to adoption of a particular kind of democratic attitude that converts antagonism into agonism, fighting into critical engagement, enemies into adversaries who are treated with respect. Respect here is not just (liberal) toleration, but positive validation of the position of others. For Young, a communicative democracy would be composed of people showing "equal respect," under "procedural rules of fair discussion and decisionmaking" (1996, 126). Schlosberg speaks of "agonistic respect" as "a critical pluralist ethos" (1999, 70). Mouffe and Young both want pluralism to be regulated by a particular kind of attitude, be it respectful, agonistic, or even in Young's (2000, 16-51) case reasonable. Thus neither proposes unregulated pluralism as an alternative to (deliberative) consensus. This regulation cannot be just procedural, for that would imply "anything goes" in terms of the substance of positions. Recall that Mouffe rejects differences that imply subordination. Agonistic ideals demand judgments about what is worthy of respect and what is not. Connolly (1991, 211) worries about dogmatic assertions and denials of identity that fuel existential resentments that would have to be changed to make agonism possible. Young seeks "transformation of private, self-regarding desires into public appeals to justice" (2000, 51). Thus for Mouffe, Connolly, and Young alike, regulative principles for democratic communication are not just attitudinal or procedural; they to the substance of the kinds of claims that are worthy of respect . These authors would not want to legislate substance and are suspicious of the content of any alleged consensus. But in retreating from "anything goes" relativism, they need principles to regulate the substance of what rightfully belongs in democratic debate. also refer Third—Decision-Making—A limited topic of discussion that provides for equitable ground is key to productive inculcation of decision-making and advocacy skills in every and all facets of life---even if their position is contestable that’s distinct from it being valuably debatable---this still provides room for flexibility, creativity, and innovation, but targets the discussion to avoid mere statements of fact Steinberg & Freeley 8—Austin is a Boston based attorney who focuses on criminal, personal injury and civil rights law, and David L. is a Lecturer of Communication Studies @ U Miami (“Argumentation and Debate: Critical Thinking for Reasoned Decision Making” 2008 http://staff.uny.ac.id/sites/default/files/pendidikan/Rachmat%20Nurcahyo,%20SS,%20M.A./__Argumentation_and_Debate__C ritical_Thinking_for_Reasoned_Decision_Making.pdf Pg.43-450) Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a difference of opinion or a conflict of interest before there can be a debate . If everyone is in agreement on a fact or value or there is no need for debate ; the matter can be settled by unanimous consent. Thus, for example, it would be pointless to attempt to debate “Resolved: That two plus two equals four,” because there is simply no controversy about this statement. Controversy is an essential prerequisite of debate. Where there is no clash of ideas, proposals, interests, or expressed positions on policy, issues, there is no debate. In addition, debate cannot produce effective decisions without clear identification of a question or questions to be answered. For example, general argument may occur about the broad topic of illegal immigration. How many illegal immigrants are in the United States? What is the impact of illegal immigration and immigrants on our economy? What is their impact on our communities? Do they commit crimes? Do they take jobs from American workers? Do they pay taxes? Do it the responsibility of employers to discourage illegal immigration by not hiring undocumented workers? Should they have the opportunity to gain citizenship? Does illegal immigration pose a security threat to our country? they require social services? Is it a problem that some do not speak English? Is Do illegal immigrants do work that American workers are unwilling to do? Are their rights as workers and as human beings at risk due to their status? Are they abused by employers, law enforcement, housing, and businesses? How are their families impacted by their status? What is the moral and philosophical obligation of a nation state to maintain its borders? Should we build a wall on the Mexican border, establish a national identification card, or enforce existing laws against employers? Should we invite immigrants to become U.S. citizens? Surely you can think of many more concerns to be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration. Participation in this “debate” is likely to be emotional and intense. However , i t is not likely to be productive or useful without focus on a particular question and identification of a line demarcating sides in the controversy. To be discussed and resolved effectively, controversies must be stated clearly. Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation and poor decisions, frustration, and emotional distress, as evidenced by the failure of the United States Congress to make progress on the immigration debate during the summer of 2007. Someone disturbed by the problem of a growing underclass of poorly educated, socially disenfranchised youths might observe, “Public schools are doing a terrible job! They are overcrowded, and many teachers are poorly qualified in their subject areas. Even the best teachers can do little more than struggle to maintain order in their classrooms.” That same concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as “We ought to do something about this” or, worse, “It’s too complicated a problem to deal with.” Groups of concerned citizens worried about the state of public education could join together to express their frustrations, anger, disillusionment, and emotions regarding the schools, but without a focus for their discussions, they could easily agree about the sorry state of education without finding points of clarity or potential solutions. A gripe session would follow. But if a precise question is posed— such as “What can be done to improve public education?”—then a more profitable area of discussion is opened up simply by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution step. One or more judgments can be phrased in the form of debate propositions, motions for parliamentary debate, or bills for legislative assemblies. The statements “Resolved: That the federal government should implement a program of charter schools in at-risk communities” and “Resolved: That the state of Florida should adopt a school voucher program” more clearly identify specific ways of dealing with educational problems in a manageable form, suitable for debate. They provide specific policies to be investigated and aid discussants in identifying points of difference. To have a productive debate, which facilitates effective decision making by directing and p lacing limits on the decision to be made, the basis for argument should be clearly defined . If we merely talk about “homelessness” or “abortion” or “crime” or “global warming” we are likely to have an interesting discussion but not to establish profitable basis for argument. For example, the statement “Resolved: That the pen is mightier than the sword” is debatable, yet fails to provide much basis for clear argumentation. If we take this statement to mean that the written word is more effective than physical force for some purposes, we can identify a problem area: the comparative effectiveness of writing or physical force for a specific purpose. Although we now have a general subject, we have not yet stated a problem. It is still too broad, too loosely worded to promote well-organized argument. What sort of writing are we concerned with—poems, novels, government documents, website development, advertising, or what? What does “effectiveness” mean in this context? What kind of physical force is being compared—fists, dueling swords, bazookas, nuclear weapons, or what? A more specific question might be, “Would a mutual defense treaty or a visit by our fleet be more effective in assuring Laurania of our support in a certain crisis?” The basis for argument could be phrased in a debate proposition such as “Resolved: That the United States should enter into a mutual defense treaty with Laurania.” Negative advocates might This is not to say that debates should completely avoid creative interpretation of the controversy by advocates, or that good debates cannot occur over competing interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that debate is best facilitated by the guidance provided by focus on a particular point of difference, which will be outlined in the following discussion. oppose this proposition by arguing that fleet maneuvers would be a better solution. Fourth—Deliberative democracy increases the ability to solve for global issues Dryzek, Professor of Political Science, 15 (John, “Deliberative Democracy and Climate Change”, Center for Humans and Nature, http://www.humansandnature.org/democracy---john-dryzek-response-55.php)//WB Contemporary political systems fail to address climate change effectively to the degree that they lack deliberative capacity. Deliberative capacity can be defined as the degree to which a system hosts authentic, inclusive, and consequential deliberation. Deliberation, in turn, means communication that is non-coercive, capable of inducing reflection, connects expression of particular interests to more general principles, and involves the making of arguments and telling of stories in terms that make sense to others who do not share one’s particular framework. Systems that lack deliberative capacity tend to do badly on climate change. In particular, the climate issue clearly reveals the pathologies of adversarial democracies such as the United States and Australia, where all issues are processed in terms of partisan advantage. Over the past two years, Australia has witnessed a struggle over the introduction of a very modest carbon tax. The leader of the conservative opposition saw an opportunity to use the issue to beat up the government (while still paying lip service to the need to do something to reduce greenhouse gas emissions). Labeling the carbon tax “a great big tax on everything,” his campaign was successful in damaging the government’s public standing. The government, for its part, continued to push the tax only because of its parliamentary dependence on Green Party support, itself conditional on the tax going through. The carbon tax is now in operation—though in highly compromised form, full of exemptions and compensation packages for big and powerful polluters. Why might a more deliberative democracy do better? There are a number of theoretical claims that can be made on behalf of deliberative democracy when it comes to intractable social-ecological issues like climate change. It can generate coherence across the perspectives of actors concerned with different facets of complex issues. It can organize feedback on the condition of social-ecological systems into politics. It can lead to the prioritization of public goods (such as ecosystem integrity) and general interests over material self-interest. It may even expand the thinking of its participants to better encompass the interests of future generations, distant others, and non-human nature. These theoretical claims find empirical support, especially in citizen forums designed to deliberate climate change (and other environmental issues). The biggest such exercise to date took place on September 26, 2009, in 38 countries following a common model coordinated by the Danish Board of Technology. This “World Wide Views” process yielded recommendations that, in just about every country, favored stronger action on climate change than the national government in question was at the time prepared to support. The results were presented at the December 2009 Conference of the Parties to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change in Copenhagen (to little effect). Other sorts of deliberative forums involving partisans from different sides on environmental issues can also yield positive results, though there is little evidence from partisan forums on climate change per se. Evidence from citizen forums goes only so far because they, for the most part, lack any link to actual governance. But there are other sorts of evidence. If we look at the comparative performance of different countries when it comes to tackling pollution, in general, and climate change, in particular, we find that consensual democracies of the sort found in Northern Europe do better than adversarial ones (with the important exception of the United Kingdom, which, for a few years, seemed to have broken the mould by showing that an adversarial democracy could generate a relatively effective response to climate change until, more recently, climate skeptics gained the upper hand in the Cameron government). Consensual democracies also feature somewhat higher deliberative quality than adversarial ones, at least in their legislatures. All this is relative: no consensual democracy has yet turned in a performance on reducing greenhouse-gas emissions that can be regarded as adequate. In addition, there may be a problem inherent to consensual democracies. They are good at incorporating moderate versions of environmentalism and acting accordingly. They are not so good when it comes to generating and accepting more radical critique, which consequently has to be generated elsewhere. There is a subtle dynamic in operation here that points to the need for both moments of consensus and moments of contestation, which can be joined in the idea of a “deliberative system.” Moments of consensus may be appropriate in the formal institutions of government—while moments of contestation should be cultivated in the broader public sphere. This deliberative system idea can also be applied beyond the boundaries of the nation-state. Climate change is, of course, in large part a global issue, requiring coordinated global action. Electoral democracy is a non-starter in the global system. But we can think of the global governance of climate change as a potentially deliberative system—however far it might currently be from deliberative ideals. That system as a whole can then be analyzed in terms of its deliberative capacity— and how it might be enhanced. The result would be collective outcomes with higher legitimacy, and so greater likelihood of getting compliance from states, corporations, and others. Equally important, outcomes could be much more effective than those currently generated in the global governance of climate change, whose performance over two decades is dismal. That effectiveness depends, of course, on the degree to which the environmental promise of deliberative democracy could be redeemed at the global level (where it has never seriously been tried). What would such a global deliberative system look like? It would have room for multiple forms of governance beyond the multilateral negotiations of the UNFCCC. Many such forms—networks to organize clean technology transfer, emissions trading, or the sharing of information and commitment, for example—are emerging, though in practice they are not very deliberative. Currently, the global public sphere on climate issues is lively and contestatory—but its activity tends to have minimal connection to governance, especially when it comes to these new forms. Both transmission of concerns generated in this public sphere and accountability to global civil society can be strengthened. There are numerous reform proposals for global governance now on the agenda, and all could benefit from a deliberative aspect. Fifth—Roleplaying allows us to more effectively influence state policy AND is key to agency – studies prove—access better internal link to education Eijkman 12 [Henk, visiting fellow at the University of New South Wales at the Australian Defence Force Academy and is Visiting Professor of Academic Development, Annasaheb Dange College of Engineering and Technology in India, has taught at various institutions in the social sciences and his work as an adult learning specialist has taken him to South Africa, Malaysia, Palestine, and India, “The role of simulations in the authentic learning for national security policy development: Implications for Practice,” http://nsc.anu.edu.au/test/documents/Sims_in_authentic_learning_report.pdf] However, whether as an approach to learning, innovation, persuasion or culture shift, policy simulations derive their power from two central features: their combination of simulation and gaming (Geurts et al. 2007). 1. The simulation element: the unique combination of simulation with role-playing . The unique simulation/role-play mix enables participants to create possible futures relevant to the topic being studied. This is diametrically opposed to the more traditional, teacher-centric approaches in which a future is produced for them. In policy simulations, possible futures are much more than an object of tabletop discussion and verbal speculation. ‘ No other technique allows a group of participants to engage in collective action in a safe environment to create and analyse the futures they want to explore’ (Geurts et al. 2007: 536). 2. The game element: the interactive and tailor-made modelling and design of the policy game. The actual run of the policy simulation is only one step, though a most important and visible one, in a collective process of investigation, communication, and evaluation of performance. In the context of a post-graduate course in public policy development, for example, a policy simulation is a dedicated game constructed in collaboration with practitioners to achieve a high level of proficiency in relevant aspects of the policy development policy development simulations —as forms of interactive or participatory modelling— are particularly effective in developing participant knowledge and skills in the five key areas of the policy development process (and success criteria), namely: Complexity, Communication, Creativity, Consensus, and Commitment to action (‘the five Cs’). The capacity to provide effective learning support in these five categories has proved to be particularly helpful in strategic decision-making (Geurts et al. process. To drill down to a level of finer detail, 2007). Annexure 2.5 contains a detailed description, in table format, of the synopsis below. Offense Switch-Side Debate SSD Good—General The purpose of debate should be determined by the unique role this forum can play—instrumental switch side debate generates unique critical thinking benefits—err neg because the benefits of their advocacy could be achieved in alternate forums Muir 93—Star A, communication studies at George Mason University (“A Defense of the Ethics of Contemporary Debate” 1993 pg. 291-292 http://www.jstor.org/stable/40237780?seq=7#page_scan_tab_contents)//JLee Firm moral commitment to a value System, however, along with a sense of moral identity, is founded in reflexive assessments of multiple perspectives. Switch-side debate is not simply a matter of speaking persuasively or organizing ideas clearly (although it does involve these), but of understanding and mobilizing arguments to make an effective case. Proponents of debating both sides observe that the debaters should prepare the best possible case they can, given the facts and information available to them.52 This process, at its core, involves critical assessment and evaluation of arguments; it is a process of critical thinking not available with many traditional teaching methods.53 We must progressively learn to recognize how often the concepts of others are discredited by the concepts we use to justify ourselves to ourselves. We must come to see how often our claims are compelling only when expressed in our own egocentric view. We can do this if we learn the art of using concepts without living in them. This is possible only when the intellectual act of stepping outside of our own Systems of belief has become second nature, a routine and ordinary responsibility of everyday living. Neither academic schooling nor socialization has yet addressed this moral responsibility,54 but switch-side debating fosters this type of role playing and generates reasoned moral positions based in part on values of tolerance and fairness. Switch Side Debate—allows us to be critical thinkers and is key to deliberative democracy Koehle 10—Joe is the Director of Debate and Communications Director at Kansas State University (“Reuniting Old Friends: The Sophists and Academic Debate- Joe Koehle” December 20, 2010 http://www.k-state.edu/actr/2010/12/20/reuniting-oldfriends-the-sophists-and-academic-debate-joe-koehle/default.htm)//JLee Debate serves as a form of broad social critique and moreover, that debate can inform theories of argumentation in terms of argument fields, analysis of social structure, political implications of policy choices, questions of value and special knowledge (455). Contemporary policy debate fundamentally justifies itself as a pedagogical activity. Although it is competitive in nature, it brings in zero revenue to academic institutions that sponsor it. The major benefit of the activity is that it claims to produce critical thinkers who are capable of responding to the problems of the world around them. In this way, it is very similar to sophistic training because it claims to produce no specialized techne, but rather a capstone that helps to synthesize training in the liberal arts itself into a useful product. In the face of charges of modern-day sophistry, it would be wise for defenders of debate to emphasize the 2500 year legacy of training that this sophistic activity has provided and the tangible benefits of seeing education through a polyvocal lens. This is especially true in an environment where the academy is under attack from outsiders because of its commitment to open communication of ideas. The presence of debate is the mark of mature and healthy institutions, and will continue to be an essential component of teaching for as long as teaching will exist (Stannard). The rhetorical pedagogy of debate cannot exist in a vacuum, however. It presumably should be directed at some end and, much like the sophists‟, that end should be in a broad concept of the political. Not just in the halls of Congress and other mega-institutions, but in the day-to-day deliberations that shape collective human action. Darrin Hicks sums it up best when he wrote that: “Rhetorical theory was responsible for disclosing the ideals, values, methods and procedures animating the public use of reason within democratic debate and discussion” (222). The lesson of the sophists is that language can shape reality and as much as we would like to assume a universal truth or system of value that is out there somewhere, we would likely not be able to ever know it or communicate it. We are stuck with the messiness of different opinions, and need a way to negotiate them. Far too often both the sophists and academic debaters have been portrayed as hopeless relativists because of their attention to these details, but this stance towards understanding and negotiating the inevitability of disagreement is the main political insight that both groups can claim. The sophistic practices of antilogic teach us that dissoi logoi is the unavoidable outcome of any group discussion. There will always be difference of opinion, but the sophistic understanding of democratic politics is that it is more useful to discover how we come to settle upon a truth rather than forcing the world to fit into one neat framework via some nonnegotiable single truth within phenomena. Embodied by switch side debate, this view of how truths are negotiated is critical to overcoming one of the foremost barriers to effective deliberation, which is the stigmatization of disagreement and confrontation. Effective deliberative democracy relies upon removing the stigma from disagreement and confrontation, brining these issues into the open where they can be negotiated instead of abolished by force (Stannard). All theories of communication attempt to produce some benefit for humanity. The increasing complexity of the world‟s problems only proves that the sophists were correct in establishing that existence is governed not by unity and perfection, but rather the inescapability of dissoi logoi. As such, it is essential to cling to pedagogical practices that not only recognize the inevitability of disagreement but teach us how to negotiate and live in a world full of difference. Despite attempts to marginalize the relevance of switch side debate, it is the most effective mechanism for resisting simplifications that cover over subtleties and exploit the complexity of the world in the pursuit of greater explanatory power. It may have its faults, but without switch side debate, rhetorical scholarship would not only lose an important connection to the world at large, but also sacrifice a useful tool in making it a better place. Switch-side debate is good—key to better debates Harrigan 8—Casey is the Director of Debate at the Michigan State University, Previously Director of debate at Wake Forest University and University of Georgia (“AGAINST DOGMATISM: A CONTINUED DEFENSE OF SWITCH SIDE DEBATE” 2008 http://www.cedadebate.org/files/2008CAD.pdf#page=47 pg.37)//JLee Switching sides is a method that is integral to the success of debate as a deliberative and reflexive activity. No other component process than switch side debate contributes more greatly to the cultivation of a healthy ethic of tolerance and pluralism, generates the reasoned reflection necessary for critical thinking, or instills responsible and critical skepticism toward dominant systems of belief. The purpose of this essay is to mount a defense of the validity of switchside debating in light of modern criticisms, drawing upon the existing body of literature related to the theory to build a case for its continued practice. SSD Good—K2 Education Switch-Side Debate key to education—demands critical thinking, and to learn multiple issues on both sides of the debate Zwarensteyn 12—Ellen C. is the director of Debate and a teacher of communications at East Kentwood High School (“High School Policy Debate as an Enduring Pathway to Political Education: Evaluating Possibilities for Political Learning” August 2012 http://scholarworks.gvsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1034&context=theses)//JLee As referenced above, the resolution provides a basis for research and discussion. Using the resolution as a starting point, students will debate the same resolution dozens or hundreds of times each year on both the affirmative and negative. This practice, called switch-side debate, establishes the expectation that a student will defend and answer multiple sides of similar arguments throughout a debate season. As a result, this practice increases one’s intellectual flexibility and understanding of multiple sides of hundreds of issues. Galloway (2007), Harrigan (2008), and Mitchell (2010) add to this discussion. Galloway (2007) theorizes the benefits to communication through switch-side debate. In part due to the rules requiring both sides be heard for equal amounts of time combined with the etiquette of listening, flowing, and answering all of an opponent’s argument, debate forces structured dialogue. In such, demands for fairness surface. Galloway advances how demanding dialogical fairness “…takes the form of a demand for equality of voice. Far from being a banal request for links to a disadvantage, fairness is a demand for respect, a demand to be heard, a demand that a voice backed by literally months upon months of preparation, research, and critical thinking not be silenced” (Galloway, 2007, p. 6). Underlying strategic calls for fairness, fairness of equitable debatable ground in switch-side debate demands recognizing a basic humanity in all persons involved. Viewing the first affirmative speech as the invitation to the rest of the debate, Galloway (2007) continues to articulate the academic benefits to switching sides. Theorizing the benefits of taking multiple sides of an issue, even sides of an issue someone does not agree with, Galloway concludes how debate encourages critical thought, meaningful exchange of ideas, and a better defense of one’s own thought since ideas need defending against opposing argumentation. After surveying literature dating back to the policy debate controversies of the 1950s and 1960s, Harrigan (2008) weighs the arguments for switch-side debate against the potential shortcomings associating with losing a sense of one’s own personal convictions and/or the loss of intellectual certitude. Harrigan (2008) fuses these two concerns together in his answer. Submitting arguments for a debate surmounts to their dissection – exposing arguments to their assumptions, representations, framing, inferences, and consequences is the ultimate intellectual rigor of any given argument. “Switching sides grounds belief in reasonable reflexive thinking; it teaches that decisions should not be rendered until all positions and possible consequences have been considered in a reasoned manner” (Harrigan, 2008, p. 47). While debaters do not speak from a personal standpoint, they air arguments for critical consumption which may impact later personal advocacy. A paradox emerges; it is this distance from the argument that lays the foundation for personal advocacy. “…[S]ound convictions can only be truly generated by the reflexive thinking spurred by debating both sides” (Harrigan, 2008, p. 46). Furthermore, promoting argumentative pluralism offers hope for developing empathy, acceptance, and understanding. Acknowledging possible truths from a variety of perspectives lends credibility to belief in individual reason and the kernels of truth rooted in many perspectives. “[A]rgumentative pluralism holds great promise for a politics based on understanding and accommodation that runs contrary to the dominant forces of economic, political, and social exclusion. Pluralism requires that individuals acknowledge opposing beliefs and arguments by forcing an understanding that personal convictions are not universal… [I]nstead of being personally invested in the truth and general acceptance of a position, debaters use arguments instrumentally, as tools, and as a switch-side debating at its best holds immense potential not only for argumentative critical thinking but also for the creation of critical personal advocacies and social forces encouraging social inclusion and pedagogical devices in the search for larger truths” (Harrigan, 2008, p. 51-52). Taken together, democracy. Switch-side debating has been taken to heart by many in the debate community as well as attracting attention at the top levels of government. The ‘real-world’, a world conceived as being occupied by persons no longer engaged in debating contests, appears to be paying close attention to the benefits to switch-side debates. Mitchell (2010) conjures the up the ancient work of Protagoras and what he “…called dissoi logoi – the practice of airing multiple sides of vexing questions for the purpose of stimulating critical thinking” (Mitchell, 2010, p. 97-98). The US Intelligence Community and the Environmental Protection Agency are two real-world examples of organizations attempting to thwart the dangers of group-think. By encouraging switch-side debate within their organization, their goal is “…to untangle disparate threads of knotty technoscientific issues, in part by integrating structured debating exercises into institutional decision-making processes” (Mitchell, 2010, p. 95). By training persons within their organization in switch-side debate or by bringing in trained policy debaters to debate for their organization, multiple issues are aired which might not otherwise be given space for consideration. Switch-side debate “…requires more than the sheer information processing power; it demands forms of communicative dexterity that enable translation of ideas across differences and facilitate cooperative work by interlocutors from heterogeneous backgrounds” (Mitchell, 2010, p. 100). This deliberation often checks against dangerous institutional groupthink and counters traditional formulaic decision-making process. Switch-side debating offers a forum for the relatively safe exploration of a variety of issues and invites arguments from multiple sources of authority. This practice may prove to be a bulwark against insular and isolated institutional or partisan practices. Citing Munksgaard and Pfister, Mitchell demonstrates the unique perspective debaters may bring to the table. ‘Having a public debater argue against their convictions, or confess their indecision on a subject and subsequent embrace of argument as a way to seek clarity, could shake up the prevailing view of debate as a war of words. Public uptake of the possibility of switchside debate may help lessen the polarization of issues inherent in prevailing debate formats because students are no longer seen as wedded to their arguments. This could transform public debate from a tussle between advocates, with each public debater trying to convince the audience in a Manichean struggle about the truth of their side, to a more inviting exchange focused on the content of the other’s argumentation and the process of deliberative exchange’ (Mitchell citing Munksgaard and Pfister, 2010, p. 110). Basing debates on a predictable resolution invites discussion centered on argument and permits continuously adapting multiple perspectives in and out of a student’s world-view. Solves Extinction Switch-Side creates critical thinking—that is key to solve threats Harrigan 8—Casey is the Director of Debate at the Michigan State University, Previously Director of debate at Wake Forest University and University of Georgia (“AGAINST DOGMATISM: A CONTINUED DEFENSE OF SWITCH SIDE DEBATE” 2008 http://www.cedadebate.org/files/2008CAD.pdf#page=47 pg.37)//JLee Along these lines, the greatest benefit of switching sides, which goes to the heart of contemporary debate, is its inducement of critical thinking. Defined as “reasonable reflective thinking that is focused on deciding what to believe or do” (Ennis, 1987, p. 10), critical thinking learned through debate teaches students not just how advocate and argue, but how to decide as well. Each and every student, whether in debate or (more likely) at some later point in life, will be placed in the position of the decision-maker. Faced with competing options whose costs and benefits are initially unclear, critical thinking is necessary to assess all the possible outcomes of each choice, compare their relative merits, and arrive at some final decision about which is preferable. In some instances, such as choosing whether to eat Chinese or Indian food for dinner, the importance of making the correct decision is minor. For many other decisions, however, the implications of choosing an imprudent course of action are potentially grave. As Robert Crawford notes, there are “issues of unsurpassed importance in the daily lives of millions upon millions of people…being decided to a considerable extent by the power of public speaking” (2003). Although the days of the Cold War are over, and the risk that “the next Pearl Harbor could be ‘compounded by hydrogen’” (Ehninger and Brockriede, 1978, p. 3) is greatly reduced, the manipulation of public support before the invasion of Iraq in 2003 points to the continuing necessity of training a well-informed and critically-aware public (Zarefsky, 2007). In the absence of debate-trained critical thinking, ignorant but ambitious politicians and persuasive but nefarious leaders would be much more likely to draw the country, and possibly the world, into conflicts with incalculable losses in terms of human well-being. Given the myriad threats of global proportions that will require incisive solutions, including global warming, the spread of pandemic diseases, and the proliferation of weapons of mass destruction , cultivating a robust and effective society of critical decision-makers is essential. As Louis Rene Beres writes, “with such learning, we Americans could prepare…not as immobilized objects of false contentment, but as authentic citizens of an endangered Thus, it is not surprising that critical thinking has been called “the highest educational goal of the activity” (Parcher, 1998). While arguing from conviction can foster limited critical thinking skills, the element of switching sides is necessary to sharpen debate’s critical edge and ensure that decisions are made in a reasoned manner instead of being driven by ideology. Debaters trained in SSD are more likely to evaluate both sides of an argument before arriving at a conclusion and are less likely to dismiss potential arguments based on his or her prior beliefs (Muir 1993). In addition, debating both sides teaches “conceptual flexibility,” where decision-makers are more likely to reflect upon the beliefs that are held before coming to a final opinion (Muir, 1993, p. 290). Exposed to many arguments on each side of an issue, debaters learn that public policy is characterized by extraordinary complexity that requires careful consideration before action. Finally, these arguments are confirmed by the preponderance of empirical research demonstrating a link between competitive SSD and critical thinking (Allen, Berkowitz, Hunt planet” (2003). and Louden, 1999; Colbert, 2002, p. 82). AT: Devil’s Advocate Devil’s Advocacy creates self-reflexivity—promotes tolerance and kills dogmatism Koehle 10—Joe is the Director of Debate and Communications Director at Kansas State University (“Reuniting Old Friends: The Sophists and Academic Debate- Joe Koehle” December 20, 2010 http://www.k-state.edu/actr/2010/12/20/reuniting-oldfriends-the-sophists-and-academic-debate-joe-koehle/default.htm)//JLee Given the variety of assaults upon switch side debate by both sides of the political spectrum, how can switch side debate be justified? Supporters of switch side debate have made many arguments justifying the value of the practice that are not related to any defense of sophist techniques. I will only briefly describe them so as to not muddle the issue, but they are worthy of at least a cursory mention. The first defense is the most pragmatic reason of all: Mandating people debate both sides of a topic is most fair to participants because it helps mitigate the potential for a topic that is biased towards one side. More theoretical justifications are given, however. Supporters of switch side debate have argued that encouraging students to play the devil‟s advocate creates a sense of self-reflexivity that is crucial to promoting tolerance and preventing dogmatism ( Muir 287). Others have attempted to justify switch side debate in educational terms and advocacy terms, explaining that it is a path to diversifying a student‟s knowledge by encouraging them to seek out paths they may have avoided otherwise, which in turn creates better public advocates (Dybvig and Iversen). In fact, contemporary policy debate and its reliance upon switching sides creates an oasis of argumentation free from the demands of advocacy, allowing students to test out ideas and become more well-rounded advocates as they leave the classroom and enter the polis (Coverstone). Finally, debate empowers individuals to become critical thinkers capable of making sound decisions (Mitchell, “Pedagogical Possibilities”, 41). Despite the power of these claims, the reality is that these justifications can only do so much to help defend switch side debate. It is necessary for defenders of the practice to utilize the insights of the sophists to help articulate new reasons w Switch-side debate solves for the Devil’s Advocate Harrigan 8—Casey is the Director of Debate at the Michigan State University, Previously Director of debate at Wake Forest University and University of Georgia (“AGAINST DOGMATISM: A CONTINUED DEFENSE OF SWITCH SIDE DEBATE” 2008 http://www.cedadebate.org/files/2008CAD.pdf#page=47 pg.37)//JLee Switch side debate (SSD) is an argumentative model that requires students to debate both the affirmative and negative sides of the resolution over the course of a multipleround tournament. In practice, SSD requires that debaters’ arguments are frequently divorced from personal conviction; in many cases students are required by the topic to take a position and argue vigorously on behalf of views that they disagree with. Debaters with ideological beliefs are thrust into the position of the Devil’s Advocate, assuming the side of the opposition and needing to understand the arguments of the opposing view well enough to argue on their behalf. Instead of approaching the debate topic from the perspective of personal belief, students often choose arguments from a strategic and competitive perspective. Because of SSD, the purpose of debate is not to convince others to accept a certain argument as preferable or “true”, but rather to choose the strongest and most intellectually rigorous position that has the greatest chance of prevailing under scrutiny (and thus earning a competitive victory). Policy debate, an activity with few formal rules and requirements, developed this norm of arguing both sides of a topic for pragmatic, pedagogical, and social reasons. Fairness O/W Education Fairness outweighs education—if we do not have any clash, we cannot test them properly—only clash is key to understanding arguments in the debate Zappen 4—James Philip is a Professor of Communications and Media, Ph.D. University of Missouri (“The Rebirth of Dialogue: Bakhtin, Socrates, and the Rhetorical Tradition” 2004 https://books.google.com/books?hl=en&lr=&id=EcAoW5mv9GIC&oi=fnd&pg=PR7&dq=+Zappen&ots=wOFk3fH2r6&sig=bb_Du NmNFl0nZuKFKBX73TpIwkg#v=onepage&q=Zappen%20debate&f=false pg. 35-36)//JLee Finally, Bakhtin describes the Socratic dialogue as a carnivalesque debate between opposing points of view, with a ritualistic crownings and decrownings of opponents. I call this Socratic form of debate a contesting of ideas to capture the double meaning of the Socratic debate as both a mutual testing of oneself and others and a contesting or challenging of others' ideas and their lives. Brickhouse and Smith explain that Socrates' testing of ideas and people is a mutual testing not only of others but also of himself: Socrates claims that he has been commanded by the god to examine himself as well as others; he claims that the unexamined life is not worth living; and, since he rarely submits to questioning himself, "it must be that in the process of examining others Socrates regards himself as examining his own life, too." Such a mutual testing of ideas provides the only claim to knowledge that Socrates can have: since neither he nor anyone else knows the real definitions of things, he cannot claim to have any knowledge of his own; since, however, he subjects his beliefs to repeated testing, he can claim to have that limited human knowledge supported by the "inductive evidence" of "previous elenctic examinations." This mutual testing of ideas and people is evident in the Laches and also appears in the Gorgias in Socrates' testing of his own belief that courage is inseparable from the other virtues and in his willingness to submit his belief and indeed his life to the ultimate test of divine judgment, in what Bakhtin calls a dialogue on the threshold. The contesting or challenging of others' ideas and their lives and their ritualistic crowning/decrowning is evident in the Gorgias in Soocrates' successive refutations and humiliations of Gorgias, Polus, and Callicles. Good Fairness allows for both sides to participate in the round—they can tell a story but is has to be under the topical version of the aff Burch 8—Elizabeth Chamblee is an Assistant Professor at Cumberland School of Law (“CAFA’s Impact on Litigation as a Public Good” 2008 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1005021 Pg. 2534-2536)//JLee Fairness arguments are typically offered as policy reasons to trump pursuit of certain reform proposals and aggregate social goals; however, I use fairness here (and in assessing CAFA) as a supplemental constraint rather than a substitute. Employing a deontological conception of fairness to balance utility aid in, not only distributing procedural costs and correcting procedural errors, but also in ensuring that the procedural system does not disproportionately favor or burden plaintiffs or defendants. Put differently, process should disperse the risk of error and the cost of access as evenly as possible. Neither party should have an Given this shortcoming, the second procedural justice component if fairness. advantage. This idea of “fairness” as avoiding lopsided distribution of error can be likened to the concept of “neutrality.” To be sure, some imparity in distributing risks may be inevitable. Finally, although analogous to fairness, participation—manifested as adequate representation in the class context—humanizes process. In its simplest form, participation necessitates that those who are bound by a decision have an opportunity to take part (and be heard) in adjudication. Moreover, it encompasses inherent rights to present evidence, observe the proceedings, cross-examine witnesses, and hear the judge’s decision. And participation, even in class litigation, affords litigants dignity by granting them a forum in which to tell their story. “Storytelling” has been criticized when used to demonstrate satisfaction with process as a proxy for “justice.” I use the tem here, however, for its cathartic value only when situated within this larger procedural fairness framework. A level playing field is required to achieve the most affective policies (Cecilia, “Justice & Fairness in International Negotiation”, Cambridge University Press, 2001, p.1-3, ISBN: 9780511157851)//WB Justice and fairness are not considerations that naturally come to mind when we think of international negotiation. This is, after all, a political activity driven by the objectives of individual countries and the prospect of mutual gains. That negotiation is all about the pursuit of narrow self-interests, with the backup of whatever power and skills can be mustered, is a common notion with well-established roots. Yet issues of justice are a major cause of con¯ict. Disagreements over justice, like con¯icts of interests, can turn violent and lead to wars. 2 They all too often undermine the capacity of negotiation to produce acceptable and durable solutions to disputes. Negotiation is a joint decision-making process in which parties, with initially opposing positions and con¯icting interests, arrive at a mutually bene®cial and satisfactory agreement. It normally includes dialogue with problem-solving and discussion on merits, as well as bargaining and the exchange of concessions with the use of competitive tactics. 3 More than other tools such as arbitration and adjudication, this is a ¯exible method of resolving differences which leaves the parties themselves with considerable control over the process and the outcome. Every Albin, Professor of Peace and Conflict Research, 1 party usually exercises leverage based on a variety of sources, and at the very least based on its ability to threaten to walk away from the table. Negotiation can bring on board new and needed parties by virtue of promising them `gains from trade'. It can result in the creation or identi®cation of new solutions to shared problems, and lend legitimacy to and facilitate the implementation of them as they have been agreed in a process of deliberation. Negotiation is used not only to produce agreement on the division or exchange of particular resources or burdens, but also to establish and reform institutions, regimes and regulations that will help to govern future relations between parties. Governments have always relied on this activity to manage their relations. In the last three decades, however, growing interdependence among states and the recognition of a range of new threats to human survival and well-being have increased dramatically the signi®cance, scope and complexity of international negotiation. Among the factors which have driven this expansion are the transborder nature of the threats, the need for voluntary multilateral cooperation and coordinated measures to tackle them, and the insuf®ciency or ambiguity of existing international regulations. Today negotiation is the principal means of collective decision-making, rule-making and dispute settlement in the management of transboundary issues. More broadly, it is fundamental to all efforts to achieve a measure of stability and order in the post-Cold War era. Environmental degradation, trade, arms control, economic integration and development, ethnic-sectarian con¯ict, the break-up and succession of states, and human rights are only some of the questions with which international negotiators now grapple. Issues of justice and fairness lie at the heart of problems in every one of these areas. Global climate change, for example, threatens many countries with devastation primarily due to the actions of other states. Yet negotiations concerned with this problem keep stumbling over the dilemma of how to distribute the formidable costs of cutting greenhouse gas emissions. Who should have to reduce their emissions and who should pay for it, given the resource inequalities and sharp differences in past and current emission levels (responsibility for the problem) between states? How much should emissions be cut and by what time, considering that reductions in the near term are prone to hamper the economic development of poorer countries? The cooperation of these countries will clearly be required to stabilise rising emission levels. But it is unlikely to be forthcoming unless industrialised states, as the principal atmospheric polluters to date, address at least some of the requests for justice advanced by the developing world. 4 Compensatory justice, expressed through preferential treatment of less developed countries the form of exemptions and ®nancial and technical assistance, was a cornerstone of the 1987 Montreal Protocol on Substances that Deplete the Ozone Layer, one of the most successful environmental agreements ever negotiated. (LDCs) in The “rules of the game” are key to create beneficial discussion Risse, Professor of International Relations, 2k (Thomas, “’Let's Argue!’ Communicative Action in World Politics”, International Organization, 54, pp 1-39)//WB A focus on arguing helps to clarify two issues in the rationalist-constructivist debate. First, it furthers our understanding of how actors develop a common knowledge concerning both a definition of the situation and an agreement about the underlying "rules of the game" that enable them to engage in strategic bargaining in the first place. Thus, arguing constitutes a necessary (though not sufficient) step in a negotiating process. Arguing is also relevant for problem solving in the sense of seeking an optimal solution for a commonly perceived problem and for agreeing on a common normative framework. Seeking a reasoned consensus helps actors to overcome many collective action problems. I illustrate this point empirically using the negotiated settlement ending the Cold War in Europe. Second, argumentative rationality appears to be crucially linked to the constitutive rather than the regulative role of norms and identities by providing actors with a mode of interaction that enables them to mutually challenge and explore the validity claims of those norms and identities. When actors engage in a truth-seeking discourse, they must be prepared to change their own views of the world, their interests, and sometimes even their identities. Some of these debates actually take place in the public sphere, which has to be distinguished from the realm of diplomatic negotiations. My empirical example for such a process concerns public discourses in the human rights area, particularly those between transnational human rights advocacy networks and national governments accused of norm violation. AT: Fairness Rigged/Delgado Our framework solves fairness—it is systemically bias in self-serving assertion to sidestep clash—all of their reasons to not defend the topic are stupid—they can be solved with actors with opposite goals Talisse 5—Robert is a Professor of Philosophy at Vanderbilt Philosophy & Social Criticism, 31.4, “Deliberativist responses to activist challenges” http://psc.sagepub.com/content/31/4/423.full.pdf) My call for a more detailed articulation of the second activist challenge may be met with the radical claim that I have begged the question. It may be said that my analysis of the activist’s challenge and my request for a more rigorous argument presume what the activist denies, namely, that arguments and reasons operate independently of ideology. Here the activist might begin to think that he made a mistake in agreeing to engage in a discussion with a deliberativist – his position throughout the debate being that one should decline to engage in argument with one’s opponents! He may say that of course activism seems lacking to a deliberativist, for the deliberativist measures the strength of a view according to her own standards. But the activist rejects those standards, claiming that they are appropriate only for seminar rooms and faculty meetings, not for real-world politics. Consequently the activist may say that by agreeing to enter into a discussion with the deliberativist, he had unwittingly abandoned a crucial element of his position. He may conclude that the consistent activist avoids arguing altogether, and communicates only with his comrades. Here the discussion ends. However, the deliberativist has a further consideration to raise as his discursive partner departs for the next rally or street demonstration. The foregoing debate had presumed that there is but one kind of activist and but one set of policy objectives that activists may endorse. Yet Young’s activist is opposed not only by deliberative democrats, but also by persons who also call themselves ‘activists’ and who are committed to a set of policy objectives quite different from those endorsed by this one activist. Once these opponents are introduced into the mix, the stance of Young’s activist becomes more evidently problematic, even by his own standards. To explain: although Young’s discussion associates the activist always with politically progressive causes, such as the abolition of the World Trade Organization (109), the expansion of healthcare and welfare programs (113), and certain forms of environmentalism (117), not all activists are progressive in this sense. Activists on the extreme and racist Right claim also to be fighting for justice, fairness, and liberation. They contend that existing processes and institutions are ideologically hegemonic and distorting. Accordingly, they reject the deliberative ideal on the same grounds as Young’s activist. They advocate a program of political action that operates outside of prevailing structures, disrupting their operations and challenging their legitimacy. They claim that such action aims to enlighten, inform, provoke, and excite persons they see as complacent, naïve, excluded, and ignorant. Of course, these activists vehemently oppose the policies endorsed by Young’s activist; they argue that justice requires activism that promotes objectives such as national purity, the disenfranchisement of Jews, racial segregation, and white supremacy. More importantly, they see Young’s activist’s vocabulary of ‘inclusion’, ‘structural inequality’, ‘institutionalized power’, as fully in line with what they claim is a hegemonic ideology that currently dominates and systematically distorts our political discourses.21 The point here is not to imply that Young’s activist is no better than the racist activist. The point rather is that Young’s activist’s arguments are, in fact, adopted by activists of different stripes and put in the service of a wide range of policy objectives, each claiming to be just, liberatory, and properly inclusive.22 In light of this, there is a question the activist must confront. How should he deal with those who share his views about the proper means for bringing about a more just society, but promote a set of ends that he opposes? It seems that Young’s activist has no way to deal with opposing activist programs except to fight them or, if fighting is strategically unsound or otherwise problematic, to accept a Hobbesian truce. This might not seem an unacceptable response in the case of racists; however, the question can be raised in the case of any less extreme but nonetheless opposed activist program, including different styles of politically progressive activism. Hence the deliberativist raises her earlier suspicions that, in practice, activism entails a politics based upon interestbased power struggles amongst adversarial factions. AT: Schlag Normative debate is valuable for its own sake—we can still win because these are interesting questions to discuss. They link to the impact more by over-determining what we think is at stake in each round West 9—Robin is a Frederick J. Haas Professor of Law and Philosophy, Associate Dean for Research and Academic Programs, Georgetown Law (“A Reply to Pierre” 2009 http://georgetownlawjournal.org/files/pdf/97-3/West.PDF pg.871-873) Why? What’s wrong with normativity? Pierre has given various answers in his twenty-year critique of normativity, but this new essay suggests yet an additional argument, which I think is wrong and merits a response. One reason for Pierre’s longstanding opposition to normativity, suggested by this essay, might be a suspicion—well-grounded—that the kind of normative questions asked, and certainly the answers given by MLS, will be, or are, or have always been in the past, imitative of the sorts of normative questions judges ask when deciding cases. Just as the truths about the world and the statements of law in MLS are basically imitative of judicial declarations of truth and law, so too are the political or moral claims about the way the world should look. And, for the same reasons, the normative questions that judges ask and the answers they give, as well as the empirical and legal questions they ask in the course of writing judicial opinions, will be—virtually by definition they must be— politically uninteresting, aesthetically unappealing, and intellectually deadening. And scholars imitate judges. So, mainstream normative jurisprudence is likewise politically uninteresting, aesthetically unappealing, and so on. As such, the problem with mainstream normative legal scholarship—MNLS—is that the normative questions it asks—what should the law be, what should the world look like, how might law contribute—imitate the normative questions asked by judges. Those latter questions, in turn, will be “truncated,” to use Unger’s term for the same phenomenon,12 or spam, to revert to Pierre’s. Spam normative questions about what the law and world should look like will invite spam answers. But if that’s the argument, there’s a pretty obvious problem with it, which Pierre’s essay itself clearly shows. Here’s the problem. Pierre may be right about the nature of normative questions posed and answered by judges. As virtually everyone who’s thought about it agrees, both judges and the scholars that imitate them, when explaining what the law is, have to also explain what the law should be. If we want to explain “the law” of compensation for injuries caused by badly manufactured products, we’re going to have to also say what we think “the law” ought to be, because “what it is” is just not all that clear. So, there’s some “normative” or “political” or “moral” analysis involved in even the most ordinary legal and adjudicative writing. Statements of “what the law is” will indeed include, perforce, a tad of “policy analysis,” a dabbling in costs and benefits, some philosophizing over fundamental values or basic principles, and at least some “weighing” of pros and cons between proffered alternatives. That dabbling will be spam-like, for the same reasons the judge’s various truth claims and statements of what the law is are such. And this is as true of imitative legal scholarship as it is My objection to this Schlagian syllogism is just this: normative legal scholarship does not have to be so confined, and if anyone pays attention to Pierre’s essay, it won’t be. It doesn’t have to be imitative. It doesn’t have to be adjudication-lite. Legal scholars could ask, and I think should ask, normative questions about what the law should be, not so as to get a better grip on what the of judicial opinion writing itself. The conclusion thus follows: if legal scholarship is spam, then so is its normative component. law is, and not so as to better imitate the cost-benefit policy analysis or the fundamental values analysis or the basic principles analysis or the prosandcons reasoning that typifies adjudication; not, in brief, so as to better sway the court toward one possible legal result over another. Legal scholars could and I think should be asking what the law should be, and what it should not be; what our social world should look like, and what it should not look like; what of the law we have is an utter disaster, and what of the law we don’t have that we perhaps should have. And we could do all of this “normative analysis” not toward the end of figuring out what the law is—that is indeed what truncates or spamifies normative analysis13—but solely because these are important questions to ask. Limits Good Good Limits are key to switch-side debate and dialogue (Ellen, “High School Policy Debate as an Enduring Pathway to Political Education: Evaluating Possibilities for Political Learning,” published 8-1-12, accessed 7-6-15, http://scholarworks.gvsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1034&context=theses)//JRom Galloway (2007) also advances an argument concerning the privileging of the resolution as a basis for debating. Galloway (2007) cites three pedagogical advantages to seeing the resolution and the first affirmative constructive as an invitation to dialogue. “First, all teams have equal access to the resolution. Second, teams spend the entire year preparing approaches for and against the resolution. Finally, the resolution represents a community consensus of worthwhile and equitably debatable topics rooted in a collective history and experience of debate” (p. 13). An important starting point for conversation, the resolution helps frame political conversations humanely. It preserves basic means for equality of access to base research and argumentation. Having a year-long stable resolution invites depth of argument and continuously rewards adaptive research once various topics have surfaced through practice or at debate tournaments. As referenced above, the resolution provides a basis for research and discussion. Using the resolution as a starting point, students will debate the same resolution dozens or hundreds of times each year on both the affirmative and negative. This practice, called switch-side debate, establishes the expectation that a student will defend and answer multiple sides of similar arguments throughout a debate season. As a result, this practice increases one’s intellectual flexibility and understanding of multiple sides of hundreds of issues. Galloway (2007), Harrigan (2008), and Mitchell (2010) add to this discussion. Galloway (2007) theorizes the benefits to communication through switch-side debate. In part due to the rules requiring both sides be heard for equal amounts of time combined with the etiquette of listening, flowing, and answering all of an opponent’s argument, debate forces structured dialogue. In such, demands for fairness surface. Galloway advances how demanding dialogical fairness “…takes the form of a demand for equality of voice. Far from being a banal request for links to a disadvantage, fairness is a demand for respect, a demand to be heard, a demand that a voice backed by literally months upon months of preparation, research, and critical thinking not be silenced” (Galloway, 2007, p. 6). Underlying strategic calls for fairness, fairness of equitable debatable ground in switch-side debate demands recognizing a basic humanity in all persons involved. Viewing the first affirmative speech as the invitation to the rest of the debate, Galloway (2007) continues to articulate the academic benefits to switching sides. Theorizing the benefits of taking multiple sides of an issue, even sides of an issue someone does not agree with, Galloway concludes how debate encourages critical thought, meaningful exchange of ideas, and a better defense of one’s own thought since ideas need defending against opposing argumentation. Zwarensteyn, Masters’ Degree in Communications, in 12 Dialogical constraints are key to a productive discussion (Elizabeth, “Context Matters: Recognizing the Effects of Epistemic and Agonistic Contexts in Public Policy Debate,” Issues in Writing Volume 16 Issue 1, Fall 2005, http://search.proquest.com/docview/208162306?pq-origsite=gscholar)//JRom Furthermore, the model suggests that epistemic public debate in a representative democracy may become corrupted when key partisan stakeholders have irreconcilable goals and use deceitful strategies to support their policy goals and their expression of these goals as public reasons. In these instances, an epistemic process may be subverted into an agonistic one, where the context affects the strategies that all stakeholders may adopt and limits resolution of the policy problem on the societal level. For instance, over time if shared education goals prove Giddens, Kennesaw State University professor, in 5 unattainable because of a lack of adequate resources, stakeholders may abandon them for narrower goals designed to help or protect a special interest group rather than the public good. Similarly, in time or in response to new exigencies, agonistic contexts might become transformed to permit epistemic problem solving. For instance, the advent of reliable national and state data about the key causes, effects, transaction costs, and outcomes of civil litigation might dramatically alter debate in the civil justice arena since they would provide a shared basis of fact for all stakeholders to reason from and toward, perhaps, shared public reasons and goals. Anyone involved in such debates, as a participant, stakeholder, or observer, should be aware of the dynamic nature of argumentation in order to understand the potential of a debate, to assess the validity of the public reasons participants offer, and to tailor one's own involvement in it to successfully play one's necessary role. Simply put, writers need to recognize whether a debate is epistemic or agonistic; if they do not understand the difference, they are likely to misjudge the strength of others' arguments and to be naive of the purposes underlying their own claims and evidence. Implications for Teaching Argumentation Although the model is intended to be useful to professional writers in approaching tasks and to rhetorical critics in analyzing texts and debates, perhaps it may also help teachers and students of argumentation. Conventional practice in teaching argumentation is to instruct students about the Toulmin model of argumentation (including claims, warrants, evidence, qualifiers and rebuttals), the three classical appeals (logos, ethos, and pathos), and the common logical fallacies (such as ad hominem, post hoc ergo propter hoc, equivocation, overgeneralization, oversimplification, and others). In addition, some instructors may introduce their students to the concepts of the rhetorical situation, stasis (what question needs to be answered), and/or kairos (the principle of conflict and resolution). But it seems to me that these concepts presuppose an epistemic macrostructure. In other words, the concepts presume that partisan debate participants want to move forward in their deliberation of an issue toward some kind of resolution that will be for the public good and respect the concerns of all stakeholders. In this framework, when participants violate modes of conduct that would enable progress and resolution, for instance when they antagonize their opponents through personal attack or misrepresent facts to deceive an audience, they can be labeled by critics (including teachers and students engaging in classroom analyses of texts) as bad actors, as misinformed participants, or simply as individuals lacking character. less concern for those with other perspectives. But students aware of the difference between agonistic and epistemic argument macrostructures may also realize that the partisan role does more to rally the troops that enable global resolution. And that realization may lead students more readily and more reliably to the insight that while nonpartisan participants exercise a more constrained demeanor in a debate, they may also have more creative roles in identifying pragmatic solutions to policy problems that affect the public good than do narrowly partisan participants. This approach might also provide students more insight into the reasons why some debate participants approach issues agonistically. Instead of teaching a writer's use of logical fallacies in argument as aberrant behavior, instructors could teach it as partisan behavior in an agonistic context, and this approach may help students in several ways. First, as partisans they may engage in writing arguments with more passion and devotion. Also, they may come to see the range of stances, tones, and roles that are available to them, learning that argumentation can be an activity involving care, nuance, subtlety, and, above all, choice. Finally, they may learn that on some occasions accepting the responsibility of the nonpartisan role (which in American society is often an academic or researcher role) has value and may bring individual satisfaction as well as meaningful change. This last outcome has value in itself, but it also has value for students who as junior members of a higher education community are learning about its nature, its discourse conventions, and its role in society. State Debate State can solve Racism, Discrimination, Can lead to progress, etc. Policy action has created positive change—solves for Racism, only our interp accesses this Minkler 12 [Meredith Minkler, Professor of Health and Social Behavior, University of California-Berkeley, Community Organizing and Community Building for Health and Welfare, New Brunswick: Rutgers, 2012, http://prospect.org/article/blackamericas-promised-land-why-i-am-still-racial-optimist]//WB I am hopeful first and foremost because of the predominant trajectory of African Americans—a history that John Hope Franklin framed with the apt title From Slavery to Freedom. In 1860, four million African Americans were enslaved while another half-million were free but devoid of fundamental rights in many of the jurisdictions where they lived. In 1860, the very term “African American” was something of an oxymoron because the Supreme Court had ruled in Dred Scott v. Sandford that no black, free or enslaved, could be a citizen of the United States. But within a decade, the Thirteenth Amendment (1865) abolished slavery, the Fourteenth Amendment (1868) established birthright citizenship and required all states to accord all persons due process and equal protection of the laws, and the Fifteenth Amendment (1870) prohibited states from withholding the right to vote on account of race, color, or previous condition of servitude. People who had been sold on the auction block as youngsters helped to govern their locales as public officials when they were adults. In 1861, Jefferson Davis of Mississippi resigned from the United States Senate to join the Confederate States of America, which he led as president. In 1870, Hiram Revels, the first black member of Congress, occupied the seat that Davis abandoned. The First Reconstruction was overwhelmed by a devastating white supremacist reaction. But the most fundamental reforms it established proved resilient, providing the basis for a Second Reconstruction from the 1950s to the 1970s. During that period, too, the distance traveled by blacks was astonishing. In 1950, segregation was deemed to be consistent with federal constitutional equal protection. No federal law prevented proprietors of hotels, restaurants, and other privately owned public accommodations from engaging in racial discrimination. No federal law prohibited private employers from discriminating on a racial basis against applicants for jobs or current employees. No federal law effectively counteracted racial disenfranchisement. No federal law outlawed racial discrimination in private housing transactions. In contrast, by 1970 federal constitutional law thoroughly repudiated the lie of separate but equal. The 1964 Civil Rights Act forbade racial discrimination in privately owned places of public accommodation and many areas of private employment. The 1965 Voting Rights Act provided the basis for strong prophylactic action against racial exclusion at the ballot box. The 1968 Fair Housing Act addressed racial exclusion in a market that had been zealously insulated against federal regulation. None of these interventions were wholly successful. All were compromised. All occasioned backlash. But the racial situation in 1970 and afterwards was dramatically better than what it had been in 1950 and before. Today, at a moment when progress has stalled, we need to recall how dramatically and unexpectedly conditions sometimes change. Until recently who’d-a thunk it possible for the president to be an African American? In the 1980s, I used to ask law students how long affirmative action programs ought to last. Champions of such programs, seeking to ensure their longevity, would say that affirmative action would be needed until the country elected a black president. That reply would elicit appreciative laughter as listeners supposed that that formula would preserve affirmative action for at least a century. But then along came Barack Obama and with him the remark that soon became a cliché: “I never thought that I’d live to see a black president.” AT: State Bad Their critiques of the state miss the mark—all of their state bad arguments do not make sense—they need to discuss why the state should not be discussed in the debate space Talisse 5—Robert is a Professor of Philosophy at Vanderbilt Philosophy & Social Criticism, 31.4, “Deliberativist responses to activist challenges” http://psc.sagepub.com/content/31/4/423.full.pdf) These two serious activist challenges may be summarized as follows. First, the activist has claimed that political discussion must always take place within the context of existing institutions that due to structural inequality grant to certain individuals the power to set discussion agendas and constrain the kinds of options open for consideration prior to any actual encounter with their deliberative opponents; the deliberative process is in this sense rigged from the start to favor the status quo and disadvantage the agents of change. Second, the activist has argued that political discussion must always take place by means of antecedent ‘discourses’ or vocabularies which establish the conceptual boundaries of the deliberation and hence may themselves be hegemonic or systematically distorting; the deliberative process is hence subject to the distorting influence of ideology at the most fundamental level, and deliberative democrats do not have the resources by which such distortions can be addressed. As they aim to establish that the deliberativist’s program is inconsistent with her own democratic objectives, this pair of charges is, as Young claims, serious (118). However, I contend that the deliberativist has adequate replies to them both.¶ Part of the response to the first challenge is offered by Young herself. The deliberative democrat does not advocate public political discussion only at the level of state policy, and so does not advocate a program that must accept as given existing institutional settings and contexts for public discussion. Rather, the deliberativist promotes an ideal of democratic politics according to which deliberation occurs at all levels of social association, including households, neighborhoods, local organizations, city boards, and the various institutions of civil society. The longrun aim of the deliberative democrat is to cultivate a more deliberative polity, and the deliberativist claims that this task must begin at more local levels and apart from the state and its policies. We may say that deliberativism promotes a ‘decentered’ (Habermas, 1996: 298) view of public deliberation and a ‘pluralistic’ (Benhabib, 2002: 138) model of the public sphere; in other words, the deliberative democrat envisions a ‘multiple, network of many publics and public conversations’ (Benhabib, 1996b: 87). The deliberativist is therefore committed to the creation of ‘an inclusive deliberative setting in which basic social and economic structures can be examined’; these settings ‘for the most part must be outside ongoing settings of official policy discussion’ (115).¶ Although Young characterizes this decentered view of political discourse as requiring that deliberative democrats ‘withdraw’ (115) from ‘existing structural circumstances’ (118), it is unclear that this follows. There certainly is no reason why the deliberativist must choose between engaging arguments within existing deliberative sites and creating new ones that are removed from established institutions. There is no need to accept Young’s dichotomy; the deliberativist holds that work must be done both within existing structures and within new contexts. As Bohman argues,¶ Deliberative politics has no single domain; it includes such diverse activities as formulating and achieving collective goals, making policy decisions and means and ends, resolving conflicts of interest and principle, and solving problems as they emerge in ongoing social life . Public deliberation therefore has to take many forms. (1996: 53)¶ The second challenge requires a detailed response, so let us begin with a closer look at the proposed argument. The activist has moved quickly from the claim that discourses can be systematically distorting to the claim that all political discourse operative in our current contexts is systematically distorting. The conclusion is anonymous, heterogeneous that properly democratic objectives cannot be pursued by deliberative means. The first thing to note is that, as it stands, the conclusion does not follow from the premises; the argument is enthymematic. What is required is the additional premise that the distorting features of discussion cannot be corrected by further discussion. That discussion cannot rehabilitate itself is a crucial principle in the activist’s case, but is nowhere argued.¶ Moreover, the activist has given no arguments to support the claim that present modes of discussion are distorting, and has offered no analysis of how one might detect such distortions and discern their nature.20 Rather than providing a detailed analysis of the phenomenon of systematic distortion, Young provides (in her own voice) two examples of discourses that she claims are hegemonic. First she considers discussions of poverty that presume the adequacy of labor market analyses; second she cites discussions of pollution that presume that modern economies must be based on the burning of fossil-fuels. In neither case does she make explicit what constitutes the distortion. At most, her examples show that some debates are framed in ways that render certain types of proposals ‘out of bounds’. But surely this is the case in any discussion, and it is not clear that it is in itself always a bad thing or even ‘distorting’. Not all discursive exclusions are distortions because the term ‘distortion’ implies that something is being excluded that should be included.¶ Clearly, then, there are some dialectical exclusions that are entirely appropriate. For example, it is a good thing that current discussions of poverty are often cast in terms that render white supremacist ‘solutions’ out of bounds; it is also good that pollution discourses tend to exclude fringe-religious appeals to the cleansing power of mass prayer. This is not to say that opponents of market analyses of poverty are on par with white supremacists or that Greens are comparable to fringe-religious fanatics; it is rather to press for a deeper analysis of the discursive hegemony that the activist claims undermines deliberative democracy. It is not clear that the requested analysis, were it provided, would support the claim that systematic distortions cannot be addressed and remedied within the processes of continuing discourse. There are good reasons to think that continued discussion among persons who are aware of the potentially hegemonic features of discourse can correct the distorting factors that exist and block the generation of new distortions.¶ As Young notes (116), James Bohman (1996: ch. 3) has proposed a model of deliberation that incorporates concerns about distorted communication and other forms of deliberative inequality within a general theory of deliberative democracy; the recent work of Seyla Benhabib (2002) and Robert Goodin (2003: chs 9–11) aims for similar goals. Hence I conclude that, as it stands, the activist’s second argument is incomplete, and as such the force of the difficulty it raises for deliberative democracy is not yet clear. If the objection is to stick, the activist must first provide a more detailed examination of the hegemonic and distorting properties of discourse; he must then show both that prominent modes of discussion operative in our democracy are distorting in important ways and that further discourse cannot remedy these distortions. Total rejection of the institutional logic of the state fails---calculated engagement on matters of critical importance – like FW is key Crenshaw 88 [Kimberle, Law @ UCLA, “RACE, REFORM, AND RETRENCHMENT: TRANSFORMATION AND LEGITIMATION IN ANTIDISCRIMINATION LAW”, 101 Harv. L. Rev. 1331, lexis] Simply critiquing the ideology from without or making demands in language outside the rights discourse would have accomplished little. Rather, Blacks gained by using a powerful combination of direct action, mass protest, and individual acts of resistance, along with appeals to public opinion and the courts couched in the language of the prevailing legal consciousness. The result was a series of ideological and political crises . In these crises, civil rights activists and lawyers induced the federal government to aid Blacks and triggered efforts to legitimate and reinforce the authority of the law in ways that benefited Blacks. Simply insisting that Blacks be integrated or speaking in the language of "needs" would have endangered the lives of those who were already taking risks – and with no reasonable chance of success. President Eisenhower, for example, would not have sent federal troops to Little Rock simply at the behest of protesters demanding that Black schoolchildren receive an equal education. the successful manipulation of legal rhetoric led to a crisis of federal power that ultimately benefited Blacks. Some critics of legal reform movements seem to overlook the fact that state power has made a significant difference – sometimes Instead, between life and death – in the efforts of Black people to transform their world . Attempts to harness the power of the state through the appropriate rhetorical/legal incantations should be appreciated as intensely powerful and calculated political acts. In the context of white supremacy, engaging in rights discourse should be seen as an act of self‐ defense. This was particularly true because the state could not assume a position of neutrality regarding Black people once the movement had mobilized people to challenge the system of oppression; either the coercive mechanism of the state had to be used to support white supremacy, or it had to be used to dismantle it. We know now, with hindsight, that it did both. Blacks did use rights rhetoric to mobilize state power to their benefit against symbolic oppression through formal inequality and, to some extent, against material deprivation in the form of private, informal exclusion of the middle class from jobs and housing. Yet today the same legal reforms play a role in providing an ideological framework that makes the present conditions facing underclass Blacks appear fair and reasonable. The eradication of barriers has created a new dilemma for those victims of racial oppression who are not in a position to benefit from the move to formal equality. The race neutrality of the legal system creates the illusion that racism is no longer the primary factor responsible for the condition of the Black underclass; instead, as we have seen, class disparities appear to be the consequence of individual and group merit within a supposed system of equal opportunity. Moreover, the fact that there are Blacks who are economically successful gives credence both to the assertion that opportunities exits, and to the backlash attitude that Blacks have "gotten too far". Psychologically, for Blacks who have not made it, the lace of an explanation for their underclass status may result in self‐blame and other selfdestructive attitudes. Another consequence of the formal reforms may be the loss of collectivity among Blacks29. The removal of formal barriers created new opportunities for some Blacks that were not shared by various other classes of African‐Americans. As Blacks moved into different spheres, the experience of being Black in America became fragmented and multifaceted, and the different contexts presented opportunities to experience racism in different ways. The social, economic and even residential distance between the various classes may complicate efforts to unite behind issues as a racial group. Although "White Only" signs may have been crude and debilitating, they at least presented a readily discernible target around which to organize. Now, the targets are obscure and diffuse, and this difference may create doubt among some Blacks whether there is difference may create doubt among some Blacks whether Formal equality significantly transformed the Black experience in America. With society's embrace of formal equality came the eradication of symbolic domination and the suppression of white supremacy as the norm of society. Future generations of Black Americans would no longer be explicitly regarded as America's second‐class citizens. Yet the transformation of the oppositional dynamic – achieved through the suppression of there is enough similarity between their life experiences and those of other Blacks to warrant collective political action. racial norms and stereotypes, and the recasting of racial inferiority into assumptions of cultural inferiority – creates several difficulties for the civil rights constituency. The formal barriers, although symbolically significant to all and materially significant to some, will do little to alter the hierarchical relationship between Blacks and whites until the way in which white race consciousness removal of perpetuates norms that legitimate Black subordination is revealed. This is not to say that white norms alone account for the conditions of the Black underclass. It is instead an acknowledgment that, until the distinct racial nature of class ideology is itself revealed and debunked, nothing can be done about the underlying structural problems that account for the disparities. The narrow focus of racial exclusion – that is, the belief that racial exclusion is illegitimate only where the "White Only" signs are explicit – coupled with strong assumptions about equal opportunity, makes it difficult to move the discussion of racism beyond the societal selfsatisfaction engendered by the appearance of Rights have been important. They may have legitimated racial inequality, but they have also been the means by which oppressed groups have secured both entry as formal equals into the dominant order and the survival of their movement in the face of private and state repression. The dual role of legal change creates a dilemma for Black reformers. As long as race consciousness thrives, Blacks will often have to rely on rights neutral norms and formal inclusion. IV. Self‐Conscious Ideological Struggle rhetoric when it is necessary to protect Black interests. The very reforms brought about by appeals to legal ideology, however, seem to undermine the ability to move forward toward a broader vision of racial equality. In the quest for racial justice, winning and losing have been part of the same experience. The Critics are correct in observing that engaging in rights discourse has helped to deradicalize and co‐opt the challenge. Yet they fail to acknowledge the limited range of options presented to Blacks in a context where they were deemed "other", and the unlikelihood that specific demands for inclusion and equality would be heard if articulated in other terms. The abbreviated list of options is itself continent upon the ideological power of white race consciousness and the continuing role of Black Americans as "other". Future efforts to address racial domination, as well as class hierarchy, must consider the continuing ideology of white race consciousness by uncovering the oppositional dynamic and by chipping away at its premises. Central to this task is revealing the contingency of race and exploring the connection between white race consciousness and the other myths that legitimate both class and race hierarchies. Critics and others whose agendas include challenging hierarchy and legitimation must not overlook the importance of revealing the contingency of race. Optimally, the deconstruction of white race consciousness might lead to a liberated future for both Blacks and whites. Yet, until whites recognize the hegemonic function of racism and turn their efforts toward African‐American people must develop pragmatic political strategies – self‐ conscious ideological struggle – to minimize the costs of liberal reform while maximizing its utility. A primary step in engaging in self‐conscious ideological struggle must be to transcend the oppositional dynamic in which Blacks are cast simply and solely as whites' subordinate "other".30 The dual role that rights have played makes strategizing a difficult neutralizing it, task. Black people can afford neither to resign themselves to, nor to attack frontally, the legitimacy and incoherence of the dominant ideology. The subordinate position of Blacks in this society makes it unlikely that African‐ Americans will realize gains through the kind of direct challenge to the legitimacy and incoherence of the dominant ideology. The subordinate position of Blacks in this society makes it unlikely that African‐Americans will realize gains through the kind of direct challenge to the legitimacy of American liberal ideology that is now being waged by Critical scholars. On the other hand, delegitimating race consciousness would be directly relevant to Black needs, and this strategy will sometimes require the pragmatic use of liberal ideology. This vision is consistent with the views forwarded by theoreticians such as Frances Fox Piven and Richard Cloward, Antonio Gramsci, and Roberto Unger. Piven and Cloward observe that oppressed people sometimes advance by creating ideological and political crisis, but that the form of the crisis‐producing challenge must reflect the institutional logic of the system. The use of rights rhetoric during the civil rights movement created such a crisis by presenting and manipulating the dominant ideology in a new and transformative way. Challenges and demands made from outside the institutional logic would have accomplished little because Blacks, as the subordinate "other", were already perceived as being outside the mainstream. The struggle of Blacks, like that of all subordinated groups, is a struggle for inclusion, an attempt to manipulate elements of the dominant ideology to transform the experience of domination. It is a struggle to create a new status quo through the ideological and political tools that are available. Gramsci called this struggle a "War of Position" and he regarded it as the most appropriate strategy for change in Western societies. According to Gramsci, direct challenges to the dominant class accomplish little if ideology plays such a central role in establishing authority that the legitimacy of the dominant regime is not challenged. Joseph Femia, interpreting Gramsci, states that "the dominant ideology in modern capitalist societies is highly institutionalized and widely internalized. It follows that a concentration on frontal attack, on direct assault against the bourgeois state ‘war of the challenge in such societies is to create a counter‐hegemony by maneuvering within and expanding the dominant ideology to embrace the potential for change. Gramsci's vision of ideological struggle is echoed in part by Roberto Unger in his vision of deviationist doctrine. Unger, who represents another strand of the critical approach, argues that, rather than discarding liberal legal maneuver’ can result only in disappointment and defeat"31 Consequently, ideology, we should focus and develop its visionary undercurrents: [T]he struggle over the form of social life, through deviationist doctrine, creates opportunities for experimental revisions of social life in the direction of the ideals we defend. An implication of our ideas is that the elements of a formative institutional or imaginative structure may be replaced piecemeal rather than only all at once .32 Liberal ideology embraces communal and liberating visions along with the legitimating hegemonic visions. Unger, like Gramsci and Piven and Cloward, seems to suggest that the strategy toward a meaningful change depends on skillful use of the liberating potential of dominant ideology. E. Conclusion For Blacks, the task at hand is to devise ways to wage ideological and political struggle while minimizing the costs of engaging in an inherently legitimating discourse. A clearer understanding of the space we occupy in the American political consciousness is a necessary prerequisite to the development of pragmatic strategies for political and economic survival. In this regard, the most serious challenge for Blacks is to minimize the political and cultural cost of engaging in an inevitably co‐optive process in order to secure material benefits. Because our present predicament gives us few options, we must create conditions for the maintenance of a distinct political thought that is informed by the actual conditions of Black people. Unlike the civil rights vision, this new approach should not be defined and thereby limited by the possibilities of dominant political discourse, but should maintain a distinctly progressive outlook that focuses on the needs of the African‐ American community. “State bad” isn't responsive—we just have to defend that discussing the state is good—their ev has to say the discussion is bad Talisse 5—Robert is a Professor of Philosophy at Vanderbilt Philosophy & Social Criticism, 31.4, “Deliberativist responses to activist challenges” http://psc.sagepub.com/content/31/4/423.full.pdf) challenges are focused on the failure of existing political institutions and processes to satisfy the ideals of publicity, accountability, and inclusion (109) that are The first two promoted by the deliberative democrat. First, the activist points to the exclusionary character of existing sites of deliberation, citing the prevalence of structural inequality and power (108). Second, he criticizes recent measures aimed at inclusion for falling ‘far short of providing opportunities for real voice for those less privileged in the social structures’ (112). Insofar as the activist’s criticisms are aimed at the failure of existing institutions to live up to the deliberative ideal, they implicitly accept that ideal. Thus, as Young points out, the deliberativist can agree with the activist that current conditions fall short of the democratic ideal, and can accept the activist’s specific criticisms of the existing order (112). Again, they differ on the issue of means, not ends: the deliberativist holds that processes of continuing public discourse can reveal and remedy the shortcomings of existing institutions and practices whereas the activist doubts that rational discussion can persuade powerful social agents to adopt a more inclusive and democratic mode of politics (112). The deliberativist may further argue that even if the activist’s suspicions regarding the efficacy of political deliberation are granted, these suspicions are not in themselves sufficient grounds for rejecting deliberative democracy. Though not ideal, deliberation may still be the best option available for democracy. Law Good Pragmatic policy-focused legal approach is critical to productive change--K’s abstractions fail William J. Novak 8, Associate Professor of History at the University of Chicago and Research Professor at the American Bar Foundation, “The Myth of the “Weak” American State”, June, http://www.history.ucsb.edu/projects/labor/speakers/documents/TheMythoftheWeakAmericanState.pd f There is an alternative. In the early twentieth century, amid a first wave of nation- state and economic consolidation and assertiveness, American social science generated some fresh ways of looking at power in all its guises—social, economic, political, and legal. Overshadowed to some extent by exuberant bursts of American exceptionalism that greeted confrontations with totalitarianism and then terrorism, the pragmatic, critical, and realistic appraisal of American power is worth recovering. From Lester Frank Ward and John Dewey to Ernst Freund and John Commons to Morris Cohen and Robert Lee Hale, early American socioeconomic theorists developed a critique of a thin, private, and individualistic conception of American liberalism and interrogated the location, organization, and distribution of power in a modernizing United States. All understood the problem of power in America as complex and multifaceted, not simple or onedimensional, especially as it concerned the relationship of state and civil society. Rather than spend endless time debating the proper definition of law or the correct empirical measure of the state, they concentrated instead on detailed investigations of power in action in the everyday practices and policies that constituted American public life. Rather than confine the examination of power to the abstract realm of political theory or the official political acts of elites, electorates, interest groups, or social movements, these analysts instead embraced a more capacious conception of governance as “an activity which is apt to appear whenever men are associated together.”35 More significantly, these political and legal realists never forgot, amid the rhetoric of law and the pious platitudes that routinely flow from American political life, the very real, concrete consequences of the deployment of legal and political power. They never forgot the brutal fact that Robert Cover would later state so provocatively at the start of his article “Violence and the Word” that legal and political interpretation take place “in a field of pain and death.” 36 The real consequences of American state power are all around us. In a democratic republic, where force should always be on the side of the governed, writing the history of that power has never been more urgent. No alternative to the law/legal system---other ideas bring more inequality and abuse Jerold S. Auerbach 83, Professor of History at Wellesley, “Justice Without Law?”, 1983, p. 144-146 As cynicism about the legal system increases, so does enthusiasm for alternative disputesettlement institutions. The search for alternatives accelerates, as Richard Abel has suggested, "when some fairly powerful interest is threatened by an increase in the number or magnitude of legal rights.*'6 Alternatives are designed to provide a safety valve, to siphon discontent from courts. With the danger of political confrontation reduced, the ruling power of legal institutions is preserved, and the stability of the social system reinforced. Not incidentally, alternatives prevent the use of courts for redistributive purposes in the interest of equality, by consigning the rights of disadvantaged citizens to institutions with minimal power to enforce or protect them . It is, therefore, necessary to beware of the seductive appeal of alternative institutions . They may deflect energy from political organization by groups of people with common grievances; or discourage effective litigation strategies that could provide substantial benefits. They may, in the end, create a two-track justice system that dispenses informal "justice" to poor people with "small" claims and "minor" disputes, who cannot afford legal services, and who are denied access to courts. (Bar associations do not recommend that corporate law firms divert their clients to mediation, or that business deductions for legal expenses—a gigantic government subsidy for litigation—be eliminated.) Justice according to law will be reserved for the affluent, hardly a novel development in American history but one that needs little encouragement from the spread of alternative dispute-settlement institutions.¶ It is social context and political choice that determine whether courts, or alternative institutions, can render justice more or less accessible—and to whom. Both can be discretionary, arbitrary, domineering—and unjust. Law can symbolize justice, or conceal repression. It can reduce exploitation, or facilitate it. It can prohibit the abuse of power, or disguise abuse in procedural forms. It can promote equality, or sustain inequality. Despite the resiliency and power of law, it seems unable to eradicate the tension between legality and justice: even in a society of (legal) equals, some still remain more equal than others. But diversion from the legal system is likely to accentuate that inequality . Without legal power the imbalance between aggrieved individuals and corporations, or government agencies, cannot be redressed . In American society , as Laura Nader has observed, " disputing without the force of law ... [is| doomed to fail ."7 Instructive examples document the deleterious effect of coerced informality (even if others demonstrate the creative possibilities of indigenous experimentation). Freed slaves after the Civil War and factory workers at the turn of the century, like inner-city poor people now, have all been assigned places in informal proceedings that offer substantially weaker safeguards than law can provide. Legal institutions may not provide equal justice under law, but in a society ruled by law it is their responsibility.¶ It is chimerical to believe that mediation or arbitration can now accomplish what law seems powerless to achieve . The American deification of individual rights requires an accessible legal system for their protection. Understandably, diminished faith in its capacities will encourage the yearning for alternatives. But the rhetoric of "community" and "justice" should not be permitted to conceal the deterioration of community life and the unraveling of substantive notions of justice that has accompanied its demise. There is every reason why the values that historically are associated with informal justice should remain compelling: especially the preference for trust, harmony, and reciprocity within a communal setting. These are not, however, the values that American society encourages or sustains; in their absence there is no effective alternative to legal institutions.¶ The quest for community may indeed be "timeless and universal."8 In this century, however, the communitarian search for justice without law has deteriorated beyond recognition into a stunted off-shoot of the legal system. The historical progression is clear: from community justice without formal legal institutions to the rule of law, all too often without justice. But injustice without law is an even worse possibility, which misguided enthusiasm for alternative dispute settlement now seems likely to encourage. Our legal culture too accurately expresses the individualistic and materialistic values that most Americans deeply cherish to inspire optimism about the imminent restoration of communitarian purpose. For law to be less conspicuous Americans would have to moderate their expansive freedom to compete, to acquire, and to possess, while simultaneously elevating shared responsibilities above individual rights. That is an unlikely prospect unless Americans become, in effect, un-American . Until then, the pursuit of justice without law does incalculable harm to the prospect of equal justice. Legal reforms restrain the cycle of violence and prevent error replication Colm O’Cinneide 8, Senior Lecturer in Law at University College London, “Strapped to the Mast: The Siren Song of Dreadful Necessity, the United Kingdom Human Rights Act and the Terrorist Threat,” Ch 15 in Fresh Perspectives on the ‘War on Terror,’ ed. Miriam Gani and Penelope Mathew, http://epress.anu.edu.au/war_terror/mobile_devices/ch15s07.html This ‘symbiotic’ relationship between counter-terrorism measures and political violence, and the apparently inevitable negative impact of the use of emergency powers upon ‘target’ communities, would indicate that it makes sense to be very cautious in the use of such powers. However, the impact on individuals and ‘target’ communities can be too easily disregarded when set against the apparent demands of the greater good. Justice Jackson’s famous quote in Terminiello v Chicago [111] that the United States Bill of Rights should not be turned into a ‘suicide pact’ has considerable resonance in times of crisis, and often is used as a catch-all response to the ‘bleatings’ of civil libertarians.[112] The structural factors discussed above that appear to drive the response of successive UK governments to terrorist acts seem to invariably result in a depressing repetition of mistakes .¶ However, certain legal processes appear to have some capacity to slow down the excesses of the counter-terrorism cycle. What is becoming apparent in the UK context since 9/11 is that there are factors at play this time round that were not in play in the early years of the Northern Irish crisis. A series of parliamentary, judicial and transnational mechanisms are now in place that appear to have some moderate ‘dampening’ effect on the application of emergency powers.¶ This phrase ‘dampening’ is borrowed from Campbell and Connolly, who have recently suggested that law can play a ‘dampening’ role on the progression of the counter-terrorism cycle before it reaches its end. Legal processes can provide an avenue of political opportunity and mobilisation in their own right, whereby the ‘relatively autonomous’ framework of a legal system can be used to moderate the impact of the cycle of repression and backlash. They also suggest that this ‘dampening’ effect can ‘re-frame’ conflicts in a manner that shifts perceptions about the need for the use of violence or extreme state repression.[113] State responses that have been subject to this dampening effect may have more legitimacy and generate less repression: the need for mobilisation in response may therefore also be diluted. Decision Making It Outweighs Decision Making outweighs any of their impacts—it is the key factor to distinguish what is policy vs critical—it does not matter if we are going to be policymakers in the future—we know that we have the greatest skill in the world, decision making—this card WRECKS Strait and Wallace 7—L.Paul, Ph. D in communications at the University of Southern California, use to teach at George Mason University, AND Brett was a debater at George Washington University (“The Scope of Negative Fiat and the Logic of Decision Making” 2007 http://groups.wfu.edu/debate/MiscSites/DRGArticles/2007/The%20Scope%20of%20Negative%20Fiat%20and%20the%20Logic% 20of%20Decision%20Making.pdf Pg. A2)//JLee More to the point, debate certainly helps teach a lot of skills, yet we believe that the way policy debate participation encourages you to think is the most valuable educational benefit, because how someone makes decisions determines how they will employ the rest of their abilities, including the research and communication skills that debate builds. Plenty of debate theory articles have explained either the value of debate, or the way in which alternate actor strategies are detrimental to real-world education, but none so far have attempted to tie these concepts together. We will now explain how decision-making skill development is the foremost value of policy debate and how this benefit is the decision-rule to resolving all theoretical discussions about negative fiat. Why debate? Some do it for scholarships, some do it for social purposes, and many just believe it is fun. These are certainly all relevant considerations when making the decision to join the debate team, but as debate theorists they aren’t the focus of our concern. Our concern is finding a framework for debate that educates the largest quantity of students with the highest quality of skills, while at the same time preserving competitive equity . The ability to make decisions deriving from discussions, argumentation or debate, is the key skill . It is the one thing every single one of us will do every day of our lives besides breathing. Decisionmaking transcends boundaries between categories of learning like “policy education” and “kritik education,” it makes irrelevant considerations of whether we will eventually be policymakers, and it transcends questions of what substantive content a debate round should contain. The implication for this analysis is that the critical thinking and argumentative skills offered by real-world decision-making are comparatively greater than any educational disadvantage weighed against them. It is the skills we learn, not the content of our arguments, that can best improve all of our lives. While policy comparison skills are going to be learned through debate in one way or another, those skills are useless if they are not grounded in the kind of logic actually used to make decisions. The academic studies and research supporting this position are numerous. Richard Fulkerson (1996) explains that “argumentation…is the chief cognitive activity by which a democracy, a field of study, a corporation, or a committee functions. . . And it is vitally important that high school and college students learn both to argue well and to critique the arguments of others” (p. 16). Stuart Yeh (1998) comes to the conclusion that debate allows even cultural minority students to “identify an issue, consider different views, form and defend a viewpoint, and consider and respond to counterarguments…The ability to write effective arguments influences grades, academic success, and preparation for college and employment” (p. 49).Certainly, these are all reasons why debate and argumentation themselves are valuable, so why is real world decision-making critical to argumentative thinking? Although people might occasionally think about problems from the position of an ideal decisionmaker (c.f. Ulrich, 1981, quoted in Korcok, 2001), in debate we should be concerned with what type of argumentative thinking is the most relevant to real-world intelligence and the decisions that people make every day in their lives, not academic trivialities. It is precisely because it is rooted inreal-world logic that argumentative thinking has value. Deanna Kuhn’s research in “Thinking as Argument” explains this by stating that “no other kind of thinking matters more-or contributes more to the quality and fulfillment of people’s lives, both individually and collectively” (p. 156). Roleplaying Simulation Good Simulations are good – less resources but effective learning Badiee and Kaurman 6/25 (Farnaz Badiee – Instructional Designer at the Center for Teaching, Learning, and Technology at the University of British Columbia and David Kaufman – professor at Simon Fraser University. “Design Evaluation of a Simulation for Teacher Education” – published online 6/25/15. Sage Journals. P.1 Accessed 6/26/15. http://sgo.sagepub.com/content/5/2/2158244015592454.article-info) dortiz Simulation techniques have been used as training and feedback tools for many years in occupations such as medicine, aviation, military training, and large-scale investment where real-world practice is dangerous, costly, or difficult to organize (for example, see Drews & Backdash, 2013). In pre-service teacher education, classroom simulations can help pre-service teachers to translate their theoretical knowledge into action through repeated trials without harming vulnerable students, and they can provide more practice time and diversity than limited live practicum sessions (Carrington, Kervin, & Ferry, 2011; Hixon & So, 2009). One such simulation is simSchool (www.simschool.org), designed to provide teaching skills practice in a simulated classroom with a variety of students, each with an individual personality and learning needs. simSchool has been shown in several studies to have potential as a practice and learning tool for pre-service teachers (Badiee & Kaufman, 2014; Christensen, Knezek, Tyler-Wood, & Gibson, 2011; Gibson, 2007). Although simSchool has been under development for more than 10 years (Gibson & Halverson, 2004), very little published research has addressed its design as an instructional tool. To address this gap, the current study evaluated the design of simSchool (v.1) from the perspective of its target users, pre-service teachers, providing both quantitative and qualitative evidence of its strengths, weaknesses, and areas for improvement. Simulation is an effective way to learn – mimics real life with no real harms Badiee and Kaurman 6/25 (Farnaz Badiee – Instructional Designer at the Center for Teaching, Learning, and Technology at the University of British Columbia and David Kaufman – professor at Simon Fraser University. “Design Evaluation of a Simulation for Teacher Education” – published online 6/25/25. Sage Journals. P.1 Accessed 6/26/15. http://sgo.sagepub.com/content/5/2/2158244015592454.article-info) dortiz Classroom simulations are starting to offer the possibility of enhancing the practicum by providing new opportunities for pre-service teachers to practice their skills. A simulation is a simplified but accurate, valid, and dynamic model of reality implemented as a system (Sauvé, Renaud, Kaufman, & Marquis, 2007). R. D. Duke (1980), the founder of simulation and gaming as a scientific discipline, noted that the meaning of “to simulate” stems from the Latin simulare, “to imitate,” and defined it as “a conscious endeavor to reproduce the central characteristics of a system in order to understand, experiment with, and/or predict the behavior of that system” (cited in Duke & Geurts, 2004, Section 1.5.2). Simulation involves play, exploration, and discovery, all elements of learning (Huizinga, 1938/1955). It has a long history in adult education, initially in the form of abstract representations using physical components such as paper and pencil or playing boards and, more recently, in many types of computer-based virtual environments (Ramsey, 2000). Simulations are distinguished from games in that they do not involve explicit competition; instead of trying to “win,” simulation participants take on roles, try out actions, see the results, and try new actions without causing real-life harm. Simulations, when paired with reflection, offer the possibility of experiential learning (Dewey, 1938; Kolb, 1984; Lyons, 2012; Ulrich, 1997). Dieker, Rodriguez, Lignugaris/ Kraft, Hynes, and Hughes (2014) pointed out that an effective simulation produces a sense of realism that leads the user to regard the simulated world as real in some sense: These environments must provide a personalized experience that each teacher believes is real (i.e., the teacher “suspends his/ her disbelief”). At the same time, the teacher must feel a sense of personal responsibility for improving his or her practice grounded in a process of critical self-reflection. (p. 22) Suspension of disbelief and this sense of personal responsibility work together to engage the learner in the simulation process so that it becomes a “live” experience; feedback and reflection complete a cycle so that the learner can conceptualize and ultimately apply the new learning (Kolb, 1984). Activism Our Interp Solves Our interpretation creates pragmatic political engagement—a focus on policy is necessary to learn the pragmatic details—debating without this is a form of spectatorship that makes it impossible to reform institutions—our framework is key to access activism—solves the aff McClean 1—David E., Ph. D in Philosophy (“The Cultural Left and the Limits of Social Hope” 2001 http://www.americanphilosophy.org/archives/past_conference_programs/pc2001/Discussion%20papers/david_mcclean.htm0//JLee Or we might take Foucault who, at best, has provided us with what may reasonably be described as a very long and eccentric footnote to Nietzsche (I have once been accused, by a Foucaltian true believer, of "gelding" Foucault with other similar remarks). Foucault, who has provided the Left of the late 1960s through the present with such notions as "governmentality," "Limit," "archeology," "discourse" "power" and "ethics," creating or redefining their meanings, has made it over abundantly clear that all of our moralities and practices are the successors of previous ones which derive from certain configurations of savoir and connaisance arising from or created by, respectively, the discourses of the various scientific schools. But I have not yet found in anything Foucault wrote or said how such observations may be translated into a political movement or hammered into a political document or theory (let alone public policies) that can be justified or founded on more than an arbitrary aesthetic experimentalism. In fact, Foucault would have shuddered if any one ever did, since he thought that anything as grand as a movement went far beyond what he thought appropriate. This leads me to mildly rehabilitate Habermas, for at least he has been useful in exposing Foucault's shortcomings in this regard, just as he has been useful in exposing the shortcomings of others enamored with the abstractions of various Marxian-Freudian social critiques. Yet for some reason, at least partially explicated in Richard Rorty's Achieving Our Country, a book that I think is long overdue, leftist critics continue to cite and refer to the eccentric and often a priori ruminations of people like those just mentioned, and a litany of others including Derrida, Deleuze, Lyotard, Jameson, and Lacan, who are to me hugely more irrelevant than Habermas in their narrative attempts to suggest policy prescriptions (when they actually do suggest them) aimed at curing the ills of homelessness, poverty, market greed, national belligerence and racism. I would like to suggest that it is time for American social critics who are enamored with this group, those who actually want to be relevant, to recognize that they have a disease, and a disease regarding which I myself must remember to stay faithful to my own twelve step program of recovery. The disease is the need for elaborate theoretical "remedies" wrapped in neological and multi-syllabic jargon. These elaborate theoretical remedies are more "interesting," to be sure, than the pragmatically settled questions about what shape democracy should take in various contexts, or whether private property should be protected by the state, or regarding our basic human nature (described, if not defined (heaven forbid!), in such statements as "We don't like to starve" and "We like to speak our minds without fear of death" and "We like to keep our children safe from poverty"). As Rorty puts it, "When one of today's academic leftists says that some topic has been 'inadequately theorized,' you can be pretty certain that he or she is going to drag in either philosophy of These futile attempts to philosophize one's way into political relevance are a symptom of what happens when a Left retreats from activism and adopts a spectatorial approach to the problems of its country. Disengagement from practice produces theoretical hallucinations"(italics mine).(1) Or as John Dewey put it in his The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy, "I believe that language, or Lacanian psychoanalysis, or some neo-Marxist version of economic determinism. . . . philosophy in America will be lost between chewing a historical cud long since reduced to woody fiber, or an apologetics for lost causes, . . . . or a scholastic, schematic formalism, unless it can somehow bring to consciousness America's own needs and its own implicit principle of successful action." Those who suffer or have suffered from this disease Rorty refers to as the Cultural Left, which left is juxtaposed to the Political Left that Rorty prefers and prefers for good reason. Another attribute of the Cultural Left is that its members fancy themselves pure culture critics who view the successes of America and the West, rather than some of the barbarous methods for achieving those successes, as mostly evil, and who view anything like national pride as equally evil even when that pride is tempered with the knowledge and admission of the nation's shortcomings. In other words, the Cultural Left, in this country, too often dismiss American society as beyond reform and redemption. And Rorty correctly argues that this is a disastrous conclusion, i.e. disastrous for the Cultural Left. I think it may also be disastrous for our social hopes, as I will explain. Leftist American culture critics might put their considerable talents to better use if they bury some of their cynicism about America's social and political prospects and help forge public and political possibilities in a spirit of determination to, indeed, achieve our country - the country of Jefferson and King; the country of John Dewey and Malcom X; the country of Franklin Roosevelt and Bayard Rustin, and of the later George Wallace and the later Barry Goldwater. To invoke the words of King, and with reference to the American society, the time is always ripe to seize the opportunity to help create the "beloved community," one woven with the thread of agape into a conceptually single yet diverse tapestry that shoots for nothing less than a true intra-American cosmopolitan ethos, one wherein both same sex unions and faith-based initiatives will be able to be part of the same social reality, one wherein business interests and the university are not seen as belonging to two separate galaxies but as part of the same answer to the threat of social and ethical nihilism. We who fancy ourselves philosophers would do well to create from within ourselves and from within our ranks a new kind of public intellectual who has both a hungry theoretical mind and who is yet capable of seeing the need to move past high theory to other important questions that are less bedazzling and "interesting" but more important to the prospect of our flourishing - questions such as "How is it possible to develop a citizenry that cherishes a certain hexis, one which prizes the character of the Samaritan on the road to Jericho almost more than any other?" or "How can we square the political dogma that undergirds the fantasy of a missile defense system with the need to treat America as but one member in a community of nations under a "law of peoples?" The new public philosopher might seek to understand labor law and military and trade theory and doctrine as much as theories of surplus value; the logic of international markets and trade agreements as much as critiques of commodification, and the politics of complexity as much as the politics of power (all of which can still be done from our arm chairs.) This means going down deep into the guts of our quotidian social institutions, into the grimy pragmatic details where intellectuals are loathe to dwell but where the officers and bureaucrats of those institutions take difficult and often unpleasant, imperfect decisions that affect other peoples' lives, and it means making honest attempts to truly understand how those institutions actually function in the actual world before howling for their overthrow commences. This might help keep us from being slapped down in debates by true policy pros who actually know what they are talking about but who lack awareness of the dogmatic assumptions from which they proceed, and who have not yet found a good reason to listen to jargon-riddled lectures from philosophers and culture critics with their snobish disrespect for the so-called "managerial class." Activism Fails The vast majority of the debate community, including everyone in this room is aware of the myth—orientation towards a goal without concrete policy ensures failure Bryant 12 [Levi, Critique of the Academic Left, http://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2012/11/11/underpants-gnomes-acritique-of-the-academic-left/] I must be in a mood today– half irritated, half amused –because I find myself ranting. Of course, that’s not entirely unusual. So this afternoon I came across a post by a friend quoting something discussing the environmental movement that pushed all the right button. As the post read,¶ For mainstream environmentalism– conservationism, green consumerism, and resource management –humans are conceptually separated out of nature and mythically placed in privileged positions of authority and control over ecological communities and their nonhuman constituents. What emerges is the fiction of a marketplace of ‘raw materials’ and ‘resources’ through which human-centered wants, constructed as needs, might be satisfied. The mainstream narratives are replete with such metaphors [carbon trading!]. Natural complexity,, mutuality, and diversity are rendered virtually meaningless given discursive parameters that reduce nature to discrete units of exchange measuring extractive capacities. Jeff Shantz, “Green Syndicalism” ¶ While finding I can’t say that I see many environmentalists treating nature and culture as distinct or suggesting that we’re sovereigns of nature –I do agree that we conceive much of our elements this description perplexing– relationship to the natural world in economic terms (not a surprise that capitalism is today a universal). This, however, is not what bothers me What I wonder is just what we’re supposed to do even if all of this is true? What, given existing conditions, are we to do if all of this is right? At least green consumerism, conservation, resource management, and things like carbon trading are engaging in activities that are making real differences. From this passage– and maybe the entire text would about this passage.¶ disabuse me of this conclusion –it sounds like we are to reject all of these interventions because they remain tied to a capitalist model of production that the author (and myself) find abhorrent. The idea seems to be that if we endorse these things we are tainting our hands and would therefore do well to reject them altogether.¶ The problem as I see it is that this is the worst sort of abstraction (in the Marxist sense) and wishful thinking. Within a Marxo-Hegelian context, a thought is abstract when it ignores all of the mediations in which a thing is embedded. For example, I understand a robust tree abstractly when I attribute its robustness, say, to its genetics alone, ignoring the complex relations to its soil, the air, sunshine, rainfall, etc., that also allowed it to grow robustly in this way. This is the sort of critique we’re always leveling against the neoliberals. They are abstract thinkers. In their doxa that individuals are entirely responsible for themselves and that they completely make themselves by pulling themselves up by their bootstraps, neoliberals ignore all the mediations belonging to the social and material context in which human beings develop that play a role in determining the vectors of their life. They ignore, for example, that George W. Bush grew up in a family that was highly connected to the world of business and government and that this gave him opportunities that someone living in a remote region of Alaska in a very different material infrastructure and set of family relations does not have. To think concretely is to engage in a cartography of these mediations, a mapping of these networks, from circumstance to circumstance (what I Unfortunately, the academic left falls prey to its own form of abstraction. It’s good at carrying out critiques that denounce various social formations, yet very poor at proposing any sort of realistic constructions of alternatives. This because it thinks abstractly in its own way, ignoring how networks, assemblages, structures, or regimes of attraction would have to be remade to create a workable alternative. Here I’m reminded by the “underpants gnomes” depicted in South Park:¶ The underpants call an “onto-cartography”). It is to map assemblages, networks, or ecologies in the constitution of entities. ¶ gnomes have a plan for achieving profit that goes like this:¶ Phase 1: Collect Underpants¶ Phase 2: ?¶ Phase 3: Profit!¶ They even have a catchy song to go with their work:¶ Well this is sadly how it often is with the Our plan seems to be as follows:¶ Phase 1: Ultra-Radical Critique¶ Phase 2: ?¶ Phase 3: Revolution and complete social academic left. transformation!¶ Our problem is that we seem perpetually stuck at phase 1 without ever explaining what is to be done at phase 2. Often the critiques articulated at phase 1 are right, but there are nonetheless all sorts of problems with those critiques nonetheless. In order to reach phase 3, we have to produce new collectives. In order for new collectives to be produced, people need to be able to hear and understand the critiques developed at phase 1. Yet this is where everything begins to fall apart. Even though these critiques are often right, we express them in ways that only an academic with a PhD in critical theory and post-structural theory can understand. How exactly is Adorno to produce an effect in the world if only PhD’s in the humanities can understand him? Who are these things for? We seem to always ignore these things and then look down our noses with disdain at the Naomi Kleins and David Graebers of the world. To make matters worse, we publish our work in expensive academic journals that only give our talks at expensive hotels at academic conferences attended only by other academics. Again, who are these things for? Is it an accident that so many activists look away from these things with contempt, thinking their more about an academic industry and tenure, than producing change in the world? If a tree falls in a forest and no one is there to hear it, it doesn’t make a sound! Seriously dudes and dudettes, what are you doing?¶ But finally, and worst of all, us Marxists and anarchists all too universities can afford, with presses that don’t have a wide distribution, and often act like assholes. We denounce others, we condemn them, we berate them for not engaging with the questions we want to engage with, and we vilify them when they don’t embrace every bit of the doxa that we endorse. We are every bit as off-putting and unpleasant as the fundamentalist minister or the priest of the inquisition (have people yet understood that Deleuze and Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus was a critique of the French communist party system and the Stalinist party system, and the horrific passions that arise out of parties and identifications in general?). This type of is the greatest friend of the reactionary and capitalist because they do more to drive people into the embrace of reigning ideology than to undermine reigning ideology. These are the people that keep Rush Limbaugh in business. Well done!¶ But this isn’t where our most serious shortcomings lie. Our most serious shortcomings are to be found at phase 2. We almost never make concrete proposals for how things ought to be restructured, for what new material infrastructures and semiotic fields need to be produced, and when we do, our critique-intoxicated cynics and skeptics “revolutionary” immediately jump in with an analysis of all the ways in which these things contain dirty secrets, ugly motives, and are doomed to fail. How, I wonder, are we to do anything at all when we have no concrete proposals? We live on a planet of 6 billion people. These 6 billion people are dependent on a certain network of production and distribution to meet the needs of their consumption. That network of production and distribution does involve the extraction of resources, the production of food, the maintenance of paths of transit and communication, the disposal of waste, the building of shelters, the distribution of medicines, etc., etc., etc.¶ What are your proposals? How will you meet these problems? How will you navigate the existing mediations or semiotic and material features of infrastructure? Marx and Lenin had proposals. Do you? Have you even explored the cartography of the problem? Today we are so intellectually bankrupt on these points that we even have theorists speaking of events and acts and talking about a return to the old socialist party systems, ignoring the horror they generated, their failures, and not even proposing ways of avoiding the repetition of these horrors in a new system of organization. Who among our critical theorists is thinking seriously about how to build a distribution and production system that is responsive to the needs of global consumption, avoiding the problems of planned economy, ie., who is doing this in a way that gets notice in our circles? Who is addressing the problems of micro-fascism that arise with party systems (there’s a reason that it was the Negri & Hardt contingent, not the Badiou contingent that has been the heart of the occupy movement). At least the ecologists are thinking about these things in these terms because, well, they think ecologically. Sadly we need something more, a melding of the ecologists, the Marxists, and the anarchists. We’re not getting it yet though, as far as I can tell. Indeed, folks seem attracted to yet another critical paradigm, Laruelle. ¶ I would love, just for a moment, to hear a radical environmentalist talk about his ideal high school that would be academically sound. How would he provide for the energy needs of that school? How would he meet building codes in an environmentally sound way? How would she provide food for the students? What would be her plan for waste disposal? And most importantly, how would she navigate the school board, the state legislature, the federal government, and all the families of these students? What is your plan? What is your alternative? I think there are alternatives. I saw one that approached an alternative in Rotterdam. If you want to make a truly revolutionary contribution, this is where you should start. Why should anyone even bother listening to you if you aren’t proposing real plans? But we haven’t even gotten to that point. Instead we’re like underpants gnomes, saying “revolution is the answer!” without addressing any of the infrastructural questions of just how revolution is to be produced, what alternatives it would offer, and how we would concretely go about building those alternatives. Masturbation.¶ “Underpants gnome” deserves to be a category in critical theory; a sort of synonym for selfcongratulatory masturbation. We need less critique not because critique isn’t important or necessary– it is –but because we know the critiques, we know the problems. We’re intoxicated with critique because it’s easy and safe. We best every opponent with critique. We occupy a position of moral superiority with critique. But do we really do anything with critique? What we need today, more than ever, is composition or carpentry. Everyone knows something is wrong. Everyone knows this system is destructive and stacked against them. Even the Tea Party knows something is wrong with the economic system, despite having the wrong economic theory. None of us, however, are proposing alternatives. Instead we prefer to shout and denounce. Good luck with that. Resistance Pedagogy Fails Rothkopf 2013 – taught international affairs and national security studies at Columbia University's School of International and Public Affairs and Georgetown's School of Foreign Service, editor-at-large of Foreign Policy, visiting scholar at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace where he chairs the Carnegie Economic Strategy Roundtable, Deputy Under Secretary of Commerce for International Trade Policy (7/1, David, Foreign Policy, “You Say You Want a Revolution?”, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2013/07/01/you_say_you_want_a_revolution_street_protests?page=full) Few things can be as inspiring — or misleading — as the sight of millions of people gathered in protest. From Egypt (again) to Turkey to Brazil, we have recently seen stirring displays of people power, prompting commentators to suggest (again) that we are living in the new 1848 — an era of discontent in which the world’s emergent middle classes are finding their voices. Putting aside the fact that many of those protesting in the Arab world and in other regions rattled recently by civil unrest are not yet middle class by any reasonable definition, the analogy holds in one particularly important respect: The revolutions of 1848 failed to produce real, immediate change. They upset the establishment to be sure, and they had longer- term consequences that should not be discounted. But they also frittered out or were quashed for an important reason: The revolutionaries were better at organizing protests than they were at institutionalizing their movements or creating, cultivating, and empowering leaders who could master existing institutions. The genius of the American Revolution was that its leaders were good not only at promoting upheaval, but also at creating mechanisms to foster that upheaval over several years (a Continental Congress, a Continental Army). And then, once victory had been achieved, they created a constitutional government that protected itself while enshrining the principles they had fought for in a system that would both protect those principles and resist the efforts of counterforces to reassert themselves. The system allowed for pluralistic expression of views and smooth transitions among political groups within the society. In other words, the system preserved and was actually sustained by the energy of the revolution. Look at some of the recent outpourings of public discontent that have captured our imaginations in the past couple of decades. Tiananmen Square. The uprisings that brought down the Soviet Union. Iran’s Green Revolution. Tahrir Square. Revolutions in Libya, Tunisia, and elsewhere in the Arab world. Taksim Square. In each case, even where revolutions have brought seeming change, the protesters were hardly among the greatest beneficiaries of the outcomes. There were really two kinds of outcomes. In the first, there was precious little change at all — as in the case of China, Iran, or, to date, Turkey. In the second, the change shifted power from one entrenched elite to another: Russia may not be communist, but it is run by a former KGB officer in a very undemocratic way; in Egypt, the Muslim Brotherhood sought to fill the void created when Hosni Mubarak was pushed out, and if the current protests there play out, expect the military to resume primary control of the state, reversing the "reforms" demanded by President Mohamed Morsy. Their notion of resistance masks state power—they’re just an illusion of change and empowerment—they make the problem worse and instill an adaptive politics of being and effaces the institutional constraints that reproduce structural violence Brown 95 [prof at UC Berkeley, Wendy, States of Injury, 21-3] For some, fueled by opprobrium toward regulatory norms or other mo- dalities of domination, the language of "resistance" has taken up the ground vacated by a more expansive practice of freedom. For others, it is the discourse of “empowerment” that carries the ghost of freedom's valence 22 . Yet as many have noted, insofar as resistance is an effect of the regime it opposes on the one hand, and insofar as its practitioners often seek to void it of normativity to differentiate it from the (regulatory) nature of what it opposes on the other, it is at best politically rebellious; at worst, politically amorphous. Resistance stands against, not for; it is re-action to domination, rarely willing to admit to a desire for it, and it is neutral with regard to possible political direction. Resistance is in no way constrained to a radical or emancipatory aim. a fact that emerges clearly as soon as one analogizes Foucault's notion of resistance to its companion terms in Freud or Nietzsche. Yet in some ways this point is less a critique of Foucault, who especially in his later years made clear that his political commitments were not identical with his theoretical ones (and un- apologetically revised the latter), than a sign of his misappropriation. For Foucault, resistance marks the presence of power and expands our under- standing of its mechanics, but it is in this regard an analytical strategy rather than an expressly political one. "Where there is power, there is resistance, and yet. or rather consequently, this resistance is never in a position of exteriority to power. . . . (T]he strictly relational character of power relationships . . . depends upon a multiplicity of points of resis- tance: these play the role of adversary, target, support, or handle in power relations.*39 This appreciation of the extent to which resistance is by no means inherently subversive of power also reminds us that it is only by recourse to a very non-Foucaultian moral evaluation of power as bad or that which is to be overcome that it is possible to equate resistance with that which is good, progressive, or seeking an end to domination. If popular and academic notions of resistance attach, however weakly at times, to a tradition of protest, the other contemporary substitute for a discourse of freedom—“empowerment”—would seem to correspond more closely to a tradition of idealist reconciliation. The language of resistance implicitly acknowledges the extent to which protest always transpires inside the regime; “empowerment,” in contrast, registers the possibility of generating one’s capacities, one’s “self-esteem,” one’s life course, without capitulating to constraints by particular regimes of power. But in so doing, contemporary discourses of empowerment too often signal an oddly adaptive and harmonious relationship with domination insofar as they locate an individual’s sense of worth and capacity in the register of individual feelings, a register implicitly located on some- thing of an other worldly plane vis-a-vis social and political power. In this regard, despite its apparent locution of resistance to subjection, contem- porary discourses of empowerment partake strongly of liberal solipsism—the radical decontextualization of the subject characteristic of 23 liberal discourse that is key to the fictional sovereign individualism of liberalism. Moreover, in its almost exclusive focus on subjects’ emotionalbearing and self-regard, empowerment is a formulation that converges with a regime’s own legitimacy needs in masking the power of the regime. This is not to suggest that talk of empowerment is always only illusion or delusion. It is to argue, rather, that while the notion of empowerment articulates that feature of freedom concerned with action, with being more than the consumer subject figured in discourses of rights and eco- nomic democracy, contemporary deployments of that notion also draw so heavily on an undeconstructed subjectivity that they risk establishing a wide chasm between the (experience of) empowerment and an actual capacity to shape the terms of political, social, or economic life. Indeed, the possibility that one can “feel empowered” without being so forms an important element of legitimacy for the antidemocratic dimensions of liberalism. Squo activism fails – too dependent on uncommitted slacktivists McCafferty, freelance writer for Baseline Magazine, in 11 (Dennis, “Activism Vs. Slacktivism,” Communications of the ACM, Vol. 54 No. 12, published December 2011, accessed 7-5-15, http://cacm.acm.org/magazines/2011/12/142536-activism-vsslacktivism/fulltext; JRom) The upshot is no matter what your cause is, you can find a great way to connect these days. Activists are making full use of blogs, social media sites, mobile apps, and other tools to promote their message and gain support. Nothing grabs the heartstrings like video, and participants are producing streaming content to take advantage of this. It makes one think of how effective technology could have been through history. Consider how the U.S. founding fathers would have tweeted Paul Revere's famous cry as "Brits R Coming," post real-time video of his nighttime ride on Facebook, and solicit the French and other sympathetic European supporters for financial and participatory support through Face-book, Kickstarter, and other sites. Yet, while no one disputes that online initiatives like these draw greater attention to a cause, opinion varies with respect to whether they make a significant, lasting impact. A number of respected thinkers say technology does not really advance activism to achieve its most critical goals: to change the hearts and minds of the public, and effect real change. On the other side of the debate are activists and other influencers who counter that the impact on hearts and minds cannot be measured. What can be measured are user-traffic numbers generated, e-petition signatures delivered, Facebook "like" counts, and other metrics that convey growing support. Back to Top A Contrarian View The conversation here is essentially positioned as a debate over activism versus slacktivism. The latter term refers to people who are happy to click a "like" button about a cause and may make other nominal, supportive gestures. But they're hardly inspired with the kind of emotional fire that forces a shift in public perception. A telling, supportive anecdote: A popular technique of organizers on all sides of the political spectrum is an online letter-writing campaign in which supporters are encouraged to simply copy and paste from a template form of the letter. Participants aren't asked to come up with their own words. It's not even clear if they read the entire content of the letters they send. Does simple "copy/paste/send" act constitute activism at its finest? In one of the more widely discussed articles casting doubt, New Yorker contributor Malcolm Gladwell maintains that successful efforts must engage a participants by convincing them that they have a great personal stake in the consequences. Traditionally, highly effective movements evolved from within parties built upon "strong tie" personal connections, such as those among classmates and church members. Activism associated with social media, however, is dependent upon "weak tie" relationships, writes Gladwell. Organizers seek involvement from Twitter followers they have never met or Facebook friends with whom they would never otherwise stay in touch, according to Gladwell. These are loose networks, whereas meaningful activism requires strong, robust organizational structure. Even in the case of the Arab spring—arguably the political movement most enhanced by multiple digital means—those casting doubt upon the influence of technology contend that the events would have mattered little if old-fashioned principles of activism were not applied: effectively planned mass assemblies in which passionate pleas for change were expressed. The fact that the Arab spring demonstrations got YouTubed, Facebooked, and tweeted is simply a logical progression in the continuing advancement of multimedia, just as broadcasting civil rights demonstrations on TV news during the 1960s at one time seemed novel in its ability to connect a cause with a nationwide audience. In the end, activism has always been—and will always be—about people. Specifically, people who show up in person. Just witness the protests over collective-bargaining rights for state union employees in Wisconsin, as the liberal public-policy group MoveOn.org led a solidarity day in which 50,000 supporters turned out in all 49 other state capitals and raised more than $3 million to support Wisconsin Democrats. "The Wisconsin protest was old-school organizing, with a digital edge," says Dave Karpf, an assistant professor in communications/information at Rutgers University and a leading researcher on political blogs and Internet-mediated activist organizations. "Angry citizens felt their rights were being trampled, so they showed up and demonstrated. It was the largest extended labor action in a generation, and it was led by labor organizations, fighting for collective bargaining rights." Activism fails – the chilling effect prevents participation and deters commitment to a particular cause Starr et al in 8 (Amory Starr, Sociology Ph. D and Chapman University professor; Luis Fernandez, Northern Arizona University professor; Randall Amster, Georgetown University professor; Lesley Wood, York University professor; Manuel Caro, Edgewood College professor; “The Impacts of State Surveillance on Political Assembly and Association: A Socio-Legal Analysis,” Qualitative Sociology, Volume 31, published 2008, accessed 7-6-15, http://www.researchgate.net/publication/225348127_The_Impacts_of_State_Surveillance_on_Political_Assembly_and_Associati on_A_Socio-Legal_Analysis)//JRom We were most alarmed to find security culture displacing organizing culture in most groups, including peace groups, pacifist groups, and other groups who only do legal activities. Activists concerned about creeping criminalization of grey and formerly legal activity take extreme precautions, foregoing inclusivity and destroying all written records of their work. Groups also reported not taking notes at meetings. “We’re afraid to have a piece of paper with anything written on it at the end of any meeting.” Many interviewees, having internalized suspicion of undercovers, said that they don’t want to be seen writing anything down, as it would make them look as if they are surveilling the meeting. Moreover, concerned about future investigations, they do not keep diaries. This lack of archiving is the destruction in advance of the history of the movement, with implications for social movements’ capacity for active reflexivity. Moreover, affiliations become more temporary and less committed, with the result that “I’ve noticed a big shift from long-term strategizing and community building.” Conservative decisions on the part of activists and organizations are understandable in light of the costs of surveillance to organizational resources. The government provides no administrative mechanisms of accountability for false accusations, improper or unwarranted investigations, or erroneous surveillance. One organization that was illegally searched spent more than 1500 hours of volunteer time dealing with the fallout for their membership and relations with other organizations. Their lawsuit for damages took 5 years to resolve. Of the 71 organizations in our study, only two had managed to take legal action regarding surveillance. Our findings indicate that the harm suffered by political organizations and individuals as a result of widespread surveillance, infiltration, and documentation, is legally cognizable and not at all speculative (cf. ACLU-NCA 2005), suggesting that legal standing can be established to overcome the burdens raised by the case of Laird v. Tatum, 408 US 1 (1972). Based on our reading of Cunningham (2004) and our data, we conclude that much current law enforcement surveillance is more properly conceptualized as counterinsurgency. The implementation of counterinsurgency (whose destructiveness is wellagainst a social movement (whose agenda is well known to be noncriminal) violates the fundamental protections of the First Amendment (which is the foundation of a democratic society, variously conceptualized as a marketplace of ideas, a context of free debate and dissent, or selfestablished) governance). Our socio-legal analysis encourages a shift in the unit of analysis and litigation from individual activists and organizations to the context of diverse associational activities which make assembly possible: the social movement. If a social movement could gain standing as a class, it could include event participants who are not members of an organization, as well as dissenters who may have never taken action because of anticipatory conformity. The concept of social movements can bind overt repression, indirect interference (with fundraising, networks, etc.), and intimidating chilling effects. The previous descriptions of the education and civil justice debates above imply that partisan voices determine the macrostructure of a debate, but that interpretation diminishes the primacy of shared goals and public reasons as the determining factors. It seems more likely that the macrostructure of a debate is set by the presence (in the case of an epistemic context) or the absence (in the case of an agonistic one) of participants who have the ability and status to assert common goals and explain them in terms of compelling public reasons. Nonpartisan participants may be more capable than partisan ones in framing these goals and reasons. For example, supporting public reasons with new verifiable and dispassionately phrased information and analyses is usually essential to gaining the attention of partisan stakeholders and to opinion leaders and changing the macrostructure of a debate. Consequently, nonpartisans may play an influential, and sometimes a pivotal, role in debates if they can garner public attention. Activism fails – lack of resources, lack of introspection, inter-organization conflicts, and subjugation of Indigenous populations (Aziz, “Anti-Globalisation Activism Cannot --Ignore Colonial Realities,” accessed 7-7-15, http://www.soaw.org/resources/anti-opp-resources/114features/483-anti-globalisation-activism-cannot-ignore-colonial-realities)//JRom Many critics of globalisation play down the role and relevance of the nation-state, attributing power almost solely to transnational corporations and international institutions like the Bretton Woods triplets. Yet this takes the focus away from the nature and power of the state and even romanticises it. Such global campaigns run the risk of distracting people's gaze from longstanding injustices underfoot. In delegitimising these global actors we must be very aware of the dangers in uncritically legitimising nation-states which are themselves based on the dispossession of Indigenous Peoples. We cannot ignore the centuries of resistance by many indigenous nations against incorporation into the colonial state. We cannot ignore the colonial foundations of the countries in which we live. To do so is to mask the true nature of our societies, and the extent to which they are built on colonisation and exploitation. How can Indigenous Peoples be expected to validate, affirm and seek incorporation into national or international movements dominated by non-indigenous activists, organisations and agendas which are reluctant to address domestic issues of colonisation with the same vigour and commitment that they put into fighting transnational capital or the WTO? Of course some important alliances have been forged between Indigenous Peoples and non-indigenous organisations confronting globalisation. Many (usually small, underresourced) activist groups struggle hard to draw the connections between corporate globalisation and colonisation, to support local indigenous sovereignty struggles and educate non-indigenous peoples about these issues. Movements to expose and oppose corporate globalisation have a very real potential to mobilise support from non-indigenous people for meaningfully addressing the issues of colonisation in New Zealand, Australia, Canada and the USA. We should be challenging the jurisdiction of these colonial settler state governments as they move to sign international trade and investment deals, in the light of their continued denial of Indigenous Peoples' rights, jurisdiction, and title. The centuries-old culture of colonisation holds the key to understanding and defeating the current wave of globalisation. If we understand how "democratic" governments like Canada can sanction the ongoing assault on indigenous lands and communities it isn't hard to understand why such governments subscribe to freemarket international trade and investment policies. In determining the values and foundations on Choudry, McGill University assistant professor, no date which we build alternatives to the neoliberal agenda our movements must be prepared to examine our own propensity to oppress. We cannot build alternatives to globalisation on the rotten foundations of the denial of occupying indigenous lands and the ongoing suppression of Indigenous Peoples' rights. "The colonisers are always building rotten foundations and expecting us to step into a completed building" says Sharon Venne. If anti-globalisation activists and organisations do not address these questions with some urgency then I fear that the growing resistance to neoliberalism in the global North risks being as inherently colonialist as the institutions and processes which it opposes. Our usage of the term colonisation will be little more than empty rhetoric if our analysis does not acknowledge the context in which corporate globalisation - and the worldwide opposition to it - is taking place. Those of us active in antiglobalisation struggles in Canada, the USA, New Zealand and Australia need to examine our role in the colonisation and globalisation of the earth. Only then can we seriously talk about liberation and real alternatives to the neoliberal agenda. Student activism fails – diversity of interests, lack of news coverage, and government repression (Philip G. Altbach, “From Revolution to Apathy: American Student Activism in the 1970s,” Higher Education Volume 8, No. 6, published 11-1979, accessed 7-7-15, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3446222)//JRom While neither the numbers of demonstrations nor their militancy can compare to the sixties, instances of sporadic activism indicate that political consciousness on campus is not entirely absent, and that dramatic issues can mobilize students. Demonstrations in 1977 at Kent State University protesting the proposed construction of a gymnasium at the site of the 1972 shootings resulted in the arrest of almost 200 students. Students in California and in several other parts of the United States have protested against American policy in Southern Africa in general and against the investment policies of universities in particular. Although these demonstrations resulted in several hundred arrests, they led to no lasting movement and were confined to a small number of campuses. The news media has not paid much attention to local student activism, and this has helped to limit its national impact. The issues have been diverse, the events sporadic and somewhat unpredictable, and the scope of demonstrations and other activities significantly smaller than was the case in the sixties. The Kent State demonstrations were covered by national media but the South Africa protests received little attention despite arrests. And other demonstrations, such as the substantial but ultimately unsuccessful efforts by students at the City University of New York to retain free tuition in the face of fiscal crisis, were hardly reported at all. The internal communications networks of the student movement, except for campus newspapers, had declined and the mass media was no longer much interested in campus affairs. In the traditional sense of leftist student activism and organizational activities, the present period is a particularly barren one. Some vestiges of the "old left" student groups still exist and are active on campuses with a strong political tradition, but these groups are very small and have a tiny following. Students are occasionally aroused by a political issue, although even in these cases demonstrations tend to be small and no ongoing organizations or movement are created. Altbach, Boston College research professor, in 79 Policy-making, good or not, is always the endgame of theorists (Bruce, “The Need For Praxis: Bringing Policy Relevance Back In,” International Security Volume 26, No. 4, published spring 2002, accessed 7-7-15, http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/016228802753696816)//JRom To be sure, political science and international relations have produced and continue to produce scholarly work that does bring important policy insights. Still it is hard to deny that contemporary political science and international relations as a discipline put limited value on policy relevance—too little, in my view, and the discipline suffers for it.1 The problem is not just Jentleson, Duke University professor, in 2 the gap between theory and policy but its chasmlike widening in recent years and the limited valuation of efforts, in Alexander George’s phrase, at “bridging the gap.”2 The events of September 11 drive home the need to bring policy relevance back in to the discipline, to seek greater praxis between theory and practice. This is not to say that scholars should take up the agendas of think tanks, journalists, activists, or fast fax operations. The academy’s agenda is and should be principally a more scholarly one. But theory can be valued without policy relevance being so undervalued. Dichotomization along the lines of “we” do theory and “they” do policy consigns international relations scholars almost exclusively to an intradisciplinary dialogue and purpose, with conversations and knowledge building that while highly intellectual are excessively insular and disconnected from the empirical realities that are the discipline’s raison d’être. This stunts the contributions that universities, one of society’s most essential institutions, can make in dealing with the profound problems and challenges society faces. It also is counterproductive to the academy’s own interests. Research and scholarship are bettered by pushing analysis and logic beyond just offering up a few paragraphs on implications for policy at the end of a forty-page article, as if a “ritualistic addendum.”3 Teaching is enhanced when students’ interest in “real world” issues is engaged in ways that reinforce the argument that theory really is relevant, and CNN is not enough. There also are gains to be made for the scholarly community’s standing as perceived by those outside the academic world, constituencies and colleagues whose opinions too often are selfservingly denigrated and defensively disregarded. It thus is both for the health of the discipline and to fulªll its broader societal responsibilities that greater praxis is to be pursued. Using debate as a site of activism to encourage social change fails Atchison and Panetta 9 – *Director of Debate at Trinity University and **Director of Debate at the University of Georgia (Jarrod, and Edward, “Intercollegiate Debate and Speech Communication: Issues for the Future,” The Sage Handbook of Rhetorical Studies, Lunsford, Andrea, ed., 2009, p. 317-334) Debates as Sites of Community Change The debate community has become more self-reflexive and increasingly invested in attempting to address the problems that have plagued the community from the start. The degrees to which things are considered problems and the appropriateness of different solutions to the problems have been hotly contested, but some fundamental issues, such as diversity and accessibility, have received considerable attention in recent years. This section will address the “debate as activism” perspective that argues that the appropriate site for addressing community problems is individual debates. In contrast to the “debate as innovation” perspective, which assumes that the activity is an isolated game with educational benefits, proponents of the “debate as activism” perspective argue that individual debates have the potential to create change in the debate community and society at large. If the first approach assumed that debate was completely insulated, this perspective assumes that there is no substantive insulation between individual debates and the community at large. From our perspective, using individual debates to create community change is an insufficient strategy for three reasons. First, individual debates are, for the most part, insulated from the community at large. Second, individual debates limit the conversation to the immediate participants and the judge, excluding many important contributors to the debate community. Third, locating the discussion within the confines of a competition diminishes the additional potential for collaboration, consensus, and coalition building. Academic radicalism fails ---rejection is dangerous and ineffective Dussel 11 [2011, Enrique Dussel is the Professor of Philosophy at the Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, “From Critical Theory to the Philosophy of Liberation: Some Themes for Dialogue”, Transmodernity: Journal of Peripheral Cultural Production, http://escholarship.org/uc/item/59m869d2] We should proceed in politics in the very same manner that Marx proceeded in economics: working on the level of macro-institutional feasibility. The “dissolution of the state” should be defined as a political postulate. To seek to bring this about empirically leads to the “anti-institutional fallacy,” and the impossibility of a critical, transformative politics. To say that we need to transform the world without exercising power through institutions – including the state (which we need to radically transform, but not eliminate) – is the fallacy into which Negri and Holloway fall. The presently given institutions, and even the particular state as a political macroinstitution, are never perfect and always require transformation. But there are moments in which institutions become diachronically repressive in the extreme, in their final entropic moment. Hegemony – the consensus exercised over the “obedient” à la Weber's legitimate domination91 – gives rise to domination in the Gramscian sense. The state machinery, in the service of the economic interests of the dominant classes in the postcolonial metropolitan nations, become definitively repressive. The popular masses go on gaining consciousness in proportion to level of their oppression. This accumulation of power-to (potentia),93 which takes place partially in the exteriority of the structures of the particular state but within the “bosom of the people” (which is not without its contradictions), confronts the political institutions currently in force. It does so to “trans-form” them (not necessarily for reforms94, but only rarely for revolution95), not necessarily to destroy them (though it could if required by the postulates), but to use them and transform them according to its ends and according to the degree of correspondence to the permanence and extension of life and symmetrical democratic participation of the oppressed people. The anti-institutionalist believes that the destruction of the state represents an important victory on the path to revolution. This sort of destruction is irrational . They have confused the “dissolution of the state” as a postulate (empirically impossible, but functioning as a principle for strategic orientation) with its empirical negation. How are we to understand the postulate of the “dissolution of the state”? Right-wing anarchism – like that of Nozick – proposes the dissolution of the state or something close to it under the guise of the “minimal state.” The unhindered market produces equilibrium, especially in Hayek's formulation; for this, the minimal state needs only to destroy the monopolies that impede the free movement of the market. A union seeking a wage increase is a monopoly, because it places demands on the market that do not emanate from free competition. The duty of the state is therefore to dissolve the union. In the service of this total market definition, the process of globalization as controlled by transnational industrial and financial capital (not with hegemony, because this was lost in the move to the last-instance use: the violent coercion of military power), equally proposes the dissolution or weakening of the particular states in postcolonial peripheral nations. The postcolonial state – however much it may be dominated by the private bureaucracies of the transnational corporations which impose their own members onto the political bureaucracies of those states (and we see, for example, a Coca-Cola distributor as president96) – still represents the last possible resistance for oppressed peoples. To dissolve or substantially weaken their states is to take away their only possible defense. The second Iraq War represents a war against a particular postcolonial state that, however corrupt and dictatorial, nevertheless had a certain degree of sovereignty and selfdetermination which interposed some resistance to the appropriation of its petroleum by foreign companies. For all of this, it is tragic that a sector of the left coincides with the North American Empire – the home-state97 of the transnationals and the ultimate example of power based on its economic political-military complex – in dissolving the particular peripheral state. If Europeans alongside Habermas seemed as though they were dissolving the old particular state, it is for the strategic fortification of a Confederation of States in the European Union. In Latin America, if it were possible to proceed to organize a Confederation of Latin American States98 without American or Spanish influence, such a weakening of the particular state would be equally useful. But for the moment, this is not the situation. Any struggle for the real, effective dissolution of a particular postcolonial state is a reactionary project. It is an entirely different thing to struggle to transform the particular postcolonial state in view of a political postulate of the “dissolution of the state” as such. This would mean that in the creation of any new institution, in every exercise of institutional power, or in the transformation of all of the institutions (the transformation of the state), one would have the “dissolution of the state” as an orienting principle. However, this cannot take the form of the objective, empirical negation of these institutions, but rather must take the form of a responsible, democratic, popular, social, and participatory subjectivization of institutional functions, in which representation proceeds by approaching (to use a Kantian word) the represented. In this situation, the symmetrical participation of all those affected would become flesh in all political actions to such a degree that the state will cease to weigh so heavily, becoming lighter, more transparent, and more public and democratic. This would not be a “minimal state” (which leaves everything to the market or to the impossibility of perfect citizens99), but more accurately a “subjectivized state” in which the citizens will participate to such a degree that the existing institutional sphere will shift toward transparency, the bureaucracy will be the minimum necessary, while its efficacy and instrumentality when it comes to the permanence and extension of human life will nevertheless be at a maximum. I do not believe that it makes sense to attempt to transform political institutions without the state, without exercising power which is communicative, democratic, legitimate, participatory, socialized, and popular. It is, however, possible to declare a postulate which could never be realized, but which functions like the “North Star” that helped the Chinese navigators to sail at night. Despite all that I have expounded, I think that the postulate of the “dissolution of the state” is a strategic orienting principle that functions as a regulative horizon. Trying to create change through debate only ensures their movement suffers because of the presence of a ballot and competition—it forces others to disagree with them Atchison and Panetta 9 – *Director of Debate at Trinity University and **Director of Debate at the University of Georgia (Jarrod, and Edward, “Intercollegiate Debate and Speech Communication: Issues for the Future,” The Sage Handbook of Rhetorical Studies, Lunsford, Andrea, ed., 2009, p. 317-334) The final problem with an individual debate round focus is the role of competition. Creating community change through individual debate rounds sacrifices the “community” portion of the change. Many teams that promote activist strategies in debates profess that they are more interested in creating change than winning debates. What is clear, however, is that the vast majority of teams that are not promoting community change are very interested in winning debates. The tension that is generated from the clash of these opposing forces is tremendous. Unfortunately, this is rarely a productive tension. Forcing teams to consider their purpose in debating, their style in debates, and their approach to evidence are all critical aspects of being participants in the community. However, the dismissal of the proposed resolution that the debaters have spent countless hours preparing for, in the name of a community problem that the debaters often have little control over, does little to engender coalitions of the willing. Should a debate team lose because their director or coach has been ineffective at recruiting minority participants? Should a debate team lose because their coach or director holds political positions that are in opposition to the activist program? Competition has been a critical component of the interest in intercollegiate debate from the beginning, and it does not help further the goals of the debate community to dismiss competition in the name of community change. The larger problem with locating the “debate as activism” perspective within the competitive framework is that it overlooks the communal nature of the community problem. If each individual debate is a decision about how the debate community should approach a problem, then the losing debaters become collateral damage in the activist strategy dedicated toward creating community change. One frustrating example of this type of argument might include a judge voting for an activist team in an effort to help them reach elimination rounds to generate a community discussion about the problem. Under this scenario, the losing team serves as a sacrificial lamb on the altar of community change. Downplaying the important role of competition and treating opponents as scapegoats for the failures of the community may increase the profile of the winning team and the community problem, but it does little to generate the critical coalitions necessary to address the community problem, because the competitive focus encourages teams to concentrate on how to beat the strategy with little regard for addressing the community problem. There is no role for competition when a judge decides that it is important to accentuate the publicity of a community problem. An extreme example might include a team arguing that their opponents’ academic institution had a legacy of civil rights abuses and that the judge should not vote for them because that would be a community endorsement of a problematic institution. This scenario is a bit more outlandish but not unreasonable if one assumes that each debate should be about what is best for promoting solutions to diversity problems in the debate community. If the debate community is serious about generating community change, then it is more likely to occur outside a traditional competitive debate. When a team loses a debate because the judge decides that it is better for the community for the other team to win, then they have sacrificed two potential advocates for change within the community. Creating change through wins generates backlash through losses. Some proponents are comfortable with generating backlash and argue that the reaction is evidence that the issue is being discussed. From our perspective, the discussion that results from these hostile situations is not a productive one where participants seek to work together for a common goal. Instead of giving up on hope for change and agitating for wins regardless of who is left behind, it seems more reasonable that the debate community should try the method of public argument that we teach in an effort to generate a discussion of necessary community changes. Simply put, debate competitions do not represent the best environment for community change because it is a competition for a win and only one team can win any given debate, whereas addressing systemic century-long community problems requires a tremendous effort by a great number of people. Deliberation Good Deliberation allows the participants to come to a reasoned decision that benefits both parties Chapell, Fellow in Politcal Theory, 11 (Zsuzsanna, “Deliberation”, Encyclopedia of Power, p.168-169)//WB Deliberation refers to a process of reflection undertaken by individuals or groups to reach reasoned and considered decisions. Deliberation has an epistemic function to improve decisions and uncover the best argument. It is often assumed that because of deliberation, individuals' beliefs and judgments are transformed as they consider new facts, arguments, and points of view. In individual deliberation, the deliberator weighs and evaluates each possible solution and then arrives at a decision. Group deliberation consists of reasoned discussion. When groups deliberate, the process acquires a dimension of power. Deliberation can be either formal or informal. Examples of formalized deliberating groups are juries or legislatures. An example of informal deliberation is the ongoing discussion between different groups in civil society, but discussions within families and civic organizations are also examples of informal deliberation. Group deliberation is characterized by communication aimed at persuasion. Ideal deliberative processes should be reasoned, equal, and open discussions where participants are prepared to change their views as a result of the arguments presented. In reality, deliberation does not live up to such a high standard. Some members of the group will be more powerful than others, and some arguments will be more persuasive than others, regardless of their merits. Although deliberation could ideally be aimed at reaching a common good for the group, in practice, the private interests of group members will be powerful forces. Inequality within the group leads to differences in the power each group member possesses. The socioeconomic background of participants can define their roles in the discussion. As an example, jury deliberations tend to be dominated by well-educated white males. Actors who are powerful outside of deliberation will be powerful in deliberative settings as well. In deliberations between states, the most powerful nation will wield more power. Inequalities also exist with regard to the ability of deliberators. Good orators are more likely to convince others, regardless of the merit of their arguments. There is a danger that intelligent and persuasive individuals could manipulate deliberation to serve their own interests. Other resources, such as time, information, or the respect of other members of the community, will also make some deliberators more influential than others. Arguments themselves will have different power. Although some place hope in the power of the best argument to defeat all others, this is not necessarily the argument that will resonate most with deliberators. Arguments that appeal to strong background beliefs and feelings will be more powerful. Arguments that support the views deliberators already hold will also be more persuasive. Deliberation is seen as a good way of increasing citizen involvement and participation in politics. In political theory, deliberative democracy has engendered a new interest in increasing deliberation in politics, as current democratic systems focus more on elections than on decision making through reasoned debate. Deliberative experiments and meetings are organized to increase citizen involvement in public policy making. In this context, deliberation appears as a potentially valuable resource. Deliberation may facilitate engagement across differences in complex and diverse societies, where people need to justify to each other their publicly articulated values, interests, identities, and goals. In this spirit, Gerard Hauser and Chantal Benoit-Barne (2002) discern in deliberation the potential to build trust by offering interlocutors the "opportunity to acquire a sense of the range of difference and the mediating grounds of similarity that make it possible for us to form a civic community based on relations of collaboration" (p. 271). Hauser and Benoit-Barne caution that collaboration does not lead to consensus, but refers instead to working together even amidst disagreement. Along these lines, Matthew Festenstein (2005) suggests three ways that deliberation may build trust: enabling participants to present themselves in ways that may overcome negative stereotypes, strengthening good will and fidelity among representatives and constituents by foregrounding reason-giving, and fostering respect for diverse viewpoints by situating interlocutors as warranting address (p. 143). While these scholars identify deliberation as a potential source of trust, they stop short of explicating how this process might unfold. Deliberation creates trust between groups when used in public spheres Robert 13 (Asen, Robert. "Deliberation and trust." Argumentation and Advocacy 50.1 (2013): 2+. Academic OneFile. Web. 5 July 2015. http://go.galegroup.com/ps/i.do?id=GALE%7CA355557329&v=2.1&u=umuser&it=r&p=AONE&sw=w&asid=a8afd042bec8d1f52d1 1442c56c79131)//WB To realize this resource, scholars need to develop theoretical models that consider how trust may function in deliberation. In developing these models, scholars cannot operate with a static concept of trust. This is a critical limit to the approaches of Robert Putnam and others, as Putnam (2007) acknowledges, since their reliance on survey data elides deliberation's transformative power (pp. 150, 158-159). The significance of this data, which helps to justify my efforts in this essay, arises from its capacity to illuminate important political and social trends. These trends may inform the wider contexts in which deliberation occurs, but they do not characterize processes of deliberation. Surveys inquiring about trust treat the concept as a discrete item that researchers may link to institutions, actors, and issues. In these surveys, trust exists as a quality prior to an expressed belief or action, such as support of a political figure or participation in a community organization. Alternatively, we may consider how deliberation may shift levels of trust. Although deliberation offers no guarantees, it may enable interlocutors to build levels of trust (Jacobs, Cook, & Delli Carpini, 2009; Mutz, 2006; cf. Sunstein, 2003). To fully appreciate the relationship of deliberation and trust, scholars need a dynamic, process-based model. Rather than seeing one as the condition for the other, we need to recognize the mutually informative and constitutive relationship of deliberation and trust. Toward this end, I develop a model of deliberative trust as a relational practice. I argue that scholars may appreciate the role of trust in deliberation not by regarding trust as an attribute of one participant or another but as a quality that may emerge in the interactions of participants--the discursive relationships they mutually construct. As a practice, trust appears not as a precondition or an outcome of deliberation but as an activity that unfolds through deliberation. Conceptualizing trust in this way comports with scholarly models of deliberation by foregrounding process and participation. As a relational practice, trust is something that people do. My argument in this essay develops over two main sections. In the first, I distinguish deliberative trust as a participatory activity from nondeliberative conceptions of trust. Practicing trust in deliberation draws on participants' experiences but does not require participants to possess shared experiences, values, and/or beliefs. As it exhibits a temporal orientation that may link disparate encounters, the practice of deliberative trustwhich remains context-specific--is informed by elements of contingency, risk, and reciprocity. In the second section, I identify four qualities for practicing trust in deliberation: flexibility, forthrightness, engagement, and heedfulness. I explicate these qualities as mutually informative and relatively autonomous practices that constitute an analytic and normative framework. As such, these qualities suggest foci for investigating deliberation and trust as well as means for bolstering trust in deliberation. Good Deliberation requires an agreed upon subject, fairness, and contributions to democratic legitimacy (George, “The Encyclopedia of Political Science”, CQ Press, ISBN: 9781608712434, p.384-386)//WB Kurian, Editor in Chief, 11 A number of political theorists, notably Joshua Cohen, Amy Guttmann and Dennis Thompson, and Jürgen Habermas, have sought to define the nature and purposes of deliberation, identify prerequisites for its existence, and construct models of “ideal deliberation.” Central to most definitions of deliberation is giving reasons and weighing arguments and information in favor of, or against, public policies. Most models of deliberation also assume that citizens share a basic level of agreement on issues before they can deliberate effectively. Because deliberation includes a variety of dimensions, however, no consensus exists about the precise definition of deliberation. In The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (1994), government scholar Joseph M. Bessette provides a common definition as “reasoning on the merits of public policy.” Some definitions of deliberation, however, do not require public-spiritedness or other motivations as requisites for deliberation. Individuals deliberate as long as they acquire and use substantive information related to public policy, even if their goals are narrowly self-interested. Scholars have put forward a variety of criteria to judge deliberation, including fairness, inclusiveness of participation, the breadth of viewpoints considered, responsiveness to popular desires, the logical and empirical validity of arguments, and contributions to democratic legitimacy. Citizen deliberation is a key factor to creating successful policies (George, “The Encyclopedia of Political Science”, CQ Press, ISBN: 9781608712434, p.384-386)//WB Kurian, Editor in Chief, 11 Citizen Deliberation Before the advent of mass democracy, theorists viewed deliberation as an elite endeavor. James Madison and other framers of the U.S. Constitution saw elite deliberation as a bulwark against the public's impulses and uninformed opinions. Legislators were responsible for filtering and refining public opinion in such a way that they would discover their constituents' true opinions—what the public would think if citizens had the same capabilities to deliberate as their leaders. Today, many observers consider citizen deliberation a vital component of democratic participation and a mechanism for maintaining democratic accountability. Citizens cannot limit their participation to voting, leaving policy deliberation to their leaders. The quality of citizen participation may improve with deliberation. In a study of individuals who attended a forum on Social Security reform, individuals who attended the forum gained more knowledge about the program than similar individuals who did not attend. Second, deliberation produced opinion change over policy options for which there was already some consensus. For policy options on which citizens had little consensus at the outset, opinions changed only among citizens who held their opinions weakly, according to a 2004 study by public opinion and policy scholar Jason Barabas. Properly designed institutions may help to develop citizens' capacities for deliberation without sacrificing the political equality and legitimacy that are the hallmarks of modern mass democracy. Among the ideas for building citizens' capacity for deliberation are “deliberative opinion polls” and holding “deliberation days” just before elections. Whatever the potential drawbacks to deliberation, few people seem to be concerned that we run the risk of having an excess of it. Given the proliferation of economic and foreign policy calamities of recent decades, it may be more plausible that governments suffer from too little careful deliberation than too much of it. Deliberation allows for ideas to change and for compromise on the best policy option to be reached Gastil & Burkhalter, PHD’s, 8 (John and Stephanie, Head of Penn State Department of Communication Arts and Sciences and associate professor at Humbolt, “Group Decision Making, Political”, The Encyclopedia of Political Science”, CQ Press, ISBN: 9781608712434, p.288-291)//WB Citizen Deliberation The modern ideal of citizen deliberation traces back to the Athenian assembly, in which male citizens acted as legislators on important public questions. In this vision of democracy, citizen decision making was essential to establishing the legitimacy of the state's decisions. This foundational idea deeply influenced democratic theorists from Jean-Jacques Rousseau to Jürgen Habermas. In general, deliberative political theory argues that democratic systems fail to the extent that they do not promote robust, widespread deliberation. A deliberative public sphere in which citizens participate is necessary to help individual citizens develop broad and public-spirited perspectives and reasoned judgments on public policy. In addition, to maintain legitimacy, formal institutions of government in representative democracy such as legislatures, courts, and chief executives should engage in deliberation in their decision-making processes to facilitate representative and well-informed outcomes. A central claim in the contemporary study of citizen deliberation is that citizens'policy views and civic attitudes can transform through public-oriented discussion, and a wide range of political reforms have demonstrated the potency of such deliberation. In the 1970s, citizen juries in the United States and planning cells (Planungszelle) in Germany experimented with varied techniques for convening small representative samples of citizens to study complex public policy issues. Government agencies, private foundations, and others have used these and related processes to gain a sense of what the general public thinks about issues after having the opportunity to deliberate. More recently, the deliberative poll has also become a popular means of assessing how public opinion changes as a result of one-to-three days of discussion. Deliberation, especially in debate, creates higher quality political judgement, and cohesion between peers, also anti-deliberation studies do not have evidence Wessler, Professor of media and communications, 8 (Hartmut, “ Deliberation”, Encyclopedia of Political Communication, p.168-169, Sage Publications, ISBN: 9781412953993, In the context of political communication, deliberation refers to a process of reasoning and discussion about political matters. Deliberation takes place in parliamentary debate, expert panels, deliberative decision-making bodies, news media content, political talk shows, online discussion forums, civil society organizations, and everyday political talk among citizens. Normative theories of deliberative democracy place particular emphasis on the democratic value of deliberation. Although by no means a uniform group, deliberative democratic theorists agree on the centrality of argumentative exchange in political communication in order to foster both the cognitive quality of political judgment (rationality) and mutual respect and cohesion among deliberators (social integration). Deliberation is usually considered to be an alternative to both bargaining and rhetoric. Although bargaining involves the pursuit of particularistic interests by means of offering incentives and applying threats, deliberation relies on the persuasive power of voluntarily accepted reasons. Whereas rhetoric can include polemics, humor, emotional appeals, and the like, deliberation is predicated on the literal use and understanding of arguments. One problem of deliberative democratic theory is how to transpose the benefits of deliberation from small-scale deliberative settings into large-scale societal communication. Bruce Ackerman and James S. Fishkin have proposed a “deliberation day” to bridge the gap: establishing a national holiday one week before major national elections on which citizens would be paid for participating in deliberation groups as well as voting 1 week later. A more mundane possibility lies in measuring deliberative qualities of the mass news media and investigating the conditions under which such deliberative media content has normatively desirable effects on political decision makers and citizens. Vis-à-vis decision makers, mediated deliberation can be thought to foster active justification of political claims and decisions, thus enhancing the quality of decisions or at least avoiding egregious mistakes. In relation to the citizenry, deliberative media content may serve as a repository of arguments and justifications (thus reducing citizens' information costs drastically) and as a model for deliberative behavior in everyday political talk. So far, there are only a few empirical studies directed at measuring the deliberative qualities of mass media content. In the print media, argumentative exchange is achieved for example in commentary, news analysis, or debate-style articles, with journalists apparently playing a particularly important role for enhancing deliberativeness. In political talk shows, the host can foster argumentation by eliciting justifications from discussants and confronting them with opposing claims. In citizen deliberation, argument repertoire has been shown to be a valid measure of deliberativeness; that is, the number of arguments a person can give for his or her own position and the number of arguments a person can imagine opponents will use to support the counter-position. Exposure to disagreement enhances argument repertoire and political tolerance but discourages political participation, suggesting that deliberative and participative behavior cannot be optimized at the same time. Critical accounts of political deliberation sometimes feature claims of decay over time, but longitudinal evidence to support such claims is scarce at best. Ballot Not Key The aff simply demands a ballot for trying to spread some discourse while claiming to create change—this ensures that no social change will ever occur—the ballot becomes a commodity Bryant 13 [philosophy prof at Collin College, Levi, The Paradox of Emancipatory Political Theory, http://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2013/05/31/the-paradox-of-emancipatory-politicaltheory/] There’s a sort of Hegelian contradiction at the heart of all academic political theory that has pretensions of being emancipatory. In a nutshell, the question is that of how this theory can avoid being a sort of commodity. Using Hegel as a model, this contradiction goes something like this: emancipatory political theory says it’s undertaken for the sake of emancipation from x. Yet with rare exceptions, it is only published in academicjournals that few have access to, in a jargon that only other academics or the highly literate can understand, and presented only at conferencesthat only other academics generally attend. Thus, academic emancipatory political theory reveals itself in its truth as something that isn’t aimed at political change or intervention at all, but rather only as a move or moment in the ongoing autopoiesis of academia. That is, itfunctions as another line on the CVand is one strategy through which the university system carries outits autopoiesis or self-reproduction across time. It thus functions– the issue isn’t here one of the beliefs or intentions of academics, but how things function –as something like a commodity within the academic system. The function is not to intervene in the broader political system– despite what all of us doing political theory say and how we think about our work –but rather to carry out yet another iteration of the academic discourse (there are other ways that this is done, this has just been a particularly effective rhetorical strategy for the autopoiesis of academia in the humanities). Were the aim political change, then the discourse would have to find a way to reach outside the academy, but this is precisely what academic politicaltheory cannot do due to the publication and presentation structure, publish or perish logic, the CV, and so on. To produce political change, the academic political theorist would have to sacrifice his or her erudition or scholarship, because they would have to presume an audience that doesn’t have a high falutin intellectual background in Hegel, Adorno, Badiou, set theory, Deleuze, Lacan, Zizek, Foucault (who is one of the few that was a breakaway figure), etc. They would also have to adopt a different platform of communication. Why? Because they would have to address an audience beyond the confines of the academy, which means something other than academic presses, conferences, journals, etc. (And here I would say that us Marxists are often the worst of the worst. We engage in a discourse bordering on medieval scholasticism that only schoolmen can appreciate, which presents a fundamental contradiction between the form of their discourse– only other experts can understand it –and the content; they want to produce change). But the academic emancipatory political theorist can’t do either of these things. If they surrender their erudition and the baroque nature of their discourse, they surrender their place in the academy (notice the way in which Naomi Klein is sneered at in political theory circles despite the appreciable impact of her work). If they adopt other platforms of communication– and this touches on my last post and the way philosophers sneer at the idea that there’s a necessity to investigating extra-philosophical conditions of their discourse –then they surrender their labor requirements as people working within academia. Both options are foreclosed by the sociological conditions of their discourse. The paradox of emancipatory academic political discourse is thus that it is formally and functionally apolitical. At the level of its intention or what it says it aims to effect political change and intervention, but at the level of what it does, it simply reproduces its own discourse and labor conditions without intervening in broader social fields (and no, the classroom doesn’t count). Unconscious recognition of this paradox might be why, in some corners, we’re seeing the execrable call to re-stablish “the party”. The party is the academic fantasy of a philosopher-king or an academic avant gard that simultaneously gets to be an academic and produce political change for all those “dopes and illiterate” that characterize the people (somehow the issue of how the party eventually becomes an end in itself, aimed solely at perpetuating itself, thereby divorcing itself from the people never gets addressed by these neo- totalitarians). The idea of the party and of the intellectual avant gard is a symptom of unconscious recognition of the paradox I’ve recognized here and of the political theorist that genuinely wants to produce change while also recognizing that the sociological structure of the academy can’t meet those requirements. Given these reflections, one wishes that the academic that’s learned the rhetoric of politics as an autopoieticstrategy for reproducing the university discourse would be a little less pompous and selfrighteous, but everyone has to feel important and like their the best thing since sliced bread, I guess. Social change in debate is a myth and creates an exclusionary dichotomy Ritter 13 JD – U Texas Law, B.A. cum laude – Trinity University, ‘13 (Michael J., “OVERCOMING THE FICTION OF “SOCIAL CHANGE THROUGH DEBATE”: WHAT’S TO LEARN FROM 2PAC’S CHANGES?,” National Journal of Speech and Debate, Vol. 2, Issue 1) The fiction of social change through debate abuses the win–loss structure of debate and permits debaters to otherize, demonize , dehumanize, and exclude opponents. The win–loss structure of debate rounds requires a judge to vote for one side or the other, as judges generally cannot give a double win. This precludes the possibility of compromise on any major position in the debate when the resolution of the position would determine the ultimate issue of “which team did the better debating.” Thus, the fiction of social change through debate encourages debaters to construct narratives of good versus evil in which the other team is representative of some evil that threatens to bring about our destruction if it is endorsed (e.g. capitalism). The team relying on the fiction of social change through debate then paints themselves as agents of the good, and gives the judge a George W. Bush-like “option”: “You’re either with us or you’re against us.” The fiction of social change through debate—like Bush’s rhetorical fear tactics and creation of a false, polarizing, and exclusionary dichotomy to justify all parts of the War on Terror— enables the otherization , demonization, dehumanization, and exclusion of the opposing team. When the unfairness of this tactic is brought to light—particularly in egregious situations when a team is arguing that the other team should lose because of their skin color—all can see that the debate centers on personal attacks against opposing debaters. This causes tensions between debaters that frequently result in debaters losing interest or quitting. By alienating and excluding members of the competitive interscholastic debate community for the purpose of winning a debate, it also makes the reaching of any compromise outside of the debate—the only place where compromise is possible—much less likely. By bringing the social issue into a debate round, debaters impede out-ofround progress on the resolution of social issues within and outside the debate community by prompting backlash. No evidence for the power of the ballot Ritter 13, JD – U Texas Law, B.A. cum laude – Trinity University, (Michael J., “OVERCOMING THE FICTION OF “SOCIAL CHANGE THROUGH DEBATE”: WHAT’S TO LEARN FROM 2PAC’S CHANGES?,” National Journal of Speech and Debate, Vol. 2, Issue 1) Up to this point, this article has shown how each of the essential components of “competitive interscholastic debate” makes it very different from any other kind of debate. But one thing that is persuasive in any kind of debate is some sort of properly conducted study (or even a mere survey) that provides empirical proof or even substantial anecdotal support. To date, none of the many academics who coach or participate in the debate community have published a study or survey to support the social change fiction. (Perhaps they have tried, and discovered they were just wrong.) But until such an empirical study of competitive interscholastic debate is conducted, students, judges, and coaches should not take it for granted. The ballot fails Ritter ‘13, JD – U Texas Law, B.A. cum laude – Trinity University, (Michael J., “OVERCOMING THE FICTION OF “SOCIAL CHANGE THROUGH DEBATE”: WHAT’S TO LEARN FROM 2PAC’S CHANGES?,” National Journal of Speech and Debate, Vol. 2, Issue 1) The structure of competitive interscholastic debate renders any message communicated in a debate round virtually incapable of creating any social change, either in the debate community or in general society. And to the extent that the fiction of social change through debate can be proven or disproven through empirical studies or surveys, academics instead have analyzed debate with nonapplicable rhetorical theory that fails to account for the unique aspects of competitive interscholastic debate. Rather, the current debate relating to activism and competitive interscholastic debate concerns the following: “What is the best model to promote social change?” But a more fundamental question that must be addressed first is: “Can debate cause social change?” Despite over two decades of opportunity to conduct and publish empirical studies or surveys, academic proponents of the fiction that debate can create social change have chosen not to prove this fundamental assumption, which—as this article argues—is merely a fiction that is harmful in most, if not all, respects. The position that competitive interscholastic debate can create social change is more properly characterized as a fiction than an argument. A fiction is an invented or fabricated idea purporting to be factual but is not provable by any human senses or rational thinking capability or is unproven by valid statistical studies. An argument, most basically, consists of a claim and some support for why the claim is true. If the support for the claim is false or its relation to the claim is illogical, then we can deduce that the particular argument does not help in ascertaining whether the claim is true. Interscholastic competitive debate is premised upon the assumption that debate is argumentation. Because fictions are necessarily not true or cannot be proven true by any means of argumentation, the competitive interscholastic debate community should be incredibly critical of those fictions and adopt them only if they promote the activity and its purposes. Academic Left Wrong The academic left criticizes conservatives for intolerance when they and guilty of it as well as they come to predetermined conclusions Young, Degree from Rutgers University, 12 (Cathy, 5/12/12, “The academic left’s intolerance”, The Boston Globe, https://www.bostonglobe.com/opinion/2012/05/11/the-academic-leftintolerance/0NMoHik0qWPI7lZi9nNQZP/story.html)//WB The politics of higher education have been hotly debated for years: Conservatives charge that academia is choked by left-wing orthodoxies; liberals dismiss “political correctness” as a right-wing smear. This week, the conservative critique got a boost — from the academic left, whose response to a blog post lambasting black studies was not to challenge the blogger but to shut her up. On Brainstorm, the blog of the Chronicle of Higher Education, the heretic, Naomi Schaefer Riley, made a post titled, “The Most Persuasive Case for Eliminating Black Studies? Just Read the Dissertations.” (Full disclosure: I have met Riley at a few social events.) The blog was inspired by a Chronicle cover story about the new generation of black studies PhDs and its sidebar profiling the first five students in Northwestern University’s black studies doctoral program. Riley sarcastically summed up three of their dissertation topics, which she described as “left-wing victimization claptrap. The response was fast and furious. Posts on other blogs and on Twitter excoriated Riley. A petition demanding her removal from the Chronicle’s blog roster gathered over 6,500 signatures. Chronicle editor Liz Miller at first defended Riley’s post as an invitation to debate; on May 7 she reversed herself, stating that the piece “did not meet The Chronicle’s basic editorial standards” and that Riley had been asked to leave Brainstorm. She also apologized for “the distress these incidents have caused.” While many have denounced the Chronicle for cravenness and censorship, other commentators, such as Atlantic editor and blogger Ta-Nehisi Coates, defend its decision — not because of Riley’s views but because of her alleged intellectual sloppiness. Her crime, evidently, was conceding in response to critics that she had not read the dissertations she ridiculed. Of course, the initial post made it clear that her judgment was based on the topic summaries in the sidebar. Is this unfair or intellectually shoddy? First, Riley wrote a blog post, not an academic essay. Second, let’s turn the tables. Suppose a blogger had slammed a doctoral program at a conservative Christian university, lampooning summaries of PhD theses which sought to show that birth control leads to society’s moral breakdown or that America’s Founders did not support church-state separation. Would Riley’s current bashers insist on perusal of the actual dissertations? Doubtful. Whether Riley’s indictment was too sweeping is another question. One project she mentioned focuses on black women’s childbirth experiences, a subject she believes is too narrow. In an e-mail exchange, Riley noted that she has also criticized esoteric research topics in other fields. Others would argue that such research can yield valuable knowledge. This is the problem with fields like black studies and women’s studies. Riley’s other two targets, however, have all the hallmarks of political advocacy posing as scholarship. Take “Strange Bedfellows: The Rise of the New (Black) Right in Post Civil Rights America” by La TaSha Levy. According to the Chronicle, Levy “argues that conservatives like Thomas Sowell, Clarence Thomas, John McWhorter, and others have ‘played one of the most-significant roles in the assault on the civil-rights legacy that benefited them.’ ” Levy’s interest in the subject apparently stems from her concern, as director of a campus black cultural center, about students reading black conservative authors. This is more than enough to suggest a hatchet job — particularly when Levy lumps John McWhorter, who is sharply critical of left-wing pieties on race but considers himself a liberal Democrat and a Barack Obama supporter, together with conservatives. (Talk about intellectual sloppiness!) The problem with fields like black studies and women’s studies is not that their subjects are unworthy of inquiry; it is that they tend to promote predetermined conclusions and agendas, which is anathema to true scholarship. Would a student whose research led her to agree with McWhorter’s critique of race-based preferences in college admissions be welcome in a black studies program? All this could have been debated in response to Riley’s post. Instead, she has been accused of everything from racism — even though her husband is black — to a viciously damaging assault on vulnerable graduate students, as if their stardom in the Chronicle did not outweigh any mythical damage from a blog post. The petitioners who succeeded in their demand for Riley’s dismissal are now celebrating a victory. But the only real winners here are those on the right who depict the academy as a bastion of “liberal intolerance” rather than intellectual freedom. Liberalism is a disease of intolerance running through America, they can not accept that people may think differently Linker, Degree from Michigan State University, 14 (Damon, 7/11/14, “How Liberalism became an intolerant dogma”, The Week, http://theweek.com/articles/445434/how-liberalism-becameintolerant-dogma)//WB Liberalism's decline from a political philosophy of pluralism into a rigidly intolerant dogma. The decline is especially pronounced on a range of issues wrapped up with religion and sex. For a time, electoral self-interest kept these intolerant tendencies in check, since the strongly liberal position on social issues was clearly a minority view. But the cultural shift during the Obama years that has led a majority of Americans to support gay marriage seems to have opened the floodgates to an ugly triumphalism on the left. The result is a dogmatic form of liberalism that threatens to poison American civic life for the foreseeable future. Conservative Reihan Salam describes it, only somewhat hyperbolically, as a form of "weaponized secularism." The rise of dogmatic liberalism is the American left-wing expression of the broader trend that Mark Lilla identified in a recent blockbuster essay for The New Republic. The reigning dogma of our time, according to Lilla, is libertarianism — by which he means My own cherished topic is this: far more than the anti-tax, anti-regulation ideology that Americans identify with the post-Reagan Republican Party, and that the rest of the world calls "neoliberalism." At its deepest level, libertarianism is "a mentality, a mood, a presumption… a prejudice" in favor of the liberation of the autonomous individual from all constraints originating from received habits, traditions, authorities, or institutions. Libertarianism in this sense fuels the American right's anti-government furies, but it also animates the left's push for same-sex marriage — and has prepared the way for its stunningly rapid acceptance — in countries throughout the West. What makes libertarianism a dogma is the inability or unwillingness of those who espouse it to accept that some people might choose, for morally legitimate reasons, to dissent from it. On a range of issues, liberals seem not only increasingly incapable of comprehending how or why someone would affirm a more traditional vision of the human good, but inclined to relegate dissenters to the category of moral monsters who deserve to be excommunicated from civilized life — and sometimes coerced into compliance by the government. The latter tendency shows how, paradoxically, the rise of libertarian dogma can have the practical effect of increasing government power and expanding its scope. This happens when individuals look to the government to facilitate their own liberation from constraints imposed by private groups, organizations, and institutions within civil society. In such cases, the government seeks to bring those groups, organizations, and institutions into conformity with uniform standards that ensure the unobstructed personal liberation of all — even if doing so requires that these private entities are forced to violate their distinctive visions of the good. The left uses a debunk moral system to charge Israel and the US with moral crimes while hiding behind a shield of righteousness Cravatts, PHD, 12 (Richard, President of Scholars for Peace in the Middle East, 3/18/12, “How The Academic Left Came To Hate Israel”, The Jewish Press, http://www.jewishpress.com/indepth/frontpage/how-the-academic-left-came-to-hate-israel/2012/04/18/0/)//WB The visceral hatred by the Left of its favorite hobgoblins, imperialist America and its codependent oppressor, Israel, finds similar expression from morally defective professors such as Juan Cole, who in his writings regularly takes swipes at Israeli and American defenses while simultaneously excusing Arab complicity for violence or terror. In fact, according to Cole it is the militancy of the West that causes the endemic problems in the Middle East, and makes America guilty for its moral and financial support of Israel. “When Ariel Sharon sends American-made helicopter gunships and F16s to fire missiles into civilian residences or crowds in streets,” Cole wrote in 2004, “as he has done more than once, then he makes the United States complicit in his war crimes and makes the United States hated among friends of the Palestinians. And this aggression and disregard of Arab life on the part of the proto-fascist Israeli Right has gotten more than one American killed, including American soldiers.” This cultural condescension – the disingenuous lie from the Left that all cultures are equal but some are more or less equal, to paraphrase Orwell – leads liberals into a moral trap where they denounce Israel’s military self-defense as being barbaric, criminal, and Nazi-like (because Israel is a powerful, democratic nation) and regularly excuse or apologize for genocidal Arab terrorism as an acceptable and inevitable result of a weak people suffering under Western oppression. In fact, when a professor such as Columbia University’s Joseph Massad writes about Palestinian terror, he essentially justifies it by characterizing the very existence of Israel as being morally defective, based, in his view, on its inherent racist and imperialist nature. “What the Palestinians ultimately insist on is that Israel must be taught that it does not have the right to defend its racial supremacy,” Massad wrote during the 2009 Israeli defensive incursions into Gaza, “and that the Palestinians have the right to defend their universal humanity against Israel’s racist oppression.” The charge of racism also enables liberals to excuse the moral transgressions of the oppressed, and, as an extension of that thinking, to single out Israel and America for particular and harsh scrutiny owing to their perceived “institutionalized” racism and greater relative power. The self-righteousness leftists feel in pointing out Zionism’s essential defect of being a racist ideology insulates them from having to also reflect on Arab transgressions, since, as Ruth Wisse pointed out in If I Am Not For Myself: The Liberals Betrayal of the Jews, liberals can excuse their own betrayal of Israel by holding it fully responsible for the very hatreds it inspires. “Ascribing to Israel the blame for its predicament, democratic countries can pursue their self-interest free of any lingering moral scruple,” Wisse wrote. “Israel is examined for its every moral failing to justify policies of disengagement, while the moral failings of Arab countries are considered no one’s business but their own, so that their blatant abuses of human rights should not get in the way of realpolitick.” Coupled with academia’s fervent desire to make campuses socially ideal settings where the other newly-popular impulse to inculcate students with a longing for what is called “social justice,” a nebulous term lifted from Marxist thought that empowers left-leaning administrators and faculty with the false ethical security derived from feeling that they are bringing positive moral and ethical precepts to campuses. For the Left, according to David Horowitz, a former radical leftist turned conservative, social justice is “the concept of a world racial and cultural strife cease to exist is divided into oppressors and oppressed.” Those seeking social justice, therefore, do so with the intention of leveling the economic, cultural, and political playing fields; they seek to reconstruct society in a way that disadvantages the powerful and the elites, and overthrows them if necessary – in order that the dispossessed and weak can acquire equal standing. In other words, the Left yearns for a utopian society that does not yet exist, and is willing to reconstruct and overturn the existing status quo – often at a terrible human cost – in the pursuit of seeking so-called justice for those who, in their view, have been passed over or abused by history. And in the minds of academic leftists, there are no superior national behaviors; all nations are equal in value and in the court of world opinion. This contorted reason is commonly referred to as “moral relativism,” and is a seminal cause of the way Israel’s actions in defending itself against genocidal Arab aggression over 60 years are seen to be no different from homicide attacks on Israeli civilians initiated by its enemies. This rationalization, that violence is an acceptable, if not welcomed, component of seeking social justice – that is, that the inherent “violence” of imperialism, colonialism, or capitalism will be met by the same violence as the oppressed attempt to throw off their oppressors – is exactly the style of self-defeating rationality that in this age has proven to be an intractable part of the war on terror. America-hating and Israel-hating academics have not infrequently wished for harm to come to these countries at the hands of the victim groups to whom they readily give their sympathies. AT Stuff AT: Framework = Policing Acting with a policy rhetoric is the only way to create the change that leftist philosophers want McClean, 01 – Adjunct Professor of Philosophy, Molloy College, New York (David E., “The Cultural Left and the Limits of Social Hope,” Presented at the 2001 Annual Conference of the Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy, www.americanphilosophy.org/archives/past_conference_programs/pc2001/Discussion%20papers/david_mcclean.htm) Our new president, possessing no towering intellect, talks of a people who share a continent, but are not a nation. He is right, of course. We are only beginning to learn to put tribal loyalties aside and to let ourselves take seriously other more salutary possibilities, though we delude ourselves into believing that we have made great progress. Perhaps so-called "compassionate conservatism," though a gimmick to win a political contest, will bear a small harvest of unintended and positive consequences, although I remain dubious about this if the task of thinking through what it might actually mean remains the chore of George W. Bush. But if the nottoo-Neanderthal-Right is finally willing to meet the not-too-wacky-Left at a place of dialogue somewhere in the "middle," then that is good news, provided the Left does not miss the opportunity to rendevous. Yet, there is a problem here. Both the Cultural Left and the Cultural Right tend to be self-righteous purists. The best chance, then, is for the emergence of Rorty's new Political Left, in conjunction with a new Political Right . The new Political Left would be in the better position of the two to frame the discourse since it probably has the better intellectual hardware (it tends to be more open-minded and less dogmatic) to make a true dialogue work. They, unlike their Cultural Left peers, might find it more useful to be a little less inimical and a little more sympathetic to what the other side might, in good faith, believe is at stake. They might leave behind some of the baggage of the Cultural Left's endless ruminations (Dewey's philosophical cud chewing) about commodity fetishization, or whether the Subject has really died, or where crack babies fit into neo-capitalist hegemonies, and join the political fray by parsing and exposing the more basic idiotic claims and dogmas of witless politicians and dangerous ideologues, while at the same time finding common ground, a larger "We" perspective that includes Ronald Reagan and Angela Davis under the same tent rather than as inhabitants of separate worlds. The operative spirit should be that of fraternal disagreement, rather than self-righteous cold shoulders. Yet I am not at all convinced that anything I have described is about to happen, though this essay is written to help force the issue, if only a little bit. I am convinced that the modern Cultural Left is far from ready to actually run the risks that come with being taken seriously and held accountable for actual policy-relevant prescriptions. Why should it? It is a hell of a lot more fun and a lot more safe pondering the intricacies of high theory, patching together the world a priori (which means without any real consideration of those officers and bureaucrats I mentioned who are actually on the front lines of policy formation and regulation). However the risk in this apriorism is that both the conclusions and the criticisms will miss the mark, regardless of how great the minds that are engaged. Intellectual rigor and complexity do not make silly ideas politically salient, or less pernicious, to paraphrase Rorty. This is not to say that air-headed jingoism and conservative rants about republican virtue aren't equally silly and pernicious. But it seems to me that the new public philosopher of the Political Left will want to pick better yardsticks with which to measure herself. Is it really possible to philosophize by holding Foucault in one hand and the Code of Federal Regulation or the Congressional Record in the other? Given that whatever it has meant to be a philosopher has been under siege at various levels, I see no reason why referring to the way things are actually done in the actual world (I mean really done, not done as we might imagine) as we think through issues of public morality and social issues of justice shouldn't be considered a viable alternative to the way philosophy has proceeded in the past. Instead of replacing epistemology with hermeneutics or God knows what else as the foundation of philosophical practice, we should move social philosophers in the direction of becoming more like social and cultural auditors rather than further in the direction of mere culture critics. We might be able to recast philosophers who take-up questions of social justice in a serious way as the ones in society able to traverse not only disciplines but the distances between the towers of the academy and the bastions of bureaucracies seeking to honestly and sometimes dishonestly assess both their failings and achievements. This we can do with a special advantage over economists, social scientists and policy specialists who are apt to take the narrow view of most issues. We do have examples of such persons. John Dewey and Karl Popper come to mind as but two examples, but in neither case was there enough grasp of the actual workings of social institutions that I believe will be called for in order to properly minister to a nation in need of helpful philosophical insights in policy formation. Or it may just be that the real work will be performed by philosophically grounded and socially engaged practitioners rather than academics. People like George Soros come to mind here. But there are few people like George Soros around, and I think that the improbability of philosophers emerging as a special class of social auditor also marks the limits of social hope, inasmuch as philosophers are the class most likely to see the places at which bridges of true understanding can be built not only between an inimical Right and Left, but between public policy and the deep and relevant reflections upon our humanity in which philosophers routinely engage. If philosophers seek to remain what the public thinks we are anyway, a class of persons of whom it can be said, as Orwell put it, One has to belong to the intelligentsia to believe things like that; no ordinary man could be such a fool, then I do not know from what other class of persons to turn to navigate the complicated intellectual and emotional obstacles that prevent us from the achievement of our country. For I do not see how policy wonks, political hacks, politicians, religious ideologues and special interests will do the work that needs to be done to achieve the kind of civic consensus envisioned in our Constitution and Declaration of Independence. Without a courageous new breed of public intellectual, one that is able to help articulate new visions for community and social well being without fear of reaching out to others that may not share the narrow views of the Cultural Left and Cultural Right, I do not see how America moves beyond a mere land of toleration and oligarchy. Disagreement is central to debate as long as it produces a policy conclusion Anderson 6 (Amanda Anderson, Andrew W. Mellon Professor of Humanities and English at Brown University, Spring 2006, “Reply to My Critic(s),” Criticism, Vol. 48, No. 2, p. 281-290)//WB MY RECENT BOOK, The Way We Argue Now, has in a sense two theses. In the first place, the book makes the case for the importance of debate and argument to any vital democratic or pluralistic intellectual culture. This is in many ways an unexceptional position, but the premise of the book is that the claims of reasoned argument are often trumped, within the current intellectual terrain, by appeals to cultural identity and what I gather more broadly under the rubric of ethos, which includes cultural identity but also forms of ethical piety and charismatic authority. In promoting argument as a universal practice keyed to a human capacity for communicative reason, my book is a critique of relativism and identity politics, or the notion that forms of cultural authenticity or group identity have a certain unquestioned legitimacy, one that cannot or should not be subjected to the challenges of reason or principle, precisely because reason and what is often called "false universalism" are, according to this pattern of thinking, always involved in forms of exclusion, power, or domination. My book insists, by contrast, that argument is a form of respect, that the ideals of democracy, whether conceived from a nationalist or an internationalist perspective, rely fundamentally upon procedures of argumentation and debate in order to legitimate themselves and to keep their central institutions vital. And the idea that one should be protected from debate, that argument is somehow injurious to persons if it does not honor their desire to have their basic beliefs and claims and solidarities accepted without challenge, is strenuously opposed. As is the notion that any attempt to ask people to agree upon processes of reason-giving argument is somehow necessarily to impose a coercive norm, one that will disable the free expression and performance of identities, feelings, or solidarities. Disagreement is, by the terms of my book, a form of respect, not a form of disrespect. And by disagreement, I don't mean simply to say that we should expect disagreement rather than agreement, which is a frequently voiced-if misconceived-criticism of Habermas. Of course we should expect disagreement. My point is that we should focus on the moment of dissatisfaction in the face of disagreement-the internal dynamic in argument that imagines argument might be the beginning of a process of persuasion and exchange that could end in agreement (or partial agreement). For those who advocate reconciling ourselves to disagreements rather than arguing them out, by contrast, there is a complacent-and in some versions, even celebratory-attitude toward fixed disagreement. Refusing these options, I make the case for dissatisfied disagreement in the final chapter of the book and argue that people should be willing to justify their positions in dialogue with one another, especially if they hope to live together in a post-traditional pluralist society. One example of the trumping of argument by ethos is the form that was taken by the late stage of the Foucault/Habermas debate, where an appeal to ethos-specifically, an appeal to Foucault's style of ironic or negative critique, often seen as most in evidence in the interviews, where he would playfully refuse labels or evade direct answers-was used to exemplify an alternative to the forms of argument employed by Habermas and like-minded critics. (I should pause to say that I provide this example, and the framing summary of the book that surrounds it, not to take up airtime through expansive self-reference, but because neither of my respondents provided any contextualizing summary of the book's central arguments, though one certainly gets an incremental sense of the book's claims from Bruce Robbins. Because I don't assume that readers of this forum have necessarily read the book, and because I believe that it is the obligation of forum participants to provide sufficient context for their remarks, I will perform this task as economically as I can, with the recognition that it might have carried more weight if provided by a respondent rather than the author.) The Foucauldian counter-critique importantly emphasizes a relation between style and position, but it obscures (1) the importance or value of the Habermasian critique and (2) the possibility that the other side of the debate might have its own ethos to advocate, one that has precisely to do with an ethos of argument, an ideal of reciprocal debate that involves taking distance on one's pre-given forms of identity or the norms of one's community, both so as to talk across differences and to articulate one's claims in relation to shared and even universal ideals. And this leads to the second thesis of the book, the insistence that an emphasis on ethos and character is interestingly present if not widely recognized in contemporary theory, and one of the ways its vitality and existential pertinence makes itself felt (even despite the occurrence of the kinds of unfair trumping moves I have mentioned). We often fail to notice this, because identity has so uniformly come to mean sociological, ascribed, or group identity-race, gender, class, nationality, ethnicity, sexuality, and so forth. Instances of the move toward character and ethos include the later Foucault (for whom ethos is a central concept), cosmopolitanism (whose aspiration it is to turn universalism into an ethos), and, more controversially, proceduralist ethics and politics (with its emphasis on sincerity and civility). Another version of this attentiveness to ethos and character appears in contemporary pragmatism, with its insistence on casualness of attitude, or insouciance in the face of contingency-recommendations that get elevated into full-fledged exemplary personae in Richard Rorty's notion of the "ironist" or Barbara Herrnstein Smiths portrait of the "postmodern skeptic." These examples-and the larger claim they support-are meant to defend theory as still living, despite the many reports of its demise, and in fact still interestingly and incessantly re-elaborating its relation to practice. This second aspect of the project is at once descriptive, motivated by the notion that characterology within theory is intrinsically interesting, and critical, in its attempt to identify how characterology can itself be used to cover or evade the claims of rational argument, as inappeals to charismatic authority or in what !identify as narrow personifications of theory (pragmatism, in its insistence on insouciance in the face of contingency, is a prime example of this second form). And as a complement to the critical agenda, there is a reconstructive agenda as well, an attempt to recuperate liberalism and proceduralism, in part by advocating the possibility, as I have suggested, of an ethos of argument. Robbins, in his extraordinarily rich and challenging response, zeroes in immediately on a crucial issue: who is to say exactly when argument is occurring or not, and what do we do when there is disagreement over the fundamentals (the primary one being over what counts as proper reasoning)? Interestingly, Robbins approaches this issue after first observing a certain tension in the book: on the one hand, The Way We Argue Now calls for dialogue, debate, argument; on the other, its project is "potentially something a bit stricter, or pushier: getting us all to agree on what should and should not count as true argument." What this point of entry into the larger issue reveals is a kind of blur that the book, I am now aware, invites. On the one hand, the book anatomizes academic debates, and in doing so is quite "debaterly" This can give the impression that what I mean by argument is a very specific form unique to disciplinary methodologies in higher education. But the book is not generally advocating a narrow practice of formal and philosophical argumentation in the culture at large, however much its author may relish adherence to the principle of non-contradiction in scholarly argument. I take pains to elaborate an ethos of argument that is linked to democratic debate and the forms of dissent that constitutional patriotism allows and even promotes. In this sense, while argument here is necessarily contextualized sociohistorically, the concept is not merely academic . It is a practice seen as integral to specific political forms and institutions in modern democracies, and to the more general activity of critique within modern societies-to the tradition of the public sphere, to speak in broad terms. Additionally, insofar as argument impels one to take distance on embedded customs, norms, and senses of given identity, it is a practice that at once acknowledges identity, the need to understand the perspectives of others, and the shared commitment to commonality and generality, to finding a way to live together under conditions of difference. More than this: the book also discusses at great length and from several different angles the issue that Robbins inexplicably claims I entirely ignore: the question of disagreement about what counts as argument. In the opening essay, "Debatable Performances," I fault the proponents of communicative ethics for not having a broader understanding of public expression, one that would include the disruptions of spectacle and performance. I return to and underscore this point in my final chapter, where I espouse a democratic politics that can embrace and accommodate a wide variety of expressions and modes. This is certainly a discussion of what counts as dialogue and hence argument in the broad sense in which I mean it, and in fact I fully acknowledge that taking distance from cultural norms and given identities can be advanced not only through critical reflection, but through ironic critique and defamiliarizing performance as well. But I do insist-and this is where I take a position on the fundamental disagreements that have arisen with respect to communicative ethics-that when they have an effect, these other dimensions of experience do not remain unreflective, and insofar as they do become reflective, they are contributing to the very form of reasoned analysis that their champions sometimes imagine they must refuse in order to liberate other modes of being (the affective, the narrative, the performative, the nonrational). If a narrative of human rights violation is persuasive in court, or in the broader cultural public sphere, it is because it draws attention to a violation of humanity that is condemned on principle; if a performance jolts people out of their normative understandings of sexuality and gender, it prompts forms of understanding that can be affirmed and communicated and also can be used to justify political positions and legislative agendas.