Educating liberty *** Rousseauvian influences on the progressive education systems of Maria Montessori and Helen Parkhurst Oscar Peeters 3113337 21-06-2012 |2 Introduction .................................................................................................................................... 3 Rousseau ........................................................................................................................................ 9 Montessori .................................................................................................................................... 25 Parkhurst .................................................................................................................................... 41 Concluding ................................................................................................................................... 57 Epilogue ....................................................................................................................................... 67 Bibliography ................................................................................................................................. 71 Appendices ..............................................................................Error! Bookmark not defined. 3| Introduction When Rousseau published his work Émile in 1762, the world was ready for a new treatise on education. A serious attempt had not been made since Plato’s ‘The Republic’, where he touched upon morality and justice. Thus, in an era dictated by a new belief in rationality and liberty, Rousseau’s book was both a product of its time and a welcome addition to it. Rousseau, both taking part in the Enlightenment and being a forerunner of the Romantics, presented to the world a new form of education, moving from a teacher-oriented curriculum to a pupil-oriented version. Shifting the focus from the tutor to the apprentice created a completely new outset for education. The significance of these first pioneering steps into the world of educational reform cannot be underestimated. For centuries, the foundation of education had been the radiating of experience and knowledge by wise, older mentors. This required a belief in the value of accumulated knowledge, carefully selected over time and passed on by someone fulfilling a teaching role (that being a parent, an educator or someone else in a responsible position). In contrast, Rousseau asserted that the potentiality of natural development was being overlooked. This ‘proto-Romantic’ concept served as one of the preludes for the return to nature the Romantics propagated in reaction to the Enlightenment thinkers, as they saw both the power of the human being in its purest form (natural, unabated by human constructs), whilst at the same time addressing the arrogance of a relentless belief in human rationality. Rousseau, in Émile, addresses this dichotomy through his new ideas on education. The fictitious child Émile is to be both let free (albeit in a designated area) in order to not hamper his or her potential for natural development. The child, instead of being constrained to a strict curriculum, a time table and a fixed learning path, chooses his or her own path, and perhaps just as important: s/he is allowed to |4 make mistakes.1 Through the possibility of making mistakes, the child is responsible for his or her own ‘lessons’. Simultaneously, Rousseau stages several experiments, both to monitor of progress and to instruct the child in various fields (mostly covering ethics).2 These are modelled in a way that the child still feels responsible for his or her own actions and accomplishments, maintaining the change in relationship between tutor and pupil. These two concepts, responsibility and liberty, combined with exercises that stimulate the child to think are three elements that other thinkers have picked up. Rousseau’s book has provided renewed views on education, but as a workable guide, it proved to be hardly useful. The extreme (though fictional) experiment Rousseau describes, clashes with conventional ethics—to what extent one can experiment with a person’s life— and practicality, as it is impossible to separate a child from others for the first twelve years of his or her life. Evidentially, the treatise contains some highly volatile ideas about pedagogy, but they were set forth in a too unrefined and unpractical manner to be useful. However, various later thinkers recognised Émile as a promising new application of the Enlightenment concept of freedom and the Romantic notion of nature. Thus, they picked up where Rousseau stopped, and set out to develop these new insights even further. Thinkers like Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi and his student Friedrich Fröbel picked up Rousseau’s new direction, concentrating ever more on the liberty of the pupil, having faith in the natural development of the child. Battling illiteracy and working to provide younger children with proper preparation for society—including politics, interaction, ethics and skills to be used in prospective jobs—and through education, the ideas of these highly influential thinkers still prevail in many modern school systems, specifically the kindergarten and the focus on individual differences between children. I have tried to keep the child as gender-neutral as possible, using ‘his or her’ when possible, and ‘s/he’ to denominate the first case pronouns. Sometimes I might use solely ‘his’ or ‘he’, for language has no grammatical construction that denominates a gender-neutral, yet personal subject. 2 Rousseau, J.J., Émile, or On Education (A. Bloom, transl.) (Harmondsworth 1991, original work published in 1762) op. cit. 1 5| The ‘long’ nineteenth century is characterised by deep social changes and their correspondent political changes. The time-span saw the rise of modern society, comprising the dawn of the middle class, the modern political system and a technological spur history had not witnessed before. As true heirs to both the Romantics and the Enlightenment it comes as no surprise that these concepts and concrete developments merged in thoughts of many people from the nineteenth century. The age saw the dawn of the ‘real’ social sciences; amongst them anthropology, history3, psycho- and sociology, linguistics and pedagogy. In this thesis, I will focus on this last development, the heightened interest in and structuring of pedagogy. Sprouting from the social turmoil in the nineteenth century, were many educational reformers, combining ideas on the development of children, ranging from psychology to philosophy to biology. The rise of the state provided the necessary means, the rise of the population the necessary ‘test subjects’, and the rise of the media the necessary publicity. In a matter of decades, entering the twentieth century, the world saw the rise of numerous new educational systems. Politically and socially entangled, these new educational systems had great promises in store for the future of society, the position of the lower and middle classes and the role of the individual. Two of these systems were extremely promising, as they vouched for two core values to be instilled in the child: responsibility and freedom. These systems were the Montessori Method by Maria Montessori and the Dalton Laboratory Plan by Helen Parkhurst. These two reformers brought forth their ideas in the first quarter of the twentieth century, and were direct heirs to the aforementioned developments in the previous age. In this treatise, I will scrutinise both reform tracts for Rousseauvian elements, to see how they moulded Rousseau’s concepts of freedom and natural development into holistic educational models of their own. Through first defining Rousseau’s view on education and upbringing, I History, naturally, had existed before, but it was in the nineteenth century that intellectuals like Leopold von Ranke founded a professional form of writing history known as historicism. 3 |6 will provide a ‘test model’ that I can use to hold these two educational systems against the light. Secondly, I will say something about the prevalence of these two systems. Montessori’s system is still prevalent in many parts of the world, and therefore seems to be a lot more successful (at least in numbers) than the Dalton system, which apart from still being present in Northwestern Europe, has almost completely disappeared. It seems that there is more to say about these systems than merely their curriculum and its approach. They can tell us something about the position of the individual in society, its behaviour and its place within a political model. In addition to that, it must be noted that out of the educational reformers around the turn of the century many were women, stepping inside the arena with such power that they have been prominent in this field ever since. This is definitely an aspect I would like to shed a light on in my comparative research of these two models. Before I continue into the main body of my argument, there is some definitional clearing up to do. I personally struggle with the terminology. I am researching ‘education’; however, this word entails two concepts, which in the English language is sadly denoted to one word. In the continental German languages there is a dichotomy of terms: the words opvoeding and onderwijs (erziehung and unterricht) mean completely different things. The former means the education of the child by the parents, comprising mostly lessons concerning moral, common sense and general knowledge, and the latter being school or ‘factual’ education. These words have different meanings, and although they can overlap, they are in no way interchangeable. This difference is important to me, because especially in modern society where schools are accessible to all people, it is the opvoeding that is often (partially) decisive for the pupil’s educational path. Also, we see differences in the meaning of the word ‘education’ in Rousseau, Montessori and Parkhurst, hence I will continue to make the distinction between the two, and will use their Dutch equivalents to elucidate my argument. Lastly, I will expound on my historiographical and methodological views. Foremost, I believe in the power of the writer. In the ‘structure versus agency’- 7| debate raging through the field of critical theory in the latter part of the twentieth century, the agency of the writer has almost completely been eradicated by the belief in underlying power structures as set forth by like poststructuralists like Michel Foucault, Roland Barthes and Jacques Derrida. Through their systematic analysis of texts, they have ‘depersonalised’ their meanings, focusing too much on structures. Especially with ‘great intellectuals’, I find this a thoroughly over-simplifying approach. It is a given that they were a product of their time, used the same language and literary conventions, but these intellectuals often sought to take a meta-stance in overviewing problems. They were aware of pros and cons, knew the history, and merely sought to describe or from solutions for the given problems. Therefore, I will take a middle stance in treating my primary sources, in a way reminiscent of Michel de Certeau. De Certeau, mainly remembered in the historian’s field for his theory on ‘strategies’ and ‘tactics’, he argued that human beings act both from inner, uncontrollable forces (somewhat Freudian) and from the use of proactively formed ‘tactics’. Secondly, we live in a world interlaced with institutions and structures. These exert power on the individual’s live through ‘strategies.’4 Thus, people are both lived through strategies, but chose to adapt to them through tactics. In a similar fashion, I will cover the writings on education as being products of their time, but willingly proposed to address problems and solutions. *** Education is vital for the functioning of society. It is an integral part of the socialisation of every human being and is essential for interaction and cooperation with others. In addition, in the increasingly secular Western world, education has taken up many of the tasks previously reserved for religion. It is thus that I attribute great value to these two school systems, as they help form Certeau, M. de, The Practice of Everyday Life (T. Tomasik, transl.) (Minneapolis 1998, original work published in 1980) op. cit. 4 |8 the responsible and autonomous human being that is essential for preserving (or creating) a wise society. I believe that by looking at the history of these two systems, we can shed a new light on them, and provide new insights on our own societies. In this thesis, I will look for the Rousseauvian view on educational reform in the works on education by Helen Parkhurst and Maria Montessori. I will pinpoint vital concepts of educational reform, and trace their development through a case study of three varied progressive educators. I will see how the ides transcended from mere theoretical ruminations to practical applications, tested in society. Furthermore, I will see how zeitgeist played an important role in the formation of these theories, as the educational reform tracts were thoroughly shaped by the hopes and ideals of their respective contemporary world views. Furthermore, I will bring forth how there was a constant reciprocity between intellectual and culture. Now, let us turn to our first prolific writer who paved the way for onderwijs. 9| Rousseau Educational reform over-arches this dissertation, a topic interesting to all times, as it concerns every human being. Important as it may seem, educational reform is a very recent phenomenon in history. The traditional curriculum centred on the ‘teacher-instructs-pupil’-model has prevailed (and still is in most places) for the majority of history. In a new approach to both define change within this system and look for its locus, I start with Rousseau; one of the first educational reformers of the modern era. It is important to pinpoint what exactly Rousseau set forth in his writings on education before we can see how these findings made their way into the twentieth century. Therefore, I will expound in this chapter on Rousseau’s thoughts and reflections on education, which comprised much more than simple ‘schooling’. In order to evaluate Rousseau’s body of thought fairly, I will expound on the context from which his ideas arose. Secondly, I will give a brief overview of Émile, ou de l’Education, followed by larger political and moral lessons apparent elsewhere in his books (amongst them du Contrat Social ou Principes du droit Politique, Considérations sur le gouvernement de Pologne and Julie, ou la nouvelle Héloïse)5 which, as I shall argue are important to grasping Rousseau’s thoughts in their totality. As Rousseau wrote books treating a wide variety of political and moral subjects, it is not easy to distil a coherent worldview. However, concerning his all-embracing view on education, it is important to see how political and moral ideas went hand-in-hand with theories about education. 5 Henceforth, du Contrat Social, Pologne, Héloïse and Émile respectively. | 10 Enlightenment’s edge I have a fascination with intellectuals that seem to belong to two contradicting traditions. Rousseau is one of those figures of interest. His works contain both parts of the Enlightenment and the Romantics, rendering them a unique testimony to the transition of eighteenth-century thought. His works contain both a belief in the universality of nature and a longing for order and progress. However, unlike his fellow ‘pure-blood’ enlightenment colleagues, he saw the uncontrollable power of nature (to a large extent interchangeable with his notion of a benevolent creating God) as a source for many of these universalisms. It brought forth more a nostalgic yearning for the state of nature, the primitive man and society, than a positivist belief in deduction and the formation of laws. This view is apparent in all his reflections on society, the nature of man, politics, ethics and most importantly for this dissertation: education. The eighteenth century witnessed some sweeping transformations of society. To name a few, it witnessed the consolidation of the modern ‘state’, the upcoming bourgeois society, saw the beginnings of mass urbanisation centred around the upcoming industrious centres, and furthermore the thorough spread of salaried employment. These three examples—which were not exclusive to the eighteenth century, but had their most impact in that era— all had their impact on what Jürgen Habermas calls ‘the public sphere’ (Öffentlichkeit).6 This public sphere, as opposed to the private sphere, was developed between modern society and feudal society, as property relations began to change under influence of transformations in society. Under the feudal system, there was no proper distinction between the private and the public. In the seventeenth and eighteenth century, however, the dawn of the modern state system under absolutism resulted in parliaments and bureaucracy, which led to an abandonment of the minimalist ‘night watch’-state. The state’s Habermas, J., Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft. (Frankfurt a. M. 1990) op. cit. 6 11 | increasing involvement in the citizen’s life resulted more and more in a thorough distinction between what was public and what was private. Industrial centres shifted the traditional source of income from agriculture more and more to factories that employed workers based on commission or salaries. ‘Going to work’ replaced working on the land to supply food, creating yet another distinction between the public and the private. Lastly, the growth of the middle class, which provided an alternative to ‘rule or being ruled’, led to the formation of a diverse array of societies, debating the events of the day. This division between the public and the private is important for this thesis, as it provides background to the writings discussed. We shall see that Rousseau’s piece, written in a time when modern time was still in its infancy, the state lacks the power and skills to employ certain ideas about the education of man. It lacks practicality and result, and serves more as a book filled with ruminations and reflections than as an actual guide for the betterment of society. Wholly different are the approaches of the two women writers that present the world their own book of instruction, ready to be implemented in an already existing educational system. Furthermore, the division between public and private sphere was of great influence for the role of women in society. Whereas in agricultural society there was no little to no schooling, it was required of all the members of the household to help with the work on the land. However, with modern times approaching—and this, of course, was less so in Rousseau’s time, but most definitely in that of Montessori and Parkhurst—the ‘traditional’ family roles were with increasing frequency affirmed: the man works, the woman takes care and the child learns. This transformation of the role of different members of the household rendered it possible for women educational reformers to take the reins in this field. I will thread into more detail on the role of feminism and the private sphere in the chapter on Montessori. I have argued that Rousseau arose from an era of Enlightenment thinkers, in an era thoroughly transformed by the upcoming state and its bureaucracy, the onset of industrialisation and the change in societal relations under influence of the middle class. Rousseau cast doubts on the universal truth of | 12 the Enlightenment thinkers, and reaffirmed God as a driving force in the nature of things. In this context, we must place Émile, a book on the education of man(kind). Educating Émile After Jean-Jacques Rousseau spent the first thirty years of his life traveling, taking up jobs of different nature, he started to put his ideas to paper, rendering them more comprehensible. In several ‘discourses’ and novels, he treated a wide variety of topics. The works that concern me the most were published within a year of each other, differing in form, but containing the same theoretical framework. Between 1761 and 1762, Héloïse, du Contrat Social and Émile (in chronological order) were published. Héloïse, treating ‘sentimentalism’ and domestic education was followed by du Contrat Social, which covered moral and political aspects of society. Both of these were combined in Rousseau’s vision on education in his ‘novel’ Émile.7 Émile serves as the sandbox for his ideas about the natural aspects of mankind, the way we live together, morality and how humans develop. Rousseau creates a fictional character that is raised alone by a tutor. Through creating a relationship between two fictional characters, Rousseau is able to develop a concise theory about the capabilities of the ‘natural man’. This, thus, should not be read as a concrete educational theory, but more in the line of his other works: philosophical reflections on mankind. The book, however, contains several elements picked up by educational reformers for their innovativeness. I am looking for these elements, to catch their momentum and impact, and to see how they are still useful for today’s educational systems. So, the fictional character Émile sprang to life: an average boy of modest intelligence and physique. The boy, entrusted by his parents (who remain I put novel in brackets; given that this was the denomination Rousseau himself gave to the book, however, the modern definition of a novel does not remotely correspond to this piece of work. 7 13 | unknown) to a tutor, is set out to receive the perfect education: that of nature. The education through nature, unaccompanied by education through things or humans, is the most reliable form of education. This tripartite division of the educational source is made to categorise the different levels of acquiring education, as all of them should be treated with varying dispositions. Thus, nature is the knowledge intrinsically contained in the human mind and body. It is the most ‘safe’ source of knowledge, since man is unable to tamper with it. It is therefore unmediated, pure knowledge, where the greatest trust should be assigned to. The second source, coming from things, is a slightly alterable source of knowledge. Man can manipulate it, select it or suppress it. However, things retain their qualities, bringing them only partially within our control. The last source of education is that of men. It is the only kind we have full control over, making it both very valuable, but dangerous when conducted wrongly. The three sources of education have to be in harmony because conflicted interests make up for an ill-educated individual. The state of nature is one of Rousseau’s most prevalent concepts, appearing in many of his books. Whether it is the state we strayed from and thus inherited feelings of inequality or the state of the savage, content with primal needs unspoiled by human constructs, it plays a thoroughly fecund role in Rousseau’s writings. Also starting from this principle in his work on education, Rousseau introduces the reader to the concept of negative education. This concept entails the view that the child harnesses a potential to develop on its own, but is capable of injuring himself (mentally and physically). Therefore, the tutor should shield him from making the most severe of mistakes, the ones that will do permanent damage. Through the refraining of interference the child is able to develop skills on its own, attributing more value to them, as he will know he acquired them without help or intrusion. The premises underlying this concept are both the belief in the intrinsic goodness of human nature (a concept widely debated by the Protestants, and although Rousseau, born in Geneva was raised a Catholic, he converted to the Calvinist Church to regain Swiss citizenship) and the belief in the capability of the child to figure things out on his own with positive result. These two assumptions are | 14 contested even today, rendering Rousseau’s book important yet fallible. The child Émile, tutored through a refraining of education is allowed to roam the surrounding lands, as the development of his physique and senses are contributive to the development of his mental strength as well. He may encounter all sorts of things, learning from them every day. A child allowed to play around the house, that is all? For the time being, yes. As Émile is shielded from any ‘uncontrolled’ (human) influences, he is not allowed to interact with other human beings beside the tutor, not allowed to read any books or theories by others and is thus raised solitarily. The tutor, responsible for shielding the child from harmful influences, is only able to retain full control of this state through the expulsion of human influences. Coincidently, Rousseau retains his belief in the potential of human nature, and thereby insists on the abdication of corrupting human constructs like scientific theories and human conventions.8 The child is not to read books before s/he is ready for it (preposterously, this cannot occur before he is twelve), as many of the abhorrences of mankind have been formed and written in through books. The child is simply not ready for those theories, as he does not have the skill yet to determine which are right and which are wrong. So, the child’s education should foremost be about exploring the senses and the physique; the intellectual training comes much later. Having done away with these vile influences, the child is able to acquire skills by him- or herself through trial and error. Apart from the liberation of the child in order to let him obtain skills by himself, Rousseau acknowledges (apparently) that the child is not fully able to acquire all the skills by himself, through nature, for he sets out to stage several events that introduce the child to basic concepts of morality and property. In one of these events, the tutor takes Émile to a piece of land, lets him work on it and sow some beans. After a few days, Émile discovers that the earth has been ploughed over and the bean sprouts removed. The child is angered, because his property (lesson one) was destroyed. However, as the gardener comes by and tells Émile that it was he who roughed the patch up, Émile is being told that 8 Rousseau, Émile, op. cit. 15 | some weeks before, the gardener had planted very expensive Maltese melon seeds in the ground, and it was he who was the victim of the destroyed crops. Émile’s second lesson then entails how differences of opinion are complex, and how property is a multi-dimensional concept. These many lessons are meant to slowly teach the child to cope with the difficulties of interaction and society. It is in society that Rousseau sees the biggest complication. On its own, the child is free, independent and unmediated. The interaction with other human beings makes him dependent, emotionally frail and susceptible to bad influences. It is thus that Rousseau wants to raise the child away from society, as the child is not reasonable enough to withstand mankind’s constructed world; man and its highly esteemed ‘wisdom’ do not realise that it is in fact slavish prejudice, and keeps us with its customs in constraint, compulsion and control. By shielding the child from external human influences, the teacher is more able to shield the child from malicious external factors. However, eventually the child has to abide in society, and it is the tutor’s task to introduce him to moral and ethical concepts to allow him to make the right decisions in life. *** Rousseau’s other works form an excellent example for how Émile should behave in life. It seems that du Contrat Social is the state version of the educational methods professed in Émile, and that Émile is the educational version of the political and moral lessons professed in du Contrat Social. As explained above, the tutor’s task is to coerce the child into developing the right skills on its own, staging events and allowing the child to roam the lands free and uninhibited by other human beings. This is remarkably similar to Rousseau’s vision of the ideal state in du Contrat Social. The citizen being free in its actions is (unknowingly) coerced into adopting the ‘general will’. Democracy is instilled, but the Legislator (reminiscent of the Tutor) is inclined to organise society in a way that the greater good will be served. In order to | 16 prevent these visions from colliding, the people are educated through festivals and other civic events what moral ideas are beneficial to society.9 The second concept the subject (both Émile and the citizen) is introduced to, is the difference between amour propre and amour de soi. These terms are fundamental to understanding Rousseau’s thoughts, so I will take the time to elucidate them a little further. Amour de soi is the primitive love of the self, inclined to self-preservation. It implies the basic natural impulses by which a human is driven, which allows a human being to make decisions based on nothing more than survival. This is an innocent force, attuned to doing well. In contrast, amour propre is self-interest and it is the first deviation of mankind from its true, good nature. Rousseau claims that amour propre does not imply negative consequences necessarily, but should always be in harmony with nature. However, ever so often, amour propre takes up too large a part of the human’s actions; it disrupts this harmony.10 Self-interest is one of the main sources of corruption in society: Thus the seeds of amour-propre, of living in the approval of others, were planted in the human soul which came to be corrupted with the artificial and negative sentiments of vanity, envy, shame, contempt, and outraged pride; and with them the thirst for revenge and retribution.11 In Émile, this self-interest is featured as the basis for sexual desire and the competitiveness felt towards others. The rivalry stands in the way of solidarity in altruism, and should therefore be treated with the greatest caution, as it is capable of disrupting society and its social ties. As we move through the different life phases, the teacher takes up a different relationship with the child. Whereas first the teacher is an ‘accomplice’, he gradually transforms into a more traditional teacher, laying Rousseau, J.J., Social Contract, the (G.D.H. Cole, transl.) (Buffalo 1988, original work published in 1762) op. cit. 10 Bertram, C., “Jean Jacques Rousseau”, in: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 ), visited on June, 21st, 2012, accessible at: <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/rousseau>. 11 Rousseau, Social Contract, 74. 9 17 | boundaries whenever possible. This is necessary, because the aforementioned amour propre tends to increase as the child ages. To keep this force at bay, restrictions are increasingly made for the pupil. These restrictions become especially apparent when Émile enters the phase of adolescence. It is this phase of adolescence, which is crucial to Rousseau as the powers of the teacher are then the weakest, and the potential for corruption is the highest through amour propre and interaction with other human beings, whilst at the same time the adolescent has a not yet mature rationale. The fourth part of the book, containing Le Profession de Foi du Vicaire Savoyard, Rousseau found one of his most important pieces. This ‘sub-plot’ in Émile tells the tale of a Vicar who was forced to question his faith after he broke the vow of celibacy. Unable to render any theories about the world and the creation, he continues to follow his lumière interieure, his free will, explaining how the freedom works. This freedom, a force that is not bound by mechanical or physical limitations, is the strongest thing humanity possesses.12 Finally, he ends up with a belief in what is natural religion, deducted from everything around him; the vicar cannot believe differently than that, a single benevolent creator created this world. That this was not a Christian god per sé aroused discussion amongst the public, invoking a ban on the book.13 This section is important, because it teaches the child Émile what religion is, how to profess it, and that there is something like an individual, almost rational, conceivable religion. At the same time, it teaches us what Rousseau’s views on religion were. Paradoxically, religion was individual, but everyone, as long as they were properly educated was ought to believe the same ‘truth’. In the last part of the book, part V; the child Émile is introduced to his future wife, Sophie. She was designed as a direct counterpart to Émile; the ideal wife that completes the man. Therefore, she had to receive a wholly different education: Rousseau, Émile, 567. Delaney, J., “Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712—1778)” in: Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (October 21, 2005) visited on June, 21st, 2012, accessible at: < http://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseau/#H6>. 12 13 | 18 the whole education of women ought to relate to men. To please men, to be useful to them, to make herself loved and honoured by them, to raise them when young, to care for them when grown, to counsel them, to console them, to make their lives agreeable and sweet – these are the duties of women at all times, and they ought to be taught from childhood. (p. 365) This statement underwent much critique, starting with Mary Wollstonecraft: What opinion are we to form of a system of education, when the author (Rousseau in Émile) says...’Educate women like men, and the more they resemble our sex the less power will they have over us.’ This is the very point I am at. I do not wish them to have power over men, but over themselves. The most perfect education, in my opinion, is (...) to enable the individual to attain such habits of virtue as will render it independent. (...) This was Rousseau’s opinion respecting men: I extend it to women (...) If children are to be educated to understand the true principle of patriotism, their mother must be a patriot…make women rational creatures, and free citizens, and they will quickly become good wives, and mothers; that is-if men do not neglect the duties of husbands and fathers. 14 Feminists ever since have scorned Rousseau for such exhortations, and it seems especially strange regarding the many educational reformers that were (and are) women. However, one must not forget that this was written in the 1750s and 1760s, and the first major feminist movements with success were still 140 years away. In addition, even more ironic might be to observe that in current western society, women are outnumbering men amongst higher education graduates. Rousseau argued that the education and role must be different, because women have different qualities and strengths from men. To return to the amour propre, women’s vanity is important to them, as appearance plays a large role in their lives. Hence, everything to do with amour Groag Bell, S. and Offen, K., Women, the Family, and Freedom: The Debate in Documents, Volume One, 1750-1880. (Stanford 1983) 60. 14 19 | propre should not be discouraged as part of their education. They are by default a social being, interacting with others more than their male counterparts do, and should be educated accordingly. Moreover, “the principles of utility and readiness apply to her education as much as they do to Émile’s. She must learn to read, to write, to do arithmetic, but only to the degree that will be useful for her.”15 In the end, it may seem that the master’s work is over, as Émile will be a tutor himself one day. However, in the final pages, Émile asks his tutor to teach him to teach, creating an everlasting chain of patronage. With this in mind, Rousseau wrote his book as a treatise of moral regeneration, after moral society has decayed for many years, burdened under social constructs and ethical depravity. Rousseau, then, has hope for the future, because of a relentless faith in human nature. He ushers us to do away with the heavy load of intellectual tradition and the Lumières that build upon this. How can man be so arrogant to try to fathom nature, God’s wonder? In addition, how can the Enlightenment thinkers try to reduce everything to laws and constants, while it is clear that nature is perfect and mankind is its flaw? Rousseau appeals for a return to nature having faith that the force to regenerate mankind lies within ourselves. Jean-Jacques Rousseau is thus positive yet not positivist. Natural development Rousseau thus led a tumultuous life, allying himself with different religions, political factions and countries. His publications spanning roughly forty years comprise many different fields, ranging from musicology to ethics. However, his views on moral and political issues proved to be the most illuminating, earning their place in many philosophical canons. A recurring theme in Rousseau’s works is the course of nature, capable of doing nothing but good. Although Rousseau recognises that the natural state might be a state more theoretical than actual, he nonetheless describes the 15 Rousseau, Émile, 369. | 20 natural state as a mode in human thought. This mode, unhindered by ‘artificial’, human constructions allows him to deduce what qualities of society and mankind are formed, and which are intrinsically inherent in human nature. Duly, by using very descriptive terms, as if Rousseau is describing a common ancestor, he conjures images of this noblesse sauvage to illustrate moral and ethical themes. We can see the natural man work through in his Discours sur l’origine et les fondements de l’inégalité parmi les hommes, where he argues that man in his natural state had no concept of inequality. It was only due to the introduction of human constructions like property that man strayed from his original path.16 Secondly, we see the course of natural development in perhaps his most famous work: Du Contrat social, ou Principes du droit Politique. In this work, Rousseau introduces the reader to general human connections and how they have developed from the aforementioned ‘theoretical’ natural state. Man, born free, must come to a social contract with his fellow men to ensue certain guarantees. Protection, rules of property, laws, etc. (in the modern era, aspects like the welfare state were duly added) are aspects of this contract. Accordingly, man submits himself to the ‘general will’. Every man is still free, and has to approve of laws, lest they become void from lack of consent. The general will, represented by a sovereign (consisting of the populace) is mediated by a Legislator, as mentioned above, reminiscent of the Tutor in Émile, coercing the people to have the ‘right’ general will. Rousseau ventures back in time, to the theoretical natural man, in order to rebuild society. By going back, he traces the human constructs that have proven faulty, having caused many of the problems in society present in his day. From this primitive state, he advises mankind what moral and political decisions they should make in order to regenerate mankind. I stress once more that this relentless belief in the theoretical, benevolent state of mankind is the basis of Rousseau’s body of thought. 16 Rousseau, Social Contract, op. cit. 21 | Education in other works Rousseau’s first reflections on education start in 1750, when he writes his Discours sur les sciences et les arts, and he briefly addresses the state of education in the country at the present time. He touches upon the function of public schools, and how they not fulfil their role in society, asking himself whether they should exist at all. Then, later, in 1758, he touches upon the subject again, addressing education in Discours sur l’Economie Politique. Although posthumously published, Rousseau again, more coherently addresses education when he writes the Considérations sur le gouvernement de Pologne. This constitution for the newly formed country Poland forms an exercise for Rousseau, and helps him to get his thoughts more coherent. Here he addresses the equality of man, and briefly touches upon state education. But perhaps most importantly, and regrettably often overlooked, is his ‘sentimental novel’ Julie, ou de la Nouvelle Héloïse, which extensively treats domestic education. As I said in my introduction, there is a difference between onderwijs and opvoeding. Whereas in Héloïse, the topic is clearly opvoeding, in Émile, the terms get tangled up ever more. As the pupil is home-tutored, receiving lessons in morality, politics, the other sex, the physique and many other fields, the distinction is blurred thoroughly. However, in Héloïse we are introduced to terms relating to the natural development of the children. The book, centred on a family, deals with relationships between people; amongst them spouses, long-lost lovers and children. Julie, the main protagonist of the book, takes care of two boys, raising them according to methods reminiscent of what one is later to find in Émile: The boys, she says, must be treated as children and allowed their natural freedom; being boisterous and uninhibited is how they express and enjoy it. Instruction will follow later when they are ready for it. (...) Their readiness to learn must be respected always and, at this age, their physical development must be a priority. They must | 22 not be subjected to any regime of books or study that makes for a sedentary life.17 Here, the state of natural education is recalled, as well as a curriculum of delayed introduction to books, a fact that was derived from Rousseau’s aversion to ‘human constructs’. Having discussed the analogy between Legislator and Tutor, we see the same role in the head of the household, the paterfamilias; a leader that inspires the other members of the family. The family could duly be seen as a miniature model of the ideal political arrangement. The fact that Rousseau seems to draw an analogy between the two, is remarkable, as the Western world now tend to see both as two completely different spheres. The European (or American) family in the Early Modern age is increasingly retreating to the private sphere, and rapidly increasing in the eighteenth and nineteenth century—, whereas politics and press increasingly start to dominate the public sphere. If the premise that humans are intrinsically the same by nature is accepted, it allows for the abstaining of distinguishing different roles and kinds of behaviour. Accordingly, Rousseau does not see a difference between performing in the public and the private sphere, and levels them, eradicating their contrasts. The distinction I made earlier between two kinds of education are a further extension of this dichotomy between the public and the private sphere. Whereas onderwijs is a largely publicly affiliated area, comprising facts and skills, opvoeding often happens behind closed doors in the private sphere.18 The latter part of education, more affiliated with moral and ethical lessons, comprises a different way and place of teaching. We are going to see that this divide will take a different turn when we approach the contemporary era, and the public and private sphere are more separated than ever. Rousseau, Émile, 23. I am aware that nowadays teachers are increasingly concerned with matters opvoeding-related as well. However, this is a new trend started by educational reformers like Maria Montessori, John Dewey and Helen Parkhurst, and is thus an argument for their innovativeness. 17 18 23 | In his work the Projet pour l'éducation de M. De Sainte-Marie, we find more background on what Rousseau’s thoughts are on what he thinks children should learn, when he claims that: “Children must learn: (i) their duties and be socialised into their native, home-spun, culture; (ii) to value honest and forth-right debate and the mind-set that goes with it; (iii) the virtues of magnanimity, fair-mindedness, temperance, humanity, and courage; (iv) patriotic zeal, and; (v) awe towards their Creator.”19 Here he presents a great deal of moral and ethical guidelines, but also patriotic and religious ones. We have learned that patriotism was useful in creating a shared general will, rendering different kinds of people to agree on decisions made by the sovereign (consisting of the populace). As we have seen in the Savoyard vicar’s part, and considering that, Rousseau was a thoroughly religious person, it is no surprise that a religious aspect is also part of the children’s lessons. Rousseau as an educational reformer Ever since the hermeneutic teachings of Heidegger and Gadamer, there has been an increased interest in (whether or not unintentional) personal involvement in the contents of his book. As I have explained in my introduction, I tend to analyse texts regarding both the writer’s agency and the text as a product of its time. To read a book just as a piece of text, independent and unmediated, is to neglect the circumstances from which the book arose. Taking the writer’s background and intentions in account can contribute much to the understanding of the text. Often, works arise from personal accounts and reflections of an author’s life. Especially in the case of Rousseau, writing opinionated and engaged pieces, it is striking how much he identifies with the characters. This realisation is important to keep in mind, as we have seen that his body of work contains certain constants, deducible from the many genres 19 Rousseau, Émile, 2. | 24 and personages he wrote with. In the last example, that of the Savoyard vicar, it has been argued that Rousseau identified fully with the religious remarks uttered by the vicar. Thus, his various treatises are doused with his personal convictions; the belief in the natural capacity of man to do well, be moral and religious and the ability to educate himself. The second aspect that must be kept in mind whilst reading Rousseau concerns the non-existence of a separation of public and private sphere. As the contrast between public and private sphere was still in its infancy, it is no surprise that this strikes us as odd, looking at it with modern eyes. Moreover, for future educational reformers, bearing in mind that there might be a difference between private and public spheres, this could lead to wholly different outcomes. Bearing these two reservations in mind, we come to conclude that Rousseau wrote a treatise worthy of looking at for future generations of educational reformers. To copy it in any literal sense would be foolish, as it is highly theoretical, thought-experiment like. The idea of taking a child away from his family for 15-something years, the solitary upbringing, the radical freedom, these are all speculative methods, derived from a philosopher who thoroughly believed in the power of human nature. Despite these reservations, many concepts can (and have been) deduced from this book. Reformers like Pestalozzi, Fröbel, Basedow and Herbart quite quickly took up his writings, and put them to action that is more practical. Dewey and Freinet in the modern era have been inspired by the freedom-oriented and child-centred approach to teaching, laying the foundation for many years of educational reform to come. Two of the most famous reformers of the twentieth century, took it up to devise practical school systems that readied the child for the modern world. In the next two chapters, we will look at what they have done to Rousseau’s heritage, and how they have turned it into something of their own. 25 | Montessori In the 150 years following the publication of Émile, the nineteenth century wreaked havoc on traditional society in Europe. It cannot be overestimated how deeply was society transformed in the course of these years: industrialisation, formation of the middle class, revolutions and restoration, dawn of consumerism, mass culture, the rise of the media, to name a few of these transformations which had thorough impact on society. The modern age, just starting to dawn when Jean-Jacques Rousseau published his book, shook society at its foundations. His book, part of both the Enlightenment tradition and a harbinger of the Romantic era, was part of this upcoming shift. Rousseau’s novel on education, interspersed with the concept of ‘freedom’, was exemplary of the eighteenth century intellectual tradition. As a prelude to the ‘long’ nineteenth century, these intellectuals set out a new mode of thought with their treatises, relying heavily on concepts previously relatively unimportant in society. How then were these concepts used when they became current, a hundred to a hundred and fifty years later? As the nineteenth century proved to be a sandbox for new political concepts, waging wars between the revolutionary and the traditional, by the 1880s most ostentatious conflicts were turned into more civil solutions. Socialist parties got a foothold in the national governments, resulting in plans to reform society. Largely, a shift occurred from the demand for democratic participation for an increasing number of the population to the demand for approaching newly arisen social problems. In this sketch of ‘zeitgeist’ (on which I will thread into more detail below), we must situate the application of educational concepts by Maria Montessori and Helen Parkhurst. How did they (re)introduce, in a practical way, concepts that had been laid out by Rousseau in a theoretical fashion? Furthermore, how were they able to offer them to a time so different from the one in which the | 26 educational concepts were originally devised? The following chapter will focus on Montessori’s attempt at doing that. Zeitgeist As I mentioned before, I am strongly biased towards a framework that foregrounds ‘agency’ in historiography. This means in this context that Montessori was less a ‘product of her time’ than a capably thinking intellectual who looked for problems and their corresponding solutions in society. However, I feel it is necessary to start with a brief description of the world which helped create the Montessori Method. This work was a product of the person Montessori, but it sprouted in a time that had its particular needs and problems. The specific issues of social demographics created the need for educational reform. I will expound upon these issues. Humanities researchers know what happened in the nineteenth century: industrialisation, revolution and restoration, restructuring of the societal layers. However, what really happened to the populace, what changed for the commoner? Since the 1960s20, social history has taken a flight, addressing issues previously unattended. Focusing on structures and superstructures, economical currents and cultural trends, social demographics and labour shifts, these historians have uncovered new insights into history. For the era preluding my topic, the nineteenth century, these scholars have researched the consequences of the aforementioned social shift. The rise of the middle class, as a result of democratisation and industrialisation, did not just have consequences for itself and its members. On the contrary, it resulted in a new position for the lower class. In feudal or pre-modern society, the gap between ruling (landowners and clergy) and ruled (peasants) classes was unbridgeable. Financially, culturally and geographically these factions differed immensely. Especially in the countryside, these differences were most explicit. In the cities, the group consisting of artisans, bankers and public figures like bailiffs and aldermen might make up an ‘in-between’ group, but these men were only And before, but the height of this historiographical trend must be situated in the 1960s with historians the likes of Raymond Williams. 20 27 | marginal, demographically speaking. However, the several shifts of urbanisation restructured society, increasing the size of the middle class. Urbanisation in centuries prior to the nineteenth need not to be overestimated; even in Italy, a country with one of the highest grades of urbanisation, urbanisation did not peak above 12-13% of the population.21 So, the nineteenth century had a lot in store for traditional demographics. The insurrection of a ‘serious’ middle class thus led to a different demographical make up in numbers, but a second implication that cannot be expressed in numbers is the change in a sense of belonging and social mobility. The former, incorporating questions like ‘who am I?’ and ‘how do I arrange my life, what assets do I reckon important? How do I behave, what societies do I attend, what political preference do I have?’, creates a sense of belonging to a class and the attitude and preferences that come with it. The latter involved possibilities of social mobility that had never been seen before. In the society sketched above, being born in a certain class was a fixed identity, rendering social opvoeding fixed as well. From the eighteenth century however, the rise of the middle class formed a stepping-stone to bridge the gap between upper and lower class. Going one step up the ladder of society was no longer unthinkable and unattainable. Furthermore, the middle class, unlike their two predecessors, was not a monolithic social stratus; this group was made up of numerous different professions, levels of wealth, religious allegiances, and ways of living. The group itself can be defined in distinctions of lower, middle and upper middle class; and even such a rudimentary categorisation would not honour the stratification that existed within the group. In all, society stratified and new aspirations and dissatisfactions were instilled due to (a feeling of) accessibility; hence, social issues had to be attended to. The church, former supplier of relief for the poor saw itself increasingly challenged by a new competitor: socialism. Relief for the poor can roughly be categorised in five elements: financial aid, medical care, schooling, ethical Malanima, P, and Volckart, O., Urbanisation 1700-1870, (May, 31 2012) visited on June, 21, 2012, accessible at: <www.cepr.org/meets/wkcn/1/1679/papers/Malanima-VolckartChapter.pdf> 4. 21 | 28 teachings and housing. The first four used to be a monopoly of the church. Financial aid was provided through alms, schooling through monks, medical care through hospices and nuns and ethical teachings through the religious writings and sermons. However, the up and coming state, increasing vastly its interference with the life of people, increasingly sought to take up these tasks. The traditional ‘night watch’ state increased in size and intervention from the seventeenth century onwards, but it surged in the nineteenth. With democracy came the demand for the state to take care of its citizens and the reciprocity between increasing taxes and the government’s responsibility to spend it on the taxed required the state to increase its tasks enormously. Financial aid was provided in the first degree through a relative tax system and secondly through the subsidising of institutions that helped out with poor relief. Both the aforementioned restructuring of society and the increase in medical knowledge led to an enormous growth of governmental expenditures on health care. State hospitals were erected and in some countries, health care systems were instilled through labour unions. Housing projects assured the mental and physical health of living conditions for the poor, restructuring city neighbourhoods to comply with newly found sources of the spreading of disease. In all these categories, the church lost vast terrain as a sphere of influence to the state. The last (combined) category that I have not covered so far, is the one that concerns me the most: schooling. Both solely ‘factual’ education and moral education were increasingly taken away from religion. Now in the hands of the state, there was a possibility to discuss the curriculum and the methods of teaching. It is precisely this discussion, which incorporated the aforementioned social issues of medical care, ethics and housing, which is important to my dissertation. *** We have seen that the makeup of society changed, and that the both the separation and intertwining between public and private was characteristic of 29 | the nineteenth century. To bridge the gap between eighteenth and twentieth century, it is important to introduce two key figures that continued the inquiries into educational reform: Friedrich Fröbel and Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi. Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi (1746-1827) was a Swiss-born educational reformer whose main merit consists of the eradication of illiteracy in his own Switzerland, and in the second degree largely across Western Europe. His strong belief in the connection between socio-ethical reform and education led him to be convinced of the importance of literacy and universal education. Furthermore, he believed that children should also learn through material objects, and not just through words, the prevailing teaching method up until then. Thirdly, continuing Rousseau’s work, he argued that children should largely be left to their own interests and experiences, as they learn a lot from using just these without any external interference. Thus by recognising the potential of the child, he also preserved individual integrity, a quality he strongly defended. These ideas were set forth in his book ‘How Gertrude Teaches Her Children’ (1801) which largely covers the Pestalozzi Method as we know it today. This first practical application of Rousseauvian ideas about individual freedom in education was a success to a certain extent; his project combating illiteracy was hugely successful and the ideas of the Pestalozzi method were used by many later educational reformers. However, there has been no widespread application of ‘the Pestalozzi Method’, as with other educational reformers.22 The second educational reformer that picked up on ideas of liberalism in the years following Rousseau’s Émile was the German-born pedagogue Friedrich Fröbel. Inspired by Pestalozzi and Rousseau, he set out to combine ideas about the intrinsic good nature of man, individual learning and the importance of curriculum. As an idealist, his thoughts on human nature Wallace, S. (ed.), “Pestalozzi, Johann Heinrich”, A Dictionary of Education (Oxford 2009) visited on 17 June 2012 , accessible on <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry=t267.e760>. 22 | 30 resembled Rousseau’s proto-Romantic ideas on the regenerative capability of humankind. He foresaw both great possibilities for the individual, but also for the collective, facilitating the German idea unification through education. He mainly focused on young children, laying the foundation for the kindergarten, a method (although varying in execution) widespread nowadays for educating young children. The original kindergarten presented the children with carefully designed toys that would stimulate optimal individual development. Although not thoroughly successful in his own life, his ideas were picked up rapidly in the 1870s. Even today according to ‘the Oxford Companion to the Mind’, “the importance of play, the unified curriculum, links with home and community, and non-directive rather than authoritarian teaching remain live issues.”23 *** As I have highlighted above, the relationship between state and citizen changed vastly throughout the nineteenth century. One of the fields the state increasingly took interest in was education. Achievements like Pestalozzi’s attempt to eradicate illiteracy helped greatly to ensure the belief in the necessity of the state’s interventions. The large-scale disappearance of illiteracy was extremely beneficial to both the citizen and the state; for example, it made it possible for the state to increase communication with the population and made the people more knowledgeable through the upcoming media. From decreasing illiteracy, it was a small step to expand the curriculum for children, from the teaching of sheer facts and figures, to include more moral teachings. These moral teachings, ranging from guidelines for sanitation to behaviour in society, were instilled to ensure a healthy, educated population that could participate in society as a ‘well-willing and responsible burgher’. Stephenson, N., “Froebel, Friedrich Wilhelm August”, The Oxford Companion to the Mind (Oxford 1987) visited on June, 19, 2012, accessible on: <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry=t159.e355>. 23 31 | It is in this trend—the quest to create the ideal citizen that was both responsible and conscious—that we must situate Maria Montessori’s approach at reforming education. Although I have largely sketched a pan-European trend in the social discontinuities of the nineteenth century, the situation in Italy was complied with this. Soit, the degree of urbanisation was somewhat higher; education was on a much lower level, regarding literacy and factual education, compared to the northern part of Europe, thus allowing enough space for educational reform.24 Because the educational grade was low, the urbanisation high (meaning both the rich and the poor classes lived close to each other), and there were ample examples of social mobility, the population’s aspirations of improvement reached an all-time high. Montessori tried to address the educational and moral deficits with a system that combined both, creating opportunities for the lower strata of society and reaffirming those for the upper ones. This hopefully would ensure the possibility of social mobility, soothe the tensions and lessen the gap between the two classes. First, let us uncover the person she was herself. 24 Duggan, C., The Force of Destiny: a History of Italy since 1796 (London 2007) 148, 274-282. | 32 The person After having given an overview of the era in which Montessori must be situated, I will address her position in it a bit more specifically. Several aspects spring to mind which I will expound upon, to sketch the person behind the method: religion, social issues, theoretical background, and lastly, her gender. Coming from a Catholic background, relief for the poor was part of her education, rendering her more prone to asserting the social issues of the day. The Catholic Church, arguably being at the peak of its influence in its ‘home country’, Italy, had provided poor relief since its insurrection.25 Nevertheless, as I have showed before, the state increasingly took it upon itself to meddle with the citizen’s business. Nonetheless, Maria Montessori, a devoutly religious person herself (Catholic in the early stages of her life, but resorting to a more theosophical approach to religion in later stages), was inclined, one way or another, to do something about the state of education in her country. Montessori, born in 1870, moved several times during her youth. She was born in a small community close to Ancona, but moved to Firenze and Roma at early stages in her life. Thus, growing up in two of the biggest cities in Italy, she came in contact with the urban issues described in the previous chapter: the paradox of social mobility that created a seemingly bridgeable gap. The slums of Rome proved to be a testing ground for her first school, as she was allowed government permits and funding to start up a school in the poor neighbourhood of San Lorenzo. It was here that the ideas were put into practice; a testing ground for theory, feedback for the publication of ‘The Montessori Method’. However, more on that later. Thirdly, the early twentieth century provided some theoretical background for Maria Montessori. Jean-Jacques Rousseau stood with one leg in Early Modern philosophy and the Enlightenment tradition, he stood with a ‘future Kahl, S., The Religious Roots of Modern Poverty Policy: Catholic, Lutheran, and Reformed Protestant Traditions Compared, (2005) visited on May, 31, 2012, accessible on: <www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/politics/faculty/mead/V53.0395/Kahl.pdf> 7. 25 33 | leg’ in the Romantic era, foreseeing many of the to be formed opinions of later intellectuals. Like Rousseau, Montessori’s legacy plays out in a crucial, transitional phase of history. The hey-day of positivism, in the latter part of the nineteenth century, was starting to wane as influential philosophers like Max Weber and Georg Simmel started to question the infallibility of the concept. Simultaneously, newly founded studies like sociology and evolutionary biology reaffirmed the belief in the conformity of mankind and society to scientific laws. The tensions resulting from these two contradictory movements in science were accompanied by the third component present in Montessori: religion. This resulted in a recipe for a highly volatile mix of ideas. The last ingredient to be added to brewing pot was Montessori’s gender. Being a woman, this era proved to be particularly interesting as women started to demand rights, after the entire male population had been set free and made participants in democratic society. The first wave feminists demanded basic equality, focusing on having the ability to go to university, to vote, and to have economic independence. They demanded that men and women were to be treated equally both officially (before de judicial system) and culturally, as there was no real equality between men and women in many aspects of life such as career choice and matrimony.26 Montessori’s progressive and first wave feminist nature was made visible through the choices she made in life. She was ambitious, and did not let conventions stand in the way of pursuing her interests. She enrolled in the University of Rome’s medicine programme, and withstood an outbreak of protest, as her male fellow-students did not deem it appropriate that they were dissecting naked bodies in the company of a woman. Notwithstanding, she was the first woman to obtain the title doctor of medicine in 1896. An apt student, she started her own practice and worked at the university with mentally challenged children. We see a striking similarity in background of educational reformers. Fröbel, Pestalozzi, Rousseau, Séguin, Itard and Dewey Buchanan, I., “First Wave feminism”, A Dictionary of Critical Theory (Oxford 2010) visited on June, 19, 2012, accessible on: <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry=t306.e251>. 26 | 34 all came into contact with children suffering from a form of mental or physical handicap. Perhaps because it is possible to apply new educational methods to these children as conventional methods did not work, these thinkers were able to devise new methods and approaches to learning. In the first decade of the twentieth century, the traditional role of women in society was evaluated. Montessori took active part in the early feminist movements, founding the radical ‘Associazione per la donna’ in 1905 and one year later aiding Anna Maria Mozzoni, an advocate for the emancipation of women, in forcing the government to take a stand on women’s rights.27 She was active on the cutting-edge of feminist movements, speaking at women’s conferences, spreading her ideas about participation and equal opportunity of education. Montessori thus was born in a time composed of new and old methodologies. A devout religious person, a woman in a time when genderrelated power structures were beginning to shift, and lastly living in a country that had both problems to solve and solutions, Maria Montessori emerged as a key educational practitioner and reformer. As mentioned before, the Montessori Method came to being as an experiment, as an application of theoretical and practical findings. San Lorenzo, Rome, proved to be the testing ground. Now let us look at these early stages of the development of Montessori education. The method After working with mentally challenged children and doing research at the university, Montessori was invited to join a governmental programme. The neighbourhood of San Lorenzo, one of Rome’s poorest districts was to be restructured. The aforementioned positivism, present in the state’s decisions, resulted in the view that if a human body lived in poor sanitation, his mental capacity—read: morality—had to be in bad condition too. Thus, the Schwegman, M.J., Maria Montessori, 1870-1952: Kind van haar Tijd, Vrouw van de Wereld (Amsterdam 1999), 96. 27 35 | government set out to profoundly restructure society: physically and spiritually, starting with San Lorenzo. In San Lorenzo, Montessori was to open a moral and educational institution that made better citizens out of people born in the lowest stratus of society. This first Casa dei Bambini was opened in 1907 and it was an allencapsulating institution that provided the children with all sorts of lessons, ranging from sensory experiences to moral education on sanitation guidelines to learning to write. The method, founded on the belief in the individuality of the child, focused on the child’s capacity to determine its own speed and the sublimation of the free, natural manifestations of the child.28 The recognition that children have different paces does not imply, however, that children are individually different, a major difference we find with our next educational reformer Helen Parkhurst. Instead, Montessori set out to blend the current curriculum with ideas about God, morality and various previous research, among them anthropology and psychology.29 In short: attention is given to “the education, health, the physical and moral development of the children”. This was largely in keeping with the governmental plans to both reform and educate the lower class. Montessori’s spirituality assured Montessori’s belief in the relentless growth of mankind, guided by divine providence. The result of the Montessori school was a “clockwork, whose ingenious cogs facilitated merely one goal: physical, mental and spiritual growth”30 In the first years the children are taught to use what God gave them: their senses. Through various exercises, the children learn to make use of their senses. Sight, smell, hearing, tasting and the ‘crown sense’ of touch are trained in a manner not unlike those of Rousseau. Through staged events or exercises, the teacher helps to develop optimally the senses. Senses are trained through exercises or with the help of carefully crafted objects designed to help the children develop skills in a natural and playful way. These objects, named ‘development material’ by Montessori, are designed to Montessori, M., The Montessori Method : Scientific Pedagogy, as applied to Child Education in ’The Children’s Houses’ (A. George, transl.) (London 1912, original work published in 1911) 15. 29 Ibidem, 73. 30 Schwegman, 115. 28 | 36 stimulate a specific sense or skill, accentuated through colour and shape. Examples include wooden cubes that increase a sense of estimation or surfaces varying in texture to stimulate a sense of touch and distinctions between smooth and rough.31 Moving from the concrete to the abstract, or in other words from the particular to the universal, the child progresses through various stages laid out by the teacher, but on the child’s own initiative. A well-known example of this ‘freedom’ comes from Montessori’s own experiences. In December 1907, a true ‘writing explosion’ took place when one of the children, playing with sandpaper letters, arranged them in a certain order, after which a word was formed. Children gathered around the former one, and soon enough numerous children were composing words. The classroom soon was filled with cries of joy: “Look, I write! I write!”32 Although the order of learning was changed, writing preceding reading, the children maintained their joy and own inventiveness, learning through objects and initiative, not through books and coercion. This is the core of Montessori’s thought. The curriculum, still the same, was no longer linear, as it did not comply with the individual wants, needs and pace of the children. Every child, in order to maintain his or her eagerness, should be able to learn in his or her own order. They would learn through objects and exercises, not through adult-created books that required the children to sit still in rigid benches. These benches were exemplary for Montessori; fixed to the ground to instil discipline. Children sitting in benches were solely required to reproduce facts, all in the same order, extinguishing juvenile innovativeness. Structure was still necessary, but instead of coming from the curriculum and the way of teaching, it came in the form of other exercises. Menial tasks like setting the table, participating in exercises of maintaining silence, and dressing oneself were arranged at a fixed time in order for the child to get a grasp of responsibility, structure and obedience. One can see that the curriculum could be left untouched, but the methods, approach and order were completely restructured. Virtues like obedience and 31 32 Montessori, 186. Schwegman, 124. 37 | responsibility, thoroughly important for the lower classes, were instilled through wholly different means, whilst at the same time maintaining the child’s eagerness to learn. After two years, Montessori’s experiment was over. According to friends, she wrote il Metodo in just twenty days, truly inspired by her findings. Rapidly, the methodology was applied in different cities, first in a second school in Roma, then onward to Milano. Lack of space does not allow me to go into much detail on how Montessori took her ideas abroad, first in Europe, and then touring around the USA, maintaining a monopoly position on her didactic materials and meeting with Helen Parkhurst and John Dewey. Her method reached India, where it was received with wild acclaim. There was an episode with Benito Mussolini, who offered her state support, which she willingly accepted. However, when fascist’s totalitarianism revealed its true nature, Montessori became increasingly reluctant to take the funding. After ten years of teaming up with one of the world’s most maligned regimes, Montessori broke with Mussolini, resulting in the forced closing of all Montessori schools in Italy, Germany, Spain and Austria. However, the Method has survived until today, thriving in Northwestern Europe and India, and less so, but surely, elsewhere in the world. Montessori was (in her own words) a piano teacher, guiding the children to play better, correcting them where they make mistakes, but letting them figure it out on their own. They set their own pace, their own order, to help them maintain their interest. The system should not be reward-oriented, but interest motivated.33 Thus, children retained a confined form of freedom not unlike in Rousseau’s system. Nevertheless, how do they compare overall? Montessori and Rousseau For Jean-Jacques Rousseau, the nature of the child was the founding principle of his entire thoughts on education. Basically an autodidact, the child 33 Montessori, 24. | 38 would roam the lands, encountering objects, learning from them and thus shaping his own moral and sensory skills and knowledge of the world. Paradoxically, Rousseau stages events that introduce the child to various concepts like property. Therefore, although Rousseau sketches a somewhat extreme version of ‘raising’ a child in which the child is left unattended most of the time, he acknowledges that there should be some sort of guiding principle to ready him for the ‘real world’. Maria Montessori, having faith in a sort of providence or the belief in a divine ‘relentless growth’, revisits the way the curriculum should be transferred to the child. By analysing what the perfect system was to facilitate an optimum of physical, mental and spiritual growth, in which the child’s eagerness was perfectly preserved, she developed a method founded on exercises and rituals. These ‘events’, not unlike Rousseau’s, ensured that the child would acquire the necessary skills, but in a natural way. Rousseau’s nature was replaced by a theosophical or Catholic regenerative spirit, and his staged events were replaced by didactic materials, carefully designed by Montessori, and rituals that instilled order, responsibility and obedience. Montessori, trained as a medical and psychological scholar, did not sit down to write up a contemplation on education. She worked with mentally deficient children, was introduced to the work of Édouard Séguin and JeanMarc Gaspard Itard and had her own ‘test case’ in the slums of Rome. Thus, through trial and error, hypothesising and experimentation, she created a methodology, applicable to society. This method, unlike Rousseau’s highly theoretical and impracticable ideas, proved to be successful enough to be exported to many different countries. Its practicality renders this work wholly different from the theoretical ruminations of Rousseau. Furthermore, because Rousseau’s work was based on little more than his own thoughts (a bit of Plato, a bit of Locke, a bit of Comenius), it is hard to place in a tradition. There are neither scientific facts nor experimental conclusions that support his findings. Montessori’s work, standing in a tradition of Rousseau himself, Fröbel, Pestalozzi, Séguin and Itard, arising in a time when educational reform was a popular topic with writers like Steiner, Dewey, Freinet and Parkhurst 39 | publishing books in compliance or in concurrence with hers, is thus part of a larger tradition and more valuable to pedagogical science. In addition, Montessori’s natural charisma, alliance with the feminist movement and tactical approach increased the popularity of her work. Montessori’s Dutch biographer Marjan Schwegman combines these elements: “Séguin and Itard paved the way for Montessori, and her legacy henceforth differed wholly from those of her predecessors, not as obscure, male heroes, but as a woman that rose to fame and acclaim in an ‘unfeminine’ way.”34 As I stated in an earlier remark, both Rousseau and Montessori lived in a time characterised by a shift in zeitgeist, the former standing with one foot in the Enlightenment and another in the Romantic era, the latter bridging positivism and modernism. Both tried to find a middle ground between universalism and particularism. When engaging in debate about philosophical and moral subjects, it is easiest to reduce everything to commonalities, capturing them in absolutes and laws. However, often this leads to unsatisfactory results. Rousseau realised this through the use of nature and feeling. He perceived mankind as uncontrollable and -directable, and that goodness was inherent in the nature of man. Against the prevailing view of his contemporaries, he argued that the artificial constructs of thousand years of history and intellectual tradition were just clouding the view of a positive outcome. Montessori, got inspired through the education of mentally deficient children, seeing the shortcomings of universalist positivism, as one method did not work for all of them. Further applying her findings to healthy, yet poor children, she came up with a method that left individual freedom intact, but taught the necessary curriculum. Montessori wrote a practical guide to channel what she perceived as divine natural growth in the best possible way. The teacher, a clockmaker or piano teacher, stimulated the children by promoting their own interest instead of quenching their caprioles and rewarding their good behaviour. It is a guide for preserving an intrinsic freedom and eagerness of the child. Senses, as in Émile, 34 Schwegman, 95. | 40 are the foundations of learning, as they are needed for every lesson. Exercises and rituals provide stability and obedience, regenerating morality and ethics among the lower classes on which the method was tested. These social issues were vital to the origin and the success of Montessori’s method. Montessori saw freedom as ultimately key to the success of society. She held a firm positive belief in humanity, seeing its capability to do well. This positive feeling came into true being when she noted that ‘first the slaves were set free, then the women, and now, it is time to liberate the children.’35 35 Montessori, 22. 41 | Parkhurst In the previous chapters we saw that Jean-Jacques Rousseau applied eighteenth-century concepts to the education of man, and wrote a—albeit highly theoretical and impracticable—treatise on the betterment of education. Then we saw how both Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi and Friedrich Fröbel picked up on these ideas and put them to practice. However, the time was not ripe for such progressive ideas on education. Roughly a hundred years later however, Maria Montessori’s intelligence and ambition created an education system when the world needed it. The state’s relation with its citizens changed, and the social situation concerning the lower classes was dire enough to call for a transformation of education. I have tried to give a rough sketch of the fin de siècle zeitgeist, to see how the time had changed, and how the demand for educational reform had peaked. It is important to grasp the circumstances under which the various reformers devised their plans. As with most reform plans, there is always a hint of regenerative impulse to be traced. Social issues are addressed, and perceived concrete solutions are given to better society and to be well rid of malevolent habits amongst people. The final decades of the nineteenth century and the first decades of the twentieth were ones of great social upheaval, containing large-scale demographic changes and industrialisation; moreover, shifting gradually to modern society. It is in these years that many educational reform plans gained momentum, as both the state and citizens showed interest in them. Montessori sought to educate the lower classes of San Lorenzo, to help them gain a fair chance in society. Now, we will see what ideas surfaced with Helen Parkhurst and her Dalton Plan. However, in order to continue to the next chapter we first have to make several leaps. The first one is a geographical leap. Unlike Montessori and Rousseau, our next subject lived in the United States. This continent on the other side of the ocean faced similar problems in the nineteenth century, but | 42 also ones deviating from their European counterparts. Moreover, we are dealing with a slightly different intellectual tradition, as American educational reformers like John Dewey (1859-1952) and Carleton Washburne (1889-1962) (developer of the Winnetka Plan) were much more influential in their own country than abroad. Secondly, we are dealing with leap in time, albeit a small one. Ever since Rousseau, there was an almost constant output of educational reformers, each predecessor influencing the next generation. Montessori, born in 1870, experienced many of the nineteenth century issues happening in the Italian city. Although Helen Parkhurst was only seventeen years younger, she became acquainted with Montessori’s work at a young age, taking in her lessons, and interwove Montessori’s philosophies with her later experiment. Thus, we will see that Helen Parkhurst, only slightly younger of age was influenced by Dewey and Montessori, but also Rousseau and was shaped by her time and experiences, and duly developed a unique approach at educating children. The person Rousseau wrote his book about raising and educating children in solitude, far away from society in the countryside. This was unrealistic, perhaps, but as a theoretical foundation, it was rewarded according to its merits. Montessori, on the other hand, wrote a book about educating the city dwellers, with a special place reserved for the lower class. This book differed immensely, as it proposed a concrete example on how to arrange a school and educational material. The third person I am discussing provides a third setting: the village. Although adapted as an educational system elsewhere, Parkhurst’s ideas arose from a village setting and the difficulties a schoolteacher dealt with there. In 1903, in rural Wisconsin, when she was just a teenager, Dalton started to teach forty pupils in a one-room schoolhouse.36 The setting posed obvious problems: one room accommodated children from several ages, backgrounds and 36 Lager, D., Helen Parkhurst and the Dalton Plan (Ann Arbor 1983) 20. 43 | different levels of intelligence, headed by just one person. In order to educate the children, Parkhurst thus relied on a great sense of responsibility of the children themselves, ordering them to instruct each other. This would become one of the key principles to the Dalton Plan, as we will see later. After she had taught the Durand children for several years, she rapidly got through higher education. She attended Rapid Falls College in 1907(now the University of Wisconsin) and graduated in just two years with the highest honours professionally rewarded.37 From there, it took her just five years to become Director of the Primary Training Department at the University. Whilst in that position, she was appointed by the Wisconsin State Department of Education to investigate the value of the Montessori Method. Montessori’s project had begun in 1907, spread nation-wide in Italy in a couple of years, and world-wide in the sequential years. In 1911, Montessori addressed a large audience in Carnegie Hall, expounding on her ideas. It must have been in this period that the Wisconsin State Department took interest in Montessori’s work and sent Helen Parkhurst to study it. She went to Rome, studied with Maria Montessori herself, and became the only person in the world legally authorised to train Montessori teachers.38 After studying a year Montessori, Parkhurst returned to the United States, where she picked up several smaller jobs for a small amount of time, before fully devoting her to development of the Dalton Laboratory Plan. In this short biography, I have noted three influences on the realisation of the Dalton Plan: the Wisconsin school, intellectual training at Rapid Falls and the year with Montessori. I will expound on the latter two further, as they are important to both the story of the Dalton Plan, as well as to the general theme of this dissertation. Dewey 37 38 Semel, S., The Dalton School, Transformation of a Progressive School (New York 1992) 19. Ibidem, 20. | 44 John Dewey was a political and moral philosopher of the latter half of the nineteenth century. On top of that, he wrote extensively on the role of education and how it should be organised. Central to the foundation of Dewey’s work on education is his belief in the shaping potential of education. Social reform could be realised through proper education, solving many of the problems modern society struggled with, argued Dewey. Although of a different origin and specificity, the United States of America contended with many of the same problems Europe did. Mass (im)migration led to chaotic urban life with an accompanying gap between rich and poor people. The problems these demographic shifts posed could be solved through a number of means, but education was the most effective, according to Dewey.39 Thus, lessons should focus heavily on experience and moral education, as to ensure maximum growth. School was for Dewey “that form of community life in which all those agencies are concentrated that will be most effective in bringing the child to share in the inherited resources of the race, and to use his own powers for social ends”.40 Dewey distinguished between two movements in education: the curriculum-oriented and the child-oriented. The curriculums focus too much on theoretical material, and thereby thoroughly discard the children’s interest and own initiative. The party that favours the child-centred approach tends to discard the role of the teacher as vital, places the child in the position to determine quantity and quality and disregards the importance of content.41 Dewey then stood at the base of founding the ‘progressive education movement’. Lawrence A. Cremin has nailed this movement down to four points, which I find essential in order to see how both Montessori’s, and Parkhurst’s methods neatly fit this category. Progressive education is: 1. A broadening of the school to include a direct concern or health, vocation, and the quality of community life. Dewey, J., ‘My pedagogic creed’ in: School Journal, Vol.: 54 (January 1897) 77-80. Dworkin, M. S. (ed), Dewey on Education (New York 1959) 43. 41 Dewey J., The Child and the Curriculum (Chicago 1956, original work published in 1902) op. cit. 39 40 45 | 2. The application in the classroom of more humane, more active, and more rational pedagogical techniques derived from research in philosophy, psychology and the social sciences. 3. The tailoring of instruction more directly to the different kinds and classes of children who were being brought within the purview of school. 4. And finally the use of more systematic and rational approaches to the administration and management of the schools.42 Dewey set up a few experiments at the University of Chicago, bringing them under the header ‘Laboratory School’. Advocating “active learning, starting with the needs and interests of the child’ he emphasised the role of experience and education and introduced the notion of teacher as facilitator of learning, rather than the font from which all knowledge flows.”43 Now, where have we seen this notion before? Rousseau played with the exact same notions, focusing foremost on experience and active learning, whilst facilitating the right circumstances. Helen Parkhurst read Dewey, admired him for his focus on group work and experience, and mentioned him as an influence in her work ‘Education on the Dalton Plan’. In the same sentence even, another person we are well acquainted with is mentioned: Maria Montessori.44 Montessori. When Helen Parkhurst made her way to Rome to study the Montessori Method, the Method had started to grow almost uncontrollably. After being particularly successful in Rome and after the bureaucrats saw what it had done to the education of the lower classes and their morale, the experiment was transplanted all over the country. Accordingly, it attracted a lot of attention internationally where it was translated in many languages. One of the leading groups that called for innovation of education was a group of leading industrialists in the United States. Members ranged from Cremin, L. A., American Education: The Metropolitan Experience (New York 1988) 229. Semel, 8. 44 Parkhurst, H., Education on the Dalton Plan (London 1922) xvi. 42 43 | 46 Thomas Edison and Alexander Graham Bell, the noted inventors of electricity related devices, to Henry Ford, the automobile producer, and the Crane family, owners of the paper printing company for the American mint. This new wealthy bourgeois group increasingly sought the perfect educational system, as they were concerned with the new social situations in the country. Alexander Graham Bell and his wife Mabel founded the Montessori Educational Association in 1913 in Washington, DC and Maria Montessori was invited under the auspices of Thomas Edison and Graham Bell himself in 1915 to speak at Carnegie Hall about her Methods.45 Thomas Edison, highly interested in her pedagogy of play stated: “I like the Montessori method. It teaches through play. It makes learning a pleasure. It follows the natural instincts of the human being (...) The present system casts the brain into a mould. It does not encourage original thought or reasoning.”46 This group of industrialists recognised that the problems the US was struggling with, and a possible solution was received with open arms. There was, however, a language barrier, one Montessori was not willingly prepared to overcome. The attention given to the problems of immigration, class differences and the resulting educational reform proposals surged when the First World War broke out. During this world-shaking event, through which many members of society got disillusioned and were forced again to think about how to reorder society to create moral citizens, new interest arose in the social and educational reformers. Increasingly, man turned to educational reformers that tried to root out immoral behaviour from the earliest years of education.47 Perhaps the most striking example was the erection of the New Education Fellowship, which organised conferences where educational reformers shared their ideas. Singh, Renu, ‘The Montessori Method’, in: Seminar, Vol.: 546 (Febuary 2005) visited on June, 21, 2012, accessible at: <http://www.eledu.net/rrcusrn_data/The%20Montessori%20method.pdf> 8. 46 Author unknown, ‘Frequently asked questions’ (June, 6, 2012) visited on June, 17, 2012, accessible on: <http://www.nps.gov/edis/faqs.htm.>. 47 Fox Lee, L., ‘The Dalton Plan and the Loyal, Capable Citizen’, in: History of Education: Journal of the History of Education Society, Vol.: 29, No.: 2 (2000), 132. 45 47 | Countless educational reformers participated in this programme, amongst them Dewey, Freinet, Petersen, Montessori and Parkhurst. Given these circumstances, it came as no surprise that educational reform had its hey-day during the First World War and in the Interbellum. The Dalton Plan proved to be a striking example of an educational system that prepared its pupils for society, instilling the necessary qualities in the child to make him a righteous person. From the very start of the programme, the child is prepared for society in all its forms; prepared to solve problems and to interact with others.48 It complied with the hopes for moral regeneration of mankind, after the horrors portrayed in the battles of the First World War. Many of these ideas reached the United States, but a full-scale impact remained remarkably absent. There was a desperate need for either English-speaking practical reformers, or the increasing practicability of English reform plans. Thus, with American officials interested heightened though not satisfied and social tensions requiring a solution, Helen Parkhurst was sent to study fully the Montessori Method. 48 Parkhurst, 21, 29. | 48 *** After studying with Montessori for a year, Parkhurst became fully acquainted with Montessori’s body of thought and was awarded the authority to train Montessori teachers. Lesley Fox Lee, a commenter on the educational reform plans of Helen Parkhurst, stated that: “Parkhurst understood the Method better than her creator. (... and that probably) Parkhurst was the closest thing to an alter ego Montessori would have amongst those whom she trained to do her work.”49 She returned to the USA in 1915 to teach the Montessori Method to future progressive educators in San Francisco. Although Montessori had created an immensely powerful, it had to carried out. It was already applied increasingly in her home country, but to make it even more successful it had to be taken abroad. Helen Parkhurst dissolved the language barrier and added a fine portion of social skills as an endeavouring and enterprising person. Thus, by adding qualities that Montessori lacked and being at the right place to employ them, Parkhurst contributed much to the diffusion of progressive education. Dalton, MA and New York City Parkhurst possibly would have become a great advocate of Montessori education if she had not possessed a drive that encouraged her to improve the model. She was also able to obtain the funds to realise her goal. Around the time Parkhurst was spreading the Montessori Method in California, she was summoned to take interest in the education of the child of one of the richest families in the United States: the Crane family. Being licensed to print the paper for the United States Mint, this family was no lightweight in the political and economic sphere of the USA. Helen Parkhurst was requested by Mrs W. Murray Crane to take direct control over the education of their child, Louise 49 Fox, 130. 49 | Crane.50 The family funded a new project in Dalton, Massachusetts, where Helen Parkhurst set up the first experiment with her educational system. After a year, she was allowed to further move her plans ahead, implementing her system at the public high school of Dalton, MA. Here, the system derived its name from this place and this school. Being presented with the opportunity to reside in a marvellous building in New York’s posh neighbourhood the Upper East Side, Parkhurst decided that the development of the system might be more effective in a populated place. Thus, again after a project lasting one year, she made the leap to New York City in 1920. It was in this school that Helen Parkhurst’s Dalton Laboratory Plan grew to full stature. Being at the school from day to day, she came to know the flaws and strengths of the system. She supervised the general outset of the school, helped in the classes and evaluated the successes and failures of the system. Her treatise ‘Education on the Dalton Plan’ was published in 1922, showing that much of the experience and preliminary work had been conducted in the years preceding her move to New York. The Dalton School in New York was the first ‘real’ application of the Dalton Plan, providing a testing ground for Parkhurst, which provided direct feedback. The school is still in existence, being one of the few instances in the world where such a reformist school is still a success. The Dalton Plan The events leading up to the writing of ‘Education on Dalton Plan’ were of direct consequence to the final product. We see that the teaching in rural Wisconsin and the fortunate testing ground at Dalton and New York were extremely beneficial to the developing of an educational method. Let us consider what the Dalton Plan entailed for the children. First and foremost, Parkhurst perceived the Dalton Plan as an improvement of the Montessori Method. We have seen that Parkhurst spent several months working with Maria Montessori, and consequentially she was 50 Semel, 21. | 50 the only person ordained by Maria to train Montessori teachers. This made her a true expert of the Montessori Method, coming to know its strengths and flaws. Furthermore, after training numerous future teachers, attending conferences to explain the material, and working ‘in the field’ for several years in varied schools, it comes as no surprise that she started to evaluate the method she came to study so closely. The Dalton Method focuses on three key aspects: responsibility, selfdiscipline and individuality. These three concepts all seem to stem from Parkhurst’s experience in rural Wisconsin. As she was teaching at a one-room school, with more pupils than one person could survey, she began to focus on the redistribution of tasks. She told the older pupils to help the young ones when they required help and the teacher was unavailable. Furthermore, she disbanded largely whole-class teaching, as the curricula of the different age groups did not allow for such methods. This required a different attitude from both the pupil and the teacher. The teacher, having had to let go of class teaching and having undergone a shift in the classic view of the tutor as transferor of knowledge, was now required to be a guide and a surveyor. The third role s/he has to fulfil, and this is where we stray from the familiar path of Dewey, Montessori and Rousseau, is that the teacher is now a careful designer of what Parkhurst calls ‘the task’.51 The task is a carefully laid out piece of work that is assumed to stimulate the child into obtaining knowledge. The route, speed and means are undefined and of secondary importance, for this is unique to every child, as the personal assets (intellect, reading ability, and cultural baggage) differ greatly from child to child. The ‘task’ should contain enough interest-arousing elements to make the child thoroughly understand the object of learning. This implies two things: primarily, it requires education to be structured along stimulating goals and questions that arouse the child’s interest and force him to look for solutions in multi-disciplinary places. Secondly, it results in the aforementioned fading of Interestingly, many Dalton schools in the Netherlands, including my former school the Helen Parkhurst College in Almere, translated 'the task' to 'learning track' (leerlijn) a set of 'goals' instead of tasks. This, at least in Dutch, has a much less strict ring to it, and with more attention to progress and interest 51 51 | disciplinary boundaries. Mathematics intrinsically is used in physics and Latin can be used in studying history. This may result in the converging of subjects, and especially in the lower grades, this is not an inconceivable way to bring across information.52 Perhaps this can be best elucidated with a concrete example from Parkhurst’s book: instead of telling the child to study Newton’s Three Laws of Motion, from such-and-such page and oblige him to conduct six pre-made experiments, Parkhurst foresees greater eagerness and potential of practicality and remembrance in getting a child to think about Newton’s laws in a much more playful and interdisciplinary manner; through the asking of triggering questions the child is forced to think of an answer (hypothesise) before the laws are given as a clear verity. The questions Parkhurst gives as an example in this case include: “Will an automobile start without an explosion of the gasoline?” and “What makes a screw go into wood?”, furthermore, on the execution of an experiment the child is posed questions like: “How do you think the action of gravity upon one side of this spot compares with that upon the other?” and “If two equal forces act upon a body in opposite directions, what would be the result?”53 The child, in this occasion, is forced to think of both the theoretical and the practical implications of Newton’s laws, through being presented both examples and theory.54 This brings us back to the second change in attitude: that of the pupil. The pupil now heavily relying on his or her own initiative and independence is given completely different modus operandi in class. One of the principles that allows for the granting of so much freedom is Parkhurst’s belief in selfregulating discipline that comes with responsibility. Parkhurst argues that if a child is the own creator of his or her learning path, speed and solutions to the created problems, s/he is responsible for his or her own success and failures. The child is much more likely to stay disciplined on a project that s/he feels At my aforementioned high school, this resulted in the subjects: Knowledge of Nature (Physics, Chemistry and Biology) and MEGA, an abbreviation for Social Studies, Economics, History and Geography (Maatschappijleer, Economie, Geschiedenis and Aardrijkskunde). Furthermore, we had interdisciplinary group projects where multiple teachers would supervise projects along which used material from various subject. This might have included less obvious combinations like biology and economy. 53 Parkhurst, 74-85 54 For the full versions, both 'inadequate' and 'amended', see Appendix A 52 | 52 belongs to him, than on a fixed curriculum that might alter in the aforementioned criteria like speed and path of preference. Furthermore, a child is less likely to get bored if s/he chooses his or her own approach at solving problems that are presented to him.55 Key to the Dalton Plan are these initiative provoking ‘goals’ or ‘tasks’ that arouse a child’s interest and keep him hooked till the very end, urging him to go on and explore more aspects of the given problem. Apart from decentralisation and the restructuring of curriculum in tasks, the third major change to the traditional educational system as described in the Dalton Plan entails the shift from traditional subjects and classrooms to ‘laboratories’. Whereas in the traditional educational system pupils stay in one classroom and listen to teacher explaining different subjects, Parkhurst introduces a school consisting of several laboratories; these core class rooms which are devoted to a single subject. Children are allowed to go to the classroom corresponding to the subject they want to spend time on. There they will find the materials to conduct the experiment, the teacher and other/older children who can provide them with explanation and the books to obtain knowledge from. Helen Parkhurst abolished bells and time tables, for those might interfere with the working process of the children, and ensured that subjects were taught by teachers who thoroughly knew their theory and were passionate about it, for they only taught what they loved, being able to truly convey their teachings. As we have seen, the three concepts I have introduced in the beginning work through in all of these practical alterations of the traditional model. The child is forced into being responsible and independent, inflicting self-discipline and initiative. It dissolves former disciplinary boundaries, coinciding with ‘tasks’ and ‘goals’. The focus of Parkhurst was to render a self-correcting pupil, driven by the force of initiative, corrected through reflection. Likely, she saw it as an adaptation of the Montessori Method; a completion of what was started. 55 Parkhurst, op. cit. 53 | However, if we make a direct comparison of Montessori and Parkhurst, we are comparing apples and oranges. Whereas the Montessori Method focuses mainly on the first part of primary education, the Dalton Plan tends to emphasise the latter part of primary education and high school. The qualities Parkhurst requires of children are evidently more likely to grow or be present in children aged nine and up. In addition, her system largely applies to ‘school subjects’, whereas Montessori’s system largely applies to acquiring basic skills like reading, distinguishing shapes, and moral behaviour. There is overlap in the covered grades, as there are Montessori high schools, and Dalton primary schools, but the two educational systems do not thwart each other. Parkhurst, coming from the United States, being more influenced by Dewey, tries to create the perfect independent system which is self-disciplined and apt in finding its own solutions and answers, Montessori, growing up in Italian cities, is a benevolent societal reformer, moulding the coarse urban dweller into a potential (individual ) success story. Parkhurst and Rousseau Besides this quick comparison between the Montessori Method and the Dalton Plan, which I have given to elucidate the (minor) differences that can be easily overlooked when discussing both authors, let us return to the main question of this dissertation. The background I have laid out here tells us that structurally, Parkhurst came up with an educational plan in a wholly different way than Rousseau did. Whereas Rousseau, spins an educational web from a purely philosophical point of view, Parkhurst arrives at her final plan through the influence of others (Dewey, Montessori), being lucky with certain opportunities and pure empirical findings. Through conclusions derived from studying Montessori and Dewey and working in Wisconsin, Dalton and New York, she comes up with a method that works best for the children she taught or supervised. Like Montessori, she finds a way to instil certain character traits | 54 in children that will be beneficial for the rest of their lives gives them the ability to pick up new knowledge and skills. Though, like Rousseau, she believes in a form of ‘tempered’ freedom, I am not under the impression that Parkhurst believes in the intrinsic capability of man to become a ‘good’ and wise person. The reason for this is the preservation of the original curriculum, which is only altered in outset and approach, but not in content. Although the content is the same, Helen Parkhurst does believe in the individual differences of children that lead to different approaches, paces and solutions. A child’s background, mental baggage, and capability to learn varies from person to person. It is in the spirit of ‘American liberalism’, the ideology concerning equality of opportunity and independence that Parkhurst’s ideas of transforming the approach to the curriculum must be placed. Helen Parkhurst thus believes in a fixed curriculum, for some knowledge is invaluable, and must be passed on. However, to stimulate the child’s interest and to preserve its uniqueness, the road to the destination is blank, waiting to be filled out by the individual child. This is an important difference with Rousseau; Parkhurst’s stimulating of initiative in children, reveals the fact that she does not believe in the child’s capability to do it all by himself.56 Parkhurst believes in the ability of children to learn, but not in their having an unquenchable thirst for knowledge; this thirst for knowledge must be constantly stimulated. Besides Parkhurst more ‘negative’ vision on the child’s initiative and the rejection of the intrinsically good nature of man, the third issue we find in the Dalton Plan concerns the preparation of the child for interaction with other members of society. While in Rousseau’s treatise, this is constantly put on the back burner, delaying Émile’s introduction to society and the other sex for as long as possible, Parkhurst regards society and its ‘unwritten laws’ as one of the key elements. As mentioned, the American spirit has shaped Parkhurst’s piece into a much more independence- and opportunity-oriented educational method. The child is ultimately prepared to cope with life’s problems and 56 Parkhurst, 151 55 | possibilities, even more so in the interaction with other human beings. Through individual solutions and the asking for help from other/older classmates, the child is introduced to innumerable social conventions and rules of behaviour. *** Corresponding to Rousseau’s view, the child in the Dalton Plan is the experimenter. While Montessori sees the teacher as the one conducting the experiments, with the pupils as her assets, the children themselves are the experimenters in both Rousseau’s and Parkhurst’s view.57 They look for problems and solutions, make plans and interact with their environment, in their own pace. Nevertheless, Parkhurst’s laboratory is much more confined to boundaries than Rousseau’s wild, natural universe. The children are constantly monitored through graphs of progress and forms of reflection, to be handed in through assignments. The laboratories are well-designed and the assignments carefully constructed to ensure optimum result. A second correspondence we can find in the role of the teacher as a personal mentor and guide. Through the abolishing of the autocratic top-down vision of transmitting knowledge, the child is able to bond with the teacher: “The Dalton Plan creates so intimate a bond between pupil and teacher that the latter becomes less of an autocrat and more of a guide. Our stores of knowledge are open to all who wish to enter.”58 *** The child thus is free but confined, kept in a place where his or her initiative is stimulated for s/he is being coerced in being proactive, while preserving his or her interest. Rousseau’s roaming wilderness is turned into a 57 58 Montessori, the Montessori Method, and Parkhurst, Education on the Dalton Plan. Early adopter of the Dalton Plan in: Parkhurst, 186.] | 56 laboratory, where the child has his or her ‘tasks’ to use as a guidebook. S/he has his or her other students as teachers of the rules of society and to help him out on his or her assignments, and lastly, as a final resort, there is the teacher that can provide him with the necessary support. Like Rousseau’s equivalent, s/he is a mentor and a guide, not a supplier of ready-made solutions. 57 | Concluding Life changed for the average Western child being born in the early twentieth century. Whereas his or her eighteenth-century counterpart would likely have had to struggle for its survival, because s/he received little to no education, the average Western twentieth-century child would have received full primary education, and was at the least being able to read. The roughly 150 years I have covered—from the publication of Émile in 1762 to the foundation of the Dalton School in New York in 1919—show a tremendous course of change for the citizen of the Western world, with results of revolutions and restorations, the penetrating state and industrialisation as its main components. In the eighteenth century, society was divided along between opposites; one minor and one major. Urban life versus rural life, lower versus upper class, power versus subject, wealth versus poverty, these were all fairly fixed forms of dichotomies that existed in this age and the preceding ones. However, philosophers and other intellectuals increasingly started to question these centuries-old structures. They started to ask questions about what it is to have true freedom and equality. Together with an increasing belief in rationality and the deductive capability of the human mind, these intellectuals either set forth ideas about the utopian restructuring of society and its individual aspects, or ushered for a revaluation of the current structures. Through careful projects like novels, stories or anonymous pamphlets, the writers expressed their ideas about the betterment of society. These tracts formed a prelude to the turmoil that would ensue in the weeks preceding and the years following the French Revolution in 1789. Radical ideas about the liberalisation of the ‘third class’ (comprising the middle and lower classes) were put into practice, with philosophically interesting and practically horrifying results. As a consolidation of the political dissatisfaction preceding 1789, the French Revolution paved the way for almost a century of domestic | 58 unrest. In a series of coups d’état, the revolutionaries and those in favour of restoration ensured a new role for the state, increasingly interfering with the life of the citizen. Paradoxically, the eighteenth century, with its increasing space for ‘public’ thoughts and the vastly increasing state apparatus, rendered the separation of public and private sphere possible. After this separation was at its peak, the newly formed boundaries again began to shift, (re)taking up certain aspects of life as a public task, instead of posed in the newly formed public sphere. To make matters a bit less abstract: curing the ill went from being a communal affair to a private affair and in the nineteenth century to a state affair. The same goes for e.g. education, armies and social security. Thus, first, we see a separation of the public and private sphere in the early modern era, then a consolidation of the two in the nineteenth century, and lastly a shifting in what affairs belongs in which realm, reducing the private sphere almost wholly to the home. The state’s increased interest in the citizen’s affairs played itself out in many different fields. Besides the increasing engagement of citizen and the political system, with the acquisition of voting rights and the lowering of electoral thresholds for men (and women in the twentieth century), we can discern an increase in the state’s interest in social issues. Increasing systems of social security and health care originally arose to help with the dangerous conditions factory workers were exposed to in the industrious centres, but as the age progressed from first-wave industrialisation to second-wave industrialisation these issues were also extended beyond these initial hotbeds. A third manifestation of the increased interest in social issues is that of education. This heightened interest plays a pivotal role in the history I have laid out in this thesis. The first three educational reformers I have described (Rousseau extensively, Pestalozzi and Fröbel less so) had immensely progressive ideas for their times. So progressive, that they might have been uttered too soon. Society and the state needed the odd hundred years of revolution and restoration to consolidate these radical ideas that would touch upon the lives of ‘the common man’ so extensively. It was not until the 1870s that the first demands for 59 | educational reform were made from an institutionalised point of view. This explains why—apart from Pestalozzi’s literacy rate successes— most ideas of these early educational reformers were not picked up until much later. The second contemporary circumstance, beneficial to the adoption of ideas on educational reform regarded the ethical and moral state of society. Problems with immigration or stratification within and outside classes lead certain members of society to believe that educational reform was necessary, and some thought that it was the state’s job to ensure equality of opportunity through it. We have seen that Montessori’s ideas thrived in physically and mentally challenged children’s homes and poor neighbourhoods of capitals, and that the idea of the kindergarten was increasingly implemented from the 1870s. In addition, the coming of the First World War and its ensuing disillusion with the moral state of mankind did much to contribute to the interest in and organisation of educational reformers. The New Education Fellowship (1921) in which e.g. Maria Montessori, John Dewey, Helen Parkhurst, Jean Piaget and Peter Petersen participated, was an example of such an organisation and focused on spreading progressive ideas about education and debating amongst themselves what would be the best theoretical and practical assets of educational reform. Thirdly, we have seen that the first feminist wave of the eighteen- and nineteen-hundreds gave Parkhurst and Montessori enough momentum, opportunity and ambition to carry out their ideas in a thorough fashion. Montessori achieved the feat of being the first female Medicine graduate, and Parkhurst mingled as a professional woman with the highest ends of the industrialist middle class. Both travelled abroad and attended numerous conferences, spoke before men, conveying a message so progressive and appealing that it lead to rapid success in the years that followed. I have given this brief overview, combining the ‘zeitgeist sketches’ I have presented in the beginning of each chapter, to highlight the transformational character of the described 150 years. Rousseau (and his direct antecedents) faced a wholly different world than Montessori and Parkhurst did. In addition, their message was of a different nature. Social science had changed, and | 60 transcended (or descended) from a philosophical point of view to a theoretical and practical science based on experiments and deduction. Ideas could be adapted or implemented, resulting in a much more concrete version of reform than was usual in the 1760s. In this thesis, I have tried to show the connections between these timeperiods, to see which elements survived the troubles and tribulations of the long nineteenth century. Let us recapitulate which elements were and were not present in each of the three reform concepts. Educating Rousseau, born in 1712, presented his ideas to a wholly different world than Montessori and Parkhurst did. The ‘public sphere’ was still in its infancy, rendering freedom of speech a perk still far away. In order to bypass censorship and public disgrace original ways of publishing had to be found. One such ways we have encountered is through the publication the ‘novels’ Émile or Héloïse. These ‘novels’, however, have little to do with the modern meaning of a novel, as they are still filled with endless ruminations on various subjects, and the protagonists—if there are any—are not followed either psychologically or as part of an eventful story. The books deal with domestic and public education, not in an argumentative way, but through describing the life of a series of fictitious characters. In Émile Rousseau gives us the story— however shallow—of a tutor and a child in a country-house, far away from regular society. Here, he describes a laissez-faire experiment with the education of a child. The child Émile is allowed to roam the countryside surrounding the house by himself, educating himself from merely two of the three sources of learning: from nature and from things. Nature, the intrinsically good component of mankind is able to largely educate the child, for all the good and untampered knowledge already remains in the individual human himself. The second source, still reliable, but a less ‘absolute’ source of knowledge is those coming from things. Man, the origin of corruption, is able to tamper with 61 | things, and propose them selectively to the pupil, thereby doing away with its innocuous, unprejudiced value. However, when no humans interfere with these things, they propose a decent source of learning. The pupil must be shielded from third source of learning, those of men, for as long as possible, until he is wise enough to form judgement of its own. The child thus should be left alone, allowing him to follow his instincts, with a guiding nature that is perfectly capable of educating an individual. He is to be protected from the corrupting intellectual tradition, and guarded from interaction with society or the other sex for as long as possible. Only in the last part of the book, s/he is introduced to his perfect-behaving, subserviently constructed counterpart. Being both a product of its time and ahead of its time, this tract is not useful in every aspect. At times, it is hard to see what Rousseau meant concretely with his philosophical ruminations. In addition, its misogynist nature renders it difficult to see if he believed in a universal nature equally present in both boys and girls. However, if we read it post-structurally, Rousseau being a product of its time could have been hardly able to write a non-religious, gender-transcending, concrete piece of educational advice. Therefore we should focus on the elements that withstood the societal upheaval of the nineteenth century and were used by the (nineteenth and) twentieth century reformers. | 62 *** Rousseau’s book was largely negatively received. His digressions from the ‘good faith’ as advocated in his La “Profession de foi du Vicaire Savoyard” (as a side story in Part IV) were received in outrage. Rousseau felt himself misunderstood and spent most of his last years in solitude. 59 Among the few people that picked up on his ideas were Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi and Friedrich Fröbel. They implemented ideas on illiteracy and socio-ethical betterment of individual humans in a much more practical fashion. However, the demand—apart from the pushing back of the illiteracy grade—was not there yet, and it was not until the 1870s that their ideas gained some momentum. From the 1900s however, when the state as a caring institution grew to full stature, there was in enormous increase in attention for educational reform. Intellectuals like John Dewey started to write about education, and how it should be remodelled to suit the needs of contemporary society. In this context, of social and ethical ‘demise’, or as many people felt it, we must locate the increase in popularity of Maria Montessori. Assigned by the Italian government to completely educate—both in opvoeding and in onderwijs— the children from a worker’s neighbourhood in Rome, her ideas flourished as she provided the poor citizens with opportunities to function in society as full members. They learned to read, to count, but also how to organise their homes and practice good hygiene. Through a combination of strict rules and temporal individual freedom through exercises, she created both discipline and maintained the individual pupil’s interest. She focused on training the senses, as they were the foundation of learning. One needs his or her senses to acquire information, rendering them exceptionally important. Montessori focused on individual discovery and initiative, but also on cooperation between pupils. Blackburn, S., “Rousseau, Jean-Jacques” The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. (Oxford 2008) visited on June, 19, 2012, accessible on: <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry=t98.e2733>. 59 63 | Montessori excelled in practicality. She was an excellent observer and an enormously dedicated tutor. The Montessori Method (1912) was ready to be implemented, providing photographs of the to be used materials, lesson outlines and a theoretical and experimental foundation to the reform programme. This rendered the Method an immediate success, first nationally, and then abroad. Within several years, she was invited to many different countries to speak about her new approach to education. However, due to the language, the Anglo-Saxon world proved to be an initial barrier to the Italian-speaking Montessori. Enter, Helen Parkhurst. *** Helen Parkhurst, a Wisconsin-born school teacher came to her reform system under influence of her background in teaching at a one-classroom school in rural Wisconsin and her thorough knowledge of other people’s reform ideas—notably John Dewey’s Chicago Laboratory School, Carleton Washburne’s Winnetka Plan and Montessori’s Method. After the United States’ officials’ interest was heightened by the initial success of Montessori, Parkhurst was sent to Italy to study her Method, and teach it to American educators. As stated, the language barrier was a severe one, in which Montessori was not willing to learn English and vice versa. After Parkhurst became well acquainted with the Method she taught it all around the States. Just as Montessori had been invited to the United States by members of some well-to-do industrialist families, Parkhurst was given the opportunity to experiment with her ideas on education on behalf of the Crane family. Here, in Dalton, Massachusetts, she laid the groundwork for the Dalton Plan. After a one-year success story, she was invited to reside in a building in the Upper East Side of New York City, where the school remains even today as a remnant of the progressive education spurt of the early twentieth century. Different than Montessori, which focused on children aged 2-10; the Dalton Plan focused on children aged 9-16. Parkhurst saw that the child’s | 64 initiative was there, however it had to be stimulated through poignant goals, tasks and questions that require the child to think out of the box, see interdisciplinary connections and plan its own time according to its demands. Parkhurst prepared the children to form their own solutions, feel responsibility through a carefully measured supply of freedom and devote their time to school subjects according to their weaknesses and strengths. Parkhurst abolished timetables and bells, restructuring the classrooms according to subject, and longer according to age. This created a wholly new dynamic in which children were stimulated to look for answers and solutions in the materials but also with the other pupils. She did not change anything of the curriculum, but merely changed the questions and restructured them according to stimulating tasks. Thus, by allowing the child to choose how to accomplish his or her tasks, Parkhurst prepared the child for society, giving them a lesson in cooperation, independence, responsibility and solution-seeking. Life What immediately becomes clear after one has read the historical and cultural background to these three educational reform plans, is how each of them was thoroughly shaped by their own time and their own experiences. Rousseau wrote his book in a time shifting from Ancien Régime via Enlightenment to Romanticism. He stands in a strong philosophes tradition, and contains both elements from the past and the future. Montessori, growing up in Italy’s urban centres, notices the poverty and together with her experience in mentally and physically challenged children’s homes, she comes up with a method for the betterment of society, focusing not solely on onderwijs but also on opvoeding. Parkhurst, teaching in rural Wisconsin, growing up in the United States, home to the ‘American dream’ of independence and selfsufficiency writes a tract on responsibility and being hardened without being callous, as cooperation is still very important. 65 | Thus, all three were products of their own lives and their own times. They proposed different outlooks for educational reform, highlighting different aspects that they deemed most important for the betterment of society. Because they stressed different aspects, it comes as no surprise that the educational reform systems were more successful in some countries than in others. We can see that the ideas of freedom and self-sufficiency are very strong components in all three educational systems. However—Rousseau realised this through his staged events—nature and liberalism cannot be the sole teacher of humanity, and the curriculum plays as an important role as ever. Nonetheless, the journey to the goal defines the learning process even more so. Luckily, these three progressive educators have realised this, stressing the individuality of children. This individuality is necessary in order to maximise the potential of each child’s capability to learn. Rousseau, Montessori and Parkhurst agree that the child’s interest and initiative can be maintained through playful exercises and freedom of choice instead of coerced teaching and punishment. The executions of these principles vary among each reform system, but I find that the core values of Rousseau’s piece are preserved; they have been made concrete and practical. In this thesis, I have combined several fields to give a proper analysis of progressive education from its earliest origins to its practical application. Although I have chosen three case studies to make the subject more explicit, it is clear that the concepts related to progressive education are not merely tied to their respective intellectual; they are used and revalued, emphasised or played down, and adapted to suit the needs of new theories. Although Montessori and Parkhurst hardly mention their predecessors, it is clear that they stand in a philosophical and pedagogical tradition. Thus, although there is no explicit acknowledgement, the ideas of eighteenth and nineteenth century reformers resonate through in the numerous pieces that have been drawn up in the following years. Through covering a time period of over 150 years, I have given both a biographical sketch of several main proponents of progressive education, but | 66 more importantly, I have touched upon some key concepts within the field. Concepts like ‘negative education’, ‘responsibility through freedom’, ‘preserving initiative’ and ‘natural development’ are recurring themes in the works of many progressive educators. By describing these concepts’ origin and prevalence, I thus hope to have contributed to a History of Ideas in the educational reform field. Many of these concepts are still relevant today, and can be adapted to modern day societies needs. By tracing their origins, use and applications, these ideas can be revalued, with possibilities for implementation in modern school systems. When society demanded for educational reform, it comes as no surprise that various interested parties came up with a variety of plans for the betterment of society. Whether it was due to the progressive or the traditional educators, education has improved immensely over the last 150 years, but new challenges lie ahead. Progressive education has come and gone in the last hundred years. In the Netherlands, the various progressive education movements are particularly strong, but in many other places of the world traditional education is still the prime way of transferring knowledge. However, in the ‘new’ globalising and internet-filled world, it is necessary to revalue these progressive educators, as they might propose new insights into the acquisition of knowledge. Internet distracts us from learning too many ‘facts’, but how will we ever be able to see connections and think abstractly when we do not have the right knowledge instantly available through memory. These and further developments pose interesting questions on the future of education. This history into progressive education focused on three case-studies might provide some help into revaluing the importance of responsibility, individuality and cooperation for future educational reformers. 67 | Epilogue In this thesis I have analysed the origins of progressive education through the study of an early and two modern examples of this movement. I have shown that it is a story closely entangled with the rest of history, for the educational reformers adapted to the problems of their time. Naturally, the history of progressive education did not stop in the 1930s. Foremost, Western Europe still had to endure its most ravaging conflict, World War II, and endure thorough social changes in the years thereafter. Furthermore, events like 1968, multiculturalism and the advance of technology force us to cast a new look at certain aspects of traditional and progressive education. I, myself, received my high school education at a school for Dalton education: the Helen Parkhurst College in Almere. I thought it a nice addition to give some examples how the original reform material as given by Helen Parkhurst was adapted to the needs of this day and age. First, let us look at the practical structure. The lower two grades comprised classes with pupils of all levels. This is unique in the Netherlands, for they either categorically divide everyone according to level (in order of increasing difficulty (or theoreticality) VMBO-BBL, VMBO-KBL, VMBO-TL, HAVO, VWO), or divide between VMBO and HAVO/VWO. Here however, children aged 12-14 would help each other gain the optimum level of education through cooperation. In the last three years of education, ages 15 and up, the so-called ‘second phase’, classes would be divided to prepare them for their exams. A day consisted of five classes of seventy minutes. As a concession to Parkhurst abolishing a timetable whatsoever, the school realised that if too large a portion of the time is devoted to the switching of classes and ‘quieting down’, it would decrease the pupil’s concentration and efficiency. Except for the middle period, periods were devoted to specific subjects; these you were required to take with your own class. During the middle period however, the so-called ‘Dalton Period’, the pupil was free to go to the classroom of the | 68 subject s/he needed to devote the most time to. The school was divided in several compartments however, so the distinction between upper (15-18) and lower (12-15) grades and levels was maintained. In each class, both the ‘free’ and fixed ones, there was roughly ten minutes of class introduction, and the remaining hour would be spent individually or in small groups. The year was divided in three trimesters of twelve weeks, plus one week of exams. Every teacher would hand out a ‘learning track’ with several stimulating goals to be achieved in the trimester, the reading materials, fields left blank to fill in expectations and a plan for ‘personal approach’. This highly individualised method, still full with stimulation of initiative stayed very true to the original Dalton Plan. After each trimester, individual ‘reflection forms’ had to be handed in, and personal talks were held with the tutors, reflecting on the made choice and the achieved results. Disciplinary boundaries faded, as many subjects merged, among them exact sciences and social sciences. But also special projects which combined languages with art or history. The walls between classes were literally torn down in the so-called ‘department’ were three separate rooms were joined into a single room, with different corners for different skills necessary for the acquisition of various languages (reading, listening, speaking). Other rooms received glass walls to maximise transparency. Thus, children were forced to cooperate and think out of the box, devote more attention to subjects for a longer period, come up with their own solutions and acquire skills instead of ‘plain’ knowledge. Concessions were made, as timetables were introduced and classes were organised according to age, but many elements were kept intact to maximise individual inventiveness and responsibility. 69 | *** For many children the system worked, however the transparency and emphasis on personal responsibility leaves room for the ill-willing student to slack or devote his or her time only to subjects s/he likes. Progress (or the lack thereof) is only visible after twelve weeks, rendering it hard for teachers to keep up with the pupil’s activities. In addition, a lot of strain is put on the tutor or mentor of a class. Although s/he is specialised in one (or at the most two) subjects, s/he is the teacher that has weekly meetings with the class, and it is his or her responsibility to track the pupil’s full functioning within the school system. Personally, I found that the heterogeneous classes, which include all levels of education, did not work for most pupils, as smart students are easily coerced into decreasing their effort in schoolwork to stay ‘cool’. I have seen many grades drop as a result of social pressure, and the effect of the initial idea, that of the strengthening of weaker students through cooperation, was utterly minimal. Although this and the other education systems described above seem to support a child-centred approach, the quality of the teachers will make or break these systems. The teacher’s inspirational qualities are vital to stimulating the children, to provide them with enough challenge to keep them wanting more and enough variety to keep it interesting. However, the quality of the teacher as vital for the well doing of the system is no different in traditional education. There is one big difference: whereas in the traditional system, education is centred on the teacher, and his or her skill is needed and tested directly during class, in progressive education the teacher’s skills are tested in a much less explicit way. In these systems, s/he is a motivator and a mentor. S/he should excel in drawing up Dalton goals and tasks, stage Rousseauvian events and/or arrange Montessorian or Fröbelian materials in a way that it maximises learning. This background-, implicitly controlling role, requires as much skill — perhaps more—as traditional teaching. It is directed towards long-term goals; | 70 skills and qualities, and less to short-term goals which are more easily measured. It demands a teacher with patience and prescience, capable of motivating in less explicit ways. I—unlike Rousseau, but in line with Parkhurst—believe that children have immense capabilities to learn, but they must be stimulated, kept eager and supplied with an endless number of goals, solutions and problems. If executed correctly, education can create moral citizens capable of realising wonderful things. 71 | Bibliography Bertram, C., “Jean Jacques Rousseau”, in: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 ), visited on June, 21st, 2012, accessible at: <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/rousseau>. Blackburn, S., ‘Rousseau, Jean-Jacques’, in: The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. (Oxford 2008) visited on June, 19, 2012, accessible on: <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry =t98.e2733>. Buchanan, I., ‘First Wave feminism’, in: A Dictionary of Critical Theory (Oxford 2010) visited on June, 19, 2012, accessible on: <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main &entry=t306.e251>. Certeau, M. de, The Practice of Everyday Life (T. Tomasik, transl.) (Minneapolis 1998, original work published in 1980). Cremin, L. A., American Education: The Metropolitan Experience (New York 1988). Delaney, J., ‘Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712—1778)’, in: Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (October 21, 2005) visited on June, 21, 2012, accessible at: < http://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseau/#H6>. Dewey J., The Child and the Curriculum (Chicago 1956, original work published in 1902). Dewey, J., ‘My pedagogic creed’ in: School Journal, Vol.: 54 (January 1897) 77-80. Duggan, C., The Force of Destiny: a History of Italy since 1796 (London 2007). Dworkin, M. S. (ed), Dewey on Education (New York 1959). Fox Lee, L., ‘The Dalton Plan and the Loyal, Capable Citizen’, in: History of Education: Journal of the History of Education Society, Vol.: 29, No.: 2 (2000), 129-138. Groag Bell, S. and Offen, K., Women, the Family, and Freedom: The Debate in Documents, Volume One, 1750-1880. (Stanford 1983). Habermas, J., Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft. (Frankfurt a. M. 1990). | 72 Hannam, C. and Stephenson, N., ‘Rousseau and education’, in: The Oxford Companion to the Mind. (Oxford 1987) visited on June, 19, 2012 , accessible at <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry =t159.e738>. Kahl, S., The Religious Roots of Modern Poverty Policy: Catholic, Lutheran, and Reformed Protestant Traditions Compared, (2005) visited on May, 31, 2012, accessible on: <www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/politics/faculty/mead/V53.0395/Kahl.pdf>. Lager, D., Helen Parkhurst and the Dalton Plan (Ann Arbor 1983). Malanima, P. and Volckart, O., Urbanisation 1700-1870 (2010) visited on June, 21, 2012, accessible at: <www.cepr.org/meets/wkcn/1/1679/papers/MalanimaVolckart-Chapter.pdf >. Montessori, M., The Montessori Method : Scientific Pedagogy, as applied to Child Education in ‘The Children’s Houses’ (A. George, transl.) (London 1912, original work published in 1911). Parkhurst, H., Education on the Dalton Plan (London 1922). Rousseau, J.J., Discourse on the Origin and Basis of Inequality Among Men (M. Cranston, transl.) (Harmondsworth 1984, original work published in 1754) . Rousseau, J.J., Émile, or On Education (A. Bloom, transl.) (Harmondsworth 1991, original work published in 1762). Rousseau, J.J., Julie, ou la Nouvelle Heloïse (Paris 1960, original work published in 1761). Rousseau, J.J., Political Writings (F. Watkins, transl.) (Edinburg 1953, original works published between 1750 and 1772). Rousseau, J.J., Social Contract, the (G.D.H. Cole, transl.) (Buffalo 1988, original work published in 1762). Schwegman, M.J., Maria Montessori, 1870-1952: Kind van haar Tijd, Vrouw van de Wereld (Amsterdam 1999). Semel, S., The Dalton School, Transformation of a Progressive School (New York 1992). Singh, Renu, ‘The Montessori Method’, in: Seminar, Vol.: 546 (Febuary 2005) visited on June, 21, 2012, accessible at: <http://www.eledu.net/rrcusrn_data/The%20Montessori%20method.pdf>. Stephenson, N., ‘Froebel, Friedrich Wilhelm August’, in: The Oxford Companion to the Mind (Oxford 1987) visited on June, 19, 2012, accessible on: 73 | <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry =t159.e355>. Wallace, S. (ed.), ‘Pestalozzi, Johann Heinrich’, in: A Dictionary of Education (Oxford 2009) visited on June, 17, 2012 , accessible on <http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry =t267.e760>.