Improvisation: Deliberate or Spontaneous? [T]here may be no single human endeavor that is more deserving of neuroscientific inquiry than our capacity to create. —McPherson & Limb (2013) Barbara Gail Montero The City University of New York bmontero@gc.cuny.edu University of Louisville 2015 In my forthcoming book: Thought in Action: Expertise and the Conscious Mind I reject “just-do-it” and defend “cognition-in-action” The three components of Cognition-in-Action Descriptive: Optimal expert action frequently is thoughtful, effortful, and attentive Rejection of the “principle of interference” : Thinking (attending, etc.) do not tend to interfere with expert performance Prescriptive: Experts should generally think, monitor their movements, etc. I used to think that improvisation may be a counterexample to “cognition-in-action” Descriptive: Improvisation is spontaneous The “principle of interference” : Thinking (attending, etc.) hinders with expert improvisation Prescriptive: Experts improvisers should “just do it.” Why think that improvisation is contrary to Cognitionin-action? Charlie Parker: “You’ve got to learn your instrument. Then, you practice, practice, practice. And then, when you finally get up there on the bandstand, forget all that and just wail” (widely attributed to Parker). Trey Anastasio, the guitarist from the band Phish: “There’s a lot of preparation and discipline that goes into it just so that, when you’re in the moment, you’re not supposed to be thinking at all" (Simonini, 2011). Mozart writes to his sister that in improvising a cadenza, he “just plays the first thing that comes to mind” (Spaethling 2000). Are we good judges of what goes on in our own minds? Methodological Principle. First person reports of what goes on in one’s own mind should be accepted as (defeasible) evidence for the truth of the report unless we have good reason to question them. Acceptance Principle. “A person is entitled to accept as true something that is presented as true and that is intelligible to him, unless there are stronger reasons not to do so" (Burge 1993: 467). Since I take seriously the claims of experts who say that they think in action, I need to take seriously the claims of those who say that they don’t. What did I do about this apparent wrench in my theory? TRIED NOT TO THINK ABOUT IT TOO MUCH! Thank you Professor Dove for prompting me to change this. What I now believe Improv isn’t as spontaneous as it might seem to an observer; bodily awareness, decision making, conscious control etc. do play a role in at least some kinds of improv. But how they do and the extent to which they do likely depends on the context and the individual. Of course: I’m still a bit unsure about it all The Score: I. Bird’s eye view of neuroimaging studies of musical improv II. Possible analogies and disanalogies to dance improv III. Reasons for why complete spontaneity might be contraindicated in improv IV. Respond to Hubert Dreyfus, John McDowell and Twyla Tharp V. Relation between monitoring movement and conscious control I. Musical Improvisation under the scanner Limb and Braun’s (2008) jazz improvisation study. Deactivation of the lateral prefrontal regions (LOFC and DLPFC), indicating spontaneity: reduced inhibition, cognitive control, planning and monitoring. Increase activity in the medial prefrontal cortex (MPFC); daydreaming, spontaneous thought. Liu et al. (2012) had similar results with rap artists. This research suggests that executive control systems are suppressed during improvisation: The idea that spontaneous composition relies to some degree on intuition, “the ability to arrive at a solution without reasoning’’ [36], may be consistent with [what]...we observed. That is, creative intuition may operate when an attenuated DLPFC no longer regulates the contents of consciousness, allowing unfiltered, unconscious, or random thoughts and sensations to emerge. Therefore, rather than operating in accordance with conscious strategies and expectations, musical improvisation may be associated with behaviors that conform to rules implemented by the MPFC outside of conscious awareness [27]. Indeed, in other domains it has been shown that focused attention and conscious self-monitoring can inhibit spontaneity and impair performance [37,38]. (Limb and Braun p. 4). Note: both Liu et al. (2012) and Limb and Braun (2008) also report activation of the ACC, SMA, PMD and IRG—areas associated with cognitive and motor control. Vague aside on the mind-body problem: “Scientists cannot effectively study creativity without the intuitions [phenomenological insights] and discoveries of the creative agents themselves” (McPherson and Limb); the firstperson account and the nuerological account are mutually supportive. The suggestion that improvisation is and ought to be spontaneous is contrary to Pablo Casals’ advice: “Don’t let the music lead you; you need to direct it” (as passed down to Inbal Segev via Bernard Greenhouse). What this means, according to Segev, is that you “don’t play as if the music will talk by itself; don’t just go on automatic pilot; you have to be alert and thinking” (personal communication). But Casals’ wasn’t talking about improvisation. Does performing a set piece employ executive processes, while improvisation is spontaneous? Ecological Validity: McPherson and Limb (2013) question the fMRI studies: If a creator is placed in an abnormal, constraining environment during the course of a scientific study, the creative process itself is threatened, calling into question the validity of any observations made thereafter. Yet this would seem to make one need to exert more conscious control. However, the possible social element is absent. Rock and blues bass player Alex Craven explained: I always have a pulse on the audience and am constantly reading the other members of the trio, ready to give them what they need and take from them what’s offered. Neurology of Trading Fours In contrast to the earlier studies, Donnay et al.’s (2014): found that the improvisers displayed not reduced, but heightened activity in executive control areas of the brain relative to playing a scale. Constrained improv Berkowitz and Ansari (2008) looked at (among other things) fixed melody with improvised rhythm, improvised melody with fixed rhythm, fixed rhythm and melody. No connection between improv and decrease in DLPC and increase in MPFC. Rhythm and melodic improv both showed (among other things) activity in the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC), which is associated with inhibition of inappropriate responses. II. Possible analogies and disanalogies to dance improvisation What is dance improv? Put aside: Improvisation as part of all set choreography Improvisation in the dance of life. (Erving Goffman 1959 and Judith Butler 1990.) A) Improv without an audience For fun To work out choreographic ideas Therapy B) Improv for an audience constrained unconstrained One difference: Music improv is more audience focused than dance improv. Music and contact improviser Richard Kim sees the lack of audience as relevant: In music improvisation…I am concerned with both the local as well as the global. Rather than simply reacting in the moment, I'm paying attention to things such as deep structure/form and motivic development. I am remembering the entire piece (or trying to) and creating the next moment with that aural history as context. This is because … I am concerned with creating an experience for an external viewer/listener that is accessible and interesting/stimulating. I think of my approach as "compositional"—thinking of what is being created as a composition, even if improvised in the moment. Viva cognition-in-action! Richard Kim improvising on the viola. In contrast is Kim’s description of contact: In contact improvisation, I am concerned almost entirely with the moment…I am not thinking ahead, making conscious choices, or retaining or shaping a sense of largescale form….The audience, if any, is simply my partner, and we are creating a mutually enjoyable experience together. It's analogous in many ways to a conversation. Alan Andre: “You need to think about time more.” As Richard and Allan see it in dance improv, conscious control and monitoring may not be entirely absent, but they are attenuated compared to music improv. Structured dance improv might be similar to constrained musical improv In or out of performance contexts: getting down to the floor ten times with increasing difficulty Or initiating movement from one body part. Compared to dancing a memorized piece*, maybe this involves increased planning (DLPFC)? *This may not be the same as performing set choreography. Is dancing with others is like trading fours? Or is it just reflexive—in the sense of a learned reflex? Sometimes that’s the point. Other times a reflexive action turns into something you do. (Mwanza’s example.) III. Against spontaneity We saw that the fMRI studies are mixed. Also, there is the question of ecological validity and, of course, some uncertainty about the brain. So plenty of room for a philosopher to ask: What are some reasons why an improviser might want to avoid spontaneity? Deliberate control adds interest not only for the audience The same style is unobjectionable, however, one wants to avoid the feeling of creating “the same old stuff.” (That’s fine for playing in the scanner, but not for playing on stage, and maybe not even oneself.) Engaging the conscious mind might help one to do so. As the contact-improv dancer Romain Bigé explained, for him an important guiding idea is “make the second choice” (personal communication). In other words, don’t do what comes naturally, habitually and automatically. This is more interesting for the improviser, partner and, if there is one, audience. Improvisational Theater A further factor in theater improv is that automatic responses tend towards stereotypes more than well-thought-out ones. Contact improv endeavors to reject gender stereotypes. (ACC supports gender neutrality?) ` Some speculative remarks on seeing the mind in action Can we see thought in action? What makes electronic music so flat? Is entirely reflexive action similarly dull? IV. Responding to Hubert Dreyfus, John McDowell and Twyla Tharp All three, as different as they are, suggest some type of “nonminded” spontaneity in action. Tharp: Her choreography arises out of improvisation It was so unconscious that she had to rely on her dancers to remember it. Dreyfus “[Expert action is] direct and unreflective...[that is to say,] nonconceptual and nonminded” (Dreyfys 2007a: p. 355). On this view, expert action, at its best, is entirely bereft of mental processing: not just conscious mental processing, but any mental processing whatsoever; actions are drawn out of experts by external forces, at times without the experts even being able to recall what occurred. For example, “after much experience, the chess master is directly drawn by the forces on the board to make a masterful move” (2013: p. 35). Merleau-Ponty “The soccer field…is pervaded by lines of force…[and that] the player becomes one with [the field]…[and] at this moment consciousness is nothing but the dialectic of milieu and action” ( Merleau-Ponty 1945: p. 168-9). Dreyfus understands Merleau-Ponty as saying that the mind dissolves into a relation with the environment: “for an expert to remain in flow and so perform at his best, he must let himself be merged into the field of forces and all monitoring must stop” (2013: p. 31). John McDowell McDowell thinks that all action exemplifies rationality. Yet he still holds that the reasons guiding expert action are not on the forefront of an expert’s mind: The idea that an expert “deliberates about what to do and acts in the light of the result should be rejected” (McDowell, 2013, p. 47). Lighting chess experiment What explicit thoughts can one have in contact? Bigé (forthcoming): The paradox of improvisation is that, although the improvisers are doing their best to be “in the present moments only", they seem to be anticipating each other's moves. In CI, this tension is clearly resolved by the fact that …[the] volitions [of the improviser] have blury or plastic contours …:if I want to lift someone, the result of the volition might be that I end up lifted, and this remains an acceptable outcome of that. Kent de Spain’s (2003) experience sampling study of dance improvisation reveals thought. So does his justification of his method: He chose seven experienced improvisers, each with a minimum of 10 years experience and a background improvisational performance in professional settings in order “to identify improvisers who would have the experience to minimize the impact of the reporting process on their dancing” (p. 38, 2003). Assumption: Once experienced, thinking does not hinder doing. Even Tharp, who employs improvisation to arrive at ideas for her dances, meticulously sifts through her video-taped improv sessions: “[i]f I find thirty seconds of movement out of three hours, I’m happy” (2003: 192). Moreover, in the battle over “some transcendent, inexplicable Dionysian act of inspiration…[versus] hard work,” she says ,“I come down on the side of hard work” (2003: 6). V. Conclusion: pondering the relation between monitoring movement and conscious control First person reports: some improvisers attest to are intentions and choices. Neuroscientific support: Donnay et al. (2014) and Berkowitz and Ansari (2008 ) suggests improv is not as spontaneous as it might seem. Arguments: this might be aesthetically advantageous. Question: What about the bare act of being consciously aware of your own movements? (Aware of movements versus thought) Many dancers—improvisatory or otherwise—allude to the importance of monitoring or attending to movement. “Improvisation,” as de Spain (2008) puts it, “is an attentional practice.” Why is attention to movement important? *Pleasurable *Perhaps there is some truth to the adage: Where attention goes, energy flows.(Could this be tested? Yeu and Cole’s (1992) grip-strength study. What about fight or flight?) Steve Paxton: Why is full consciousness so important to me?” Because consciousness can be felt to change according to what it experiences. If a gap of consciousness occurs at a critical moment, we lose an opportunity to learn from the moment. A blackout lasting fractions of a second during a roll is not acceptable as full consciousness of the roll, and the gap will remain embedded in the movement as part of the overall feeling of the movement. If consciousness stays open during these critical moments, it will have a experience of them, and will enlarge its concept to match the new experience. This expanded picture becomes the new ground for moving (p. 177). *Learn from the moment for the present and the future. *But perhaps also: full consciousness of movement (generally) introduces an element of control. Conscious control: deliberately moving the body, or deliberating engaging the mind: “When we knowingly give rise to any new motion of our body or new perception of our mind” (Hume, 1888: p. 708). Focus on your breathing. Does it change? It is possible to consciously attend to one’s (passive) movements without consciously controlling them: Anterior cord syndrome causes (among other things) a complete loss of motor function below the injury while preserving (among other things) proprioception. Does this contradict James’ contention that “volition is nothing but attention” (1890/2007 p.424)? Or is the volition merely ineffective? Or is volition merely action + attention? In any case, as Kimble and Perlmuter (1970) observe, “the act of paying attention to… performances or describing the steps as they occur tends to destroy the automaticity of such behavior” (p. 375). And, as I have argued here and in my book, automaticity is not always a good thing. Habit is a great deadener. —Vladimir in act 2 of Waiting for Godot. THANK YOU !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! Berkowitz AL, Ansari D. (2008) Generation of novel motor sequences: The neural correlates of musical improvisation. NeuroImage 41: 535–543. Bigé, R. (forthcoming), L'excursion du temps. Movement et anticipation en contact improvisation, Oscillations, vol. I/3. Burge, Tyler ((1993). "Content Preservation," Philosophical Review 102: 457-88. de Spain, K. (2008) The cutting edge of awareness: Reports from the inside of improvisation. In Taken by surprise. Donnay, G.F., Rankin, S.K., Lopez-Gonzalez,, M., Jiradejvong, P., Limb, C.J. (2014) Neural substrates of interactive musical improvisation: An fMRI study of ‘trading fours’ in jazz. 9(2). Dreyfus, Hubert L. (2013) The Myth of the Pervasiveness of the Mental. In J.K. Schear (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate (New York: Routledge). Limb, C.J., and Braun, A.R. (2008) Neural substrates of spontaneous music performance: An fMRI study of jazz improvisation, 3(2): 2–9. Liu, S., Chow, H.M., Xu, Y., Erkkinen, M.G., Swelt, K.E., Eagle, M.W., Braun, A.R. (2012) Neural correlates of lyrical improvisation: an fMRI study of freestyle rap. Nat.Sci. Rep. 2, 834. McDowell, John. (2013) “The Myth of the Mind as Detached.” In J.K. Schear (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-inthe-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate (New York: Routledge): 41-58. McPherson, M., Limb, C.J. (2013) Difficulties in the neuroscience of creativity: Jazzimprovisation and the scientific method. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1303, 80–83 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. (1945) Phenomenology of Perception.vTaylor & Francis Books Ltd Montero, B. (2016) Thought in Action: Expertise and the Conscious Mind. (OUP) Paxton, S. (2008) Drafting Interior Techniques, in Taken by surprise: A dance improvisation reader Simonini, R. (2011), Trey Anastasio and the art of improvisation Tharp, T. (2002) The Creative Habit: Learn it and use it for Life. Simon and Shuster Paperbacks. Yue G, Cole KJ. Strength increases from the motor program: comparison of training with maximum voluntary and imagined muscle contractions. /Neurophysiol. 1992;67:111