INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF ORGANIZATION THEORY AND BEHAVIOR, 8 (4), 541-558 WINTER 2005 CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION: OPPORTUNITIES FOR CITIZEN GOVERNANCE Nancy Meyer-Emerick* ABSTRACT. Critical theory has rarely articulated an agenda for social change linking theory to practice. This paper provides several examples of “critical theory in practice” and focuses specifically on Fay’s Critical Social Science (CSS) model. The methods of conflict transformation are then applied to CSS in order to accomplish two goals. First, political conflicts resulting from decision making can be used to transform both individuals and systems. Second, CSS more adequately accounts for some of the non-rational aspects of human nature, such as our resistance to change, thus improving its catalytic validity as a critical social theory. Together, the processes of CSS and conflict transformation provide a framework for enhancing the potential for citizen governance. INTRODUCTION This paper begins by identifying the gaps in critical theory as defined by the Frankfurt School and Habermas’s discourse theory. Critical Social Science (CSS) fills in those gaps to enable researchers or practitioners who are working with citizen groups to build decisionmaking capacity in order to enable them to self-govern. Yet even the methods from CSS are difficult to achieve because human beings are inherently uncomfortable with change, and CSS is particularly disconcerting because it generally challenges an individual’s core beliefs and worldview. This psychological disruption causes both personal and interpersonal conflict. The paper describes how this conflict can be overcome using conflict transformation processes. ----------------------------* Nancy Meyer-Emerick, Ph.D., is an Associate Professor at the Maxine Goodman Levin College of Urban Affairs, Cleveland State University. Her research interests include democratic governance, policy analysis, and risk analysis. CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION Copyright © 2005 by PrAcademics Press 542 MEYER-EMERICK THE ORIGINS OF CRITICAL THEORY Critical theory was developed in the 1920s by members of the “Frankfurt School”, the Institute for Social Research at the University of Frankfurt, Germany (Adorno, Frenkel-Brunswik, Levinson, & Sanford, 1982; Arato & Gebhardt, 1978; Held, 1980; Jay, 1973; Kellner, 1989). Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, and Herbert Marcuse were the primary scholars associated with the theory, which built chiefly on the work of Marx, Kant, Hegel, Weber, and Durkheim (Fay, 1987; Kincheloe & McLaren, 2000; Morrow, 1994). This group initially used the term “Critical Theory” to highlight their “substantive, neo-Marxist theory of advanced capitalism” (Fay, 1987, p. 4) and to acknowledge its roots in Kant’s critical philosophy and Marx’s critique of ideology. Morrow (1994, p. 99) states that “at the time of his inauguration as director of the Frankfurt Institute, Horkheimer defined the programmatic task of Critical Theory as ‘the question of the connection between the economic life of society, the psychic development of individuals, and the changes in cultural domains in the narrower sense. To these belong not only the so-called spiritual contents of science, art, and religion, but also law, custom, fashion, public opinion, sports, leisure pastimes, life style, etc.’ (Horkheimer, 1972, p. 43, translated by Morrow).” The Frankfurt School theorists’ analysis was derived from philosophy, sociology, psychology, economics, and political science, however they rejected the positivist methods of the natural sciences, seeking instead to formulate a historical theory of society. Having lived through the destruction of World War I and recognizing that people were unable to free themselves from domination by the market, they rejected Marx’s economic determinism. Instead they came to believe that even people’s personalities were being subsumed by the market, therefore any plausible theory needed to identify paths to liberation. After field research in Nazi Germany in the 1930s revealed the growing fascism among the proletariat in whom they held such hope, Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse, among others, fled to the United States. Yet here too they were dismayed by “contradictions between progressive American rhetoric of egalitarianism and the reality of racial and class discrimination” (Kincheloe & McLaren, 2000, p. 280) as well as social scientists’ complete reliance on empirical methodology. Horkheimer and Adorno, and others, returned to Germany in 1953 to CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 543 reestablish the Institute for Social Research, but Marcuse remained and the student movement of the 1960s popularized his philosophical work. With the exception of Marcuse (e.g., 1969, 1972) none of the original critical theorists was able to advance an enlightened and emancipatory theory of political action. This insurmountable difficulty was partially the result of the obscurity of their writing. They were afraid to expose their analysis lest it be co-opted and its emancipatory potential destroyed. Works such as Marcuse’s “One Dimensional Man” (1964) and Horkheimer and Adorno’s “Dialectic of Enlightenment” (1972) explicitly lacked the possibility of resistance (Fay, 1987, p. 6). Nevertheless, the immense contribution of the Frankfurt School critical theorists persists, although in different forms. THE DEVELOPMENT OF CRITICAL THEORY Since the 1960s, Jürgen Habermas (e.g., 1973, 1975, 1984, 1987, 1990) has been considered the most prominent of the intellectual heirs of the Frankfurt School. However, he dramatically revised critical theory focusing on knowledge interests and communicative action. The three primary knowledge interests were “an empirical-analytical interest in potential control, a hermeneutic-historical interest in understanding; and a critical-emancipatory interest in freedom and autonomy (Habermas, 1971)” [italics in original] (Morrow, 1994, p. 144). Unfortunately however, despite the brilliance of Habermas’ extensive analysis, it lacks an emancipatory political agenda. As Zanetti (1997) states, “Without a political agenda—a connection to practice—critical theory can be nothing but philosophy “after the fact,” an intellectual cul-de-sac. It can interpret, but not change, the world” (p. 156). Yet, critical theory as derived from the Frankfurt School is only one of the many ‘critical’ theories in the social sciences today. Morrow (1994) describes the development of critical theory from its origins to the present day and then discusses it from three sociological perspectives: as an approach to the sciences, a conception of society, and a vision for realizing certain values. He identifies aspects of critical theory in all the social science disciplines: for example, anthropology, history, political science, communications and cultural studies, psychology, geography and urban studies, and economics. Parallel developments can be seen also in more applied and professional fields such as education, social work, organizational studies and public 544 MEYER-EMERICK administration, legal studies, and planning and policy research. Critical theory has also had a strong influence on feminist theory and cultural studies. Largely following Habermas’ method, critical theory in Germany has been further developed by “Wolfgang Bonß, Helmut Dubiel, Klaus Eder, Axel Honneth, Hans Joas, Claus Offe, and Albrecht Wellmer” (Morrow, 1994, p. 16). Offe, for example, has been involved “with the founding of the Green Party and has observed its ‘maturation’ process with critical support” (Mayer & Ely, 1998, p. 336). Joachim Hirsch “is one of Germany’s leading political theorists. He has published extensively on social movements, regulation theory, and the state and system of states in capitalism” (Anderson, 2002, p. x). Although Morrow (1994) states that critical theory is not currently associated specifically with any group in France, in French Quebec it is with Rioux and Nielsen, and can be loosely associated with the work of contemporary French “sociologists Alain Touraine…and Pierre Bourdieu… as well as the late philosopher and historian Michel Foucault” (p. 17). However the vast majority of critical theorists are Anglo American. According to Morrow (1994, p. 17), Examples of contemporary British and North American sociologists and social, political, and cultural theorists closely associated with critical theory are the work of Zygmunt Bauman, Anthony Giddens, David Held, John Keane, William Outhwaite, and John B. Thompson in Britain; Ben Agger, Robert Antonio, Andrew Arato, Stanley Aronowitz, Seyla Benhabib, Richard Bernstein, Norman Birnbaum, Craig Calhoun, Jean Cohen, Fred Dallmayr, Nancy Fraser, Henry Giroux, Alvin Gouldner, Martin Jay, Douglas Kellner, Tim Luke, Tom McCarthy, Paul Piccone, Mark Posner, and Philip Wexler in the United States; Barry Adam, Gregory Baum, Ioan Davies, Rick Gruneau, Barb Marshall, William Leiss, Greg Nielsen, John O’Neill, Marcel Rioux, and Charles Taylor in Canada; and in Australia and New Zealand in work associated with the journal Thesis Eleven (e.g., Beilharz, et al…) and individuals such as Johann Arnason, Bob Connell, Michael Pusey, Robert E. Young, and Barry Smart. Prominent critical theorists within U.S. public administration literature include Richard Box, Robert Denhardt, Arthur Felts, John Forester, Jay White, and Lisa Zanetti. CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 545 Morrow (1994) defends critical theory from the common claims that it is antiscientific, elitist, and rationalistic. Critical theory is not antiscientific simply because it questions the nature of knowledge and the traditional scientific method. He insists that it is a valid program of research in the social sciences and, while it is often associated with specific ideologies, because it makes this association explicit these linkages can be examined for legitimacy. Critical theorists are often charged with being elitist because their language appears obscure and unrealistic. Morrow suggests that this is due in part to the necessity of discussing philosophical and theoretical concepts with which readers may be unfamiliar. He states, “viewed more closely, the deeper aspirations of contemporary critical theory are very different. On the one hand, critical theory aspires to facilitate a democratization of knowledge in the sense that every person is recognized de facto as a philosopher and encouraged to develop the faculties of fundamental questioning. At the same time, however, there is a refusal to identify the adequacy of theories with their immediate accessibility. A side of scientific inquiry is also inevitably elitist in the sense that novel interpretations of nature and society are often difficult to grasp and translate into popular formulations” (p. 27-28). Finally, and ironically, critical theory is now sometimes attacked as being too rationalistic, primarily by postmodern theorists. Morrow (1994) notes that there are modernist and postmodernist types of critical theory; “although retaining a similar political engagement in its opposition to orthodoxies of Marxism and academic disciplines, postmodern critical theory – as in the work of Michel Foucault – ‘indicts, sometimes explicitly, more often implicitly, the idea that modernity contains within itself the potential for human emancipation’ (Leonard, 1990, p. xiv)” (p. 29). Morrow uses the work of critical realist Roy Bhaskar to bridge the gap between positivism and postmodern relativism. Bhaskar distinguishes between “thought and objects of thought, hence between ‘intransitive’ and ‘transitive’ objects of scientific knowledge. Intransitive objects are thus ‘the (relatively) unchanging real objects which exist outside and perdure independently of the scientific process,’ whereas transitive objects involve ‘the changing (and theoretically –imbued) cognitive objects which are produced within the science as a function and result of its practice’ (Bhaskar, 1986, p. 51)” (Morrow, 1994, p. 78). Ultimately, “critical social science has three distinctive features: ‘an 546 MEYER-EMERICK emphasis on reflexivity, the acceptance of a methodological and ontological orientation distinct from the naturalistic paradigm, and a commitment to social criticism and advocacy’ (Sabia & Wallulis, 1983, p. 6)” (Morrow, 1994, p. 110). Bernstein (1978) researched foundational questions about human nature, social and political knowledge and how it affects lives, and the relation of theory and practice in order to integrate what was right and reject what was false in the complex debate within the social sciences in the 1960s and 70s. He examined social science as natural science and from three contrasting perspectives: analytic philosophy, particularly the “linguistic turn” and the history and philosophy of science; phenomenology; and from the perspective of the Frankfurt School Critical Theorists. Bernstein (1978) found that the critical theory of society was central to the restructuring of social and political theory and that “the search for empirical correlations, the task of interpreting social and political reality, and the critique of this ‘reality,’ are not three distinct types of inquiry. They are the three moments of theorizing about social and political life” (p. 174). He concluded that “We can recognize that there will be no significant movement toward emancipation unless there is a transformation of social and political institutions. But we must also recognize that human beings are capable of bringing to consciousness the interpretations, evaluations, and standards that they tacitly accept, and can subject them to rational criticism” (p. 236). Leonard has identified some practical examples of this process. Leonard (1990) proposes that many social movements are examples of “critical theory in practice” although not explicitly identified as such. He discusses four popular movements. The dependency theory developed by Henri Fernando Cardoso focused on socioeconomic development in Latin America. Cardoso’s (1977) “radically critical” theory sought to “provide social agents with the theoretical tools for understanding and changing their oppressed condition” (p. 16). However, dependency theory is not verified until social actors are able to actually implement the changes implied by their analysis. Freire’s (1970) “pedagogy of the oppressed” is a second example of critical theory in practice. In this educational model (as will be discussed further below) the “teacher” works with the students to enable them to develop their own critical consciousness of oppression and use this CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 547 knowledge to take action. Liberation theology as defined by Gutierrez (1973) is “a theological reflection born of the experience of shared efforts to abolish the current unjust situation and to build a different society, freer and more human” (as cited in Leonard, 1990, p. xxi). The women’s movement is a fourth example of a critical theory in practice specifically because of its “ongoing critical self-examination and consciousness-raising” that provides feminist theories with prescriptions for practice (Leonard, p. xxii). Leonard agrees with Fay that the difference between a “truly critical and a manipulative, instrumentalist social theory ‘is not only the fact that people come to have a particular self-understanding, and that this new self-understanding provides the basis for altering social arrangements, but also the manner in which they come to adopt this new ‘guiding idea.’ In fact, rational discourse must be the cause of the oppressed’s change in basic self-conception’ (Fay, 1977, p. 224-225)” (Leonard, 1990, p. xxii-xxiii). Other processes, particularly Critical Social Science (CSS) as defined by Fay (1987) address some of the gaps within the original critical theory. Morrow (1994, p. 194) states, “Brian Fay provides a useful summary of the basic scheme of a strong program for a critical social science, at least from the perspective of a focus on its task as a theory of praxis….This general model applies rather well to the early form of Critical Theory advocated by Horkheimer and remains pertinent to Habermas’s overall schema, but the latter’s abandonment of the classical revolutionary model of transition puts greater emphasis on its educative functions as a research program.” CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE Fay critiqued the foundations of critical theory and developed a scheme of “critical social science” that would enable emancipatory political action. Although an extensive discussion of his work is beyond the scope of this paper, several key concepts provide the link between critical theory and conflict transformation. Fay distinguishes CSS as a theory of science from the Frankfurt School critical theory, which attempted to describe how society functioned. He uses the term “science” to distinguish this form of critical theory from other “theories of social life which are critical in the requisite sense in both intention and content, but which are not products of the Frankfurt School” (Fay, p. 5). 548 MEYER-EMERICK Fay describes the human condition as a variation of selfestrangement theory, forms of which have existed throughout human history. This theory posits that humans are ignorant of their true nature and situation and so live unsatisfying lives. But it also proposes that people can be enlightened and therefore emancipated to change their social condition. According to Fay, in modern times it is thought that emancipation can only be achieved through scientific knowledge, which could also be appropriated to improve society (Fay, p. 22). Fay maintains that his CSS is scientific, critical, practical, and non-idealistic. He defines CSS as scientific because it can provide “comprehensive explanations in terms of a few basic principles which are subject to public evidence” (p. 26). It is critical in its “sustained negative evaluation of the social order on the basis of explicit and rationally supported criteria” (p. 26). CSS is practical because it arouses “some members of society identified by the theory to transform their social existence in specified ways through fostering in them a new self-knowledge to serve as the basis for such a transformation” (p. 26). And CSS is non-idealistic as it is “not committed to the claims either that ideas are the sole determinant of behavior…or that emancipation simply involves a certain sort of enlightenment…or that people are able and willing to change their self-understandings simply on the basis of rational argument” (p. 26.). Fay’s (1987, pp. 3132) basic CSS scheme outlines the criteria for a truly critical social theory in Table 1. TABLE 1 Criteria for a Truly Critical Social Theory I. A theory of false consciousness which 1. demonstrates the ways in which the self-understandings of a group of people are false (in the sense of failing to account for the life experiences of the members of the group), or incoherent (because internally contradictory), or both. This is sometimes called an “ideology-critique”; 2. explains how the members of this group came to have these selfmisunderstandings, and how they are maintained; 3. contrasts them with an alternative self-understanding, showing how this alternative is superior. CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 549 TABLE 1 (Continued) II. A theory of crisis which 4. spells out what a social crisis is; 5. indicates how a particular society is in such a crisis. This would require examining the felt dissatisfactions of a group of people and showing both that they threaten social cohesion and that they cannot be alleviated given the basic organization of the society and the self-understandings of its members; 6. provides an historical account of the development of this crisis partly in terms of false consciousness of the members of the group and partly in terms of the structural bases of the society. III. A theory of education which 7. offers an account of the conditions necessary and sufficient for the sort of enlightenment envisioned by the theory; 8. shows that given the current social situation these conditions are satisfied. IV. A theory of transformative action which 9. isolates those aspects of a society, which must be altered if the social crisis is to be resolved and the dissatisfactions of its members lessened; 10. details a plan of action indicating the people who are to be the “carriers” of the anticipated social transformation and at least some general idea of how they might do this. Although Fay’s basic CSS scheme appears valid, he emphasizes that it is incomplete due to the assumptions it makes about human nature, that is, its ontological rather than epistemological grounding. First, it is too rational in its “activist conception of human beings” (p. 46) which posits that people will always use their intelligence, curiosity, reflection, and willfulness to actively emancipate themselves. Alternatively, Fay proposes that people will only sometimes alter their beliefs and behavior based on new information about the world (i.e., intelligence). People also are not always curious or seeking out new information in order to understand their world more fully, nor are they generally reflective or willing to examine their deeply held beliefs in relation to the evidence. 550 MEYER-EMERICK This is the core problem that arises when critical theorists attempt to educate and enable people to identify their ‘false consciousness’ about their condition to answer the question “what is the proper end of my life and thus what sort of person ought I to be” (p. 49). Finally, even given new information or self-consciousness, humans will not always change or act (i.e., be willful) based on what they have learned, because change, even for the better, is difficult for people. Secondly, individuals are also deeply influenced by the norms of their cultural community. Fay describes this as the activist theory of society, which is conventional in the sense that an individual could not have a social life without it. Third, people and societies intentionally change themselves through time and Fay describes this as the activist theory of history. These three theories imply that people are always potentially active, yet as Fay notes, they do not always think or behave that way. This reality is problematic for traditional critical theory and CSS because their allure is based, in part, on the belief that once people lose their false consciousness via enlightenment, they will be empowered to act, thus becoming emancipated. If our human nature dictates that we are only partially active, the basic scheme of CSS must be revised. Fay has done this based on four limits. First of all, there is no final “truth” because human beings are historical – in process. And because we are constantly revising what we believe, we also are reconsidering our actions. As we do this, rational disagreement on courses of action is to be expected. The second limit is due to our physical bodies. Fay states, “People are in part what they are because of inherited biological tendencies and in part because of a somatic learning in which they acquire behavioral dispositions which are rooted in their bodily constitution” (p. 207). Thus our bodies themselves may limit “emancipation” and as Fay emphasizes, also allow us to be physically controlled and coerced. The third limit is our “embeddedness” within the human community. We cannot be truly autonomous individuals because so much of who we are is grounded in our traditions. Even more importantly, humans are dependent on each other in countless ways, particularly those attempting to undertake social change. Thus, Fay states, “Humans are not only active beings; they are also embodied, traditional, historical, and embedded….Intelligence, curiosity, reflection, and will are only partly responsible for making humans what they are, and so it is only in certain circumstances and in partial ways that they can be effective” (p. 209). CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 551 Fay warns that there is a dangerous fourth limit to CSS due to its narrowly defined assumptions about human nature. He dubs it the ‘tyranny scenario,’ (p. 209) reminiscent of the revolutions rooted in critical theory that became despotic. Fay proposes that while many movements began with good intentions (enlightening the masses, empowerment, and emancipation), they became corrupted when the leaders found these processes slow and difficult. Convinced of their vision, movement leaders imposed ‘emancipation,’ making the new order equally or more oppressive than the one they were attempting to overthrow. To address the four limits, Fay (1987, p. 213) developed the amendments to the basic CSS scheme as shown in Table 2. After a somewhat lengthy explanation of Fay’s basic and amended CSS schemes, we can now explore how conflict transformation processes might be used to operationalize some of the theories and sub-theories. TABLE 2 Amendment to Truly Critical Social Theory I. A theory of the body which 1. develops an explicit account of the nature and role of inherited dispositions and somatic knowledge 2. formulates a theory of body therapy; 3. spells out the limits which inherited dispositions and somatic knowledge place on liberation. II. A theory of tradition which 4. identifies which parts of a particular tradition are, at any given time, changeable; 5. identifies which parts of a particular tradition are, at any given time, not changeable or worthy of change. III. A theory of force which 6. develops an account of the conditions and use of force in particular socio-political settings; 7. explicitly recognizes the limits to the effectiveness of a critical theory in the face of certain kinds of force. 552 MEYER-EMERICK TABLE 2 (Continued) IV. A theory of reflexivity which 8. gives an explanation of its own historical emergence, and in this portrays itself as a necessarily one-sided construction in a particular historical setting; 9. explicitly eschews transcendental aspirations regarding experience of all humans (or all members of the working class, or all women, or all blacks, or some other subset of humanity identified as oppressed), and gives up any pretensions to capture the “essence” of liberation; 10. offers an account of the ways in which it is inherently and essentially contextual, partial, local, and hypothetical. CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION AND THE CSS SCHEMES Conflict transformation, versus conflict resolution or management,is unique in that it focuses on the social construction of meaning, the importance of the history and cultural differences between peoples, and the “dialectical nature of peacemaking that seeks to change both destructive individual behavior and the larger social system. Using the term transformation acknowledges the possibility that conflict can also be destructive but affirms a goal of mutually beneficial process and result” (Lederach, 1995, p. 17). Lederach (1995) describes conflict transformation as non-violent social change that is focused on facilitating a particular community’s movement through the phases of conflict while also achieving justice. It is based on three theories. The first is a theory of popular education, specifically the work of Freire (1970). Fay (1987, p. 108) emphasizes that Freire’s work [used in conflict transformation] is one of the few instances of “critical scientific thinking about reflection and educative enlightenment” that has been “about the public world of concerted social and political action.” The second is the use of appropriate technology, and a third is ethnographic methodology. Among its working assumptions are (Lederach, 1995, p. 9-10): 1….social conflict is “a natural, common experience present in all relationships and cultures;” 2….“people are active participants in creating the situations and interactions they experience as conflict;” CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 553 3. “Conflict emerges through an interactive process based on the search for and creation of shared meaning;” 4. “The interactive process is accomplished through and rooted in people’s perceptions, interpretations, expressions, and intentions, each of which grows and cycles back to common sense knowledge” 5….“a person’s common sense and accumulated experience and knowledge are the primary basis of how they create, understand, and respond to conflict;” 6. Culture is “rooted in the shared knowledge and schemes created and used by a set of people for perceiving, interpreting, expressing, and responding to social realities around them;” 7. Therefore…“understanding the connection of social conflict and culture is not merely a question of sensitivity or of awareness, but a far more profound adventure of discovery and digging in the archeology of accumulated shared knowledge common to a set of people.” Lederach (1995) emphasizes that popular education is never neutral. “It is centered on the concept of conscientization, the process of building awareness of self-in-context that produces individual growth and social change” (p. 26). People and their common knowledge are valued as key resources. In CSS, just the opposite is implied; it is the leaders who are valued. Indeed, Fay warns that “There is in critical science the potential for great harm because it claims to know the needs and capacities of its audience better than the members of this audience themselves do” (p. 81). Alternatively, the conflict transformation facilitator more often elicits solutions from the community rather than prescribing them and engages in mutual learning with the participants. Lederach also applied principles from appropriate technology to emphasize that by enabling a particular community to use their own knowledge and resources to solve conflict, they are able to do so long after the initial conflict transformation intervention. He states, “The idea is not simply that you teach people to fish rather than give them food; more importantly, they fish in their own ponds!” (p. 28). Finally, Lederach uses methods from ethnography to discover how the community perceives itself. This is accomplished through careful observation of the language people use and how they understand their own behavior and world. Thus equipped with a basic framework for 554 MEYER-EMERICK conflict transformation, it is now possible to identify its specific potential for the CSS schemes. In the discussion that follows, please refer to the Basic and amended CSS schemes as outlined earlier. Conflict transformation provides a method to fulfill “the theory of false consciousness” through Freire’s conscientization process, which Lederach (1995) states, “is needed when the conflict is hidden and people are unaware of imbalances and injustices” (p. 12). In line with Fay’s sub-theories 1 and 2, conscientization through conflict transformation’s ethnography enables a people to undertake an ideology critique, determine how their particular culture developed a false consciousness, and how it is maintained. These steps in turn, may lead them to develop alternatives. Conscientization and appropriate technology may also enable the fulfillment of the “theory of education”, because it assists people in identifying whether, per sub-theory 7, a specific critical theory provides an accurate “account of the conditions necessary and sufficient for the sort of enlightenment envisioned by the theory” (Fay, 1987, p. 32). Next, by its very nature, conflict transformation responds to II a theory of crisis because as people become aware of social inequities their demand for change will intensify. This demand for change might be identified, per sub-theory 4, as social crisis and lead to the fulfillment of sub-theory 5, the examination of the ‘crisis’ and how it cannot be resolved given existing social relations. In the process of conflict transformation, a historical account of the crisis may also be developed, per sub-theory 6. Thus, “a transformation of the system and structure is assumed, in which the relationships are embedded and which can be changed by building on the energy and impact of conflict itself. In other words, conflict is seen as a transforming agent of systemic change” (Lederach, 1995, p. 18). During the conflict transformation process, the “theory of transformative action” will be developed to resolve the conflict crisis. Per sub-theory 9, the “aspects of a society that must be altered” (Fay, 1987, p. 32) during the process are “the nature of unequal relationships and the need for addressing and restoring equity, as seen, of course, from the view of those experiencing the injustices” (Lederach, 1995, p. 12). As Lederach (1995) notes, conflict moves through phases and results in some form of confrontation. Out of this confrontation both sides may recognize their interdependence and begin “a plan of action indicating CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 555 the people who are to be the ‘carriers’ of the anticipated social transformation and at least some general idea of how they might do this” (Fay, 1987, p. 12) or sub-theory 10. Conflict transformation also addresses some components of Fay’s amended scheme, particularly the “theory of tradition,” the “theory of reflexivity,” and partially, the “theory of force” (Fay, 1987, p. 213). It addresses sub-theory 4 if one is willing to equate Lederach’s concept of “culture” with Fay’s theory of “tradition.” This author has made this linkage because, as Lederach (1995, p. 10) states, “understanding conflict and developing appropriate models of handling it will necessarily be rooted in, and must respect and draw from, the cultural knowledge of a people.” Therefore, by learning and honoring a cultural heritage, the facilitator can work with the community to discover how a conflict came to be and how it might be resolved. Using Fay’s terminology from sub-theory 4, the community would be identifying “which parts of a given tradition are…changeable” and from sub-theory 5 which are “not changeable or worthy of change” (Fay, 1987, p. 213). Conflict transformation would focus on those parts of a tradition that must be changed in order to achieve reconciliation but also justice. In addition it does not dictate what people should do (one of Fay’s concerns) but enables the community to decide what is possible as they go through the process over time. If this author understands the “theory of reflexivity” correctly, conflict transformation can assist in explaining sub-theory 8, the historical emergence of a CSS theory and its “necessarily one-sided construction in a particular historical setting” using the same method a community would use to explore the archaeology of conflict (p. 213). Thus, in my view, they would be exploring the “archaeology of a CSS theory.” Because conflict transformation focuses very specifically on the culture of a particular community and is never finalized, its methods comply with the tenets of sub-theory 9. Conflict transformation does this because the community defines its own aspirations given its cultural heritage and current historical circumstances. In the same fashion, it fulfills sub-theory 10 by accounting for the “ways in which it is inherently and essentially contextual, partial, local, and hypothetical” (p. 213). Conflict transformation only partially speaks to the “theory of force”, particularly sub-theory 6, because traditionally it addresses more blatant conflict, not the subtle uses and abuses of power that critical theory identifies as force. However, a particular community in conflict 556 MEYER-EMERICK could potentially develop “an account of the conditions and use of force in [its] particular socio-political setting” (p. 213). CONCLUSION The application of conflict transformation theory and practice to Fay’s basic and amended schemes enables us to see that critical theory and CSS can have a political agenda, and in particular, a non-violent one unlike so many revolutions in the modern era. The conflict transformation process also grounds leadership for change in the community rather than with outside authorities thus reducing the potential for a “tyranny scenario.” Incorporating conflict transformation into Fay’s CSS models during research enhances what Lather calls its “catalytic validity” which “represents the degree to which the research process reorients, focuses, and energizes participants toward knowing reality in order to transform it…” (Lather, 1986, p. 272). Those who choose to adopt the processes of CSS and conflict transformation in their work with citizens will have embarked on what Zanetti (1998) calls a “transformative practice” facilitating truly democratic self-governance. ACKNOWLEDGEMENT The author wishes to thank the anonymous reviewers for their helpful suggestions. REFERENCES Adorno, T. W., Frenkel-Brunswik, E., Levinson, D. J., & Sanford, R. N. (1982). The Authoritarian Personality (Abridged). New York: W.W. Norton. Anderson, J. (Ed.). (2002). Transnational Democracy. London: Routledge. Arato, A., & Gebhardt, E. (Eds.). (1978). The Essential Frankfurt School Reader. Oxford, U.K.: Basil Blackwell. Bernstein, R. J. (1978). The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Bhaskar, R. (1986). Scientific Realism and Human Emancipation. London: Verso. CRITICAL SOCIAL SCIENCE AND CONFLICT TRANSFORMATION 557 Cardoso, H. F. (1977). “The Consumption of Dependency Theory in the United States.” Latin American Research Review, 12 (3): 7-23. Fay, B. (1977). “How People Change Themselves: The Relationship between Critical Theory and Its Audience” (pp. 200–233). In T. Ball, (Ed.), Political Theory and Praxis: New Perspectives. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Fay, B. (1987). Critical Social Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York: Seabury Press. Gutierrez, G. (1973). A Theology of Liberation. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis. Habermas, J. (1971). Knowledge and Human Interests (J. Shapiro, Trans.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1973). Theory and Practice (J. Viertel, Trans.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1975). Legitimation Crisis (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1, Reason and the Rationalization of Society (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1987). The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 2, Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason (T. McCarthy, Trans.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1990). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (C. Lenhardt and S. W. Nicholsen, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Held, D. (1980). Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Horkheimer, Max. (1972). Sozialphilosophische Studien. Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Suhrkamp. Horkheimer, M. & Adorno, T. W. (1972). Dialectic of Enlightenment (J. Cumming, Trans.). New York: Herder and Herder. 558 MEYER-EMERICK Jay, M. (1973). The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute for Social Research, 1923 – 1950. Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Kellner, D. (1989). Critical Theory, Marxism, and Modernity. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Kincheloe, J. L., & McLaren, P. (2000). “Rethinking Critical Theory and Qualitative Research.” In N. K. Denzin and Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of Qualitative Research (2nd ed., pp. 279-313). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc. Lather, P. (1986). “Research as Praxis.” Harvard Educational Review, 56: 257-277. Lederach, J. P. (1995). Preparing for Peace: Conflict Transformation Across Cultures. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press. Leonard, S. T. (1990). Critical Theory in Political Practice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Marcuse, H. (1964). One Dimensional Man. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Marcuse, H. (1969). An Essay on Liberation. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Marcuse, H. (1972). Counterrevolution and Revolt. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Mayer, M., & Ely, J. (1998). The German Greens: Paradox between Movement and Party. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press. Morrow, R. A. with Brown, D. D. (1994). Critical Theory and Methodology.Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc. Sabia, D. R., Jr., & Wallulis, J. (Eds.) (1983). Changing Social Science: Critical Theory and Other Critical Perspectives. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Zanetti, L. A. (1997). “Advancing Praxis: Connecting Critical Theory with Practice in Public Administration.” American Review of Public Administration, 32: 145-167. Zanetti, L. A. (1998). “At the Nexus of State and Civil Society: The Transformative Practice of Public Administration.” In C. S. King & C. Stivers (Eds.), Government is Us: Public Administration in an Anti-Government Era (pp. 102-121). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.