RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE By Stephen R. Latham* Richard Epstein does not claim to be a health-law expert. A less startlingly prolific law professor might argue that two books' and several article-length publications2 in a given area are enough to justify a claim of expertise in it, but not Epstein. This level of scholarly production is, for him, just about the right one for legitimately staking out a secondary field of interest. In any case, even if Epstein's scholarship could ground a claim of healthcare expertise, it is not a claim he would want to make. He wants to be considered an outsider to health-law-one who, untainted by special interests and unattached to the standard assumptions of the field, is free to rethink it according to first principles.3 Epstein strides into the health-policy arena like a heroic * Assistant Professor of Law and Director of the Center for Health Law and Policy, Quinnipiac College School of Law. I would like to thank Professor Leonard Long for organizing the symposium on The Works of Richard Epstein for which this essay was produced. I would also like to take this opportunity to thank Richard Epstein for the assistance and encouragement he so kindly offered me during my time in Chicago. 1. RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, MORTAL PERIL: OUR INALIENABLE RIGHT TO HEALTH CARE? (1997) [hereinafter MORTAL PERIL]; RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, ANTIDISCRIMINATION IN HEALTH CARE: COMMUNITY RATINGS AND PREEXISTING CONDITIONS (1996). 2. For law-review articles dealing with health law, health insurance, and bioethics, see, for example, Richard A. Epstein, Why is Health Care Special?, 40 U. KAN. L. REv. 307 (1992); Richard A. Epstein, Rationing Access to Medical Care: Some Sober Second Thoughts, 3 STAN. L. & POL'Y REv. 81, (1991); Richard A. Epstein, Surrogacy: The Case for Full Contractual Enforcement, 81 VA. L. REv. 2305 (1995); Richard A. Epstein, Market and Regulatory Approaches to Medical Malpractice: The Virginia ObstetricalNo-FaultStatute, 74 VA. L. REv. 1451 (1988); Richard A. Epstein, The HistoricalOrigins and Economic Structure of Workers' Compensation Law, 16 GA. L. REv. 775 (1982); see also Richard A. Epstein, A Rush to Caution: Cloning Human Beings, in CLONES AND CLONES: FACTS AND FANTASIES ABOUT HUMAN CLONING (Cass R. Sunstein & Martha C. Nussbaum eds., 1998). Shorter healthcare pieces include Richard A. Epstein, Thinking the Unthinkable, BOSTON GLOBE, July 19, 1998 at El (regarding the sale of organs); Richard A Epstein, Sell Your Body, Save a Life, WALL ST. J., April 16, 1998 at A2; and Richard A. Epstein et al., Articulating a Social Ethic for Health Care, 279 JAMA 745 (1998). 3. MORTAL PERIL, supra note 1, at 5. QLR [Vol. 19:727 sheriff into Tombstone: this town is a mess, and the job of cleaning it up requires, precisely, a tough-minded stranger. The centerpiece of Epstein's healthcare work is his dauntingly long (and broad) book, Mortal Peril; the 1997 work came out in paperback just in time to play a role in the newly revived national debate on health policy. 4 The book's fundamental approach-opposed "as a matter of first principles" to governmental subsidization or provision of healthcare, opposed to the establishment of any, even minimal, positive rights to healthcare, and strongly in favor of unimpeded private-market transactions as the best means of distributing health-related serviceshas angered many critics. One reviewer has likened Epstein to Ebenezer Scrooge;5 another has denounced his trademark blend of libertarian commitments with law-and-economics analysis as a "meanspirited" political theory.6 Mean-spirited it is not. Indeed, although Epstein occasionally talks a tough game with regard to the need to ration scarce healthcare resources, most of his concrete proposals are justified by their overall tendency to expand access to healthcare or to improve overall social health. Thus, if Epstein prefers a free market for organ sales to the current government-regulated organ-donation scheme, that is because he believes that the supply of organs will increase if people can sell them freely. If he opposes EMTALA's requirement that hospitals screen and stabilize patients before inquiring into their insurance status, that is not because he wants to see hospitals turning the uninsured out into the streets, but because he predicts that the imposition on hospitals of the costs of such emergency treatment will result in reduction of overall service availability. If he wants healthcare facilities to cut off care to certain intransigents who repeatedly injure their own health through drug or alcohol abuse, it is partly because he thinks the treatment dollars 4. The paperback was published in May 2000, by Perseus Books. 5. Henry T. Greely, Richard Epstein's Mortal Peril: Ebenezer Scrooge Meets the American Health Care System, 1998 U. ILL. L. REv. 727. The comparison strikes me both as ad hominem and inapt-inapt because, while Epstein sings the praises of private charity as the preferred solution to the failure of the free market to address the healthcare needs of the poor, and rejects any role for government in addressing those needs, Scrooge famously declined to contribute to charities by pawning off moral responsibility for the poor to the government: "Are there no prisons?... The Treadmill and the Poor Law are in full vigour, then?" CHARLES DICKENS, A CHRISTMAS CAROL (Dover 1991) (1843). 6. Troyen A. Brennan, Moral Imperatives Versus Market Solutions: Is Health Care a Right?, 65 U. CHI. L. REv. 345, 356 (1998) (reviewing RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, MORTAL PERIL: OUR INALIENABLE RIGHT TO HEALTH CARE? (1997)). 20001 RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE spent on them could be better spent elsewhere, and partly because a credible threat of medical cutoff will actually assist them in altering their suicidal ways. Even his broad condemnation of Medicare (and of all other schemes of social health insurance) is justified by a broad belief that the wealth-reduction and transfers that such schemes create when they are first enacted will, in the end, cut into the potential gains in overall health of later generations. As it happens, I disagree with Epstein's analysis on virtually every one of the above-mentioned points. On the other hand, I agree with him on a number of others: his criticism of the ADA as too simple a solution to the complex questions it is brought to bear upon, his rejection of the idea that medical licensure should be used to compel conduct rather than simply to control quality, his general position on physician-assisted suicide, his analysis of the problems with limiting expenditures on futile care. And, for the record, even where I disagree with his ultimate positions, I approve strongly of his efforts to bring economic analysis to bear both upon health policy and upon related fields (such as bioethics) where it is too seldom used; and agree, also, with the general position that private markets can and ought to play a greater role in the delivery of healthcare, and in the management of healthcare liability, than has previously been allowed. I shall not engage in a point-by-point review of Epstein's very many policy positions in healthcare, however. Such a review would be largely duplicative: a number of health policy scholars have already offered detailed criticisms, and Epstein has responded to the most 7. In addition to Brennan, supra note 6, see Mary Ann Bailey, Our Irrelevant Right to Health Care, 16 YALE L. & POL'Y REV. 407 (1998); Ezekiel Emanuel, Book Review: Mortal Peril: Our Inalienable Right to Health Care?, 337 NEJM 5 (1997); Thomas L. Greaney, How Many LibertariansDoes It Take to Fix the Health Care System?, 96 MICH. L. REV. 1825 (1998); Uwe E. Reinhardt, Wanted: A Clearly Articulated Social Ethic for American Health Care, 278 JAMA 1446 (1997); and the excellent collection of critical essays collected in Symposium, Is America's Health Care System in Mortal Peril?, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 683. These include Thomas S. Ulen, An Introduction to Mortal Peril, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 683; Laura G. Dooley & Robert S. Gaston, Stumbling Toward Equity: The Role of Government in Kidney Transplantation, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 703; Greely, supra note 5; Mark A. Hall, Public Choice and Private Insurance: The Case of Small Group Market Reforms, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 757; Richard L. Kaplan, Taking Medicare Seriously, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 777; Russell Korobkin, Determining Health Care Rights from Behind a Veil of Ignorance, 1998 U. ILL. L. REv 801; David Orentlicher, The Alleged Distinction Between Euthanasia and the Withdrawal of Life-Sustaining Treatment: Conceptually Incoherent and Impossible to Maintain, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 837; Robert F. Rich & William D. White, Federalism QLR [Vol. 19:727 trenchant of them.8 My intention is instead to concentrate not on the details of Epstein's analysis, but on the theoretical bases upon which he advances them. My plan is as follows: First, I shall outline what I take to be some technical problems with the opening theoretical argument of Mortal Peril. From there, I shall turn to some general practical and theoretical consideration of the "argument from charity" that appears in Mortal Peril and elsewhere in Epstein's works. I end with a brief argument, contra Epstein, for the idea that healthcare might be an economic "public good" that private markets will not adequately supply. This short critical essay is animated by my general admiration for Epstein's work in healthcare. I agree with Epstein that there is insufficient consideration given to individual liberty in health policy, the largely ineffectual murmerings of bioethicists about "autonomy" notwithstanding; and insufficient consideration of market solutions to problems of scarcity in the healthcare field. And I start from the assumption that Epstein's healthcare work-like much of his broader work in legal theory-is not mean but utopian in spirit. He wants to show us a better way to live-and he wants to show it to us in spite of his recognition that we may never choose to live in that way.9 The critical bite of utopian proposals lies in their ability to expose our foolish refusal to change our ways, even though we have the power so to change them. The free-market, simple-common-law-rules critique that Epstein brings to bear upon so many subjects often has that critical bite, even if we do not finally accept its prescriptions in every case. and Health Care Policy, 1998 U. ILL. L. REv. 861; and Gary T. Schwartz, Medical Malpractice, Tort, Contractand Managed Care, 1998 U. ILL. L. REv. 885. 8. See Richard A. Epstein, Living Dangerously: A Defense of Mortal Peril, in Symposium, Is America's Health Care System in Mortal Peril?, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 909. 9. This is the definition of utopian writing offered by Judith N. Shklar in her MEN AND CITIZENS: A STUDY OF ROUSSEAU'S SOCIAL THEORY (1969). For Epstein's recognition that his policy suggestions will be refused, see MORTAL PERIL, supra note 1, at 79, 182-83. 20001 RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE I. WEALTH/UTILITY GAP(S) IN THE HEALTHCARE MARKET A. Epstein's Straw Man Epstein's preference for markets over governments as institutions for the distribution of scarce social resources is well-known. The preference is grounded in intertwined considerations of liberty and economy; markets, he believes, are both more free and more efficient than democracies. He appears to subscribe to some version of the Interest Group theory of politics, and believes (correctly) that governmental regulation is often hijacked by groups whose interests in framing the regulation (or deregulation) are high and whose transactioncosts of organization are low. Even in a well-run democracy, those interest groups will be able to use regulation to impose rules of conduct on others against their will, and thus to extract rents. Individual market transactions, in contrast, are voluntary, and force nothing upon the unwilling. Thus they enjoy an advantage from the point of view of liberty even where, in a given case, regulation might be slightly more efficient than an imperfect market. To this libertarian intuition, Epstein adds the economist's truism that individual actors are better informed about their preferences and capacities than are third-party regulatorseven objective, non-hijacked third-party regulators. ° This well-known position of Epstein's gives special power to an unusual gambit with which he chooses to begin Mortal Peril. At the start of Chapter One, Epstein proposes to advance the best possible case for a positive (that is, government-supported) right to healthcare. His rhetorical intention, of course, is to advance that case and then to defeat it, thus persuading his readers from the very start that the proper starting-point for discussions about health policy should be the traditional negative-rights common-law regime of voluntary unregulated exchange, rather than any regime of state-guaranteed healthcare rights. True to his common-law roots, Epstein suggests that the strongest argument for a positive right to healthcare must be one that can show why free markets would fail to allocate healthcare resources efficiently; specifically, he suggests that it is one that "exploits the wedge between 10. Epstein has articulated these general views in numerous places. See generally RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, PRINCIPLES FOR A FREE SocIETY: RECONCILING INDIVIDUAL LIBERTY WITH THE COMMON GOOD (1998); RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, SIMPLE RULES FOR A COMPLEX WORLD pts. I, 11 (1995) [hereinafter SIMPLE RULES]. QLR [Vol. 19:727 maximizing social wealth and maximizing utility."1' Let us examine Epstein's straw-man, pro-positive-fights argument and his response to it. Parties' voluntary market transactions, Epstein argues, normally increase both the parties' wealth and their utility; indeed, where transactions are completed, the correspondence between wealth and utility is "well nigh complete." But the two cease to move hand in hand "when certain transactions do not get completed because the prospective buyer lacks the necessary funds."' 2 In a free market for healthcare goods and services, poor people might suffer substantial disutility due to their inability to purchase the healthcare they need. Rich people could outbid poor people for scarce medical resources, even in circumstances where those resources would increase poor people's utility more than the rich people's. Thus, an exclusive regime of negative fights in healthcare-one which permitted free-market transactions in all aspects of healthcare, but which included no positive rights to healthcare, and which confined the government's role to prohibiting force and fraud, breaking up monopolies and subsidizing only true economic "public goods"-might, compared to a regulatory regime that provided some positive fight to healthcare, do rather well at maximizing social wealth, but comparatively poorly at maximizing social utility. Having laid out this "strongest" argument for positive rights to healthcare, Epstein attempts to defeat it by claiming that the utility gap left open by the inability of the poor to purchase healthcare could-and, in a system of negative rights, would-be plugged by voluntary charitable transactions. Those transactions would increase the utility both of giver and of recipient, would enable the poor to receive adequate care, and-a bonus, technical point for the consequentialist theorists in the crowd-would, because they are voluntary, obviate the need for the government to make theoretically problematic interpersonal comparisons of utility. I see several difficulties with the above argument. In what follows, I shall argue that Epstein has overstated the case for the probable success, in wealth and utility terms, of completed transactions in a free healthcare market. His analysis ignores some well-known idiosyncrasies of the market for healthcare services (i.e., its various imperfections and defects), as well as some well-known features of all 11. MORTAL PERIL, supra note 1, at 31. 12. Id. at 34. 2000] RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE markets (i.e., that they have losers) which may be of special concern to health policy. B. Market Failure Recall Epstein's opening assertion that a series of completed voluntary market transactions in a world of strictly negative rights advances wealth and utility simultaneously. We can accept, for the sake of argument, that this is true in the limited case of a hypothetical perfect market-though even that assumption will be unsettled if we allow for the possibility that transactions affect the utilities of non-parties through mechanisms of sympathy and, more damagingly, of envy. 3 Would social wealth and social utility rise hand-in-hand in a real-world free market for healthcare goods and services? There are some serious reasons to doubt it. Just look at the voluntary transactions that Americans complete today, with their health in mind: the pointless millions spent on alternative therapies and dietary supplements whose efficacy is unproven, on weight-loss programs whose inefficacy is proven, on fad exercise machinery, on outright quackery. There is plenty of evidence that people are not very good at balancing their long and short-term healthcare interests; at understanding, and acting rationally upon, statistical risk; at assimilating available information about healthcare goods and services; at facing their own mortality. Imagine what further terrible healthcare decisions might be made in less regulated markets-markets without an FDA, licensure and certification for health facilities and professionals, prescription requirements, drug labeling laws, and so on.14 More subtly, even if we assume counterfactually that healthcare consumers make good self-interested decisions when given the opportunity, there are a number of reasons to believe that a free market in healthcare services might not afford them that opportunity. Healthcare markets suffer from a number of imperfections that virtually 13. On the problem of envy and Pareto optimality, see Thomas Rice, Can Markets Give Us the Health System We Want?; Martin Gaynor & William B. Vogt, What Does Economics Have to Say About Health Policy Anyway? A Comment and Correction on Evans and Rice; and Thomas Rice, A Reply to Gaynorand Vogt, and Pauly; all of which are in HEALTHY MARKETS? THE NEW COMPETITION IN MEDICAL CARE (Mark A. Peterson ed., 1998). I believe Rice wins the debate on this narrow but important point. 14. Our imaginations need not be unguided by history here. See JAMES HARVEY YOUNG, THE TOADSTOOL MILLIONAIRES: A SOCIAL HISTORY OF PATENT MEDICINES IN AMERICA BEFORE FEDERAL REGULATION (1961). QLR [Vol. 19:727 assure that a series of completed voluntary transactions will not maximize social utility. For example: demand for health services is irregular and unpredictable; uncertainty as to the quality and efficacy of proposed medical treatments plagues both the demand and the supply side, and is not resolved by post-treatment observation of outcomes; the pervasive use of insurance creates risks of moral hazard; and even without insurance there are ineradicable agency problems in the patientdoctor relationship.15 These objections (and others) are quite familiar in the literature, and Epstein is well aware of them. Indeed, on page 2 of Mortal Peril, he cites Kenneth Arrow's seminal 1963 paper 6 for the proposition that "[t]he health care market has special problems of monopoly, information deficits, volatility, uncertainty, surprise, insurability, and inequality of bargaining power that do not plague ordinary competitive markets."' 7 He nonetheless dismisses the arguments of those who would use "pervasive market failure" as an excuse to press for government intervention and redistribution in health care. His reasoning is that governmental intervention, far from solving market failure, gives rise to regulatory failure that "only exacerbates problems of information, uncertainty and monopoly."' 8 Now, I join Epstein in being wary of this by-now-familiar gesture toward "market failure" as an excuse for banishing market solutions from healthcare policy debates. The question must always be, "The market as compared to what?" and as Neil Komesar has pointed out, market, judicial and regulatory failures tend to occur simultaneously.' 9 Even within the health care field, market failure can be compensated for, is not universal, and is not always worse than regulatory failure. 15. For important debates on the imperfections of the healthcare market, see Kenneth J. Arrow, Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care, 53 AM. ECON. REV. 5, 941 (1963); the critique of Arrow in PAUL STARR, THE SOCIAL TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN MEDICINE 225 (1982); and HEALTHY MARKETS? THE NEW COMPETITION IN MEDICAL CARE (Mark A. Peterson ed., 1998), especially the debate on the applicability of economic theory to healthcare among Thomas Rice, Robert G. Evans, Mark V. Pauly, Martin Gaynor and William B. Vogt. See id. at 27129. 16. See Arrow, supra note 15, at 941. 17. MORTAL PERIL, supra note 1, at 2. 18. Id. 19. "Institutions [e.g., markets, courts and the political process] often move together-when one is at its best, the others are often at their best; when one is at its worst, the others are often at their worst." NEIL K. KOMESAR, IMPERFECT ALTERNATIVES: CHOOSING INSTITUTIONS IN LAW, ECONOMICS AND PUBLIC POLICY (1994). 271 20001 RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE There is, to my mind, an important role for market forces to play in the delivery and financing of healthcare services and products, and a fair bit of deregulation to be done. My quarrel with Epstein here is simply that the market imperfections he acknowledges in his Introduction seem forgotten by the time he makes his "strongest argument for positive rights in healthcare" in Chapter One. In Chapter One, Epstein argues as though, in a free market for health care, the principal gap between wealth-maximization and utilitymaximization would be created by the inability of the poor to complete certain transactions. But the existence of market imperfections should certainly make us less sanguine than Epstein evidently is about the ability of completed transactions in an unregulated healthcare market dependably to maximize either social utility or wealth. In a market replete with such imperfections, not only incomplete transactions but also faultily-completed ones-those, for example, completed by parties whose decisions are made for them by agents whose interests are not perfectly aligned with their own; or on the basis of imperfect information; or under the influence of perverse financial incentiveswill sometimes fail to advance utility or wealth, and will often fail to optimize them. C. Market Losers and Their Victims There is another point to be made about the misfiring of completed market transactions. While it is certainly true that people are the best judges of their own subjective preferences from moment to moment, it is not at all clearly true that people (or firms) are always very good at pursuing their own interests through market transactions. Epstein's discussions of the market seem sometimes to miss the distinction between markets reaching efficient equilibria and people making efficient choices. Indeed, in a world of market participants who have imperfect knowledge and foresight, competitive markets reach efficient equilibria in part because large numbers of players in them make terrible decisions and fail. Some others make perfectly sensible decisions and fail because of bad luck, as, for example, when the bus-stop that used to be outside their coffee-shop door gets eliminated, or an unusual run of warm winter weather limits the ski-resort's revenue. Forty percent of start-up restaurants fail. This vigorous Darwinian competition is of course painful for the restaurateurs themselves; but it also imposes minor costs of dislocation upon customers, and more major costs of QLR [Vol. 19:727 dislocation upon cooks and waiters and suppliers and landlords. The poor decisions and bad luck of market losers do not affect only themselves. We tolerate the disutility created by closing restaurants, however, because that disutility is generally overwhelmed by the tremendous welfare gains that competition affords to diners everywhere, in terms of lower costs, higher quality, greater variety, and so on. There are analogous injuries from competition to be observed everywhere in today's vigorously competitive market for healthcare finance-a market to which, surprisingly, Epstein pays very little attention. Management Service Organizations are unwinding because of an inability to increase efficiency and capture managed-care contracts, 20 provider mergers are dissolving because of an inability to settle turf and management battles." Such failures move the market toward more efficiency, but they have tremendous human cost in terms of loss of continuity of care, loss of coverage, consumers' transaction costs, and so on. It seems likely that these costs are often quite highsubstantially higher than those associated with the dislocations in the restaurant business, for example. A single provider's poor market choices can impose externalities on patients by the thousands; an insurer's poor choices can impose enormous dislocation costs upon employees, patients, providers, and even local governments. Consumers' poor market choices can literally kill them, or impose lifealtering financial burdens on their families. It is an important question for national health policy whether we wish to pay for the long-run efficiency of a competitive market by letting the harsh burdens of business and consumer failures within that market fall where they may. As I write, Harvard Pilgrim Health Plan is about to emerge from a period in receivership, during which time the Massachusetts Attorney General attempted to broker a publicly guided refinance, reorganization and rescue plan." This is in part because he did not want to incur the human costs of letting the Plan fold--costs that might have included personal and economic displacement for many, loss of previously-paid- 20. See Uwe E. Reinhardt, The Rise and Fall of the Physician Practice Management Industry, 19 HEALTH AFFAIRS 1, 42 (2000). 21. See, e.g., Lawton R. Bums et al., The Fall of the House of AHERF: The Allegheny Bankruptcy, 19 HEALTH AFFAIRS 1, 7 (2000). For a detailed portrait of competition in physician practice management, see JAMES C. ROBINSON, THE CORPORATE PRACTICE OF MEDICINE (1999). 22. See Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court Temporary Receiver's Second Status Report, cited in Ruthardt v. Harvard Pilgrim Health Care, No. SJ-2000-003 (Mass. Mar. 3, 2000). 20001 RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE for benefits by people who have paid premiums for years but who now have medical conditions that would preclude their acquiring new coverage, loss of medical records, administrative costs, shopping costs for consumers, and so on. In sum: Epstein is overly optimistic about the ability of free-market transactions to optimize welfare (whether calculated in terms of wealth or utility) among those who participate in them, both because he underestimates the importance of classical market failure in the healthcare market, and because he ignores the enormous costs of displacement associated with the failure of large-scale healthcare businesses even in a reasonably efficient market. These wealth/utility gaps are considerably harder to plug with charity than the gap affecting poor market non-participants. They affect not just the poor, but those wealthy enough to participate in the market but who make poor business or personal choices; and those who make rational probability-based choices (say, about health coverage) but who are unlucky enough to get hit by lightning; and those whose healthcare is impacted by the poor choices and bad luck of others. Given the difficulties of amassing proper information and of discriminating between different claims of damage and need, can we imagine a charitable-giving solution to the problems that would be created if, for example, Harvard Pilgrim were allowed to fold? I think not. These arguments, of course, are not enough to invalidate Epstein's policy prescriptions. It may be that the disutility and wealth loss associated with governmental intervention in the healthcare market would be worse than that which would be experienced in an unregulated market. But the theoretical argument in favor of markets is not as clean or easy as Epstein makes it seem. II. THE ARGUMENT FROM CHARITY Since the publication of Mortal Peril,Epstein has encountered and responded to another argument for positive rights to healthcare-one which he regards as powerful, and perhaps as more powerful than the utility-gap argument he uses in Mortal Peril. It is a Rawlsian argument for positive healthcare rights-one advanced, in this instance, by Russel Korobkin,23 though similar arguments have earlier been advanced by 24 Korobkin imagines parties others, most notably Norman Daniels. 23. See Korobkin, supra note 7. 24. See NORMAN DANIELS, JUST HEALTH CARE (1985). QLR [Vol. 19:727 behind a Rawlsian veil of ignorance, unaware of whether they will be born in good or bad health. Forced to choose between a world whose basic social institutions include some positive rights to health care and one whose basic social institutions do not, Korobkin argues, selfinterested risk-averse parties would choose at least some limited form of publicly-funded emergency care, and a requirement of communityrating on private health insurance. Epstein's answer to Korobkin's pro-positive-rights argument 5 is the same as his earlier answer to his own straw-man, utility-gap argument: he invokes voluntary charity. Just as voluntary charity could plug the utility-gap left by the free market, so it could alleviate the concerns of parties behind the veil of ignorance for the healthcare of the least-well-off members of society. Epstein argues that, in a negativerights regime, the natural phenomenon of human empathy will ground a strong enough moral duty of charitable assistance to assure that those who find themselves unhealthy upon emergence from behind the veil will not lack the primary social good of health-at least insofar as that can be attained by receiving healthcare. It is tempting to read Epstein as a good Rawlsian here. Justice, as Rawls famously puts it near the opening of his A Theory of Justice, is 26 the first virtue of social institutions. Institutions, on Rawls' account, are not only or even especially political entities such as parliaments or administrative agencies; they include markets, systems of property, public rituals-indeed, any publicly recognized system of rules "which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities, and the like., 27 Thus, when Epstein argues that a "moral duty of charitable assistance" would supply the needs of the poor, he may-provided he conceives of that moral duty as one that would be publicly recognized, shared, and broadly enforced by social normssimply be proposing that the demands of Korobkin's parties for some positive rights to healthcare would in fact be met by a just social institution: the institution of private charity. The difficulty with reading Epstein as a Rawlsian in this way is that the demands of Rawlsian justice would only be met if the "voluntary charity" were in fact voluntary only in name. The parties behind the veil will not settle for a mere possibility, or even a likelihood, that their needs will be met by some goodhearted soul; they 25. 26. 27. Epstein's response to Korobkin is in Epstein, supra note 8, at 912-14. See JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 3 (rev. ed. 1999) (1971). Id. at 47-52. 20001 RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE want some level of guaranteebuilt into their social institutions. To the extent that a duty of private charitable giving is to be publicly enforced, it is likely to lose its attraction to the libertarian Epstein, whether that enforcement is achieved by use of government force or by powerful social sanction. I suspect, also, that it would lose its attraction to the economist Epstein. In Simple Rules for a Complex World Epstein argued, precisely against those who criticize charitable giving because they "believe that individuals have an affirmative right to receive support that must be made secure by government," that "[t]he precariousnature of charitable giving is one of the features that make it most effective."28 This is because the strictly voluntary nature of charitable giving allows benefactors to abandon failed projects easily, and thus to make optimal use of their resources. So, on Epstein's view, a publicly enforced norm of charitable giving would interfere both with the liberty of the givers and with the efficiency of their giving. So much for reading Epstein as Rawls. But so much, also, for charity's standing as an answer to Korobkin's arguments. Charity is contingent in a way that justice is not, and this contingency alone is enough to leave Epstein's response to Korobkin wanting. This point can be driven home by the simple observation that the recipients of charity are generally required to be grateful. This is so even if the charitable giver feels a deep moral obligation to give. But gratefulness is not required of one who receives only his just deserts-unless it be a gratefulness that operates on a different level, by offering thanks for the fact of living in a just regime. Charity of the genuinely superrogatory sort that Epstein favors cannot satisfy the theoretical demands of the parties behind the Rawlsian veileven if it could, in fact, meet their practical needs. This leads us, of course, to the more mundane question whether charity actually could meet those practical needs. Is it realistic to hope that voluntary charity could meet the needs of the least-well-off, or plug the utility-gap created by the inability of the poor to participate in healthcare markets? Again, there are some serious reasons to doubt it. One may begin, as a few of Epstein's critics have, with some daunting empirical data. Contemporary healthcare costs are enormous-so enormous that they completely dwarf the sum total of charitable giving in America, whether 28. SIMPLE RULES, supra note 10, at 142. QLR [Vol. 19:727 in health or non-health areas.2 9 In addition, we are aware that some currently-existing needs for healthcare are not being met by charity. Is it realistic for Epstein to believe that, if government programs were abolished, charity would step in to carry such an enormous burdenespecially given that it is failing to carry a much smaller evident burden even now? Epstein has an answer to this criticism: namely, that it is wrong to think that the amount spent on healthcare would remain the same in a negative-rights regime. Government subsidization of medical care through Medicare and Medicaid, Epstein argues, has led the elderly and the poor to overconsume healthcare. Current cost-levels are inflated, because people who receive goods for free tend to use more of them. The moral hazard so well documented in the Rand experiments of the 1980s 30 has driven healthcare costs up beyond what a free-market regime would have allowed. In addition, current charity levels are deflated, because the American public is used to healthcare for the poor being the government's business. Epstein essentially argues that government programs such as Medicare and Medicaid have, to some extent, crowded out private charity. Had the programs never existed, spending levels would be lower and charity levels would be higher.' He points to the higher levels of charity that existed in the era of laissez faire, and to the long tradition of charitable giving in healthcare, in particular.32 The moral-hazard and crowding-out arguments advanced by Epstein do not strike me as powerful enough to justify his faith that voluntary charity could truly cover the tremendous costs of healthcare for the poor. First, as to moral hazard: most of the modem increase in healthcare cost has not been due to overconsumption by the insured, but to the inflationary pressure of underlying technical advances in medical machinery and pharmaceutical products." The "managed care revolution" of the 1990s has supplied an illustration of this truth: the widespread introduction of financial incentives for patients and providers to reduce rates of healthcare consumption had powerful shortterm effects in keeping healthcare costs down, but it is currently 29. See Greely, supra note 5, at 750. See generally Hall, supra note 7. 30. See Emmet B. Keeler & John E. Rolph, The Demand for Episodes of Treatment in the Health Insurance Experiment, J. HEALTH EcON. 7, 337 (1988). 31. See Epstein, supra note 8, at 918. 32. See MORTAL PERIL, supra note 1, at 36. 33. See Henry Aaron & William B. Schwartz, Rationing Health Care: The Choice Before Us, 247 SCIENCE 418 (1990). 20001 RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE emerging that those savings were "one-shot deals": the underlying engine of healthcare cost inflation-technological advance-is still chugging away. Thus, managed care companies that were boasting of stabilizing costs five years ago have been jacking up premiums this year . 4 Overutilization of services was a cost problem, but it was never the core cost problem: the core problem is that healthcare is simply not the same product it used to be. Let government programs be eliminated, and utilization will of course go down; but costs will still be very high and growing. Of course, if we posit a world in which a regime of negative rights had always obtained, we might indeed see less healthcare cost-but we would also see substantially lower-quality medicine. Public funding has subsidized the educations of most medical researchers-and their research, as well-over the last many decades. This has included subsidization of a great deal of productive medical research which it is likely that private industry would not have undertaken at sufficient levels on its own. 35 As to the "crowding out" argument: there is little to do other than to register my skepticism that government involvement in healthcare is what prevents our natural human empathy from grounding an ethic of charity forceful enough to meet the enormous needs of the poor of the nation for healthcare. There are poor people whose healthcare and other needs are not currently being met by the government, and charity is not filling the gap. If government presence in some areas of healthcare is enough to "crowd out" charity even in areas where government does not work, I am left wondering how strong the human impulse to charity really is. Finally, charity has some other features which make it troubling as a potential substitute for government-supported positive rights to healthcare. First, even if the quantity of charity were very large, its targets would remain discretionary. Individual needy persons might find themselves neglected by voluntary charities on grounds of prejudice that would be impermissible in public programs. Second, and more importantly, charitable transactions are not always as purely utility-enhancing as Epstein imagines. Charity is 34. Mary Chris Jaklevic, Healthcare Costs Rise in 1998, 30 MOD. HEALTHCARE 2, 2 (2000). 35. This is because social returns to research far exceed returns to the parties that undertake it. See Zvi Griliches, Returns to Research and Development Expenditures in the Private Sector, in NEW DEVELOPMENTS IN PRODUCTIVITY MEASUREMENT AND ANALYSIS (John W. Kendrick & Beatrice N. Cavaccara eds., 1980). QLR [Vol. 19:727 neither always nobly motived nor always gratefully received. A number of philosophers-Hegel3 6 and Kant 7 among the continentals, Emerson38 and Thoreau39 here at home-have noticed that the impulse to charity can be more self-aggrandizing than self-effacing. Charity can as easily be motivated by pity for the smallness of the other as by love for him as an equal. It can invite in the giver a lordly feeling of superiority which is inappropriate in one who is dispensing justice--or dispensing aid which is meant to be a substitute for justice. And it can inspire in the recipient feelings of profound alienation, resentment and rebellion. Finally, to move from the psychological to the pragmatic, it should be pointed out that not all charity is given by the rich to the poor. It is highly probable that, if the healthcare needs of the poor were to be left to charity rather than to social subsidy, a large proportion of the charity in question would be given by the poor to the poor, most especially by family members who, for lack of government aid, would sacrifice opportunities for employment and education in order to care for their ailing elders or their disabled children. A social insurance policy, grounded in a Rawlsian contract, can be funded in such a way as to limit burdens on the least-well-off. The burdens of charity cannot be thus easily distributed. III. HEALTH AS A PUBLIC GOOD? Central to Epstein's defense of the market as a means for the distribution of scarce healthcare resources must be the notion that private investors will devote the proper amount of resources to the production and distribution of healthcare goods. This is why, in his article responding to critics of Mortal Peril,Epstein takes Sarah Singer 36. See G.W.F. HEGEL, THE PHENOMENOLOGY OF SPIRIT 517 (A.V. Miller trans., 1977) (The spirit of the gratitude of one who finds that his personality is "dependent on the contingent personality of another, on the accident of a moment, on a caprice ... is, therefore, the feeling of the most profound dejection as well as of extreme rebellion .. " The "beneficent spirit of wealth ... knows itself to be independent and arbitrary, and at the same time knows that what it dispenses is the self of another. Wealth thus shares its dejection with the recipient; but in place of rebellion appears arrogance."). I plan to explicate these and other mysterious anti-charity arguments in my forthcoming essay, The Sting of Charity. 37. See IMMANUEL KANT, LECTURES ON ETHics 235-36 (Louis Infield trans., Hackett Publ'g Co. 1963) (1930) ("The giving of alms flatters the giver's pride.... Alms degrades men."). 38. See Ralph Waldo Emerson, Self Reliance, in EMERSON'S ESSAYS (Houghton, Mifflin, & Co. 1980) (1840). 39. See HENRY DAVID THOREAU, WALDEN (The Heritage Press 1939) (1849). 2000] RICHARD EPSTEIN ON HEALTHCARE and Alain Enthoven to task for mischaracterizing universal access to healthcare as a "public good. '0 He accuses them of attempting to "piggyback their claims for a positive right to health care on the narrower economic conception of a public good";4 ' the latter referring only to the narrow class of goods which (like street lights) will be underproduced in the private market because they produce nonexcudable benefits. He is certainly correct-Singer and Enthoven do not use the term in its classical economic sense.4'2 But, having correctly dismissed their illegitimate use of the term, he too swiftly dismisses the possibility that health, itself, might be a public good in the real, economic sense." Consider my own health. It certainly seems as though the social benefits from my being healthy exceed those that I, myself, enjoy. When I am healthy, I feel good, and am able to earn my wages and enjoy my leisure. But my health has considerable benefits to others, too-and not only in obvious ways such as the herd-immunity benefits they derive from my immunization. When I am healthy, the plans I make with my colleagues and students and family and friends are all subject to relatively little uncertainty. When I fall ill, meetings need to be cancelled, alternative childcare arrangements need to be made, substitutes need to be trained, deadlines are missed. My illness imposes costs on others beyond those that it imposes upon me, and my health confers benefits on others beyond those it confers on me. It would seem, then, that consumption of my health is non-rival: my enjoyment of my health does not prevent my colleagues from enjoying it, and no other person's enjoyment of my health "uses it up" either. My students, my spouse, my friends may all enjoy it. It would seem, also, that consumption of my health is nonexcludable. I could attempt to collect monthly fees from others in the amount that each of them has benefited (e.g., in terms of reduced uncertainty) from my remaining healthy. But, even assuming that I could surmount the daunting calculative difficulties and generate an accurate fee schedule, the scheme would quickly fall apart because it 40. Epstein, supra note 8, at 911-12. Id. 42. See Alain C. Enthoven & Sara J. Singer, Markets and Collective Action in RegulatingManaged Care, 16 HEALTH AFFAIRS 6, 26-27 (1997). 43. The following arguments are advanced with apologies to Dan Polsby. See Daniel D. Polsby, What if This Is as Good as It Gets?, 2 GREEN BAG 115, 122 (1998) (reviewing RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, PRINCIPLES FOR A FREE SOCIETY: RECONCILING INDIVIDUAL LIBERTY WITH THE COMMON GOOD (1998)). 41. 744 QLR [Vol. 19:727 would be impossible for me to withhold my health selectively from those who declined to pay. It follows, then, that my health is a public good. The social value of my health is greater than its value to me, and I have no means of capturing that differential. I will therefore fail to spend as much time and effort on keeping myself healthy as would be socially optimal. Perhaps I need a subsidy.