Philosophia DOI 10.1007/s11406-009-9187-3 Individuating Mental Tokens: The Split-Brain Case Elizabeth Schechter Received: 10 July 2008 / Revised: 21 February 2009 / Accepted: 9 March 2009 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2009 Abstract Some philosophers have argued that so long as two neural events, within a subject, are both of the same type and both carry the same content, then these events may jointly constitute a single mental token, regardless of the sort of causal relation to each other that they bear. These philosophers have used this claim—which I call the “singularity-through-redundancy” position—in order to argue that a split-brain subject normally has a single stream of consciousness, disjunctively realized across the two hemispheres. This paper argues, against this position, that the kind of causal relations multiple neural events bear to each other constrains the mental tokens with which functionalists who are realists can identify them. Keywords Split-brain phenomenon . Functionalism . Realism . Multiple realizability . Individuating mental tokens . Mind-brain relationship E. Schechter (*) Philosophy Department, University of Maryland, College Park, MD, USA e-mail: lizschechter@gmail.com Philosophia Introduction Many people believe that the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject1 can each sustain a unique stream of consciousness, and in fact that even outside of experimental conditions, when such subjects’ behavior is comparatively normal, they have two streams of consciousness, and indeed two minds. This “duality” claim regarding split-brain subjects’ consciousness and cognition is particularly popular among cognitive scientists who study the brain, i.e., neuropsychologists. In fact the neuropsychological community seemed to more or less converge upon a mental and conscious duality claim for split-brain subjects some time ago. Philosophers who have studied the split-brain phenomenon have not reached the same degree of convergence. Some have urged caution in or skepticism towards counting minds and streams of consciousness;2 others have argued forcefully against the duality positions for split-brain subjects. Marks (1980) and Tye (2003) for example have both suggested that claims of mental and conscious duality in splitbrain subjects rest upon an unmotivated and extravagant way of individuating mental tokens. Essentially they have argued that because the two hemispheres of a splitbrain subject will normally generate experiences with the same contents, we should identify them with the same stream of consciousness. This paper examines what I call the “singularity-through-redundancy” (or STR) position: the claim that multiple neural events of the same psychological type and carrying the same content can be identified with a single mental token, regardless of their causal relations to each other. I will approach this claim largely via the writings of Marks (1980) and Tye (2003), since they have developed and defended this claim most explicitly. But the claim enjoys broader appeal; Dennett, for example, gestures towards a similar position (1991), and even Sperry seemed to feel its pull at times (see his 1975 for example). Split-brain subjects are discussed throughout much of this paper because the splitbrain studies motivated the development of the singularity-through-redundancy position. The paper’s ultimate concern isn’t with consciousness in the split-brain 1 See Gazzaniga (2000) or Gazzaniga and LeDoux (1978) for an introduction to the split-brain phenomenon. A “split-brain” subject is a human subject whose corpus callosum (which connects the two cerebral hemispheres in the subjects I will call “normal”) has been surgically sectioned, and whose hemispheres are thus (largely) divided at the cortical level. (In some split-brain subjects the anterior commissure has also been sectioned.) The riveting behavior that these subjects exhibit occurs, for the most part, only under the highly artificial experimental conditions distinctive of what I will call the “split-brain experiment.” During the split-brain experiment, sensory information about a particular stimulus is directed as much as possible only to one hemisphere at a time. When such experiments are performed on “normal” subjects, at least some of this sensory information is made available to the non-receiving hemisphere via the corpus callosum. In a split-brain subject, however, most of this information remains available only to receiving hemisphere. Yet experimenters have shown that either hemisphere can respond intelligently to a stimulus in various ways, and these responses often seem the result of conscious processing. (See, to take just one set of examples, Sperry et al. (1979); Shallice states nicely how compelling some of the evidence for right hemisphere consciousness is; see his 1997: p.264.) Meanwhile, the non-receiving hemisphere appears largely or wholly unaware of what the other hemisphere has been presented with. 2 See the commentary following Puccetti’s 1981, including that of Churchland (1981), Green (1981), and Margolis (1981); see Rey (1983) for a response to Puccetti as well. See also Nagel (1979) and Lockwood (1989). Philosophia subject, however, but rather with the STR position more abstractly. This position concerns several fundamental issues in psychology: most obviously how to individuate mental tokens, and the relationship between psychological and neural entities; it also concerns the proper form for a functionalist theory of the mental to take. If defenders of the singularity-through-redundancy position are correct, proponents of the mental and conscious duality positions have committed a significant and fundamental error, and failed to draw the appropriate lessons from important and well-motivated functionalist principles. This paper’s underlying concern is whether, contra the STR position, the kinds of causal relationships that multiple neural events bear, or fail to bear, to each other, constrain the mental events with which we can identify them. I submit that they do. In “Redundancy, Unity, and Streams of Consciousness” I shall locate the STR claim with respect to the debate about the structure of consciousness in split-brain subjects. In “Constituting a Single Token” and “Three Claims Regarding Irrelevance” I argue against singularity-through-redundancy as a characterization of split-brain consciousness. In “Mental Tokens” I describe a hypothetical subject for whom I think the case of (mental) singularity-through-redundancy could be made most strongly. I nonetheless argue that the STR claim would fail even in this case. In fact, I suggest that a functionalism with realist commitments must use facts about the causal dependence or independence of neural events to individuate mental tokens. Redundancy, Unity, and Streams of Consciousness This section explains the prima facie motivation for attributing to a split-brain subject a single stream of consciousness, and describes the singularity-throughredundancy model, which, if tenable, may offer a way to defend this attribution. I also clarify the element of the STR position that is the concern of this paper. The Motivation for a Unity Claim for Split-brain Subjects Marks and Tye say that “normal” subjects—in this context, subjects who each possess an intact corpus callosum—behave in a unified fashion, and that we believe that this is partly due to these subjects each having a single stream of consciousness or a unified consciousness. In daily life, meanwhile, the gross behavior of split-brain subjects usually resembles that of these “normal” subjects. Marks asks, “If we account for our integrated behavior, at least in part, by assuming unity of consciousness and can do the same for split-brain patients, why not do so?” (22)3 Marks and Tye accept that there are occasional times during the split-brain experiment at which split-brain subjects have two streams of consciousness.4 Notwithstanding such moments they believe that a split-brain subject’s consciousness is normally singular or unified. They therefore face the challenge of showing how the split-brain experimental paradigm could alter the structure of a split-brain 3 All references to Marks are taken from his 1980. All references to Tye are taken from his 2003. In order to focus on the singularity-through-redundancy position in particular, this paper must assume many (not uncontroversial) claims without argument. One such claim is that the right hemispheres of splitbrain subjects are associated with conscious mental states, as Marks and Tye contend. 4 Philosophia subject’s consciousness, especially since it does not alter that of the “normal” subject. (“Normals” do not exhibit the conscious dissociation under conditions of perceptual lateralization that split-brain subjects appear to.) The solution both philosophers take is to say that conscious unity can supervene on certain properties of conscious contents. When present, the corpus callosum ensures conscious unity even under conditions of lateralized perception, by allowing some kind of interhemispheric communication of contents. But even without a corpus callosum, the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject will normally be subject to the same (or to highly similar) conscious contents, Marks and Tye (among others) believe, because they will be receiving the same (or highly similar) information from the environment and the body. The singularity-through-redundancy claim asserts that what Marks calls the “independent duplication of information” (see pp. 17–24) suffices for a unified consciousness. Multiple neural events of the same mental type (conscious experience), and bearing the same content, can together constitute a single mental token, even if their contents are produced independently of each other. This paper’s central concern is whether neural events operating “independently” of each other can indeed constitute a single mental token, as the defenders of STR argue that they can. But of course a natural objection to the entire debate about STR, as it has just been described, is that the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject don’t generate conscious phenomena totally causally independently of each other. This is quite correct: if via her left hemisphere, for instance, a split-brain subject says, “Oh no, not again,” then both her right and left hemisphere will generate conscious auditory representations of this verbal expression. This demonstrates that we need to get clearer about the kind of causal independence that is in question. Tye’s defense of STR refers to right and left hemisphere consciousness-realizing events as simply being “causally unrelated” (127); Marks speaks of the absence of “direct” causal interaction between right and left hemisphere consciousness-realizing events in the split-brain subject, but without clarifying the distinction between direct and indirect causal interaction. I believe that it is essential to get a little clearer than this on the kind of causal independence whose relevance to the constitutive conditions for mental tokens is at issue. I will postpone until “Is Causal Independence Psychologically Relevant?”, however, a discussion of the kind of causal relationship that I believe characterizes the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject, and that, I argue, does pose constraints on the mental individuation of neural events. Until that time I will just speak of the causal independence of right and left hemisphere neural events without qualification. I do this, for now, in part because the STR position itself, as currently defended in the philosophical literature, makes no serious attempt to distinguish between different kinds of causal independence in the generation of mental and conscious phenomena, casting causal independence, without qualification, as not in and of itself relevant to psychological individuation. The Empirical Inadequacy of the Singularity-through-redundancy Characterization of Split-brain Consciousness One objection to the singularity-through-redundancy characterization of split-brain consciousness is empirical: the two hemispheres are almost certainly not subject to identical conscious contents outside of experimental situations, and thus the right Philosophia and left hemisphere’s neural events cannot be considered redundant from the psychological perspective. The hemispheres are no doubt subject to more similar contents outside of experimental situations than they are inside of them, and this no doubt offers at least a partial explanation for the fact that split-brain subjects behave differently in the two types of circumstance. Nonetheless, since the hemispheres have different patterns of perceptual access to the world, and since they also have different processing styles and capacities, and appear to experience emotions somewhat differently, and to have access to a somewhat different store of long-term memories—not to mention the fact that one hemisphere can presumably generate a fairly normal stream of inner speech and one hemisphere probably can’t—it would be a stretch to imagine that the hemispheres are associated with highly similar, much less identical, conscious contents. In order to focus on the STR position considered more abstractly, however, I set aside this empirical objection in most of what follows. For most of the paper I will assume that the two hemispheres of a split-brain patient are subject to highly similar conscious contents; towards the end of the paper I consider what we should say of a subject who possessed two hemispheres that independently generated neural events bearing truly indistinguishable psychological properties at every moment. Disunity Versus Duality Ordinary language generally treats “unified consciousness” and “single stream of consciousness” as near-synonyms—as mere different parts of speech. Much philosophical and psychological writing on the structure of consciousness similarly equates having a unified consciousness with having a single stream of consciousness. Yet some of those who have argued that split-brain subjects have two minds and two streams of consciousness prefer not to speak of mental or conscious disunity so much as duality.5 After all, since the hemispheres may be associated with many of the same psychological states, and since they share a history (in one sense), and so forth, it might be misleading to describe them as disunified, for the term “disunity” connotes conflict and discord. Ascribing a dual consciousness has fewer of these potentially misleading implications, and so, too, I submit, should ascriptions of multiple streams of consciousness. Two streams of consciousness are highly unlikely to have indistinguishable psychological properties. They could nonetheless be either fairly unified or fairly disunified with each other, and how unified they were could very well depend in part upon the degree of overlap between their contents. This paper is concerned not with the qualitative character of mental tokens, but with their individuality; it argues (among other things) that the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject are each associated with an (at least largely) unique set of mental, including conscious, tokens. For the most part I set aside the issue of how psychologically similar to each other (and thus perhaps how unified with each other) those tokens may be. 5 Bogen (1990) seemed to prefer this formulation, for example. Philosophia I speak in this paper, therefore, of whether or not the STR position gives us reason to believe that split-brain subjects have a single stream of consciousness, rather than of whether or not it gives us reason to believe that they have a unified consciousness. This is why I speak of the singularity-through-redundancy rather than the unity-through-redundancy position. In doing so I do not mean to pre-judge the issue of whether or not semantic relations among contents might in fact serve to meld what would otherwise be two streams of consciousness into one. Perhaps, that is, having a unified consciousness—in the sense of a coherent set of mental contents—is all there is to having a single stream of consciousness. But perhaps not; there might for instance be a single stream of consciousness whose contents were very disunified, in the sense of discordant. I therefore remain neutral on this issue, for now, by speaking of streams of consciousness, and not of unity or disunity. A split-brain subject possessing two distinct streams of consciousness might still enjoy a high degree of conscious unity (in the sense proposed just above), and a high degree of unity might play an important role in explaining the behavior that Marks and Tye call “unified.” Defenders of the singularity-through-redundancy characterization of split-brain consciousness do not merely believe, however, that the two “disconnected” hemispheres are largely unified in the sense of having highly similar conscious contents (something that many defenders of the conscious duality model also seem to believe). They claim something stronger. Defenders of the STR position equate having a unified consciousness with having a single stream of consciousness, and having a disunified consciousness with having two streams of consciousness.6 They therefore claim that to the extent that the two hemispheres are associated with the same conscious contents, they are associated with the same conscious tokens. It is this stronger claim that I reject. Constituting a Single Token The STR position holds that multiple neural events may, causally independently of each other, jointly constitute a single mental event. This section criticizes two analogies Tye offers in support of this position: the first seems simply nonanalogous, and the second is subtly question-begging against those who would claim that the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject are associated with distinct mental tokens. Tye rejects attributing to split-brain subjects “two separate streams of consciousness that remain two from the time of the commissurotomy” in favor of saying that such subjects “are single persons whose phenomenal consciousness is briefly split into two under certain special experimental conditions, but whose consciousness at other times is unified” (126; emphasis added; citing Marks 1980 as well). Likewise, as a “rough necessary condition for two simultaneous conscious experiences belonging to the same stream of consciousness”, Marks offers, “e1 and e2 belong to the same unified consciousness only if they are known, by introspection, to be simultaneous” (13; emphasis added), thus tying possession of a single stream of consciousness to possession of a unified consciousness. Both philosophers meanwhile also accept what is widely accepted, i.e. that a stream of consciousness is composed of token experiences (or in Tye’s case, a single token experience—this is one of the main positions argued for in Tye 2003). 6 Philosophia The Projector Analogy Tye anticipates that some will object to the STR position by saying that, “a single experience cannot have as its physical basis neural events in the left and right hemispheres that are themselves causally unrelated.” But, he asks, “why not?” Consider the following example. Two movie projectors each project an image onto a screen at time t. Only a single image is present on the screen at t, since identical slides are in the projectors and they are aimed at exactly the same part of the screen. There are two projections but only one image. One projection is redundant. Each projection on its own suffices for the screen image. (127) There are three problems with this analogy. Note, first, that the generation of a single image isn’t necessarily a function of the projectors’ projecting “redundant” slides: one machine could project an image of a child at play, the second of a hulking monster, and the result would be a single image of a monster lurking over an unsuspecting child at play. More troublingly, the two projections appear not to realize but to produce the image. One could, for example, alter the (apparent) number of images without manipulating the slides or projectors at all, simply by moving (or removing altogether) the screen. But everyone will accept that a mental event can causally depend upon two independently acting neural events. The relationship between realizer and realized is more intimate than the relationship between cause and effect, and Tye needs to provide an analogy more clearly involving the former. Even if the projections did jointly realize the image, however, the doublyprojected image offers an inadequate analogy to a case of mental singularity through neural redundancy in particular, because the individuation criteria for images and experiences are simply too different. Clearly an audience would assume they were seeing a single image, so long as all beams of light projected onto the same portion of the screen. And perhaps counting images is just a matter of determining how many images a normal viewer (e.g. a human being whose visual system is functioning normally) would appear to see. But as Tye himself points out, the fact that split-brain subjects don’t “see double” or experience having multiple streams of consciousness is to be expected, regardless of how many streams of consciousness any of them actually have. When it comes to counting images on a screen, in other words, phenomenology may be almost everything. But when it comes to counting conscious experiences, particularly those that do have redundant contents, phenomenology tells us almost nothing. If the disanalogy between individuating images and individuating experiences isn’t immediately obvious, it is because Tye’s first analogy plays off of our naïve or pre-theoretic notion of conscious experience as, to borrow Dennett’s (1991) oftborrowed phrase, a Cartesian theater. Once we rid ourselves of the illusion that conscious experience is a thing we watch, it is unclear what a conscious experience is supposed to be analogous to in this example. Maybe to the beam of light? But there are two of those. Philosophia The Restaurant Analogy In his second analogy, Tye, while seated at a restaurant, waves both of his arms at once to catch his server’s attention. There are two arm-wavings here, he says, and yet one event of signaling his server. Note, however, that the two arm-wavings together seem necessary to give the signaling event its precise character; neither arm-waving is redundant in that respect. There are, for example, social and psychological differences between trying to catch your server’s attention by waving one hand, and trying to catch his attention by waving both hands, just as there are social and psychological differences between trying to catch his attention by waving both hands wildly in the air, and trying to catch his attention by shouting “Hey, boy!”7 Nonetheless, even if the event of signaling with one hand and the event of signaling with two hands have a different character, each appears to be but a single event, and individuating events (tokens), rather than providing a qualitative analysis of their nature, is our current concern. Still, it is worth asking why Tye seems right that waving both arms in a restaurant is one way of realizing a single event. How do we know that waving two biological arms in the air isn’t just one way of realizing two waving-one-arm events—waving two prosthetic arms being a different way of realizing two waving-one-arm events? Actually, waving two biological arms in the air may be one way of realizing two waving-one-arm events. But Tye could agree that there are two waving-one-arm events. His claim is that there is just one signaling event. Events are individuated relative to a particular level of description. There is a single signaling event in Tye’s restaurant case because signaling one’s server is a communicative act, and we individuate such acts partly in terms of intention. Thus if two parties seated near each other talked and decided (their situation being somewhat desperate) to both wave their hands at the same time in the hopes of finally catching their server’s attention, they arguably both participate in a single signaling event. But if the same two parties both waved their hands at once by mere coincidence, then there were arguably two, simultaneous signaling events. Part of the reason we may find it hard to conceive of a reason we would want to say, of the original case that Tye provided, that there are two signaling events, is because we are just so used to thinking of a single human organism as having a single mind and a single set of intentions (at a time) that are (in some sense) integrated prior to behavior. In Tye’s original “restaurant” analogy, the two armwaving events aren’t initiated causally independently of each other in the way we deem relevant to individuating communicative actions, because we attribute to Tye a single intention to signal by waving both arms. But of course precisely what is under consideration is whether and to what extent we can apply this reasoning to split-brain subjects. Identifying Tye’s two armTye himself introduces the example by asking us to imagine a “case in which I am in a restaurant, and, being anxious to leave, I signal the waiter by raising both hands in the air and waving them” (127; emphasis added). Tye’s feeling it necessary to imply that of course he wouldn’t wave both hands in the air to catch his server’s attention unless he were particularly anxious constitutes an inadvertent admission that neither arm-waving is truly redundant, since both arm-wavings are necessary to give the signaling event its precise social and psychological significance. 7 Philosophia waving events with a single signaling event rests upon the assumption that there was a single mental event causally responsible for both arm-waving events. Duality advocates claim that the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject are associated with distinct mental events that drive the subject’s (unified-seeming) behavior causally independently of each other (in some relevant sense). Tye obviously disagrees, but his restaurant analogy offers only question-begging support for his position. Note that it isn’t just the number of token intentions to signal that determines how many signaling events we locate. In the case in which two parties waved at once, each possessed a unique token intention to wave; whether we see one or two signaling events depends upon whether there was an interactive process leading to the formation of the two token intentions. We ask the parties, “Did you talk to each other, and come to a mutual decision to jointly signal your server? Or did you each come to the decision to wave independently—was it mere coincidence that you both waved at once?” We try to determine whether there was a certain kind of causal relationship between the admittedly distinct token intentions that produced the wavings. So it is, too, I shall argue, when the events we are counting aren’t communicative actions but cognitive acts. To determine whether two neural events realize one and the same mental event, we must know something about their causal relationship to each other. The next section considers more closely the causal relationship that is required between neural events in order for them to realize a single token of a mental type. Three Claims Regarding Irrelevance This section treats three distinct arguments potentially supporting the singularitythrough-redundancy position, particularly as applied to split-brain consciousness. These arguments all deny psychological significance to the causal relationships that hold, or fail to hold, between right and left hemisphere neural events in the splitbrain subject. The first argument is premised upon a type-token confusion; the second and third arguments fail to grasp the precise kind of causal interaction that seems lacking between right and left hemisphere events in the split-brain subject. Multiple Realizability and the Type-token Distinction Fodor (1975) has argued that the kinds postulated by psychology will not reduce to the kinds postulated by any purely physical (non-functional) science, because the kinds of psychology—the types of entities to which it will refer in its laws—are multiply realizable. What makes a given event a pain event, or an event of believing something, as opposed to some other kind of mental event or no mental event at all, isn’t a matter of its intrinsic physical properties, but the role it plays within a functionalist story, a role connecting it to (at a minimum) sensory inputs, motor outputs, and other mental events. Thus creatures whose physical construction was radically different from ours could nonetheless possess the same types of mental states that we do. All that would be required is for their physical construction to somehow implement a functional design similar to that implemented by our own brains (whatever design that turns out to be). Philosophia The principle of multiple realizability is foundational to the functionalist program, and has been appealed to in order to support the singularity-through-redundancy claim. Marks answers the question, “Why should neural processes unrelated by direct causal routes not be the physical basis for a single mental state?” (23) in part by citing Fodor (1975). Tye says that when a split-brain subject’s right and left hemisphere, causally independently of each other, each generate a neural event of the type experience and carrying the same content, “There is. . . . a single experience. . . with a neurological realization or constitution that is partly redundant and that differs from the neurological realization or constitution” that that same experience would have “in normal subjects” (127). Same mental events, different realizers, in other words. By casting the neuro-functional differences between split-brain and “normal” subjects as merely differences in how experiences are realized, rather than as differences in how many experiences are realized, those sympathetic to the STR position seek to obviate a simple objection. This objection states that while the hemispheres of a split-brain patient, S, may be subject to the same types of experiences (where contents are included in type), they are surely subject to distinct token experiences, for S’s hemispheres realize the experiences they realize independently of each other. This objection rests on the intuition that facts about the causal properties of a neural event constrain the mental events with which we can identify it. Drawing on the language of multiple realizability, Marks and Tye respond that such facts concern how psychological phenomena are implemented, but are not psychological facts properly speaking. We can, and should, refer to those facts at some times—such as when we need to explain why the consciousness of split-brain subjects, and not that of “normal” subjects, becomes dual or disunified during the split-brain experiment.8 Marks writes that this duality is itself explained by the fact that the experimental controls defeat the mechanisms which are, as a result of commissurotomy, responsible for unity of consciousness in these patients. Similarly there is a natural explanation for the behavioral differences between split-brain patients and normal controls. The mechanisms which subserve unity of consciousness in the normal controls differ in ways that make them immune to failure in the experimental situation. (22–3) But facts about functional neuroanatomy are facts about the mechanisms subserving various mental phenomena, not facts about which mental phenomena are actually being subserved. Marks believes that the moral of the split-brain cases is that bilateral neural representation is a physical basis for unity of consciousness; but it is irrelevant how such representation is achieved, whether through the commissures or through mechanisms for independent duplication. (22; emphasis added) 8 It is essential to keep in mind that for Marks and Tye (and seemingly others to whom the singularitythrough-redundancy position appeals), to have a unified consciousness is to have a single stream of consciousness, and to have two (or more) streams of consciousness is to have a disunified consciousness. These same thinkers also view streams of consciousness as mental tokens (or composites of mental tokens). Philosophia Facts about how mental phenomena are implemented in the “normal” and in the “split” brain should not constrain the individuation of psychological entities—such as streams of consciousness—which are, after all, multiply realizable. If the principle of multiple realizability is correct, then creatures with a wide variety of physical constitutions could possess streams of consciousness. This does not mean that physical facts are irrelevant to individuating particular streams of consciousness, however. A mental token is a physical thing—a realizer of a particular mental type. The thesis of multiple realizability, and the fact that, as Marks says, the “general account of mind advocated by philosophers as diverse as Fodor and Grice. . . does not require corresponding types of neurological states for each type of psychological state” (23; emphasis added), provides no support for the further claim that causally unrelated neural events can form “the basis for a single mental state” (23; emphasis added; citing Fodor (1975) and Grice (1975)). The latter is a claim about mental tokens. And the principle of multiple realizability doesn’t say anything about how to individuate mental tokens. It is simply silent on this matter. Since the principle of multiple realizability provides no guidance where counting mental tokens is concerned, we must turn elsewhere for this guidance. Is Causal Independence Psychologically Relevant? The defender of the singularity-through-redundancy position must claim that multiple neural events can constitute a single mental token even if they occur causally independently of each other. There is a broader and a narrower way of making this claim. Framed broadly, the claim states that the causal independence of multiple neural events never provides reason to identify them with multiple mental tokens. Framed narrowly, the claim states that although the causal independence of multiple neural events usually provides reason not to identify them with a single mental token, there is a particular kind of case that constitutes an exception to this general rule: the case in which the neural events in question have “redundant” psychological properties. I will consider the broad interpretation in this subsection and the narrower interpretation in the next. The principle underlying the intuitive objection to STR is simply that the neural events that constitute a single token of a mental type must be themselves be causally related in some important way. Up until this point we have postponed asking what way that might be. The question is crucial because causal connectedness in and of itself is cheap; my conscious neural events are connected to your conscious neural events via your reading of this paper I have written, for example. What we really want to know is whether there is some psychologically relevant difference between intrahemispheric and interhemispheric causal interactions in the split-brain subject, such that we have reason to believe that intrahemispheric neural events may jointly constitute a single stream of consciousness, while interhemispheric neural events cannot. What we really want to know is what kind or degree of causal distance between two neural events should constrain our identifying them with a single mental token. On Marks’ interpretation, those disposed to object to STR believe that the neural events that jointly constitute a single mental token must be “causally connected in a Philosophia fairly direct way, on some reasonable understanding of ‘direct’” (21). But Marks says that this “crucial causal principle” is not strongly motivated. Why should neural processes unrelated by direct causal routes not be the physical basis for a single mental state? (23) Psychofunctionalist psychology does not require any direct causal links between the neural events which are the physical basis for a single psychological state. It would be sufficient if causally unrelated neural events jointly, though separately, produced effects which were, from the standpoint of the psychology, the basis of a single mental state. (23) Anyone familiar with the binding problem (or problems) may be inclined to agree with Marks. The binding problems (roughly) concern how it is that we perceive objects possessing multiple perceptual properties, and entire scenes composed of such objects, given the fact that perceptual information, both across and within sensory modalities, is processed in a distributed manner in the brain (such that color and shape, for example, are represented in different brain areas). If we state a priori, as it were, that two neural events can only constitute a single mental event when they are directly causally linked, then we may not find the neural correlates of many of the mental tokens that (let’s assume) we have compelling reasons to believe we possess. It is difficult to go further at this point without getting a little clearer on the kind of causal connection between neural events whose relevance to psychological individuation is being debated here. For there is a psychologically relevant difference between the kind of causal independence between perceptual processing areas that gives rise to the binding problems, and the kind of mutual causal independence characterizing the two “disconnected” hemispheres. To begin with, behavioral evidence alone allows us to conclude that whatever neural mechanisms are responsible for phenomenal and functional binding, they operate intrahemispherically in split-brain subjects (at least largely). For the splitbrain experiments show that in these subjects perceptual information is not bound, either phenomenally or functionally, across the hemispheres. They also show that although the two “disconnected” hemispheres do interact with each other in complex ways, this interaction is generally sustained only via the mediation of environmental and behavioral events.9 9 Due to the fact that the hemispheres are connected via numerous sub- and non-cortical structures (and often via the anterior commissure), there may be certain types of mental states that the hemispheres generate or experience in an interactive way, and certain ways in which the hemispheres interact absent the mediation of behavioral and environment and bodily events. Emotional or affective states and processes have often been seen as constituting such exceptions to the general rule of interhemispheric “independence” (e.g. Sperry et al. 1979; Lockwood 1989). (Though there is also competing evidence for the emotional independence of the two hemispheres; see instance Schiffer et al. 1998.) My fundamental concern in this paper isn’t with the structure of split-brain consciousness per se however but with the singularity-through-redundancy claim. That claim doesn’t hinge upon the possibility of any kind of wholly neural, inter-hemispheric interaction in the generation of mental phenomena; it rather asserts that even without such interaction, the two hemispheres can jointly generate a single stream of consciousness. I therefore ignore many complications and subtleties regarding sub- and non-cortically mediated interhemispheric interaction in split-brain subjects. Philosophia Let me take a few paragraphs to demonstrate these claims. Consider an experiment in which Kingstone and Gazzaniga (1995) showed to each hemisphere of a split-brain subject, J.W., one half of a word pair, and then asked him to draw (the referent of) what he’d seen. (For instance, if the word pair was “day–night”, “day” would be in J. W.’s left visual field and thus received by his right hemisphere, while “night” would be in his right visual field and thus received by his left hemisphere.) When not permitted to watch himself as he drew, he usually drew only a single word in the pair (especially when using his right hand, over which the left hemisphere generally exerts dominant but not exclusive control); when permitted to watch himself as he drew, J.W. was somewhat more likely to draw (the referents of) both words. In the crucial trial type (during which J.W. was allowed to watch himself in free vision as he drew), each hemisphere was shown a different half of a “conceptually ambiguous” word pair: each of these word pairs could be drawn either as a literal combination of the referents of the two words, or as an emergent object, i.e. as the single object referred to by the compound word formed by joining the two words in the pair. For instance, a drawing of the word pair “head-stone” could consist either in a literal combination of the two words—e.g. a rock and a human head—or in a single emergent object—a tombstone. It is well known that that there is little evidence for phenomenal binding across the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject; when asked to describe what they see, for instance, subjects generally only describe (using the left hemisphere) left hemisphere percepts. This study suggested that right and left hemisphere percepts also aren’t bound together functionally somehow in the split-brain subject: when asked to draw what he’d seen, J.W. sometimes drew the referent of one hemisphere’s word, sometimes the referent of the other’s, and sometimes both—but he never drew the single referent of the compound word formed by putting the two words together.10 Supporters of the STR position might point out that J.W. would once in a while draw something like an arrow poised over a bow when given the word pair “bowarrow” (in an earlier trial type, in which the two words in a pair couldn’t always be combined to form a compound word referring to a single emergent object). He did sometimes draw an “integrated” picture of the referents of both words in the pair, that is. Doesn’t this show that drawing and looking behaviors can be used to bind right and left hemisphere percepts functionally, if not phenomenally? But as the authors of this study pointed out, the production of this sort of drawing does not require any internal transfer of information between the hemispheres. If there were such internal transfer of information—if either hemisphere could communicate to the other information about the word it had received, without having to literally draw a picture—then we would expect J.W. to at least sometimes draw the single, emergent referent of the compound word in the crucial trial type. (As he easily did when compound words were presented entirely within his right visual field, i.e., entirely within the view of his left hemisphere.) We would expect J. W. to at least sometimes draw a skyscraper, that is, rather than a windshield scraper lying under a sunny sky. But he never did. 10 J.W. used a single hand on each trial; the hemispheres were apparently switching control of the drawing hand. (Miller and Kingstone 2005 found that both hemispheres can exert a degree of motor control over the ipsilateral hand sufficient for the production of crude drawings.) Philosophia Instead, using one hemisphere, J.W. would draw the referent of the word that hemisphere had received (“arrow”). Then the second hemisphere would come to dominate performance. If the existing image (e.g. of an arrow), now visible to the second hemisphere, could be treated as part of the background for a drawing of the word it had received (e.g. “bow”), the first image was (sometimes) used in this way. But if the existing image (e.g. of a windshield scraper) couldn’t be treated as part of the background for a drawing of the referent of the second hemisphere’s word (“sky,”), J.W. just drew the referent of that second word anyway (or in many instances stopped drawing altogether). In other words, when producing an “integrated” drawing would have required some kind of internal integration of mental states across the hemispheres (integration of the sort involved when J.W.’s left hemisphere saw the entire word pair “honeymoon,” leading J.W. to draw two touching faces, eyes closed, surrounded by hearts), no such drawing was forthcoming. “Indeed,” Kingstone and Gazzaniga explain, the only time that right and left hemisphere “word information. . . [is ever] integrated is on the sheet of paper in the drawing itself” (1995: 324; emphasis added). Although right and left hemisphere neural events interacted to produce some of these drawings, they didn’t interact in a way that is in principle different from the way in which two different subjects’ neural events might interact. After all, if you and I were told to make a single drawing between us, and you were shown only the word “bow” and I was shown only the word “arrow,” and we both took a turn with a pencil, we might produce an arrow drawn across a bow, too—just like J.W. The two hemispheres of a split-brain subject may interact at every moment. But their interaction, at least by and large, does not supervene on wholly neural and mental events. It supervenes partly on behavioral and environmental events. Interhemispheric neural event pairs in split-brain subjects do not jointly produce mentation. They do jointly produce behavior, in the sense that there are behaviors in which split-brain subjects engage that involve the joint participation of both right and left hemisphere. But then there are many behaviors in which my sister and I engage that involve the joint participation of her and my neural events also. Marks seems right in claiming that two neural events need not interact with each other directly in order to constitute a single mental event. The various proposed solutions to the binding problems (see for instance Golledge et al. 1996; O’Reilly et al. 2003; Robertson 2003; Treisman 1996; Treisman and Gelade 1980) seem compatible with this assertion. They are also compatible with a recognized limit to how causally distant from each other these neural events can be, before we cease being able to recognize them as constituting a single mental token. Right and left hemisphere neural event pairs in split-brain subjects are for the most part located at a point past this distance, for their interaction occurs largely via the behavior that they cause. When duality theorists say that in a split-brain subject the right and left hemisphere generate experience causally independently of each other, this is the kind or degree of causal independence they have in mind. Is Redundancy Psychologically Relevant? There is a narrower claim that the STR position might be interpreted as making. This is the claim that even if, as a general rule, the mutual causal independence of two Philosophia neural events requires identifying them with distinct mental tokens, there is an important exception to this rule: those instances in which the two neural events in question have indistinguishable mental properties. In such instances, either set of events seems redundant from a psychological standpoint. Why, then, identify each set with a unique set of mental tokens? After all, Marks calls it “a commonplace that the neural structure of human brain [sic] is highly redundant”; why should it, “be surprising if the redundancy is sometimes irrelevant for the purposes of psychology” (23–24)? Tye, too, says that There seems no obvious reason why nature should not have made us so that, in certain circumstances, there is redundancy at the neural level in the generation of perceptual experience. After all, it is well known that the human brain has a neurological structure that is highly redundant anyway. Why not also here? (128) The purported redundancy in the split-brain case is from the psychological perspective, but at the neural level: there are two neural events instantiating, but a single mental token of, a mental type. The realizing events are thus psychologically redundant, and the fact that there are two of them is psychologically irrelevant. This analogy to the “well known” redundancy of the human brain may be subtly question-begging, however. Two neural events need do more than bear the same content (and instantiate the same mental type) in order to be redundant. In most contexts, for instance, your neural event representing a rapidly approaching truck will hardly be redundant simply because I already have neural event with the same content. Psychological redundancy seems to occur within a mental system, where what constitutes a single mental system seems itself to be a matter of causal organization. It makes sense to speak of the structure of the brain (and perhaps even of some of the contents of the brain) as to some extent redundant, assuming that the brain is a functional system characterized by a certain functional organization and so forth. Thus if one area of the brain is damaged, another area can functionally compensate for its loss.11 But those who advocate a conscious and mental duality model for split-brain subjects believe that the two “disconnected” hemispheres are distinct mental systems, and that right hemisphere neural events are therefore not psychologically redundant. Indeed, it seems fairly simple to show that right and left hemisphere neural events aren’t really redundant in the split-brain subject. If, for example, something catastrophic suddenly happened to S’s left hemisphere visual system, his right hemisphere visual system would not be able to compensate for it, nor would his right hemisphere visual representations be able to serve as “back-up” copies of the representations he’s just lost, at least for many cognitive purposes. For instance, S wouldn’t be able to describe (via his left hemisphere) his right hemisphere experiences. 11 Though even here there may not be exact redundancy in many instances; sometimes one area of the brain functionally compensates for the damaged area, at least to some extent, without performing the exact same operations. We should be careful not to individuate mental functions and capacities too grossly. (See the criticisms of the STR position in “Functionalism, Physicalism, and the Realist Commitment”.) Philosophia This seems to suggest that attempting to formulate the STR position narrowly, as stating that the causal independence of two neural events is psychologically irrelevant so long as the events in question are redundant from a psychological perspective, doesn’t really change the main issue. For what qualifies as genuine redundancy itself seems to depend upon facts about causal interaction and independence. But the defender of STR might press that at most left and right hemisphere neural events aren’t redundant in the split-brain subject because the two hemispheres aren’t functionally identical, for instance, and thus right and left hemisphere neural events won’t have truly identical functional roles. But if a subject did possess two genuinely psychologically redundant neural events, couldn’t they jointly realize a single mental token—no matter the manner of their causal connection to each other? Mental Tokens This section considers whether the constitutive conditions for mental tokens are purely psychological/functional or partly physical (neural). I argue that they are partly neural, for a method of individuation that is sensitive to the causal properties of realizers is required at least by those of us who are realists about functionalist explanation. Purely Psychological Versus Partly Neural Constitutive Criteria for Mental Tokens It is worth emphasizing again that the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject surely do not have identical psychological properties. Among other things, minds— certainly minds like ours—are so complex that, even if two hemispheres had identical patterns of perceptual access to the world, and even if they were functionally identical in terms of their perceptual and cognitive processing styles, it is highly unlikely that they would really be subject to all the same types of mental state with the same contents at every moment. (Absent some kind of integrative process to ensure that they were, that is.)12 Furthermore, while a description of an event’s mental type and content tells us a lot about its psychological properties, it doesn’t tell us everything. Even in a case in which the two hemispheres of a split-brain subject each generated a neural event of the type “belief that X”, the belief might well be put to different uses in each hemisphere. Of course, the two uses would still have to have a lot in common in order for both states to remain beliefs (with the same content); they would have to share a single core or central causal role. Still, there are a great many things that can be done with any token mental state, even keeping its functional type and content constant. As Gazzaniga and LeDoux once put it, “it is unlikely that the two independent mental systems (each with its own sensory input, processing and storage mechanisms, and motor output) would maintain equivalent attentional and motivational states over an extended period” (1978: 117). The same goes for other types of states as well. 12 Philosophia Thus the redundancy condition—which states that two neural events must truly be redundant with respect to their psychological properties if they are to jointly realize a single mental token via a causally independent processes—will be very difficult to meet. There will frequently be a way to distinguish between even two type- and content-identical mental tokens, even within a single creature, by attending to their psychological properties alone, for example, by looking at the other (instantiated) types of mental states they interact with. The singularity-through-redundancy position may still be founded on an important principle, however. This principle says that, whatever criteria we use to individuate neural events, when it comes time to individuate mental events or tokens, we should use purely psychological properties to do so. Thus if two neural events truly do have indistinguishable psychological properties—if they are of the same mental type, with the same content, and are functionally related to all the same types of mental events with the same contents—then a psychological theory need not distinguish them, but may rather identify them with a single mental token. Perfect Parallelism: the Strong Case for Singularity-through-redundancy We have seen that the principle of multiple realizability cannot provide support for the claim that causally unrelated neural events may constitute a single mental token. We have noted that the neural redundancy, sensory decomposition and binding that exist in the “normal” brain are not analogous to the “redundancy” and causal independence at issue in the debate about STR, and therefore not relevant to evaluating that position. Can anything else be said in favor of singularity-throughredundancy—or can anything be said more decisively against it? In fact I think that something more can be said in favor of it, though I also think that ultimately, the position is still untenable. To evaluate the position at its strongest and most plausible, consider a hypothetical case of what I will call “perfect parallelism.” Our “perfectly parallel” subject, PP, unlike our split-brain subject S, has two functionally identical hemispheres (or two whole brains if you prefer). Unlike those of our split-brain subject, PP’s two hemispheres operate in perfectly “redundant” or parallel fashion: every time PP’s left hemisphere generates a neural event realizing the belief that X, or a desire for Y, PP’s right hemisphere does also, and at the exact same time, of its own accord. And every time one of PP’s hemispheres generates a motor plan, and initiates a motor impulse to, say, grab Z, PP’s other hemisphere does also, at the exact same time and again wholly independently, such that the set of neural events in either hemisphere alone would have sufficed for that exact same action having been performed. (Note that because PP’s hemispheres are both functionally identical and subject to identical psychological properties at every moment, the defender of STR will argue that they disjunctively realize a single mental system.) But somehow (one must imagine) PP’s two hemispheres operate in perfectly parallel fashion like this wholly independently of each other in the following sense: there is not a single activity of either of PP’s hemispheres throughout PP’s life that depended upon PP’s other hemisphere’s actual activities; each hemisphere would have behaved identically had the other hemisphere been totally absent. So how many beliefs that X does PP have? How many streams of consciousness? How many minds? Philosophia Perfect parallelism is clearly a fiction, but one that may suggest that those sympathetic to the STR claim still have an important theoretical point against duality theorists, who have tended to take facts about the causal independence of neural events as in and of themselves relevant to psychological individuation. The defender of the singularity-through-redundancy position would presumably press, here, that while PP’s neuroanatomy may be striking and fascinating from some neuroscientific standpoint, the fact that PP’s beliefs, desires, experiences, intentions, memories, motor commands, and so forth, are realized “disjunctively” by two causally independent sets of neural events, is now without question psychologically irrelevant. For surely we lose nothing, from an explanatory perspective, by attributing to our perfectly parallel subject, PP, only a single belief that X, a single desire that Y, and so forth, at every moment, and indeed a single mental system, itself disjunctively realized across two hemispheres. And surely we gain nothing by attributing to PP two sets of mental tokens with indistinguishable psychological properties at every moment. Occam’s razor alone would suggest that we attribute the less extravagant number of mental tokens to PP. In which case the STR position, even if not tenable with respect to split-brain subjects for purely empirical reasons, is premised upon a sound principle for individuating mental tokens: utilizing their purely psychological properties, and not their neural ones. In which case many members of the neuropsychological community have made a significant error. Functionalism, Physicalism, and the Realist Commitment Contra this position, I believe that the causal relations a neural event stands in, with respect to other neural events, always matter to its individuation as mental token. At least, they matter to those functionalists who are also realists. In the abstract, functionalism doesn’t say much about the nature of mental tokens; functionalism proper is neutral with respect to what sorts of things can occupy the roles tagged by mental state terms, and is therefore in principle compatible even with ontological dualism.13 Of course the vast majority of functionalists are physicalists, who believe that all existing phenomena are actually physical (or have physical properties). This paper is written from the standpoint of a psychofunctionalism with realist commitments; so far as I can tell, Marks and Tye are both realist psychofunctionalists as well. Psychofunctionalism states that the best account of the constitutive conditions for mental phenomena will come from the functional analysis of a developed psychological theory. To commit to psychological realism is just to believe that there really are mental phenomena doing the things, playing the roles, that our best psychological theory will describe. The realist believes that there really are things out there instantiating the mental types implicitly defined by our best psychological theory. 13 Though this is not to say that a functionalist psychological theory cannot refer to any non-functionally defined terms. My point here is merely that functionalism can be neutral with respect to the kinds of things that can realize functional types, not that all forms of functionalism are so neutral, nor that the best form will be. Philosophia The functionalist who is also a realist thus has an additional reason for being a physicalist. To paraphrase Rey (1977, p. 57; also citing Wiggins 1977), causation just seems in fact to require physical stuff. Identifying mental tokens, the realizers of mental types, with physical things, offers a way for functionally defined entities to have causal powers. For the psychological realist, neuroscience has the potential to vindicate a psychological theory, to show that the theory is not just empirically adequate or useful with respect to predicting behavior, but that the story the theory tells is also true. Of course the realist runs greater risks as well; neuroscientific discoveries can falsify the psychological realist’s best theory, in a way that they can’t falsify the best theory of the non-realist. The realist expects and in fact requires that at multiple points in the development of a psychological theory, neuroscientists will hunt for physical things doing the things that the theory describes mental phenomena doing. If the realist is lucky, neuroscientists will find such a thing. If she is less lucky, no such thing will be found, and she will either have to repeatedly revise her theory or (perhaps, ultimately, following enough failures of the right sort) drop the theory altogether and start anew. And sometimes neuroscientists may not only find something playing the role her theory described—they may find more of those things than anyone expected. From the perspective of the functionalist who is also a realist, causal relationships to (instantiated) types of mental state are essential to a neural event’s mental type identity. But are causal relationships to instantiated types of mental event all that matter to a neural event’s (mental) token identity, too? Or are causal relationships to particular mental tokens also essential to a neural event’s (mental) token identity? It seems quite clear that relationships to particular tokens matter. That one of your neural events and one of my neural events are identical with respect to the types of mental state to which they are causally related provides good reason to accept that they instantiate the same mental type. But clearly it provides no reason for identifying these two neural events with a unique mental token. For the two neural events are causally related to distinct actual occupiers of these mental types. The point can be put in the following way. A mental token’s type identity is a matter of its bearing certain relationships to any mental tokens of particular types. But a mental token’s token identity is a matter of it bearing certain relationships to particular mental tokens. The relationships that matter are of course causal ones: a realist functionalism, again, is distinguished by a commitment to the reality, to the causal efficacy, of the entities characterized in (some) functionalist psychological theory. While it is admittedly difficult to say at this point at exactly what level of abstraction away from the physical a psychofunctionalist story will be pitched, it nonetheless seems very likely that how any of these mental tokens are individuated will be in part a physical matter. A mental token is an occupier of a given functionally defined role; counting tokens is a matter of determining how many occupiers of that role there are. Occupiers are physical things; their physical properties are relevant to determining how many of them exist. Admittedly, the physical, causal properties that an occupier of a psychological role possesses may not all be relevant to its individuation as a mental token; indeed, a great number of them (e.g., the number of dendritic spines synapsed upon) are no doubt irrelevant. For that matter, not all of a neural event’s psychologically defined, actual causes and Philosophia effects may matter to its identity qua mental token. Perhaps a token percept that gives rise to a certain belief, for instance, might have been that same percept even if it hadn’t given rise to that belief. So not all of the causal relationships that a mental token does and does not bear to other mental tokens need be essential to its token identity. But certain counterfactual relationships such as the causal relationships a mental token can and can not bear to other role-occupiers is clearly the sort of physical, functional property that matters to its token identity. And, more broadly speaking, the larger web of causal and potential interactions that it is embedded in matters. At least, it matters from the perspective of a functionalism committed to the view that mental tokens are real causal actors. I submit that the realist must admit that the perfectly parallel subject PP has two sets of mental tokens with indistinguishable psychological properties at every moment. Granted, by offering a complete psychological characterization of one of PP’s hemispheres, you will have offered a complete characterization of PP’s other hemisphere as well, since PP’s two hemispheres possess the same mental architecture and all the same psychological properties. Nevertheless, a characterization of the structure of PP’s cognitive life would not be complete without the acknowledgment that there are in fact two of everything heretofore mentioned in this characterization: two of every type of mental state, two of every type of psychological process, two streams of consciousness, and two minds. Granted, you would never, by stipulation, see any evidence of these two sets of tokens with indistinguishable psychological properties in PP’s behavior.14 Granted a psychological theory for PP would therefore never have to mention the existence of two sets of mental states with indistinguishable mental properties in order to be empirically adequate with respect to even a single one of PP’s perfectly unified behaviors. Instrumentalists, therefore, need not recognize two such sets. But as Ramsey et al. (1990) point out, the realist commitment means that consistency with behavioral data isn’t all that is relevant to evaluating a functionalist story. Whether that functionalist story correctly identifies the events that actually caused the behavior is also relevant. I take it that scientific psychology isn’t just looking for the readily observable evidence for a thing, but for something more subtle, for the underlying causes of what we observe. (Putnam’s (1975) disease examples are still relevant here.) And (by stipulation) there are two sets of such causes in the perfectly parallel subject. There are two sets of neural events in PP, and each set of neural events meets the criteria for various types of mental state, and does so causally independently of the other. We should say that each set of neural events in PP constitutes a unique set of mental tokens, then, simply because each set of neural events does constitute a set of mental tokens. All that ultimately turns on the acceptance or rejection of the STR position with regard to our perfectly parallel subject, then, is realism itself. 14 Although surely you could see evidence for these two sets of mental states under certain counterfactual circumstances: if PP suffers a massive stroke to one entire hemisphere while giving a lecture, PP won’t pause mid-sentence for even a moment. But we are imagining that nothing of this sort ever happens, that PP’s two hemispheres in fact operate in perfectly parallel fashion throughout PP’s entire life. Philosophia When we set aside the fantastical case of PP, and imagine instead applying the STR model to any subject we will ever actually encounter, the stakes of the debate become sharper, more immediate. As I mentioned in “The Empirical Inadequacy of the Singularity-through-redundancy Characterization of Split-brain Consciousness” and “Purely Psychological Versus Partly Neural Constitutive Criteria for Mental Tokens”, the STR model of split-brain subjects is straightforwardly empirically inadequate. It is only by classifying mental phenomena very grossly—not the direction that a developing psychological science seems to be moving in—that one could claim that the two hemispheres are associated with psychologically redundant neural events. The hemispheres don’t have identical perceptual access to the world or to the body. They also aren’t identical with respect to their perceptual processing styles. They also aren’t identical with respect to their cognitive capacities. Indeed, the only way to make STR plausible as a characterization of the split-brain phenomenon is to not look very closely at it. And this is just what the STR position encourages: to ignore as merely “implementational” details that in fact matter from a psychological perspective. This is the creeping verificationism of the STR position, and realists must resist it. Defenders of the “singularity-through-redundancy” view might worry, however, that by attributing distinct mental tokens to PP’s two hemispheres, we actually lose something of explanatory value with respect to behavior: we lose an explanatory role for streams of consciousness to play. For now having a single stream of consciousness can’t be an explanation for unified behavior, and having multiple streams of consciousness can’t be an explanation for disunified behavior. But this misses the point that perfect parallelism would be extraordinary. To the degree that an overlap in conscious contents ever plays a role in producing unified behavior, then we should expect two streams of consciousness with identical contents to produce unified behavior. It is just that it is highly unlikely that two streams of consciousness with identical contents will ever exist, for reasons discussed at the beginning of this section. Conclusion Even if split-brain subjects had two hemispheres associated with highly similar or in fact identical conscious contents, this would not mean that such subjects had single streams of consciousness. Mental tokens are causal actors. Causally distinct mental actors—i.e. neural events that have psychological properties and that are causally independent in the strong sense described in “Is Causal Independence Psychologically Relevant?”—are distinct mental tokens. Well motivated functionalist principles give no reason to think otherwise. In fact, while functionalism says little about individuating tokens, a functionalism with realist commitments should use some physical properties to individuate mental tokens. Doing so respects the role that mental state types and contents play in functionalist explanations, and the status of mental tokens as causal actors. References Bogen, J. (1990). Partial hemispheric independence with the neocommissures intact. In C. Trevarthen (Ed.), Brain circuits and functions of the mind, pp. 215–230. London: Cambridge University Press. Philosophia Churchland, P. S. (1981). How many angels... ? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 103–104. Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gazzaniga, M. (2000). Cerebral specialization and interhemispheric communication: does the corpus callosum enable the human condition? Brain, 123, 1293–1326. Gazzaniga, M., & LeDoux, J. (1978). The integrated mind. New York: Plenum. Golledge, D., Hilgetag, C., & Tovée, M. (1996). Information processing: a solution to the binding problem. Current Biology, 6, 1092–1095. Green, M. (1981). May we forget our minds for the moment? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 107– 108. Grice, P. (1975). Method in philosophical psychology (from the banal to the bizarre). Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48, 23–53. Kingstone, A., & Gazzaniga, M. (1995). Subcortical transfer of higher order information: more illusory than real? Neuropsychology, 9, 321–328. Lockwood, M. (1989). Mind, brain and the quantum. Oxford: Blackwell. Margolis, J. (1981). Mental ascriptions and mental unity: Molar subjects, brains, and homunculi. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 110–111. Marks, C. (1980). Commissurotomy, consciousness, and unity of mind. Montgomery, Vermont: Bradford Books. Miller, M., & Kingstone, M. (2005). Taking the high road on subcortical transfer. Brain and Cognition, 57, 162–164. Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. O’Reilly, R., Busby, R., & Soto, R. (2003). Three forms of binding and their neural substrates: alternative solutions. In A. Cleeremans (Ed.), The unity of consciousness (pp. 168-190). Oxford University Press. Puccetti, R. (1981). The case for mental duality: evidence from split-brain data and other considerations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 93–123. Putnam, H. (1975). Mind language and reality: Philosophical papers, Vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Ramsey, W., Stich, S., & Garon, J. (1990). Connectionism, eliminativism, and the future of folk psychology. Philosophical Perspectives 4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind: 499–533. Rey, G. (1977). Survival. In A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons, pp. 41–66. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Rey, G. (1983). The lack of a case for mental duality. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 733–734. Robertson, L. (2003). Binding, spatial attention and perceptual awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 93–102. Schiffer, F., Zaidel, E. B., & Chasan-Taber, S. (1998). Different psychological status in the two hemispheres of two split-brain patients. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology, and Behavioral Neurology, 11, 151–156. Shallice, T. (1997). Modularity and consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan & G. Güzeldere (Eds.), The nature of consciousness, pp. 255–276. Cambridge, MA: MIT. Sperry, R. (1975). Mental phenomena as causal determinants in brain function. Process Studies, 5, 247– 256. Sperry, R., Zaidel, E., & Zaidel, D. (1979). Self recognition and social awareness in the deconnected minor hemisphere. Neuropsychologia, 17, 153–166. Treisman, A. (1996). The binding problem. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 6, 171–178. Treisman, A., & Gelade, G. (1980). A feature integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 97–136. Tye, M. (2003). Consciousness and persons. Cambridge, MA: MIT. Wiggins, D. (1977). In A. Rorty (Ed.), The identities of persons (pp. 139–174). University of California Press.