Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Structure Author(s): Arlie Russell Hochschild Source: American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 85, No. 3 (Nov., 1979), pp. 551-575 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2778583 . Accessed: 28/09/2011 17:11 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Journal of Sociology. http://www.jstor.org Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Structure ArlieRussellHochschild of California,Berkeley University perspectiveas a lens This essay proposesan emotion-management and structure.Emothroughwhichto inspectthe self,interaction, tion,it is argued,can be and oftenis subjectto acts of management. The individualoftenworkson inducingor inhibitingfeelingsso as to renderthem"appropriate"to a situation.The emotion-manageaccountof emotion.It difdrawson an interactive mentperspective perspectiveon the one hand and the fersfromthe dramaturgical perspectiveon the other.It allows us to inspectat psychoanalytic therelationamongemocloserrangethaneitherof thoseperspectives tive experience,emotionmanagement,feelingrules, and ideology. Feelingrulesare seenas theside of ideologythatdeals withemotion is thetypeofworkit takesto cope and feeling.Emotionmanagement jobs, morecommonin the midwithfeelingrules.Meaning-making dle class,put morepremiumon the individual'scapacityto do emoin child rearingsugof class differences tionwork.A reexamination gests that middle-classfamiliespreparetheirchildrenfor emotion familiespreparethemless. In moreand working-class management reproduce thisway each class preparesits childrento psychologically theclass structure. under the tacit assumptionthat emotion, Social psychologyhas suffered is not governedby social because it seemsunbiddenand uncontrollable, rules. Social rules,for theirpart, are seen as applyingto behaviorand thought,but rarelyto emotionor feeling.If we reconsiderthe natureof emotion2and the natureof our capacityto tryshapingit, we are struck linksemergeamongsocial by theimperialscope of social rules.Significant and emotiveexperience-links feelingrules,emotionmanagement, structure, I tryto tracein thisessay.The purposeis to suggestan area forinquiry. I This paper summarizespart of the argumentpresentedin a forthcoming book. This study has been generouslysupportedby a GuggenheimFellowship. Althoughgratitude in footnoteslike this is (as this paper demonstrates)conventionalized,and although conventionmakes authenticityhard to decipher,I want anyway to expressappreciation to Harvey Faberman,Todd Gitlin,Adam Hochschild,Robert Jackson,JerzyMichaelowicz, Caroline Persell, Mike Rogin, Paul Russell, Thomas Scheff,Ann Swidler, Joel Telles, and the anonymousreviewersfor the AIS. 2 I defineemotionas bodily cooperationwith an image,a thought,a memory-a cooperation of which the individualis aware. I will use the terms"emotion" and "feeling" interchangeably, although the term "emotion" denotes a state of being overcome that "feeling"does not. The term"emotion management"is used synonymously with "emotion work" and "deep acting." @) 1979 by The Universityof Chicago. 0002-9602/80/8503-0003$02.00 AJS Volume 85 Number3 551 AmericanJournalof Sociology Why is the emotiveexperienceof normaladultsin daily lifeas orderly as it is? Why,generallyspeaking,do people feel gay at parties,sad at funerals,happyat weddings?This questionleads us to examine,not conbutconventions offeeling. ventionsof appearanceor outwardcomportment, onlywhenwe imagine,by conConventions of feelingbecomesurprising emotivelifemightactually trast,what totallyunpatterned, unpredictable and in thefamilyor worklifeof norbe like at parties,funerals, weddings, mal adults. ErvingGoffman(1961) suggestsboth the surpriseto be explainedand willhold in check partof theexplanation:". . . We findthatparticipants certainpsychologicalstates and attitudes,forafterall, the verygeneral rule that one enterinto the prevailingmoodin the encountercarriesthe understanding thatcontradictory feelingswillbe in abeyance.... So genthatwe need to look at erally,in fact,does one suppressunsuitableaffect, offenses to thisruleto be reminded of its usual operation"(Goffman1961, p. 23). If we take thispassage seriously,as I urgewe do, we may be led back to theclassicquestionofsocialorderfroma particularvantagepointthatof emotionmanagement. Fromthisvantagepoint,rulesseemto govern how people tryor trynot to feelin ways "appropriateto the situation." Such a notionsuggestsbow profoundlythe individualis "social," and definitions of situations,with "socialized"to tryto pay tributeto official no less thantheirfeelings. Let me pause to pointout thatthereare twopossibleapproachesto the social orderingof emotiveexperience.One is to studythe social factors thatinduceor stimulateprimary(i.e., nonreflective, thoughby definition The otheris to study conscious)emotions-emotions passivelyundergone. streamofprimary secondaryactsperformed upontheongoingnonreflective emotiveexperience. The firstapproachfocuseson howsocial factorsaffect whatpeoplefeel,thesecondon howsocial factorsaffect whatpeoplethink and do about what theyfeel (i.e., acts of assessmentand management). Those who take thefirstapproachmightregardthosewho take thesecond as being"overlycognitive."But in factthetwoapproachesare compatible, and indeedthe second,takenhere,relieson someaccumulationof knowledgegarneredfromthefirst.3 If we takeas our objectof focuswhatit is peoplethinkor do aboutfeelFor comprehensive, if somewhatdated, reviewsof the theoreticalapproaches to emotion,see Hillman (1964), Carlson et al. (1959), Reymert(1950), and McDougall (1937). These reviews exclude several more recent theoreticalattemptsby Tomkins (1962), Arnold (1968), and Plutchik (1962). For a psychoanalyticaccount, see Rapaport (1953). Also see Rabkin (1968), Sprout (1952), Scheff(1973, 1977a, 1977b), Levy (1973), and Katz (1977). Various social scientistshave developed their approaches via inspection of a particular emotion or feeling,as for example, jealousy (Davis 1936; Clanton and Smith 1977), envy (Foster 1972), embarrassment(Goffman1956; Gross and Stone 1964), and love (Goode 1974; Swanson 1965). For a selectivereview see Hochschild (1975). 3 552 EmotionWork aboutemotion ings,severalquestionsemerge.First,withwhatassumptions is emotion and situationdo we begin?In otherwords,(a) how responsive to deliberateattemptsto suppressor evokeit? (b) What sociologicalapSecond,whatare thelinksamongsocial structure, proachis mostfruitful? To beginwith,(c) are ideology,feelingrules,and emotionmanagement? therefeelingrules? (d) How do we knowabout them?(e) How are these rulesused as baselinesin socialexchanges?(f) Whatin thenatureofwork waysadultsof varyingclasses and childrearingmightaccountfordifferent managetheirfeelings?I shall sketchoutlinesof possibleanswerswiththe thequestions. aim,in somemeasure,of refining TWO ACCOUNTS OF EMOTION AND FEELING In orderto addressthefirstquestion,we mightconsidertwobasic accounts account of emotionand feelingfoundin social psychology:the organismic in whattheyimply account.The twoapproachesdiffer and theinteractive aboutour capacityto manageemotion,and thusin whattheyimplyabout of rulesabout managingit. I cannotdo fulljusticehereto theimportance norcan I offera the questionof whatemotionis and how it is generated, on thatquestion. fullreactionto theampleliterature view,theparamountquestionsconcernthe Accordingto the organismic relationof emotionto biologicallygiven"instinct"or "impulse."In large part, biologicalfactorsaccountfor the questionsthe organismictheorist of SigmundFreud (1911, 1915a, 1915b; see Lofposes.The earlywritings gren 1968), CharlesDarwin ([1872] 1955), and in some thoughnot all respects,WilliamJames (James and Lange 1922) fit this model.4The concept"emotion"refersmainlyto stripsof experiencein whichthereis no conflictbetweenone and anotheraspectof self; the individual"floods out," is "overcome."The image that comesto mindis that of a sudden, 4 W. McDougall (1948) and, to some extent,S. S. Tomkins (1962) also fitthis classification.Both focuson the relationof emotionto drive or instinct(Tomkins elaborates a relation between emotion and "drive signals" wherebyemotion is said to amplify drive signals). The centralissues on which the two theoreticalcamps divide are fixity, reflexivity, and origin. (1) The organismictheorists,unlike their interactivecounterparts, assume a basic fixityof emotion,based in biological givens. (2) They assume that social interactiondoes not basically affectemotions; the social surface remains what is implied by the term"surface." In the interactiveaccount. this is not the case. Labeling, management,and expressionof feeling (more clearly differentiated by the interactionists)are processeswhich can reflexively "act back" on emotion,and indeed come to constitutewhat we mean by the term "emotion." (3) Again, the organismic theoristsare more concernedwith tracingemotionback to its origins.For Freud and James the originswere energicor somatic, and for Darwin, phylogenetic.The interactive theoristsare less concernedwith origin than with the interfaceof a situation and experience.The focus on originleads the organismictheoriststo focus on commonalitiesbetween differentpeoples, and between people and animals. The focus on social interfaceleads the interactioniststo focus on differences. For recentinnovations in the interactivetradition,see Kemper (1978) and Averill (1976). 553 AmericanJournalof Sociology Freud'stenautomaticreflexsyndrome-Darwin'sinstantsnarlexpression, sion dischargeat a givenbreakingpointof tensionoverload,Jamesand Lange's notionof an instantaneous unmediatedvisceralreactionto a perceived stimulus,the perceptionof which is also unmediatedby social influences. In thisfirstmodel,social factorscan enterin onlyin regardto howemotionsare stimulatedand expressed(and even here Darwin took the universalistposition) (see Ekman 1972, 1973). Social factorsare notseen as an influenceon how emotionsare activelysuppressedor evoked.Indeed, emotionis characterized by the fixityand universality of a knee-jerkreactionor a sneeze.In thisview,one could as easilymanagean emotionas one could managea kneejerk or a sneeze.If theorganismic theoristwere to be presentedwiththe conceptof feelingrules,he or she wouldbe hard put to elucidatewhat theserulesimpingeon, or whatcapacityof the self couldbe calledon to tryto obeya feelingrule (see Hochschild1977). Recentattemptsto linkan organismic notionof emotionto social structure, suchas Randall Collins's(1975) wonderfully bold attempt, fromthe suffer problemsthat were implicitin the organismicaccountto beginwith.By Collins,as by Darwinon whomhe draws,emotionsare seen as capacities (or susceptibilities) withina person,tobe automatically triggered, as Collins developsit, by one or anothergroupin controlof theritualapparatusthat does the "triggering"(1975, p. 59). A whollydifferent avenue of social control,thatof feelingrules,is bypassed,becausetheindividual'scapacity to tryto,or trynotto feel-that to whichtheruleapplies-is notsuggested by theorganismic modelwithwhichCollinsbegins. In the interactiveaccount,social influences permeateemotionmoreinsistently, moreeffectively, and at moretheoretically positediunctures.In large part,sociopsychological factorsaccountforthe questionsthe interactive theoristposes. The writingsof Gerthand MIills(1964), Goffman (1956, 1959, 1961, 1967, 1974), Lazarus (1966), La7arus and Averill (1972), Schachterand Singer(1962), Schachter(1964), Kemper(1978), Averill(1976). and aspectsof late Freudianand neo-Freudianthoughtfit thismodel.To invokethe Freudianvocabulary,theimagehereis not that of a "runawayid," but of an ego and superego,actingupon,shaping,nagging,howeverineffectively, temporarily, or consciously,the id.5 Emotion is sometimespositedas a psychobiological meansof adaptation-an ana5 The stresson will (included in the concept of ego, but not all that "earo"refersto) is not a clean divider of the organismicfrom the interactivetheorist.Schachterand Gerth and Mills, whom I see as membersof the interactivecamp, lay no particular stresson volition.Goffmanstressesthe phenomenathat call tacitlyforwill. He stresses the patternedresultsof it, but provides no theoreticalaccount of will itself.He posits no actor qua emotionmanagerwho mightaccomplishthe acts that,by inference,must get accomplishedto pull offthe encountershe describesso well. In my view, we must reinstitutea self capable of experiencingemotion and of working on it in socially patternedways. (On the issue of will,see Piaget in Campbell [1976]; Solomon [1973].) 554 EmotionWork such as shiveringwhencold or perlogue to otheradaptivemechanisms, fromtheseotheradaptivemechanisms, spiringwhenhot.But emotiondiffers subjectto theinand imagining--themselves perceiving, in that thinking, involved. fluenceof normsand situations-areintrinsically As in the firstmodel,social factorsaffecthow emotionsare elicitedand of expressed.However,in addition,social factorsguide the microactions labeling (Schachter1964; Schachterand Singer 1962; Katz 1977), in(Gerthand Mills 1964), and managingemotion(Lazarus 1966). terpreting in turn,reflectback on that whichis labeled,interThese microactions, to whatwe call "emotion" intrinsic preted,and managed.They are,finally, of thought,is seen as in second school this Emotion, 1976). (see Schafer moredeeplysocial. Lazarus's (1966) workin particularlends empirical weightto the interactivemodel. It suggeststhat normaladults,such as have a considerable university studentson whomhe conductedexperiments, one mightexpectfrom control than It is more emotion. capacityto control Freudin his all of which from or an animal, insane adult, a smallchild,an it is the emotive But since earlierwritingsand Darwin drewinspiration. would do well to we experienceof normaladults we seek to understand, account.6 beginwiththeinteractive The InteractiveAccountof Emotionand Social Psychology If emotionsand feelingscan to somedegreebe managed,howmightwe get The ina conceptualgraspof themanagingact froma social perspective? teractiveaccountof emotionleads us into a conceptualarena "between" designedappearanceson theone hand the Goffmanian focuson consciously eventson the other. and the Freudianfocuson unconsciousintrapsychic The focusof Mead (1934) and Blumer(1969) on conscious,active,and had not theirfocuson responsivegesturesmighthave been mostfruitful of feeling.(See obscuredtheimportance deeds and thoughtalmostentirely Shott [1979] foran attemptto consideremotionfroma symbolicinteractionistperspective.)The selfas emotionmanageris an idea thatborrows withneither. frombothsides-Goffmanand Freud-but squarescompletely focusing and departures, Here I can onlysketchout a fewbasic borrowings on thedepartures. ErvingGoffman Goffman guidesour attentionto social patternsin emotiveexperience.He theindividualis activelynegotiating catchesan irony:momentto moment, 6 My own account of emotiondraws on that proposed by Katz (1977). For Katz emotion is generatedby a "schematic discrepancy,"that is, a discrepancybetween the individual's schemata and his currentperception,memory,or imaginingof an event or object. Also see the interestingwork of Lazarus, Kanner, and Folkman (1979). 555 AmericanJournalof Sociology a courseof action,but in the long run,all the actionseemslike passive acquiescenceto social convention.The conserving of conventionis not a passivebusiness.Goffman's approachmightsimplybe extendedand deepenedby showingthatpeoplenot onlytryto conform outwardly, but do so inwardlyas well. "When theyissue uniforms, theyissue skins" (Goffman 1974) couldbe extended:"and twoinchesof flesh." Yet, ironically, to studywhyand underwhatconditions "participants ... hold in checkcertainpsychological states. . ." (Goffman1961,p. 23), we are forcedpartlyout of the perspective whichgave birthto the insight.I shall tryto showwhythisis so, whatthe remediesmightbe, and how the resultscould be conceptuallyrelated to aspects of the psychoanalytic tradition. First,Goffman, forreasonsnecessaryto his purpose,maintainsforthe mostparta studieddisregardforthelinksbetweenimmediatesocial situationsand macrostructure on the one hand,and individualpersonality on theother.If oneis interested in drawinglinksamongsocialstructure, feeling rules,and emotionmanagement, thisstudieddisregardbecomesa problem. Goffman's "situationism"is a brilliantachievement, one that mustbe understood as a development in theintellectual historyofsocialpsychology. Earlierin the centurya numberof classicworkslinkedsocial structure to or "dominantinstitutions"to "typical identities,"and thus personality, also relatedfindings in sociologyand anthropology to thosein psychology or psychoanalytic in theory.These studiesappeared a numberof fields-in Ruth Benedict (1946); in psychoanalysis, Erich Fromm anthropology, (1942), Karen Horney (1937), and Erik Erikson (1950); in sociology, David Riesman(1952, 1960), Swansonand Miller (1966), and Gerthand Mills (1964). Possiblyin responseto thisparadigmGoffman proposedan intermediate levelof conceptualelaboration, "between"social structure and personality. His focusis on situations,episodes,encounters. The situation,the episodically emergent encounter, is not onlynearlydivorcedfromsocial structure and frompersonality; he evenseemsto intendhissituationism as an analytic substitutefor these concepts (see Goffman1976, p. 77). Structure,he seemsto say,can be notonlytransposed but reduced"in and down,"while personality can be reduced"up and out" to thestudyofhere-now, gone-then interactional moments. Each interactional episodetakeson the characterof a minigovernment. A cardgame,a party,a greeting on thestreetexactsfromus certain"taxes" in the formof appearanceswhichwe "pay" forthesake of sustainingthe encounter. of safetyfromdisrepute.(Thanks We are repaidin thecurrency to HarveyFarbermanfordiscussionon thispoint.) This modelof the situationqua minigovernment, whileusefulforGoffman'spurposes,leads us away fromsocial structure and personality-two 556 EmotionWork conceptswithwhichany studyof feelingrulesand emotionmanagement wouldbe wise to deal.7To studywhyand underwhatconditions"participants ... hold in checkcertainpsychological states. . ." (Goffman1961, p. 23), we are forcedout of thehere-now, gone-then situationism and back, in part at least, to thesocial structure and personality model.We are led to appreciatethe importanceof Goffman's work,as it seemshe does not, as the criticalset of conceptualconnecting tissuesby whichstructure and personality, realin theirownright,are moreprecisely joined. if we are to understandthe originand causes of changein Specifically, "feelingrules"-this undersideof ideology-we are forcedback out of a studyof theimmediate situationsin whichtheyshowup, to a studyofsuch thingsas changingrelationsbetweenclassesor thesexes. If we are to investigatethe ways people try to manage feeling,we shall have to posit an actorcapable of feeling,capable of assessingwhen a feelingis "inappropriate," and capable of tryingto managefeeling.The problemis thatthe actorGoffman proposesdoes not seemto feelmuch,is not attunedto, does notmonitorcloselyor assess,does notactivelyevoke, inhibit,shape-in a word,work on feelingsin a way an actorwouldhave to do to accomplishwhat Goffman says is, in fact,accomplishedin one encounterafteranother.We are leftknowingabout "suppressivework"as a finalresult,but knowingnothingof the processor techniquesby which it is achieved.If we are to argue thatsocial factorsinfluencehow we try to managefeelings, if we are to carrythe social that far,we shallhave to carryour analyticfocusbeyondthe "black box" to whichGoffman ultimatelyrefersus. Goffman'sactors activelymanage outer impressions, but theydo not activelymanageinnerfeelings.For example,a typicalGoffmanian actor, Preedyat the beach (Goffman1959), is exquisitelyattunedto outward appearance,but his glances inward at subjectivefeelingare fleeting and blurred.The very topic, sociologyof emotion,presupposesa human capacity for,if not the actual habit of, reflecting on and shaping innerfeelings,a habit itselfdistributed variouslyacross time,age, class, and locale. This variationwoulddrop fromsightwerewe to adopt an ex7Time: to link the momentaryact of emotion work with the concept of personality, we must alter our perspectiveon time. An emotive episode and the attemptto shape it is, afterall, a briefstrip of time. Situationssuch as Goffmanstudies are also short. The focus is on the act, and the act ends, so to speak, when the theatercloses and starts again when it reopens. If we extend Goffman'sanalysis, by speaking now of "deep" acting, we, like him, are focusingon short episodes, on "stills" from which long movies are composed. The notion of personalityimplies a fairlydurable, transsituationalpattern.The Casper Milquetoast personalitymay lead an anxietyavoidant life of 73 years. Not momentarystills, but many decades are at issue. Again, we must shift our situationistfocus at the structuralend when we come to speak of institutions,which live even longer than people do. 557 AmericanJournalof Sociology clusivefocuson the actor'sattentiveness to behavioralfacadeand assume a uniform passivityvis-a-visfeelings. This skewin the theoretical actoris relatedto whatfrommyviewpoint is anotherproblem:Goffman's conceptof acting.Goffman suggeststhatwe spenda gooddeal of effort managingimpressions-that is, acting.He posits only one sortof acting-the directmanagement of behavioralexpression. His illustrations, though,actuallypointto twotypesof acting-the direct management of behavioralexpression(e.g., thegiven-off sigh,theshoulder shrug),and the management of feelingfromwhichexpressioncan follow (e.g., the thoughtof some hopelessproject). An actor playingthe part of King Lear mightgo about his task in two ways. One actor,following the Englishschoolof acting,mightfocuson outwarddemeanor,the constellationof minuteexpressionsthat correspondto Lear's sense of fear and impotentoutrage.This is the sortof actingGoffman theorizesabout. Anotheractor,adheringto theAmericanor Stanislavskyschoolof acting, mightguide his memoriesand feelingsin such a way as to elicitthe corresponding expressions. The firsttechniquewe mightcall "surfaceacting," the second"deep acting."Goffman fails to distinguishthe firstfromthe second,and he obscuresthe importance of "deep acting."Obscuringthis, we are leftwiththeimpression thatsocial factorspervadeonlythe"social skin,"the tried-for outerappearancesof theindividual.We are leftunderestimating thepowerof the social. In sum,if we are to accept the interactiveaccountof emotionand to about the studythe selfas emotionmanager,we can learnfromGoffman linkbetweensocial ruleand feeling.But to elaboratethisinsightwe might well selectivelyrelax the theoreticalstricturesGoffman has stoicallyimand on personality. posed againsta focuson social structure Freud "black-boxpsychology"withsome theory The need to replaceGoffman's of self,in thefullsenseof theterm,mightseemto lead to Freudianor neoFreudian theory.Yet, here,as with Goffman, only some aspects of the Freudianmodelseem usefulto my understanding of conscious,deliberate efforts to suppressor evoke feeling.I shall brieflydiscusspsychoanalytic theoryto showsomepointsof departure. Freud, of course,dealt with emotions,but forhim theywere always secondaryto drive.He proposeda generaltheoryof sexualand aggressive drives.Anxiety,as a derivativeof aggressiveand sexual drives,was of while a wide rangeof otheremotions,including paramountimportance, weregivenrelativelylittleattention.He develjoy, jealousy,depression, oped,and manyothershave sinceelaborated,the conceptof ego defenses as generallyunconscious,involuntary means of avoidingpainfulor un558 EmotionWork pleasantaffect.Finallythenotionof "inappropriate affect"is used to point to aspectsof the individual'sego functioning and not used to pointto the social rulesaccordingto whicha feelingis or is notdeemedappropriateto a situation. The emotion-management perspective is indebtedto Freudforthegeneral notionof what resourcesindividualsof different sortspossess foraccomplishingthetaskof emotionwork(as I have definedit) and forthenotion ofunconscious involuntary emotionmanagement. The emotion-management perspective differs fromtheFreudianmodelin its focuson thefullrangeof emotionsand feelingsand its focuson consciousand deliberateefforts to shape feeling.Fromthisperspective, we notetoo that"inappropriate emotion"has a clearlyimportant socialas wellas intrapsychic side. Let me briefly illustratethedifferences betweenthetwoperspectives. In Shapiro'swell-known workon "neuroticstyle,"he givesan example: An obsessive-compulsive mindedand active patient-a sober,technically man-was usuallyconspicuouisly in lackingin enthusiasm or excitement circumstances thatmightseemto warrant them.On one occasion,as he talkedabouta certain thegoodchanceof an imof his,namely, prospect successin his work,his soberexpression was momentarily portant interruptedby a smile.Aftera fewmoreminutes of talking, duringwhichhe hissoberness maintained onlywithdifficulty, he beganquitehesitantly to speakof certain hopesthathe had onlyalludedto earlier.Thenhe broke intoa grin.Almostimmediately, he regained however, hisusualsomewhat worried expression. As he didthis,he said,"Of course,theoutcomeis by no meanscertain," andhe saidthisin a tonethat,if anything, wouldsuggestthe outcomewas almostcertainto be a failure.Aftertickingoff severalof the specific possibilities fora hitch,he finallyseemedto be himself again,so to speak.[Shapiro1965,p. 192,emphasis mine] What seemsinteresting about thisexamplediffers accordingto whether one takes the psychiatricperspectiveor the emotion-management perspective.First,to the psychiatrist in the case above, what circumstances warrantwhat degreeand type of feelingseemsrelativelyunproblematic. A doctor"knows"what inappropriate affectis; the main problemis not so much to discernmisfitsof feelingto situationbut to explain them and to cure the patient of them. From the emotion-management perspective,on the otherhand, the warrantingfunctionof circumstances is problematic. Further,the meansused to assess thiswarranting function may well be the same for a psychiatristas for a salesclerkor school disciplinarian.For, in a sense we all act as lay psychiatrists using unexaminedmeansof arrivingat a determination about just "what" circumstanceswarrant"that much"feelingof "that sort." What the psychiatrist, the salesclerk,and the schooldisciplinarian may shareis a habitof comparing, situation(e.g., highopportunity, associated with an accomplishment at work) withrole (e.g., hopes,aspirations,ex559 AmericanJournalof Sociology pectationstypicalof, and expectedfrom,thoseenactingthe role). Social factorscan enterin, to alterhow we expecta role to be held,or played. mindedand active" If, forexample,thepatientwerea "sober,technically womanand if the observer(rightlyor wrongly)assumedor expectedher to value familyand personalties overworldlysuccess,less enthusiasmat "appropriate."Lack of enthe prospectof advance mightseem perfectly thusiasmwould have a warrantof that social sort.Again,if the patient fornuclear was an antinuclearactivistand his discoveryhad implications energy,thatwould alter the hopes and aspirationshe mightbe expected to have at workand mightwarrantdismay,not enthusiasm. of a feelingby makinga comparison We assess the "appropriateness" betweenfeelingand situation,not by examiningthe feelingin abstracto. This comparisonlends the assessor a "normal" yardstick-a socially normalone-from which to factorouit the personal meaningsystems whichmay lead a workerto distorthis view of "the" situationand feel inappropriately with regard to it. The psychiatristholds constantthe sociallynormalbenchmark and focuseson whatwe have just factoredout. The studentof emotionmanagement holds constantwhat is factoredout and studiesthe sociallynormalbenchmark, especiallyvariationsin it. in what,fromthe twoperspectives, seems There is a seconddifference perspecinteresting in the above example.Fromthe emotion-management tive,whatis interesting is the characterand directionof volitionand conwhat is of moreinterestis sciousness.From the psychiatricperspective, The man above is not doingemotionwork, pre-willand nonconsciousness. thatis, makinga conscious,intendedtryat alteringfeeling.Insteadhe is his enthusiasmby "being himself,"by holding,in Schutz's controlling term,a "naturalattitude."He "no longerneeds to strugglenot to grin; he is not in a grinningmood" (Shapiro 1965, p. 164). In orderto avoid affective deviance,someindividualsmayfacea hardertask thando others, thetaskof consciously workingon feelingsin orderto makeup for"a natural attitude"-explanablein psychoanalyticterms-that gets themin social trouble.The hysteric workingin a bureaucratic settingmayface the necessityformoreemotionworkthantheobsessivecompulsivewho fitsin more naturally. In sum, the emotion-management perspectivefostersattentionto how how people tryto appear to feel. people tryto feel,not,as forGoffman, It leads us to attendto howpeopleconsciouslyfeeland not,as forFreud, The interactiveaccountof emotionpoints how people feelunconsciously. to alternatetheoreticaljunctures-betweenconsciousnessof feelingand consciousnessof feelingrules,betweenfeelingrules and emotionwork, betweenfeelingrulesand social structure. In the remainderof thisessay, it is thesejunctureswe shallexplore. 560 EmotionWork EMOTION WORK to changein degreeor quality By "emotionwork"I referto theact oftrying an emotionor feeling.To "workon" an emotionor feelingis, forour purposes,the same as "to manage"an emotionor to do "deep acting."Note that"emotionwork"refersto theeffort-theact of trying-and notto the outcome,whichmay or may not be successful.Failed acts of management and on thataccount stillindicatewhatideal formulations guidethe effort, are no less interesting thanemotionmanagement thatworks. feeling. The verynotionof an attemptsuggestsan activestancevis-'a-vis In my exploratory characterized theiremotionworkby studyrespondents a varietyof activeverbforms;"I psychedmyselfup.... I squashedmy angerdown.. . . I triedhardnot to feeldisappointed.. . . I mademyself have a good time.. . . I triedto feelgrateful.. . . I killedthehope I had burning."There was also the activelypassive form,as in, "I let myself finallyfeelsad." Emotionwork differsfromemotion"control"or "suppression."The merelyto stifleor preventfeeling."Emolattertwotermssuggestan effort tionwork"refersmorebroadlyto theact of evokingor shaping,as wellas suppressing, feelingin onself.I avoid the term"manipulate"because it suggestsa shallownessI do notmeanto imply.We can speak,then,of two broad typesof emotionwork:evocation,in whichthecognitivefocusis on in whichthe a desiredfeelingwhichis initiallyabsent,and suppression, cognitivefocusis on an undesiredfeelingwhichis initiallypresent.One the respondent, goingout with a priest20 years her senior,exemplifies problemsof evocativeemotionwork: "Anyway,I startedto tryand make myselflike him.I made myselffocuson theway he talked,certainthings he'd donein thepast.... WhenI was withhimI did likehimbut I would go homeand writein my journalhow muchI couldn'tstandhim. I kept changingmy feelingand actuallythoughtI reallyliked him wlhileI was withhimbuta coupleofhoursafterhe was gone,I reverted back to different exemplifies the work,not of working feelings...."8 Anotherrespondent feelingup, but ofworkingfeelingdown: Last summerI was goingwitha guyoften,and I beganto feelvery thathe had just brokenup witha strongly abouthim.I knewthough, 8 The illustrationsof emotion work come from a content analysis of 261 protocols given to students in two classes at the Universityof California, Berkeley,in 1974. Many of the illustrationscome fromanswers to the question, "Describe as fullya,nd concretelyas possible a real situation,importantto you, in which you experienced eitherchanginga real situation to fit your feelingsor changingyour feelingsto fita situation.What did it mean to you?" Three coders coded the protocols.The findings will be reportedin a later study. I will only mentionhere that 13% of the men but 32% of the women were coded as "changing feeling"instead of changingsituation, and of those who changed feelings,far more women reported doing so agentially rather than passively. 561 AmericanJournalof Sociology girla yearago becauseshe had gottentoo seriousabouthim,so I was I alsowasafraidofbeinghurt,so I attempted afraidto showanyemotion. I talked myselfinto not caringabout Mike . . . to changemyfeelings. butI mustadmitit didn'tworkforlong.To sustainthisfeelingI had to almostinventbad thingsabout him and concentrateon themor continue to tell myselfhe didn't care. It was a hardeningof emotions,I'd say. It a lot of workand was unpleasant, on tookbecauseI had to concentrate I couldfindthatwas irritating abouthim. anything Oftenemotionworkis aided by settingup an emotion-work system,for example,tellingfriendsof all theworstfaultsof thepersonone wantedto fall out of love with,and thengoingto thosefriendsforreinforcement of thisviewof theex-beloved.This suggestsanotherpoint: emotionworkcan be done by the selfupon the self,by the selfupon others,and by others upon oneself. In each case theindividualis consciousof a momentof "pinch,"or discrepancy,betweenwhat one does feeland whatone wantsto feel (which is, in turn,affected by whatone thinksoneoughtto feelin sucha situation). In response,the individualmay tryto eliminatethe pinchby workingon feeling.Both the sense of discrepancyand the responseto it can varyin time.The managingact,forexample,can be a five-minute stopgapmeasure, orit can be a morelong-range gradualeffort suggested by theterm"working through." Thereare varioustechniquesof emotionwork.One is cognitive: the attemptto changeimages,ideas; or thoughtsin the serviceof changingthe feelingsassociatedwiththem.9A secondis bodily: the attemptto change somaticorotherphysicalsymptoms ofemotion(e.g.,trying to breatheslower, tryingnot to shake). Third,thereis expressive emotionwork: trying to changeexpressivegesturesin theserviceof changinginnerfeeling(e.g., fromsimpledisplayin that it is tryingto smile,or to cry). This differs directedtowardchangein feeling.It differs frombodilyemotionworkin thattheindividualtriesto alteror shapeone or anotheroftheclassicpublic channelsforthe expressionof feeling. Thesethreetechniques aredistincttheoretically, buttheyoften,ofcourse, in practice.For example: go together 9 There may be various types of cognitive emotion work. All can be described as attemptsto recodifya situation.By recodificationI mean reclassification of a situation into what are previouslyestablishedmental categoriesof situations.As in an initial, more automaticcodificationof a situation,deliberaterecodification means asking onself (a) What categoryin my classificationschema of situationsfits this new situation? (the schema may include blame-insituations,blame-outsituations,credit-insituations, credit-outsituations,etc.), and (b) What categoryin my classificationschema of emotions fitsthe emotion I'm feelingrightnow? (i.e., is it anger, general anxiety,disappointment?). In deliberate recodifications,one tries to change the classificationof outward and inward reality. (To translate this idea into Lazarus's framework,we might speak of the individual tryingconsciously to alter his or her appraisal of a situationso as to change the coping process [Lazarus 1966].) 562 EmotionWork in highschool.BeforegamesI didn'tfeeltheupI was a starhalfback up." (This was due to surgeof adrenalin-ina word I wasn't"psyched and stillexperience-Iwas also I was experiencing difficulties emotional an A studentwhosegradesweredropping.) Havingbeen in the past a intense by coachesas a player,a "hitter"recognized emotional, fanatical, I veryhardworkerand a playerwith"desire,"thiswas veryupsetting. I could to get myself"uip." I would try to be outwardly did everything "rah rah" or get myselfscared of my opponents-anythingto get the I triedto looknervousand intensebeforegames,so at adrenalin flowing. bored, catchon.... WhenactuallyI wasmostly leastthecoacheswouldn't I was in the or in anyevent,not"up." I recallbeforeonegamewishing mycousinplayforhis school,ratherthan"outhere." standswatching Emotionworkbecomesan objectof awarenessmostoften,perhaps,when the individual'sfeelingsdo not fitthe situation,that is, when the latter feelings in thesituation.A situation(such doesnotaccountforor legitimate of itself("this is a as a funeral)oftencarrieswithit a properdefinition framecarrieswithit a senseofwhatit is timeof facingloss"). This official amongsituaconsistency to feel (sadness). It is whenthistripartite fitting tion,conventionalframe,and feelingis somehowruptured,as when the at the thought desireto laugh delightedly bereavedfeelsan irrepressible comeintofocus.It is thenthat of an inheritance, thatruleand management themorenormalflowof deep convention-themorenormalfusionof situation,frame,and feeling-seemslikean accomplishment. the unsecretary, The smoothlywarmairlinehostess,the ever-cheerful the teacherwho irritatedcomplaintclerk,the undisgustedproctologist, unflappablepokerplayermay likes everystudentequally,and Goffman's all have to engagein deep acting,an actingthatgoeswellbeyondthemere withsituaorderingof display.Workto makefeelingand frameconsistent engage.But they andprivately tionis workin whichindividualscontinually do so in obeisanceto rulesnotcompletely of theirownmaking. FEELING RULES We feel.We tryto feel.We wantto tryto feel.The social guidelinesthat directhow we want to tryto feelmay be describableas a set of socially shared,albeitoftenlatent(not thoughtabout unlessprobedat), rules.In knownand howare they whatway,we mayask, are theserulesthemselves developed?10 10 That we can single out such a thing as "feelingrules" is itselfa commentaryon the ironic posture of the self legitimatedin modern culture. Modern urban cultures fostermuch more distance (the stance of the observingego) from feelingthan do traditional cultures. Jerzy Michaelowicz, a graduate student at the University of California,San Diego, observed that traditionaland tight-knitsubculturesput people directlyinside the frameworkof feelingrules and remove ironic distance or sense of choice about them. He reportedon some researchin which one Hassidic rabbi was asked, "Did you feel happy at the Passover ceremony?" "Of course!" came the incredulous reply. 563 AmericanJournalof Sociology To beginwith,let us considerseveralcommonformsof evidencefor or those feelingrules.In commonparlance,we oftentalkaboutour feelings For example,we of othersas if rightsand dutiesapplieddirectlyto them. oftenspeak of "havingthe right"to feelangryat someone.Or we say we "should feel moregrateful"to a benefactor.We chide ourselvesthat a friend'smisfortune, a relative'sdeath,"shouldhave hit us harder,"or that another'sgood luck,or our own,shouldhave inspiredmorejoy. We know feelingrules,too,fromhowothersreactto whattheyinferfromouremotive display.Anothermay say to us, "You shouldn'tfeel so guilty;it wasn't yourfault,"or "You don't have a rightto feeljealous, givenour agreement."Anothermay simplydeclarean opinionas to the fitof feelingto situation,or may cast a claim upon our managerialstance,presupposing this opinion.Othersmay questionor call foran accountof a particular feelingin a situation,whereastheydo not ask foran accountingof some othersituatedfeeling(Lymanand Scott 1970). Claimsand callingsforan accountcan be seen as rule reminders. At othertimes,a personmay,in addition,chide,tease,cajole, scold,shun-in a word,sanctionus for"misfeeling."Such sanctionsare a clue to the rulestheyare meantto enforce. as to the extent(one can feel Rightsand dutiesset out theproprieties "too" angryor "not angryenough"),thedirection(one can feelsad when one shouldfeelhappy), and the durationof a feeling,giventhesituation againstwhichit is set. These rightsand dutiesof feelingare a clue to the to one finalreachof socialcontrol. depthof social convention, in theoryat least,betweena feelingruleas it is There is a distinction, knownby our senseof whatwe can expectto feelin a givensituation,and a ruleas it is knownby oursenseof whatwe shouldfeelin thatsituation. For example,one mayrealistically expect(knowingoneselfand one'sneighbor's parties) to feelboredat a large New Year's Eve partyand at the Howsametimeacknowledge thatit wouldbe morefitting to feelexuberant. ever,"expectto feel"and "shouldideallyfeel"oftencoincide,as below: in manywaysthanI imagdifferent Marriage, chaos,unreal,completely of our weddingat eight ined.Unfortunately we rehearsed the morning o'clock.The wedding was to be at eleveno'clock.It wasn'tlikeI thought wouldknowwhatto do). Theydidn't.Thatmademe nervous. (everyone me (nordidanyonein the My sisterdidn'thelpmegetdressedor flatter I wantedto be so roomuntilI askedthem).I was depressed. dressing day.I neverdreamed howanyonewouldcryat their happyonourwedding A wedding is "thehappyday" of one'slife.I couldn'tbelieve wedding. thatsomeof mybestfriends couldn'tmakeit to mywedding and that addedto a lot oflittlethings. andall these So I started outto thechurch thatI alwaysthought wouldnothappenat mywedding wentthrough things mymind.I brokedown-I criedgoingdown."Be happy"I toldmyself. Thinkof thefriends, (But I finally said to and relatives thatarepresent. married, you are. It's forRich [my myself, "Hey peoplearen'tgetting longaislewe lookedat each husband]andyou.") Fromdownthepretty 564 EmotionWork other'seyes. His love for me changedmy whole being. From that point on we joined arms.I was relievedand the tensionwas gone. In one sense it meantmisery-but in the truesense of two people in love and wanting to share life-it meant the world to me. It was beautiful.It was indescribable. In any given situation,we ofteninvestwhat we expect to feel with idealization.To a remarkableextenttheseidealizationsvary socially.If the"old-fashioned bride"above anticipatesa "right"to feeljealous at any possiblefutureinfidelity, the young"flowerchild" below rejectsjust this right. . . .when I was livingdown south,I was involvedwitha groupof people, friends.We used to spend most eveningsafterwork or school together. We used to do a lot of drugs,acid, coke or just smoke dope and we had this philosophythat we were very communaland did our best to share everything-clothes, money,food,and so on. I was involvedwiththis one man-and thoughtI was "in love" withhim.He in turnhad told me that I was very importantto him. Anyway,this one woman who was a very good friendof mine at one time and this man startedhaving a sexual relationship, supposedlywithoutmy knowledge.I knewthoughand had a lot of mixedfeelingsabout it. I thought,intellectually, thatI had no claim to the man,and believedin fact that no one shouldever try to own anotherperson.I believedalso thatit was none of mybusinessand I had no reasonto worryabout theirrelationship together,forit had nothingreally to do withmy friendship witheitherof them.I also believedin sharing. But I was horriblyhurt,alone and lonely,depressedand I couldn'tshake the depressionand on top of those feelingsI feltguiltyforhavingthose possessivelyjealous feelings.And so I would continuegoingout withthese people everynight,and tryto suppressmy feelings.My ego was shattered. I got to the pointwhereI couldn'teven laugh around them.So finallyI confronted my friendsand left for the summerand traveledwitha new friend.I realizedlater what a heavy situationit was, and it took me a longtimeto get myselftogetherand feel wholeagain. Whetherthe conventioncalls fortryingjoyfullyto possess, or tryingcasually not to, the individual compares and measures experience against an expectationoftenidealized. It is leftformotivation ("what I want to feel") to mediate between feelingrule ("what I should feel") and emotion work ("what I tryto feel"). Some of the time many of us can live with a certain dissonance between "ought" and "want," or between "want" and "try to." But the attempts to reduce emotive dissonance are our periodic clues to rules of feeling. A feeling rule shares some formal properties with other sorts of rules, such as rules of etiquette, rules of bodily comportment,and those of social interaction in general (Goffman 1961). A feeling rule is like these other kinds of rules in the followingways: It delineates a zone withinwhich one has permission to be free of worry,guilt, or shame with regard to the situated feeling.Such zoning ordinances describe a metaphoricfloorand ceil- 565 AmericanJournalof Sociology ing,therebeingroomformotionand play betweenthetwo.Like otherrules, feelingrulescan be obeyedhalfheartedly or boldlybroken,the latterat varyingcosts.A feelingrulecan be in varyingproportions externalor internal.Feelingrulesdiffer curiouslyfromothertypesof rulesin thatthey do not apply to actionbut to whatis oftentakenas a precursorto action. Therefore theytendto be latentand resistantto formalcodification. Feelingrulesreflectpatternsof social membership. Some rulesmay be nearlyuniversal,such as therulethatone shouldnot enjoykillingor witnessingthe killingof a humanbeing,includingoneself.1"Otherrulesare unique to particularsocial groupsand can be used to distinguish among themas alternategovernments or colonizersofindividualinternalevents. FRAMING RULES AND FEELING RULES: ISSUES IN IDEOLOGY Rules formanagingfeelingare implicitin any ideologicalstance; theyare the"bottomside" of ideology.Ideologyhas oftenbeenconstrued as a flatly cognitiveframework, lackingsystematicimplicationsforhow we manage feelings, or, indeed,forhowwe feel.Yet, drawingon Durkheim(1961),12 Geertz(1964), and in parton Goffman (1974), we can thinkof ideologyas an interpretive framework thatcan be describedin termsof framing rules and feelingrules.By "framing rules"I referto therulesaccordingto which we ascribedefinitions or meaningsto situations.For example,an individual can definethesituationofgettingfiredas yetanotherinstanceofcapitalists' abuse of workersor as yet anotherresultof personalfailure.In each case, theframemayreflect a moregeneralruleaboutassigning blame.By "feeling rules"I referto guidelinesforthe assessmentof fitsand misfitsbetween feelingand situation.For example,accordingto one feelingrule,one can be legitimately angryat the boss or company;accordingto another,one cannot.Framingand feelingrulesareback to backand mutuallyimplyeach other. 11 But this,too. seems to be culturallyvariable. Erving Goffmanpoints out that hangings in the 16th centurywere a social event that the participantwas "supposed to enjoy," a rule that has since disappeared in civilian society. 12 Durkheim, in The ElementaryForms of Religious Life, conveys just this understandingof the relation of world view to feelingrules: "When the Christian,during the ceremoniescommemoratingthe Passion, and the Jew, on the anniversaryof the fall of Jerusalem,fast and mortifythemselves,it is not in giving way to a sadness which they feel spontaneously.Under these circumstances,the internal state of the believeris out of all proportionto the severe abstinencesto which theysubmit themselves. If he is sad, it is primarilybecause he consentsto beingsad. And he consentsto it in order to affirmhis faith" (Durkheim 1961, p. 224). Again, "An individual . . . if he is stronglyattached to the societyof which he is a member,feels that he is morally held to participatingin its sorrows and joys; not to be interestedin them would be equivalent to breakingthe bonds unitinghim to the group; it would be renouncing all desire for it and contradictinghimself"(1961, p. 446, emphasesmine). 566 EmotionWork It followsthatwhenan individualchangesan ideologicalstance,he or she dropsold rulesand assumesnewones forreactingto situations, cognitivelyand emotively.A sense of rightsand dutiesapplied to feelingsin and acsituationsis also changed.One uses emotionsanctionsdifferently fromothers.For example,feelingrulesin Amerisanctioning ceptsdifferent can societyhave differed formen and womenbecause of the assumption bringswithit a movement basically.The feminist thattheirnaturesdiffer new set of rulesforframingtheworkand familylifeof menand women: the same balance of prioritiesin workand familynow ideallyapplies to men as to women.This carrieswithit implicationsforfeeling.A woman can nowas legitimately (as a man) becomeangry(ratherthansimplyupset or disappointed)over abuses at work,sinceherheartis supposedto be in thatworkand she has therightto hope,as muchas a manwould,foradvancement. Or, a manhas therightto feelangryat thelossofcustodyifhe has shownhimselfthe fitterparent."Old-fashioned"feelingsare now as perspectives subjectto new chidingsand cajolingsas are "old-fashioned" on thesame arrayof situations. an alternaOne can defyan ideologicalstancenotsimplyby maintaining an alternativeset of feeling tive frameon a situationbut by maintaining rightsand obligations.One can defyan ideologicalstanceby inappropriate necessaryto feel affectand by refusing theemotionmanagement to perform to feel.Deep what,accordingto the officialframe,it would seem fitting ideologiobeisance to a given can be a form of work, then, actingor emotion cal stance,lax emotionmanagement a clue to an ideologylapsedor rejected. sets As some ideologiesgain acceptanceand othersdwindle,contending of feelingrulesrise and fall.13Sets of feelingrulescontendfora place in standardwithwhichto comparethe actual people'smindsas a governing lived experienceof, say, the seniorprom,the abortion,the wedding,the thedivorce.Whatwe call "the changing birth,thefirstjob, thefirstlayoff, of the "same" sorts climateof opinion"partlyinvolvesa changedframing of events.For example,each of twomothersmay feelguiltyabout leaving hersmallchildat day care whileworkingall day. One mother,a feminist, mayfeelthatshe shouldnot feelas guiltyas she does. The second,a traditionalist,may feelthatshe shouldfeelmoreguiltythan,in fact,she does feel. Part of what we referto as the psychologicaleffectsof "rapid social change,"or "unrest,"is a changein the relationof feelingrule to feeling and and a lack of clarityaboutwhattheruleactuallyis, owingto conflicts 13 Collins suggeststhat ideologyfunctionsas a weapon in the conflictbetweencontending elites. Groups contend not only for access to the means of economic production or the means of violence but also for access to the means of "emotion production" (1975, p. 59). Rituals are seen as useful tools for forgingemotional solidarity (that can be used against others) and for settingup status hierarchies(that can dominate those who findthat the new ideals have denigratingeffectson themselves). 567 AmericanJournalof Sociology sets of rules.Feelingsand framesare betweencontending contradictions We may,like themarbut notyet reconventionalized. deconventionalized, ginalman,say, "I don'tknowhowI shouldfeel." as RandallCollinsrightly It remainsto notethatideologiescan function, elitesand social betweencontending notes( 1975), as weaponsin theconflict strata.Collinssuggeststhatelitestryto gain access to the emotivelifeof adherentsby gaininglegitimate access to ritual,whichforhimis a formof emotivetechnology. Developinghis view,we can add thatelites,and indeed social groupsin general,struggleto assertthe legitimacyof theirframing rules and theirfeelingrules. Not simplythe evocationof emotionbut laws governingit can become,in varyingdegrees,the arena of political struggle. FEELING RULES AND SOCIAL EXCHANGE The seemingly staticlinksamongideology,feelingrules,and emotionmanagementcome alive in the processof social exchange.Studentsof social interaction have meanttwo thingsby the term"social exchange."Some to theexchangeof goodsand servicesbetweenpeople (Blau have referred 1964; Simpson1972; Singelmann1972). Others(G. H. Mead) have reaccountingreferredto an exchangeof gestures,withoutthe cost-benefit "exferredto in thefirstusage.Yet acts of display,too,maybe considered changed"in the limitedsense that the individualveryoftenfeelsthat a gestureis owed to oneselfor another.I refer,then,to exchangeof acts of of patternedentitlement. displaybased on a prior,sharedunderstanding Any gesture-a cool greeting,an appreciativelaugh, the apologyfor an outburst-is measuredagainsta priorsense of what is reasonablyowed another,giventhe sortof bond involved.Againstthis backgroundmeasure,somegestureswillseemmorethanample,othersless. The exchangeof gestureshas, in turn,two aspects; it is an exchangeof displayacts (Goffman1969,1967)-that is, of surfaceacting-and also an exchangeof emotionwork-that is, of deep acting.In eithercase, rules (displayrulesor feelingrules),once agreedupon,establishtheworthof a gestureand are thusused in socialexchangeas a mediumofexchange.Feeling rulesestablishthebasis of worthto be ascribedto a rangeof gestures, includingemotionwork.Emotionworkis a gesturein a social exchange; it has a functionthereand is not to be understoodmerelyas a facetof personality. Thereseemto be twowaysin whichfeelingrulescomeintoplay in social exchange.In the first,the individualtakes the "owed" feelingto heart, takesit seriously.For example,a youngwomanon the eve of her college graduationfeltanxiousand depressedbut thoughtthatshe "oughtto feel happy," and that she "owed this happiness"to her parentsformaking 568 EmotionWork her graduationpossible.The parentsfeltentitledto a seriesof gestures indicatingher pleasure.The younggraduatecould "pay" her parentsin emotivedisplay,a surfaceactingdissociatedfromher "real" definition of the situation.Goingone step further, she could pay themwitha gesture of deep acting-of tryingto feel.The mostgenerousgestureof all is the act of successfulself-persuasion, of genuinefeelingand framechange,a deep actingthatjells, thatworks,thatin theend is notphony(since it is whattheemotionis) thoughit is nonetheless nota "natural"gift. The secondway feelingrulescomeintoplay in exchangeis shownwhen the individualdoes not take the affective convention seriously;he or she plays withit. For example,an airportobservation:There are two airline ticketagents,one experienced, one newon thejob. The newagentis faced withthetaskof rewriting a complexticket(involvingchangeofdate,lower fare,and creditof the difference betweenthepreviousand presentfareto be made towardan air travelcard,etc.). The newticketagentlooksforthe "old hand,"whois gone,whilethecustomers in lineshiftposturesand stare intentlyat the new agent.The "old hand" finallyreappearsafter10 minutes,and the following conversation takesplace: "I was lookingforyou. You're supposedto be my instructor." Old hand: "Gee," withan ironic smile,"I am reallysorry.I feelso bad I wasn'there to help out" (they both laugh). The inappropriate feeling(lack of guilt,or sympathy)can be playeduponin a way thatsays,"Don't takemynonpayment in emotion work,or display workpersonally.I don't want to work here. You can understand that."The laughterat an ironicdistancefromtheaffective conventionsuggestsalso an intimacy;we do notneedtheseconventions to hold us together. Whatwe shareis thedefianceof them. COMMODITIZATION OF FEELING In the beginning we asked how feelingrulesmightvaryin salienceacross social classes.One possibleapproachto thisquestionis via theconnections amongsocial exchange,commoditization of feeling,and the premium,in manymiddle-class jobs,on thecapacityto managemeanings. Conventionalized feelingmay come to assumethe propertiesof a commodity.When deep gesturesof exchangeenterthe marketsectorand are boughtand sold as an aspect of labor power,feelingsare commoditized. Whenthemanagergivesthecompanyhis enthusiastic faith,whentheairline stewardessgivesher passengersher psyched-upbut quasi-genuine rewhatis sold as an aspectoflaborpoweris deep acting. assuringwarmth, But commoditization of feelingmaynothave equal salienceforall social classes.It mayhave moresalienceforthemiddleclass thanfortheworking class. The way each class socializesits childrenmay,furthermore, prepare themforfuturedemandsfortheskillof emotionmanagement. 569 AmericanJournalof Sociology WhenI speakofsocialclass,it is not strictly speakingto income,education,or occupationalstatusthatI refer, butto something roughly correlated to these-the on-the-jobtaskof creatingand sustainingappropriate meanings.The bankmanager,theIBM executive,forexample,maybe required, in part,to sustaina definition of self,office, and organization as "up and coming,"or "on thego," "caring,"or "reliable,"meaningsmosteffectively sustainedthroughacts upon feeling.Feelingrulesare of utmostsalience in jobs such as these; rule remindersand sanctionsare more in play. It is not,as ErichFrommsuggests, thatthemodernmiddle-class man"sells his personality," but that,moreprecisely,manyjobs call foran appreciationof displayrules,feelingrules,and a capacityfordeep acting. Working-class jobs more oftencall for the individual'sexternalbehaviorand theproductsof it-a car partassembled,a truckdelivered500 milesaway,a road repaired.The creationand sustaining of meaningsgoes on, but it is not such an important aspectof work.Physicallaboris more commoditized, meaning-making and feeling,less. Surely,too, thereare or lower-class workingjobs thatdo requirethecapacityto sustainmeanings and to do so, whennecessary, by emotionwork;thejobs of prostitute(ElmerPascua,workin progress)and personalservantrequirefeelingmanagement.But to theextentthatmeaning-making worktendsto be middle-class work,feelingrulesare moresalientin themiddleclass. or airlinestewardess, Thereare jobs,likethatofsecretary withrelatively low financialrewardsand littleauthority, whichnonetheless requirea high degreeof emotionand displaymanagement. Such jobs are oftenfilledby women,manyof whomcomefromthemiddleclass. Suchworkersare especially important as a sourceof insightabout emotionmanagement. Being less rewardedfortheirworkthan theirsuperiors,theyare morelikelyto feeldetchedfrom,and be perceptiveabout,the rulesgoverning deep acting. Deep actingis less likelyto be experiencedas part of the self and morelikelyto be experienced as partof thejob. Justas we can learnmore about "appropriatesituation-feeling fits"by studyingmisfits,so too we can probablyunderstand commoditized feelingbetterfromthoseforwhom it is a salientformof alienation(see Kanter's[1977] excellentchapterson secretaries). CLASS, CHILD REARING, AND EMOTION WORK Middle-and working-class parentstendto controltheirchildrenin different ways (Kohn 1963, 1969; Bernstein1971). Given the generalpatternof each class tendsto prepareits childrenwiththe skills class inheritance, and to pass on class-appronecessaryto "its" typeof workenvironment priateways. Middle-classparentstendto controlvia appeals to feeling,and thecon570 EmotionWork trolis moreof feeling.14 The working-class parent,by contrast,tendsto controlvia appeals to behavior,and thecontrolis moreof behaviorand its consequences(Kohn 1963; Bernstein1971). That is, themiddle-class child is morelikelyto be punishedfor"feelingthewrongway,or seeingthings in thewronglight,"or havingthe"wrongintention," whereastheworkingclass child is morelikelyto be punishedforwrongbehaviorand its consequences.The class difference in socializationamountsto different degrees of trainingforthecommoditization of feeling.This is yetanotherway the class structure reproduces itself.(Thanksto CarolinePersellforthispoint.) It maywell be that,especiallyamongthemiddleclass,a corresponding value is now placed on "authenticity," on thingsas they"trulyare" or "once were."Authenticity, whichLionelTrillinghas describedas the"new moralvirtue,"whenit refersto unworked-over feeling,may be rendered scarceforthosein themeaning-making sector.For thissector,thepattern may be that of conventionalizing feeling,puttingit on the market,and lookingfor"authenticity" (see Trilling1972).15 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION Why,we asked at the beginning, do we feel in ways appropriateto the situationas muchof thetimeas we do? One suggestedansweris: because we activelytryto managewhatwe feelin accordancewithlatentrules.In orderto elaboratethissuggestion we consideredfirstthe responsiveness of emotionto acts of management as it is treatedin theorganismic and interactiveaccountof emotion.Accordingto theinteractive account,we are not 14 As Kohn comments,". . . middle class mothersare far more likely to punish their son physicallyfor what they call loss of temper than for behavior definedas wild play. They appear to findthe child's loss of temper,but not his wild play, particularly intolerable" (1963, p. 308). Again, ". . . The interviewreportsindicate that the distinctionbetween wild play and loss of temperwas most often made in termsof the child's presumedintent,as judged by his precedingactions . . . if his actions seemed to stem fromthe frustrationof not having his own way, theywere judged to indicate loss of temper" (Kohn 1963). 15 Accordingto Trilling,the place of "sincerity,"as a moral virtue, has been taken (Trilling'sverb is "usurped") by "authenticity."Sincerityrefersto the relationbetween innerfeelingand outward display. Trillingoffersmany definitionsof authenticity, but one seems to referto the relationbetween the self as emotion managerand the inner feelingsso managed.He citesWordsworth'spoem "Michael" about a veryold shepherd: "When Michael, afterhaving lost his son Luke to the corruptionof the city,continues to build the sheepfold which he and the boy had ceremoniallybegun together,his neighborsreportof him that sometimeshe sat the whole day, 'and never liftedup a single stone"' (1972, p. 93). There is no act of self upon feeling; he is not psyching himself"up" or "down," he is not "lettinghimself"feel grief,or deliberately"getting into" his grief.It is on thisaccount called "authentic,"and deemed nowadays valuable. What now ironicallyunderminesauthenticity,as a virtue,is the cultural beliefin the mutabilityof inner feelingand the individual's capacity, with therapeuticguidance or otherwise,via "emotion work" or otherwise,to change fundamentallywhat is not implacablyascribed afterall. 571 AmericanJournalof Sociology floodof feeling,and thoseoccaalwayspassivevis-a-visan uncontrollable sionalefforts to activelyshape our feelingcan sometimes be effective. Taking thisaccountI beganto articulatetheemotion-management perspective firstby distinguishing it fromthe dramaturgical perspectiveon the one hand and the psychoanalytic perspectiveon the other.I thensuggested some links amongemotiveexperience,deep acting,and feelingrules. In turn,feelingruleswereseen as the bottomside of ideologyand therefore subjectto thesamepressuresforchangeas are ideologies. of feeling(i.e., what one is supposedto feel) are used in Conventions social exchangebetweenindividuals.Individualsoperatetheirexchanges accordingto a priorsense of what is owed and owing.Individualssee themselves as beingowedand as owinggesturesof emotionwork,and they exchangesuch gestures.People bond,in the emotivesense,eitherby fulfillingthe emotiverequirements situationscall forth(e.g., the graduate to one side tryingto feel happy) or by holdingjust theserequirements (the ironicticketagentacknowledging thesincerefeeling"due" theother evenwhileplayingwiththatnotionof debt). Justas gesturesof emotionworkcan be exchangedin private,so they can be exchangedin the marketplace,as an aspect of what is sold and boughtas laborpower.In such a case we can speak of the "commoditization" of emotionwork.This prevailsmoreforworkerswhosejob it is to make and sustainmeanings(e.g., "this is an up-and-coming company"; "this is a pleasant,safe airplane")-jobs foundmorein the middleclass. Commoditization is less salient for those in physicallabor or nonsocial mentallabor,morecommonin theworkingclass. A reexamination of class in childrearingsuggeststhatmiddle-class familiespreparetheir differences childrenforemotionmanagement familiesless. Each, more,working-class in this way, preparesits childrento psychologically reproducethe class structure. The emotion-management perspectivecan be applied to any numberof areas. We know littleabout how feelingrules vary in contentfromone occupationto another.The funeralparlordirector,the doctor,the complaintsclerk,the day-careworkerall apply a sense of "should" to the situated feelingsthat emergein the course of a week. How do these "shoulds"differ?Crosscutting occupationaland class differences, theyare likelyto exhibitculturaldifferences associatedwithgenderand ethnicity. Indeed,a goodplace to studychangein feelingruleswouldbe thestrataof is extendedover personsforwhomtherightof mento cry,or feelfearful, a greaterrangeof situations,and forwhomthe rightof womento open zone. How has this set of angeris extendedover a larger,sanction-free, offeminist feelingrules,as theunderside ideology,alteredtheunderstanding betweenmen and womenas to what feelingsare latently"owed" and "owing"? We need to ask how different sexes, classes, and ethnicand 572 EmotionWork religiousgroupsdifferin the sense of what one "ought to" or "has the rightto" feelin a situation.How different is the burdenof hiddenwork tryingto obey latent laws? Finally,in whose interestare these feeling rules?Some managingof feelingpromotesthesocial good. Some does not. Surelytheflightattendant'ssensethatshe "shouldfeelcheery"does more to promoteprofitforUnitedthanto enhanceherowninnerwell-being. REFERENCES Arnold,Magda B. 1968. The Nature of Emotion. Baltimore: Penguin. Averill,James R. 1976. "Emotion and Anxiety: Sociocultural,Biological, and Psychological Determinants."Pp. 87-130 in Emotion and Anxiety: New Concepts,Methods and Applications,edited by M. Zuckermanand C. D. Spielberger.New York: Wiley. Benedict,Ruth. 1946. Patternsof Culture.New York: Penguin. Bernstein,Basil. 1971. Class, Codes and Control.New York: Schocken. Blau, Peter. 1964. Exchange and Power in Social Life. New York: Wiley. Blumer, Herbert. 1969. Symbolic Interactionism:Perspectiveand Method. Englewood Cliffs,N.J.: Prentice-Hall. Campbell,Sarah, ed. 1976. The Piaget Sampler. New York: Wiley. Carlson, Anton J., et al. 1959. Feelings and Emotions: The Mooseheart Symposium. New York: McGraw-Hill. Clanton, Gordon,and Lynn G. Smith. 1977. Jealousy.Englewood Cliffs,N.J.: PrenticeHall. Collins, Randall. 1975. ConflictSociology.New York: AcademicPress. Darwin, C. (1872) 1955. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals.New York: PhilosophicalLibrary. Davis, Kingsley.1936. "Jealousy and Sexual Property."Social Forces 14:395-410. Durkheim,Emile. 1961. The ElementaryForms of theReligiousLife. New York: Collier. Ekman, P. 1972. "Universals and Cultural Differencesin Facial Expressionsof Emotion." Pp. 207-83 in Nebraska Symposiumon Motivation 1971, editedby J. K. Cole. Lincoln: Universityof Nebraska Press. , ed. 1973. Darwin and Facial Expression.New York: AcademicPress. Erikson,Eric. 1950. Childhood and Society.New York: Norton. Foster, George M. 1972. "The Anatomy of Envy: A Study in Symbolic Behavior." CurrentAnthropology13:165-202. Freud, Sigmund. 1911. "Formulationsregardingthe Two Principlesin Mental Function." Pp. 13-21 in Collected Papers. Vol. 4. New York: Basic. . 1915a. "Repression."Pp. 146-58 in StandardEdition. Vlol. 14. London: Hogarth Press. . 1915b. "The Unconscious." Pp. 177-79 in Standard Edition. Vol. 14. London: Hogarth Press. Fromm, Erich. 1942. Escape fromFreedom. New York: Farras & Rinehard. Geertz,Clifford.1964. "Ideology as a Cultural System." Pp. 49-76 in The Interpretation of Cultures.London: Hutchinson. Gerth, Hans, and C. WrightMills. 1964. Character and Social Structure: The Psychology of Social Institutions.New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Goffman,Erving. 1956. "Embarrassmentand Social Organization."AmericanJournal of Sociology 62 (November): 264-71. . 1959. The Presentationof Self in Everyday Life. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday. 1961. "Fun in Games." Pp. 17-84 in Encounters.Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. 1967. InteractionRitual Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday. 1969. StrategicInteraction.Philadelphia: Universityof PennsylvaniaPress. 1974. Frame Analysis.New York: Harper & Row. 573 AmericanJournalof Sociology . 1976. "Gender Advertisements."Studies in the Anthropologyof Visual Communication,vol. 3, no. 2 (Fall). Goode, William. 1974. "The Theoretical Importance of Love." Pp. 143-56 in The Family, Its Structureand Functions,edited by Rose Coser. New York: St. Martin's. Gross, F., and G. P. Stone. 1964. "Embarrassmentand the Analysisof Role Requirements."AmericanJournalof Sociology 70 (July): 1-15. Hillman, James. 1964. Emotion: A ComprehensivePhenomenologyof Theories and Their Meanings for Therapy. Evanston, Ill.: NorthwesternUniversityPress. Hochschild,Arlie Russell. 1975. "The Sociologyof Feelingand Emotion: SelectedPossibilities." Pp. 280-307 in Another Voice, edited by Marcia Millman and Rosabeth Moss Kanter. New York: Anchor. . 1977. "Reply to Scheff."CurrentAnthropology18, no. 3 (September): 494-95. Horney,Karen. 1937. The NeuroticPersonalityof Our Time. New York: Norton. James,William,and Carl B. Lange. 1922. The Emotions.Baltimore: Williams& Wilkins. Kanter, Rosabeth. 1977. Men and Women of the Corporation.New York: Basic. Katz, Judith. 1977. "Discrepancy, Arousal and Labelling: Towards a Psycho-Social Theory of Emotion." Mimeographed.Toronto: York University. Kemper,Thomas D. 1978. "Toward a Sociological Theory of Emotion: Some Problems and Some Solutions."AmericanSociologist13 (February): 30-41. Kohn, Melvin. 1963. "Social Class and the Exerciseof Parental Authority."Pp. 297-313 in Personalityand Social Systems,edited by Neil Smelserand William Smelser.New York: Wiley. -. 1969. Class and Conformity.Homewood, Ill.: Dorsey. Lazarus, Richard S. 1966. Psychological Stress and the Coping Process. New York: McGraw-Hill. Lazarus, Richard S., and JamesR. Averill.1972. "Emotion and Cognition: With Special Referenceto Anxiety."Pp. 242-83 in Anxiety: CurrentTrends in Theory and Research,edited by D. C. Spielberger.Vol 2. New York: AcademicPress. Lazarus, Richard S., Allen D. Kanner,and Susan Folkman. 1979. "Emotions: A CogniAnalysis."In Theories of Emotion, edited by R. Plutchikand tive-phenomenological H. Kellerman.New York: AcademicPress,in press. Levy, Robert I. 1973. Tahitians,Mind and Experiencein the Society Islands. Chicago: Universityof Chicago Press. Lofgren,L. Borge. 1968. "PsychoanalyticTheory of Affects."Journal of the American PsychoanalyticAssociation16 (July): 638-50. Lyman, S., and Marvin Scott. 1970. Sociology of the Absurd. New York: AppletonCentury-Crofts. McDougall, W. 1937. "Organization of the AffectiveLife: A Critical Survey." Acta Psychologica2:233-46. . 1948. An Outline of Psychology.12th ed. London: Methuen. Mead, A. H. 1934. Mind, Self and Society,edited by Charles Morris. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Plutchik,Robert. 1962. The Emotions: Facts, Theoriesand a New Model. New York: Random House. Rabkin, Richard. 1968. "Affectas a Social Process." AmericanJournal of Psychiatry 125 (December): 772-79. Rapaport, D. 1953. "On the PsychoanalyticTheory of Affects."InternationalJournal of Psycho-Analysis34:177-98. Reymert,Martin, ed. 1950. Feelings and Emotions: The Mooseheart Symposium.New York: McGraw-Hill. Riesman,David. 1952. Faces in the Crowd: Individual Studiesin Characterand Politics. New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress. . 1960. The Lonely Crowd: A Study of the ChangingAmericanCharacter.New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress. Schachter,Stanley. 1964. "The Interactionof Cognitiveand PhysiologicalDeterminants of Emotion States." Pp. 138-73 in PsychobiologicalApproaches to Social Behavior, edited by P. H. Leiderman and D. Shapiro. Stanford,Calif.: Stanford University Press. 574 EmotionWork Schachter,S., and J. Singer. 1962. "Cognitive,Social and PhysiologicalDeterminants of Emotional State." PsychologicalReview 69:379-99. Schafer,Roy. 1976. A New Language for Psychoanalysis.New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress. and Emotion." AmericanBehavioral Scientist Scheff,Thomas J. 1973. "Intersubjectivity 16 (March-April): 501-22. . 1977a. "The Distancingof Emotion in Ritual." CurrentAnthropology18, no. 3 (September): 483-91. . 1977b. "Toward a Sociology of Emotion." Mimeographed. Santa Barbara: Universityof California. Shapiro, David. 1965. NeuroticStyles.New York: Basic. Shott, Susan. 1979. "Emotion and Social Life: A Symbolic InteractionistAnalysis." AmericanJournalof Sociology 84 (May 1979): 1317-34. Simpson,Richard. 1972. Theoriesof Social Exchange. Morristown,N.J.: GeneralLearning Press. Singelmann,Peter. 1972. "Exchange as Symbolic Interaction: Convergencesbetween Two TheoreticalPerspectives."AmericanSociological Review 37 (4): 414-24. Solomon, Robert. 1973. "Emotions and Choice." Review of Metaphysics27 (7): 20-41. Sprout,W. J. H. 1952. Social Psychology.London: Methuen. Swanson, Guy E. 1965. "The Routinizationof Love: Structureand Process in Primary Relations." Pp. 160-209 in The Quest for Self-Control: Philosophiesand Scientific Research,edited by Samuel Z. Klausner. New York: Free Press. Swanson, Guy E., and Daniel Miller. 1966. Inner Conflictand Defense. New York: Schocken. Tomkins,S. S. 1962. Affect,Imagery,Consciousness.2 vols. New York: Springer. Trilling,Lionel. 1972. Sincerityand Authenticity.Cambridge,Mass.: Harvard University Press. 575