VIDYĀ AND AVIDYĀ: SIMULTANEOUS AND COTERMINOUS? — A HOLOGRAPHIC MODEL TO ILLUMINATE THE ADVAITA DEBATE Stephen Kaplan Department of Religious Studies, Manhattan College Certainly the most crucial problem which Śaṅkara left for his followers is that of avidyā. If the concept is logically analyzed, it would lead the Vedānta philosophy toward dualism or nihilism and uproot its fundamental position. Sengaku Mayeda1 Avidyā is the fundamental existential problem and the fundamental philosophical/ theological problem within Advaita Vedānta. On the one hand, it is the cause of rebirth, samsāra, and the evil that exists within the world.2 Remove ignorance and one ˙ will realize that ātman is Brahman. It is also the crucial philosophical issue within Advaita thought. Advaita need not explain why a perfect deity was motivated to create the world, nor why an all-loving God created a world with evil. Ultimately, for Advaita, there is no creation, nor any God (Īśvara) who creates the world.3 The highest truth is that there is no birth, no death, no change (ajātivāda). The highest truth is Brahman, one without a second, the true self, ātman. This nondual ātman/ Brahman is pure consciousness (caitanya), the witness consciousness (sāksin), con˙ sciousness without qualities (nirviśesa cinmatram), self-illuminating consciousness ˙ (svaprakāśa).4 Śaṅkara tells us: ‘‘Just as darkness does not exist in the sun, since it has light as its nature, so there is no ignorance in Ātman, since It has constant knowledge as Its nature. Likewise, as the nature of Ātman is changeless, It has no change of state, for if It had any change of state, Its destruction would certainly occur.’’ 5 This notion of ātman/Brahman presents a serious philosophical challenge to Advaita Vedānta, namely, it demands that one explain how all (reality) can be undivided, unchanging, and pure consciousness, yet appear to be everything but nondual, unchanging, and pure consciousness. The Advaita answer is avidyā, ajñāna (ignorance). This answer tells us that Brahman does not really change; it is only ignorance that makes it appear to change. The duality imposed upon ātman/ Brahman is no more real than the snake that is imagined in the famous rope-snake illusion. Any pretense that the notion of avidyā resolves the philosophical quagmires concomitant with the idea of nonduality (advaita) and non-origination (ajāti) is facile even for the Advaitin stalwart.6 Nonetheless, Advaitins have continuously tried to present avidyā in intelligible ways. These efforts may be said to raise at least as many questions as they answer.7 For introductory purposes, the list of questions raised by Advaitins and their opponents may be summarized as follows. If Brahman 178 Philosophy East & West Volume 57, Number 2 April 2007 178–203 > 2007 by University of Hawai‘i Press is everywhere and pure consciousness, from where does avidyā come? If Brahman is partless, how can avidyā be a part of Brahman? If avidyā is not a part of Brahman, is it all of Brahman? Or, if avidyā is not a part of Brahman, is it other than Brahman? If Brahman is the real, is avidyā unreal? If it is unreal, how can it have any effect? If it is neither real nor unreal, then what is it and what is its locus (āśraya) and its content (visaya)? If the locus of avidyā is ātman, how can that which is pure consciousness ˙ nondual be the locus of that which obscures pure consciousness and nondualand ity? If the locus of avidyā is the jı̄va, then how can the effect of ignorance—namely, the jı̄va—be the locus of ignorance? These are serious philosophical questions that Advaitins have historically asked themselves and that critics have asked Advaitins. However, when all the logical disputations are stripped to their essentials and all the polemics are dispersed, I believe that this problem can be boiled down to the following: how can vidyā and avidyā be simultaneous and coterminous? How can Brahman be both pure, self-illuminating consciousness and have ignorance appear with it? Explaining how pure consciousness and avidyā could be sequential or how vidyā and avidyā could exist in different places would hardly pose as difficult a problem. However, either the notion that cit and avidyā are sequential or the notion that they exist in separate ‘‘locations’’ would completely destroy the fundamental tenets of Advaita’s nondualism. There is only Brahman. Therefore, given Advaita’s nondualism, consciousness and ignorance must be simultaneous and coterminous. But how can this be? A good deal of Advaita Vedānta philosophizing has been engaged in trying (1) to answer this question and its variants and (2) to declare that this question is in fact no question since vidyā and avidyā are not really contraries.8 On the one hand, the attempts to answer this question have led to the polemical divide between the Bhāmatı̄ and the Vivarana schools of Advaita. On the other hand, the attempts to ˙ deny the legitimacy of these questions have been attacked by opponents of Advaita, who see the doctrine of avidyā riddled with contradictions. In both cases, Advaitins have spent an enormous amount of energy wrestling with opponents, real and selfconstructed, over the nature of avidyā and its relation to ātman, Brahman, pure consciousness. Analogies such as the rope-snake analogy, the dreamer-dream analogy, the silver-shell analogy, the crystal-red flower analogy, and the space and space-of-thepot analogy have been invoked to illustrate how ignorance and ātman can be simultaneous and coterminous. Advaitins such as Padmapāda tell us that the success of these analogies is not to prove their point but to ‘‘assist the pramānas by removing ˙ doubts that may arise.’’ 9 Some would contend that these analogies have been successful; others would argue that they are as bankrupt as the nondualist position that they are attempting to illuminate. Karl Potter, with reference to the rope-snake analogy, wonders if a more sophisticated analogy is available: [W]hat becomes free, Brahman or the self? I.e., is the rope in the model analogous to Brahman or to the individual self? We need an analogy which explains a three-way relation—among Brahman, self, and world. How can we use the epistemological model of illusion, which presupposes the existence of a knower and a known, to throw light on Stephen Kaplan 179 the relation among Brahman, a knower, and the known? A more sophisticated analogy seems to be called for.10 I will argue that the contemporary world provides us with a new and maybe ‘‘more sophisticated’’ way to illuminate some aspects of this Advaita quagmire. The new analogy will allow us to focus on the nature of Brahman. While Brahman is the subject of most of the questions asked above, the analogies employed to answer these questions shift, as Potter notes, away from addressing the nature of Brahman and its relation to the knower and the known. These analogies shift to an emphasis on the epistemological problem of the presence of avidyā—to the presence of illusory images such as the snake or the mirage. The artifacts employed in these analogies do not provide insight into the nature of Brahman. They do not focus on the nature of Brahman as a pure, unchanging, self-illuminating consciousness that simultaneously appears with ignorance. Rhetorically speaking, the dreamer is not changeless, the sandy soil is not partless, and the moon is not self-illuminating. The rope is not partless, unchanging, or self-illuminating. As such, these analogies, while extremely valuable in certain regards, are neither intended nor useful in illuminating the nature of Brahman and how Brahman can be sat and cit, and yet avidyā appears to us. The analogy that will be offered in this essay is based on holography, the technique by which one can produce three-dimensional optical artifacts from a film that has no images. We will see that holography has some truly fascinating characteristics that will help illuminate this philosophical issue that has plagued Advaita since its inception. Its strength as an analogy lies precisely in its ability to illuminate the nature of Brahman; other analogies have different strengths. Holography presents us with two domains, one of which mirrors our fourdimensional world and one in which there exists no subject-object duality. In this second domain each part contains the whole, and multiple images may be stored in the same location without any trace of even a single image. This second domain, with its extremely unique characteristics, will provide us with the parallels to the nature of ātman/Brahman. While the reality element in all the other analogies—the rope, the silver, et cetera—mimic the nature of ordinary, dualistic existence, this second domain—specifically, the hologram—is radically different. Its simultaneous, coterminous existence with holographic images will provide us with a heuristic model that can mirror the alleged simultaneous and coterminous existence of cit and avidyā. The success of this model to illuminate an aspect of the Advaita quagmire will not establish the truth of the Advaita concept, nor is it meant to denigrate the value of the other analogies. Rather, I believe holography can serve as a powerful and unique tool for illuminating some parts of a vexing problem within Advaita thought. Before proceeding any further, and rather than waiting until the last page, I will now present the conclusion to this essay. Simply stated, this analogy ultimately fails. Holography with its two domains can serve not only as a model for the unchanging ātman/brahman, not only as a model for the notion that there is only one Self, which is pure consciousness and Being, and not only as a model for how vidyā 180 Philosophy East & West and avidyā can be simultaneous and coterminous, but also simultaneously it can serve as a model that can represent a process, anātma, śūnyatā view of ultimate reality. An explanation of this alternative position in light of the holographic model is certainly beyond the confines of this essay. This comment is only intended to highlight the failure of this model to exclusively illuminate the Advaita Vedānta position. This analogy works for both this ātmavāda position and an anātmavāda position simultaneously. The analogy ultimately fails because it not only does what the Advaitins need, but it does more than the Advaitins want. The remainder of this essay will show how this model illuminates the Advaita position, knowing that this model illuminates not only this position.11 The Basic Doctrine and the Problem In what follows I will not review all the intricacies of the Advaita position on avidyā, nor will I examine all the details of the debates internal to Advaita that fractured this school into two camps. Furthermore, while the charges and countercharges made by rival schools of Indian philosophy, both orthodox and nonorthodox, are a fascinating window into the history of Indian philosophizing, the following review of this subject will be limited. Some material from each of these three areas will be presented as background material for understanding the alleged dilemma of the simultaneous and coterminous existence of vidyā and avidyā. I will begin with an overview of the Advaita notion of avidyā in order to present the dilemma with which Advaitins have been wrestling. As a testament to the importance of the notion of avidyā, Śaṅkara opens his bhāsya to the Brahma Sūtra with a discussion of avidyā. Here he defines ignorance ˙ as adhyāsa (imposition). In general, adhyāsa is the projecting of the characteristics of one thing upon another. ‘‘It is an awareness, similar in nature to memory, that arises on a different (foreign) basis as a result of some past experience.’’ 12 Śaṅkara adds: This superimposition, that is of this nature, is considered by the learned to be avidyā, nescience. And the ascertainment of the nature of the real entity by separating the superimposed thing from it is called vidyā (illumination). This being so, whenever there is a superimposition of one thing on another, the locus is not affected in any way either by the merits or demerits of the thing superimposed. All forms of worldly and Vedic behaviour that are connected with valid means of knowledge and objects of knowledge start by taking for granted this mutual superimposition of the Self and non-Self, known as nescience; and so do all the scriptures dealing with injunction, prohibition, or emancipation.13 This mutual imposition of the not-self and the self is the root of all distinctions, and as such, no cause can be asserted since all cause implies such distinctions. Hence, avidyā is, for Advaitins, beginningless. It is the innate epistemological disposition of the individual to see difference and diversity, to bifurcate the world into subject and object (grāhaka and grāhya), of me and not-me—asmat and yumat.14 The individual sees diversity and does not know ātman/Brahman. The individual Stephen Kaplan 181 imposes upon the true self the characteristics of the unconscious material world— namely, body and mind—and obscures the pure-consciousness nature of the true self. The true self (ātman) is never an object of knowledge; it is always the pure witness consciousness, eternal, unchanging, infinite, without parts. Avidyā is said to have two powers or functions.15 It has both a concealing nature (āvaranaśakti) and a projecting nature (viksepaśakti). As the words indicate, the ˙ ˙ former is associated with the capacity to obscure the nature of ātman/Brahman; it is the non-apprehension aspect of avidyā (agrahana). Brahman as pure conscious˙ ness is self-illuminating (svaprakāśa)—needing no other source of consciousness/ illumination by which it knows or is known. Avidyā conceals the svaprakāśa nature of Brahman from the individual as a small bit of cloud can obscure the sun from an observer.16 The projecting power of ignorance is that which presents the diversity of appearances. It is the power associated with the presentation of the snake in the rope-snake analogy.17 This is the misapprehension aspect of avidyā (viparyayagrahana). Advaitins also employ the examples of dreaming and dreamless sleep to illus˙ trate these two powers. In the dream state, the dreamer projects the dream characters, and the nature of the true self is obscured. In the third state of consciousness, dreamless sleep, there is no projection of characters; however, the true state of the self, the ātman, is obscured by sleep.18 These two powers may operate together as in waking or they may be separated as in dreamless sleep. These two powers are also said to be separated for Īśvara, the lord. Īśvara is omniscient (sarvajñā) and does not suffer from the concealing nature of avidyā, but is associated with the projecting nature of avidyā. The latter presents the world to the jı̄vas. Sarvajñātman expresses the distinction between Īśvara and the jı̄vas as follows: ‘‘God, being free from the superimposition of the intellect and being unconcealed by avidyā, is omniscient and his knowledge is not veiled. But the knowledge of the individual soul is veiled by avidyā and hence the individual soul is ignorant.’’ 19 Attributing two powers to avidyā may help to explain how it functions, but this leads to one of the problems noted above, namely, whether these two powers of avidyā are real powers. If they are real powers, then is there another reality in addition to ātman/Brahman? Clearly, Advaitins cannot tolerate such a notion; Brahman is one without a second. However, if avidyā is not a real power, then how can it have any effect? How can it cause bondage?20 The Advaita response to the horns of this dilemma is not to choose either side: avidyā is not real (sat) nor is it unreal (asat). The real is Brahman; it is, by definition, that which never undergoes change, that which always is. On the other hand, the unreal is that which has no existence, such as the barren woman’s son or the footprints of birds in the sky.21 Avidyā fits neither of the categories above. Therefore, Advaita Vedānta declares that avidyā is anirvacanı̄ya— literally, indescribable, unutterable. Ontologically, it is that which is experienced but which cannot be described as either being or nonbeing.22 Again, the Advaitin returns to the rope-snake illusion to say that the snake is not existent, nor is it nonexistent like a sky-flower, but it is definitely an object of experience. One sees the snake and one reacts in fear to the snake that is experienced. Mandana Miśra ˙˙ states: 182 Philosophy East & West Avidyā is not the essence of Brahman, nor another thing; not absolutely nonexistent, nor existent. It is just for this reason that [it] is called ‘nescience’ (avidyā), ‘illusion’ (māyā), ‘false appearance’ (mithyāvabhāsa). If it were the essence of anything, whether different or not different (from it), it would be ultimately real, and therefore not avidyā. If it were absolutely non-existent, it would not enter into practical activity any more than a skyflower. Therefore, it is inexpressible (tasmād anirvacanı̄yā).23 While avidyā is neither sat nor asat, it is nonetheless said to be a positive entity (bhāvarūpa). R. Balasubramanian tells us: Anavabodha or ajñāna (also called avidyā), which means ignorance, is not a negative entity, but something positive (bhāvarūpa). What is negative cannot be the cause of anything. Since ajñāna is the cause of all evil, it is something positive.24 Sureśvara employs the term amitra, enemy—literally, not a friend—to explain this idea.25 He tells us that avidyā is always to be understood in the context of the term amitra since the absence of a friend—a mitra—does not mean nobody or nothing. It refers positively to someone who is opposed to friendship, namely an enemy. Likewise avidyā is not the absence of knowledge, but is that which obscures knowledge and/or projects false knowledge. In spite of this latter point one should not surmise that avidyā has or could possibly have any effect on ātman/Brahman. Śaṅkara very clearly tells us: ‘‘Neither avidyā nor its effect pertains to Kshetrajñā pure and simple. Nor is illusory knowledge able to affect the Real Thing. The water of the mirage, for instance, can by no means render the saline soil miry with moisture. So, too, avidyā can do nothing to Kshetrajñā.’’ 26 Any apparent change is only the result of avidyā—it is only māyā. These two terms—avidyā and māyā—are inextricably intertwined in Advaita although different Advaitins develop these terms in distinct ways.27 Since ignorance has no effect on Brahman and since the latter is always selfilluminating pure consciousness and unchanging, one may wonder why some Advaitins would declare that Brahman is the locus (āśraya) of avidyā. Would it not make more sense to say that the jı̄va is the one to whom avidyā belongs? But, can one make the latter claim without running into the problem, for example, that the jı̄va is the product of avidyā? Similarly, how can one postulate that ātman/ Brahman is the object (visaya) of avidyā, in the same manner that the shell is the ob˙ silver in place of the shell? How can that which is svaject in the illusion of seeing prakāśa and sarvajñā be concealed by ignorance? These questions regarding the locus and object of avidyā became the distinguishing issue for the two Advaita schools—the Vivarana and the Bhāmatı̄. The former maintains that the locus of ˙ avidyā is ātman, while the latter maintains that the locus of avidyā is the jı̄va. Both schools agree that the object (visaya) is ātman/Brahman. Without trying to resolve or˙to exhaust the history of this debate, a brief glimpse into some of the issues surrounding it is pertinent. First, it needs to be noted that two of Śaṅkara’s chief disciples took opposing points of view on this issue. Mandana ˙˙ Miśra articulates what will become the Bhāmatı̄ position, and Sureśvara articulates what will become the Vivarana position. Both positions are formalized later by their ˙ Stephen Kaplan 183 followers—namely, Vācaspati Miśra and Padmapāda, respectively. It should also be noted that looking to Śaṅkara to resolve this debate becomes problematic. Currently it seems that a number of leading scholars, including Karl Potter, Daniel Ingalls, Sengaku Mayeda, and Paul Hacker, contend that Śaṅkara was not so much interested in answering the question of the locus of avidyā as providing guidance for the realization of moksa.28 This reading is heavily based on his BGBh 13.2.16 and BSBh 4.1.3, ˙ responds to the question ‘‘Whose ignorance?’’ with the reply that it is where Śaṅkara a question without sense (praśna nirarthakah) (BGBh 13.2.16). Leaving the question ˙ of the locus of avidyā unanswered did not become the Advaita path. Citing Sureśvara, a proponent of the view that avidyā has its locus and object in ātman, will provide us with not only the problems that the Bhāmatı̄ school faces, but also the objections that Sureśvara’s own position, the Vivarana position, faces. A ˙ brief mention of the objections that the Viśistādvaitins raise will provide additional ˙ ˙ insight into the problems that the Vivarana school encountered. (The Viśistādvaitins, ˙ ˙˙ to their specifically Rāmūnuja, dismiss the Bhāmatı̄ view with little comment relative extensive attack on the Vivarana school.29) ˙ Sureśvara’s opening comments in chapter 3 of the Naiskarmyasiddhi present ˙ four reasons that the Bhāmatı̄ view regarding the locus of ignorance is unacceptable: [T]he not-Self cannot be the locus of ignorance, because ignorance is its very nature; and what is of the nature of ignorance cannot, indeed, be the locus of ignorance. Even if it were possible, what change could this ignorance bring about in the locus which is of the nature of ignorance? The non-Self does not have the possibility of attaining knowledge; should there be this possibility, it could be said that ignorance which is by nature the negation of knowledge is located in it. Further, since the not-Self is a product of ignorance, [it cannot be the locus]. Indeed, what exists earlier cannot be located in that which itself comes into being from that [earlier] thing. There is also the reason that the not-Self has no nature of its own independently of ignorance. Owing to these very reasons it should be known that ignorance is not about the not-Self. Thus, the not-Self is not the locus of ignorance; nor does ignorance have the not-Self as its content.30 In brief, Sureśvara is informing us that the jı̄va is a product of ignorance and therefore must come after ignorance. If it must come after ignorance, then the jı̄va cannot be the locus of ignorance. The effect cannot precede the cause. Furthermore, if the jı̄va were the locus of ignorance and thus the ignorance resided in the jı̄va, then ignorance could never be removed from the jı̄va since it would be ignorant by nature. Since these scenarios are ridiculous for Sureśvara, he concludes that the jı̄va cannot be the locus or bearer of avidyā. Having allegedly refuted his opponent’s position that the jı̄va is the locus of avidyā, Sureśvara proceeds to lay out five objections that can be raised regarding his (Sureśvara’s) position that ātman is the object/content of ignorance. He then follows these reasons with his rebuttal of their reasons: What, then[,] is the content of ignorance which is located in the Self? We say that the Self is the content [of ignorance]. It may be objected that ignorance is incompatible with the 184 Philosophy East & West Self for the reason that the Self is of the nature of knowledge, that it is without a second to it, that the relation between the locus and the content involves difference, that the Self is the source of knowledge, and that [it] is unattached and ever free. The reply is that it is compatible. If it be asked, ‘‘How?’’ the reply is that the differentiation in the Self is due to ignorance alone like the snakeness of the rope. Therefore, when ignorance is removed, the evil of duality ceases to be.31 Sureśvara offers us a series of allegedly strong reasons why it makes no sense to say that ātman could possibly be the object (visayam) of ignorance, including (1) the no˙ tion that ātman is always free and unattached, and (2) that the nature of ātman is knowledge. If ātman is the nature of jñāna, without anything other, always free and without attachments, then how can it simultaneously and coterminously be the object and locus of avidyā? Sureśvara is acknowledging the questions that opponents of Advaita have long raised and with which we began this essay. He summarily dismisses these questions by invoking the rope-snake analogy. Just as a rope is concealed by the appearance of an illusory snake, so also ātman can be concealed by ignorance. Thus, just as the rope is the object of one’s ignorance, so also ātman is the object (visaya) of ignorance. ˙ response provokes two questions. First, can simply citing an analogy Sureśvara’s be taken as a serious philosophical rebuttal to the objections he articulates? The objections are strongly articulated; the response is much briefer, although the response does have a more extensive history in Advaita thought. Second, one may ask if this analogy provides an adequate response to the particular problems that Sureśvara is citing. It seems that the objections that are being raised are not questioning what the object of ignorance must be, but rather how ātman/Brahman could be that object. What is concealed—namely, rope/ātman—is not a seriously contentious point. Both Advaita schools agree on this point. One has no problem imagining how the rope can be concealed by the snake because the rope is not self-illuminating; it is not vidyā. But how can Brahman, the ever-free, pure consciousness, be concealed? The analogy is mum on this. In addition, the rope is not concealed by itself. It is concealed by one who imagines the snake and imposes the snake on the rope. However, in the case of ātman, as Sureśvara points out, there is no other (ananyatvāt), and therefore one must wonder how the analogy of the rope-snake helps illuminate not only what is obscured but also how that ‘‘what’’ can be obscured. We can see this point in the objections raised by the opponents of Advaita, such as Viśistādvaitins and Buddhists. Both of these opponents direct their attack on the Advaita˙˙ notion of avidyā, not primarily at what is concealed but how that particular ‘‘what’’—namely, ātman/Brahman—could be the visaya as well as the āśraya of avidyā. For example, Viśistādvaitins, notably Rāmūnuja˙ and Vedānta Deśika, assert that ˙˙ avidyā represents not only a weak point of Advaita philosothe Advaita position on phy but a clear line of demarcation between their position on Brahman and their opponents’. Viśistādvaita does not declare Brahman to be without qualities, nirguna, but only without˙˙defiling qualities. Nor do they declare that there is no distinction between Brahman and the jı̄vas. Therefore, since the Viśistādvaitins do not have to ˙˙ Stephen Kaplan 185 explain how a nondual, nirguna, pure-consciousness Brahman appears as everything but that, they can attack the Advaita notion that Brahman can be obscured by avidyā.32 Rāmūnuja says: And further, while declaring that Brahman having a uniform illuminating nature is screened by avidyā, [this] would [in effect] be declar[ing] the destruction of its own nature itself. The screening of light means an impediment to the origination of light, or the destruction of the existing [light]. Because of the admission of light not capable of being produced, the screening of light is but the destruction of light.33 If Brahman is all—without measure and without end to measure—Rāmūnuja wants to know how the obscuring of the self-illuminating consciousness, which is its Being, cannot be the destruction of its self-illuminating nature. In other words, if you, the Advaitin, claim that ātman is the object of ignorance, you must explain how ātman can be obscured if it is nondual and self-illuminating, and furthermore, if it can be obscured, why does this obscuration not destroy ātman? To such objections Advaitins once again resort to analogies. Here the analogy of the cloud that covers the light of the sun is appropriate.34 In such cases, the light of the sun is not destroyed; it is merely obscured. But one may ask if this analogy works for the Advaitin since it introduces diversity, the cloud, into the nature of the undivided Brahman. Such an analogy may work for the Viśistādvaitin, who does not ˙ assert the unqualified nondualism of Advaita, but it still ˙seems to place Advaita squarely in the position of being asked: how can vidyā and avidyā be simultaneous and coterminous if Brahman is uniform, self-illuminating, unchanging consciousness? Finally, since much of the Advaita response has been through analogy and since the next sections will develop a new analogy, I conclude this section by returning to Śaṅkara for comment on the use of analogy and for his insight into this aspect of avidyā. Śaṅkara, like other Advaitins, finds analogy an extremely important tool to illuminate that which śruti reveals. For example, in BSBh 2.1.27 Śaṅkara states that śruti reveals that Brahman is unchanging and partless, in spite of its appearance to the contrary. Śaṅkara then invokes a purvapaksin, who announces that not even the ˙ Vedas can make us accept that which is contradictory. Śaṅkara responds by readily acknowledging that contradictory qualities cannot exist, and furthermore he states that neither reason nor perception can resolve such philosophical conundrums as these. However, Śaṅkara is not left speechless.35 He responds to his opponents’ challenge to his position with analogy—specifically, an analogy invoking the notion of avidyā. In the example in question, he utilizes the analogy of the one moon that appears to be many because of eye disease: That is nothing damaging, since it is admitted that this difference of aspects is created by ignorance. For a thing does not become multiformed just because aspects are imagined on it through ignorance. Not that the moon, perceived to be many by a man with blurred vision (timira—diplopia), becomes really so. Brahman becomes subject to all kinds of (phenomenal) actions like transformation, on account of the differences of aspects, con- 186 Philosophy East & West stituted by name and form, which remain either differentiated or non-differentiated either as real or unreal, and which are imagined through ignorance. In Its real aspect Brahman remains unchanging and beyond all phenomenal actions.36 Where reason and perception cannot go, analogy illustrating the concept of avidyā will be offered. Reason, in particular, cannot deal with such notions as the partlessness and apparent parts of Brahman because such juxtapositions strike us as contradictory to reason.37 In turning to holography as an analogy, I wonder what Śaṅkara’s response to this analogy would have been, given the fact that each part of the hologram can reproduce the whole yet the sum total of all the parts of the hologram also produce only one whole? Would he find this analogy illuminating not only of avidyā, but also of the problem of apparent contradictoriness? Before presenting the holographic analogy, a review of the preceding analogy is in order. The analogy provides us with a moon, which, while technically not selfilluminating, appears to be self-illuminating. (As such, in this particular aspect, this analogy has the advantage over the rope-snake analogy in that the latter is not remotely self-illuminating.) This analogy also shows us that the moon does not change just as Brahman does not change. However, it does reveal a person who is changing and who is other than the moon that is analogously related to Brahman. Not missing a trick, Śaṅkara appears to anticipate the criticism above. He follows the preceding passage, which utilizes the moon analogy to explain how ignorance makes Brahman appear manifold, with a passage that invokes a different analogy. This second analogy is the analogy of a dreamer and the multiplicity of dream objects. In this analogy, we do not have two separate things, as in the preceding analogy. Rather there is only one dreamer, who produces a dream with a diversity of objects. Śaṅkara says: Moreover, there is no occasion for dispute here as to how there can be creation of various kinds in the same Brahman without changing Its nature; for we read in the Upanisad that a diverse creation occurs in the same soul in dream without any change of nature. ‘There are no chariots, nor animals to be yoked to them, nor roads there, but he creates the chariots, animals, and roads’ (Br. IV.iii.10). In the world also in the case of gods, as also jugglers and others that various kinds of creation of elephants and so on take place without any destruction of their nature. Similarly even in the same Brahman there can be a diverse creation without any destruction of Its nature.38 This dream analogy, unlike the rope-snake and moon analogies, avoids the pitfalls of introducing a second reality in addition to Brahman. However, the dream analogy avoids that pitfall by introducing the notion of change into Brahman. The dreamer dreams characters and events. The dreaming mind, analogously Brahman, is a changing, evolving mind. Yet, repeatedly, Advaita tells us that Brahman is unchanging. These analogies are useful epistemological tools to illustrate the relation between the false knowledge and the knower, but, as Karl Potter indicated, they seem to fall short as models to illuminate the nature of Brahman as a pure, unchanging, self-illuminating consciousness that is not marred by avidyā. For a possible insight into this problem, we shall turn to holography. Stephen Kaplan 187 Holography and the Formation of a Model As indicated, holography is the technique by which one can reproduce threedimensional optical images from an imageless film. Holography is very different from other forms of optical-imaging reproductions. Photography, for example, uses lenses to capture an image on a piece of film. In photography, a point-by-point correspondence exists between the object and the image captured. The lens focuses the light onto the film in a manner that corresponds to the object being photographed. The patterns produced on the film resemble the object. As we know, one can look at the photographic negative to see what object was photographed. The photographic image can be printed on paper, flashed on a wall, or called up on a computer screen. In each of these cases, the photographic image is flat—it has only two dimensions. There is only one perspective from which to view the recorded object. One does not have the ability to change one’s angle of view and see a different side or face of the recorded object. Holograms are different. They record information about the whole object—the object as three-dimensional. Holography means to write the whole. Holography is a lensless process of optical recording and reproduction. The hologram refers to the medium on which the information necessary to reproduce a three-dimensional image is recorded. Generally speaking, holograms are made with silver halide film similar to regular black-and-white photographic film, except with a much higher resolution.39 This higher-resolution film is used to record the interference patterns that form the basis of the hologram. The interference patterns do not resemble in any way, shape, or form the object that is being filmed. The holographic interference patterns are produced with a laser. A laser is a single-frequency light source that is in phase—in other words, the light waves are in step with each other. (Light from an ordinary light bulb is neither in phase nor single-frequency.) The hologram records not only the varying intensities of the light as it reflects off the object, as does a photograph, but it also records the phase relations of the light reflecting off the object.40 In order to produce a hologram, the laser is aimed at a device that splits the beam into two separate light waves. One of the waves is directed toward the film; the other is directed toward the object and then, reflecting off the object, toward the film. The former is called the reference beam and the latter is the scene or object beam. At the film, the two beams of light converge. Their convergence creates the interference patterns, which spread across the film. These interference patterns are like waves created in a pool of water into which two stones are thrown. No image of the object is recorded on the film; only the confluence of the waves from the object beam and the scene beam are recorded on the film. In order to reconstruct an image of the original object, a laser beam of the same frequency as that which was used to construct the hologram is directed at the holographic film.41 This procedure of passing a reference beam back through the film will cause that which was originally coded onto the hologram in the form of interference patterns to be decoded from the hologram. This decoding process presents 188 Philosophy East & West us with the optical conditions that allow us to perceive the image as a threedimensional object. As a three-dimensional image, a holographic image cannot be displayed on a wall, on a piece of paper, or on a computer screen. Any such attempt would yield only a two-dimensional reproduction. The holographic image appears suspended in space. You can look at this three-dimensional image from different perspectives. Holograms have the visual characteristics of our everyday visual world. These images have height, width, and depth. Before utilizing holography as a model for understanding the Advaita notion of avidyā, three highly unusual characteristics of the film must be noted. First, since the film is without any images, it does not exhibit the subject-object dichotomies found in our spatiotemporal world. For example, a photographic negative of my two children would exhibit two discreet individuals that stand in subject-object relationship to each other. On the negative, one can also observe these individuals and the various parts that constitute them—legs, arms, heads, et cetera. However, the holographic film does not exhibit any such subject-object relations corresponding to the objects filmed—no son, no daughter, no arms, no legs, et cetera. Here, the information about the individuals is enfolded throughout the interference patterns that are spread over the film. Only interference patterns exist on the film, not images.42 Second, the film exhibits redundancy. In this context, redundancy means that each piece of the hologram can reproduce the entire holographic image, yet the whole film only produces one holographic image. Concretely illustrated, one can tear a hologram into four parts, for example, and each part will reproduce the entire holographic image. Recall, the film has no images; rather, only interference patterns are recorded on the film and they are spread throughout the film. The spreading of the interference patterns across the film allows any part of the film to produce a complete holographic image of the original object. Thus, while the sum of the parts of a hologram equals the whole of the hologram, each part also ‘‘equals’’ the whole. Finally, one holographic film is able to record multiple scenes. In distinction from photography, in which a double exposure of the negative will blur both images, one may record on one holographic film multiple scenes by changing either the angle at which the laser hits the film or the frequency of the laser used to create the hologram. (In fact, color holograms are produced by recording the same scene on the same holographic film with lasers of different frequencies.) This ability to record a series of different scenes/objects on one holographic film provides it with enormous storage potential. This holographic situation presents us with two domains called the explicate domain and the implicate domain.43 The explicate domain refers to the object or objects filmed and to the holographic images that are reproduced. The implicate domain refers to the film with its unusual characteristics. The explicate domain is that order with which we are most familiar. It is our normal spatiotemporal world in which objects are made up of parts and in which objects and parts of objects stand in relation to other objects and parts. Distinctness, difference, duality, and relationship are the chief characteristics of an explicate domain. Stephen Kaplan 189 The second domain—the implicate domain—refers to the film with its unusual characteristics. In this domain, in which each part is enfolded into all the other parts, one does not talk about subjects or objects, discreet parts, or the relations between parts. The nonduality of subject and object, and of part and whole, is the appropriate language for the implicate domain. In this domain there are no individuals— individuality is enfolded into the whole. About the implicate domain, the renowned physicist David Bohm has said: ‘‘in the implicate order the totality of existence is enfolded within each region of space (and time). So, whatever part, element, or aspect we may abstract in thought, this still enfolds the whole and is therefore intrinsically related to the totality from which it has been abstracted.’’ 44 This domain, which is radically unlike our normal spatiotemporal world, in which each subject stands in relation to other subjects, will help us illuminate the Advaita notion of vidyā and avidyā as simultaneous and coterminous. Correlating the Advaita Position with the Model In this section, I will show that this holographic analogy is a valuable tool for understanding how vidyā and avidyā can be simultaneous and coterminous. More specifically, the power of this analogy will be shown to arise from the correlations between the highly unusual characteristics of the implicate domain and the qualities of ātman/Brahman. I know of no other ‘‘entity’’ that can serve to illuminate the nondual reality of Brahman like the implicate domain. As such, I know of no other entity that can serve as the basis from which to illuminate how the unchanging, nondual Being/Consciousness can appear as a myriad of subjects and objects. The rope, the moon, space, the sandy soil, the dreamer, and so forth all have characteristics that mirror our ordinary four-dimensional world. These entities do not mirror the nature of Brahman; each, for example, is constituted by parts that stand in relation to other parts. That is not true of the hologram—of the implicate domain of holography. In spite of these alleged values, this holographic analogy is not intended (1) to quell the myriad criticisms of the Advaita position, (2) to eliminate all the internal wrangling between the schools of Advaita, or (3) to prove the truth of the Advaita worldview. I do not know, for example, if this analogy, or for that matter any of the analogies, resolves the debates surrounding the locus of avidyā. Nor can I imagine that this analogy would convince a non-Advaitin to fall before a Śaṅkara mūrti. In addition, this analogy is not intended to replace all other Advaita analogies. One cannot think ‘‘Advaita’’ without conjuring up the rope-snake analogy. The goal of this essay is to add to our wealth of knowledge without subtracting or denigrating other analogies. Finally, like all analogies, the holographic analogy has positive, neutral, and negative correlations. In other words, some aspects of the familiar system upon which the model is based can be successfully related to the item or issue to be explained (the explanandum). Other aspects of the familiar system—for example, holography or the rope-snake illusion—are either irrelevant to the point being made or problematic when raised in relation to the issue to be explained.45 In spite 190 Philosophy East & West of these points, I believe that the holographic analogy is a powerful tool for illuminating this long-standing quandary within Advaita. It will allow us to envision how pure consciousness can be everywhere, and everywhere the same, yet ignorance can be somewhere and somehow, as anirvacanı̄ya. It will allow us to envision how vidyā and avidyā can be simultaneous and coterminous. My construction of this holographic metaphor begins by correlating Brahman to the implicate domain. In such a schema, the implicate domain would be analogous to Brahman as the one true metaphysical reality of all existence. To unfold this analogy, we need to condense the Advaita talk of Brahman to a limited number of characteristics and relate them to the implicate domain. Six well-known, essential, and interrelated qualities of Brahman will serve this purpose. First, Brahman is Being—it is the one Being of all existence, without measure and without end to measure. Second, it is the nondual reality of all existence. It is one without a second (advaita). Third, there is only one true self, ātman, and that ātman is Brahman (tat tvam asi). Fourth, this one Being is unchanging. It is always the same (samatām gatam), ˙ characterized as such by ajāti (non-origination). Fifth, it is always cit—pure, selfilluminating (svaprakāśa) consciousness, and this cit is sat, the Being of ātman/ Brahman. Sat must be cit. If cit were other than sat, there would be duality, and therefore there could be no knowledge of ātman/Brahman as nondual. And finally, sixth, ātman/brahman is always free, never ignorant, never wallowing in samsāra. ˙ As indicated, in constructing this holographic metaphor, the implicate domain of holography is analogized to Brahman, and therefore its characteristics would be analogized to ultimate reality, to the nature of all existence, to paramārtha. As such, the implicate domain must be imagined to be everywhere and everything. It would be imagined as the Being of all. Second, utilizing the characteristics of the implicate domain as an analogy for Brahman in this fashion would present us with a model for Brahman that is without the discreet parts of our empirical world. In the implicate domain there is no self, me, standing in relation to an object, you. Self and object are enfolded into the implicate domain. In the explicate world there is an ‘‘I,’’ the typist, and an it, the keyboard; however, in the implicate domain the duality of ‘‘I’’ and ‘‘keyboard’’ do not exist. In this domain, both are folded into a nonduality of being—into an implicate domain that lacks such distinctions. In the implicate domain, there are only interference patterns that in no way, shape, or form resemble particular entities. The implicate domain, like Brahman, is characterized by nondualism—the nondualism of subject and object. Third, from this perspective each piece of the implicate domain can reproduce the whole and as such is equal to all other ‘‘pieces’’ of the implicate domain. In this sense, one can say that the implicate domain is a state in which there is one self, and that one self is the nature of all of the implicate domain. This one self of the implicate domain, like ātman/Brahman, would be without the particularity of individuality—it would be without duality—without the duality of subject and object. It would be like ātman that art Brahman. Stephen Kaplan 191 Fourth, the implicate domain can be understood, from one perspective, as unchanging. All aspects of individual, explicate, spatiotemporal objects are enfolded into the implicate domain. From the information encoded onto a hologram, explicate, spatiotemporal entities unfold, but these entities are not present as spatiotemporal entities in the implicate domain. Thus, the implicate domain, as the enfoldment of all spatiotemporal entities, remains unchanged. David Bohm, as physicist and metaphyscian, puts the issue as follows: ‘‘All implicates all,’’ even to the extent that ‘‘we ourselves’’ are implicated together with ‘‘all that we see and think about.’’ So we are present everywhere and at all times, though only implicately (that is, implicitly). . . . The general law, i.e., holonomy, has to be expressed in all orders, in which all objects and all times are ‘‘folded together.’’ 46 All objects and all times may be enfolded, from one perspective, in the implicate domain, and the unfoldment of objects or holographic images does not alter their enfolded nature. The implicate domain of the hologram is unchanging even as images are unfolded from it and appear to us. Fifth, by analogy, since the implicate domain would be coextensive with the being of all, the knowledge of any part of the implicate domain would be the knowledge of all since each part can reproduce the whole. In this model, a realization of the implicate domain, as implicate and not as explicate, could not entail a subject knowing an object since the implicate domain does not contain the characteristics of duality. A realization of the implicate domain—as completely enfolded—would be different from viewing a piece of holographic film and noting its lack of subjectobject dichotomies. As a model for the Advaita worldview, we are not talking about one object, the viewer, looking at a second object, the film. In the metaphysical situation, the implicate domain, like Brahman, would analogously be everywhere—it would be co-extensive with all that exists. Therefore, if a realization of the implicate domain qua its implicate nature were to occur, the alleged realizer would not be separate from the ‘‘object’’ of this realization, namely the being of this domain. And therefore the consciousness that knows the nondual Being of the implicate domain cannot be other than the implicate domain since the subject-object dichotomies have been enfolded. There cannot be Being as one thing in the implicate domain and consciousness as another thing; all is enfolded into the implicate domain. In this model, being (sat) would have to be consciousness (cit). And finally, sixth, since sat is cit in this model and since they/it can be understood as unchanging, then one can see how this unchanging reality, which is sat and cit, which is always nondual, must always be unattached and free. I have just taken six major characteristics of ātman/Brahman and analogously related each to the implicate domain of holography. In so doing, one can envision a reality without subject-object duality, in which each piece equals the whole, where being and consciousness would not be separable nor alterable. In such a reality the Being that is consciousness would exist unchanged, and it would be simultaneous and coterminous with the appearance of explicate artifacts, with subjects and objects, with avidyā. 192 Philosophy East & West Conclusion: Questions Facing Advaita and Questions Confronting This Proposal Having made these correlations between the implicate domain and ātman/Brahman, I will now return to two sets of vexing questions that Advaita faces in order to develop this analogy further, and then I will examine three questions looming over this proposal. First, if Brahman is partless, how can avidyā be a part of Brahman? If avidyā is not a part of Brahman, is it all of Brahman? Or, if avidyā is not a part of Brahman, is it other than Brahman? Second, how can avidyā be both concealing and projecting yet not alter Brahman? In other words, why does avidyā not destroy vidyā? How can pure consciousness be everywhere, and everywhere the same, yet ignorance be somehow somewhere, even if only anirvacanı̄ya? Each set of questions is asking, in their own way, how vidyā and avidyā can be simultaneous and coterminous. First, might one imagine the partlessness of Brahman in terms of the partlessness of the implicate domain? If so, it would be an undivided wholeness consisting of enfolded, interference-like patterns that have no particularity, no subject-object dualism, and thus no discreet parts. These interference-like patterns are spread throughout the implicate domain and are therefore coterminous with it. They cannot be distinguished from the implicate domain since they are the implicate domain. Thus, they are not separate, nor separatable from the implicate domain. They are all of it; yet they do not alter its inalterability since, as we have seen in the passage from Bohm, all (both temporally and spatially) may be enfolded in each piece. Therefore, one cannot say that these interference patterns are a part of the implicate domain (i.e., Brahman), nor something other than the implicate domain (i.e., Brahman). They are all of the implicate domain, yet they are not any thing; they are no particular thing. Their presence is the Being and hence consciousness of the implicate domain (i.e., Brahman). In this context, it should also be noted that all particular things, whether part of the holographic analogy or of the Advaita worldview, could not be some place other than the implicate domain (i.e., Brahman) since the implicate domain (i.e., Brahman) is everywhere. The unfoldment of explicate artifacts (i.e., the appearance of the world of duality) could not therefore be someplace other than this most fundamental order. The second set of questions may be summarized as follows. How can avidyā conceal the true nature of Brahman and project subject and objects yet not affect Brahman? Why does avidyā not destroy vidyā? How can they be simultaneous and coterminous? In the same way that the projection of holographic images does not affect the hologram, so also the appearance of duality does not affect Brahman. In this model, the projection of explicate individuality does not affect the enfolded implicate domain; the latter remains enfolded. Just as recognizing the unfolding of the interference patterns obscures one’s knowledge of the implicate domain by projecting an explicate artifact and simultaneously concealing the implicate domain from view, so also adhyāsa conceals pure consciousness and projects duality. And furthermore, just as the implicate and explicate domains are simultaneous and coterminous Stephen Kaplan 193 in this model, so also we can imagine how Brahman as Being and pure consciousness can be simultaneous and coterminous with the projecting and concealing world of avidyā. The projections, which are the consequence of avidyā, would no more alter Brahman as sat and cit than the appearance of holographic images alter the implicate domain. Explicate holographic images appear at the same time that the implicate domain exists. Without the implicate domain, no explicate images could be projected. Of course, there can be an implicate domain without the projection of the explicate holographic images. Likewise, in this analogy, there can be Brahman with and/or without the world of māyā, but the appearance of māyā does not destroy the nonduality of Brahman (i.e., the implicate domain). This model allows us to imagine how vidyā and avidyā can be simultaneous and coterminous. Before concluding, three questions that threaten the intellectual integrity of this proposal must be confronted. But first, it needs to be repeated that this analogy is not intended to be an actual replica or scale model of the Advaita worldview; rather, it is only a heuristic device capable of providing additional insight into Advaita Vedānta. The three questions threatening this proposal are: (1) Who is the observer in this analogy? (2) What is the source of illumination that would be comparable to the light in a holographic situation? (3) What causes ignorance? First, who is the observer? While the rope-snake and other analogies allow Advaita to explain how illusions can appear in the place of an unchanging substratum like the rope, a number of these analogies leave the notion of an observer who experiences the illusion, the snake, et cetera hanging untouched in the air. On the one hand, like these traditional Advaita analogies, the holographic analogy seems to be limited in this regard. I have talked about the implicate domain and the explicate holographic images, but who, what, and where is the observer of these images? While the notion of an observer seems to be a problem, it should be noted that as a heuristic model, which analogizes the implicate domain to the Being of all existence, something akin to Bohm’s proposal, one would have to say that both the observer and the observed are simultaneously an explication of the implicate domain.47 From this perspective, one could say that, if all were fundamentally implicated in the implicate-like Being, then both observer and observed would be the result of this projection process. Applying this holographic model, each subject, each grasper (grāhaka), would be an unfoldment from the fundamental implicate-like domain just as the observed would be. Each subject-grasper (grāhaka) is presented to itself as it presents that which is object, the grasped—grāhya. Analogously, from the Advaita perspective both subject and object—grāhaka-grāhya—are simultaneous and mutually interdependent. There is no grasper without the grasping (grahana) of ˙ the grasped. Returning to the opening discussion, Śaṅkara told us that avidyā is the imposition of both subject and object—of both you and me.48 There can be no presentation of the image of an other without the notion of subject that stands in relation, nor can there be a sense of subject without the notion of at least body and senses that become an object to one’s self.49 Just as for Advaita, which sees the duality of subject and object as the projection of avidyā from the nondual Brahman, so also in this 194 Philosophy East & West holographic analogy one can imagine that both the knower/observer and the known/observed would be unfolded from the nondual implicate domain. The second question concerns the source of illumination. A hologram needs to be illuminated by a reference beam in order for one to see an image. What functions as the source of illumination? Is this a new element, like the addition of pots that divide space in the analogy of ākāśa and ghatākāśa? From where do the pots come?50 Utilizing holography as a model, where the implicate domain is compared to Brahman, this issue is not actually a problem. On this premise, the implicate domain is analogized to Brahman, which is Being and consciousness. Thus, the source of illumination is inherent in the nature of its Being. It is all Being and simultaneously all cit, pure consciousness; thus, to ask, as an analogy, where the source of illumination would come from is to forget the analogy. One could clearly declare that the nature of Being is not cit. This analogy does not pretend to prove that sat is cit. This analogy is merely trying to understand the Advaita position, and that position declares that sat is cit. Therefore, as an analogy, if the implicate domain is a heuristic model for the Advaita metaphysical view of Being, then there need be no question as to whence the illumination would come. It is the basic fabric of the nonduality of existence and consciousness. This leads us to the final question. If (1) the illuminating source is Being/ consciousness itself, which is said to be everywhere and nowhere changing, and (2) the observer and that which the observer observes is an appearance that unfolds from this implicate-like metaphysical order, then what could be the reason for the unfoldment of the latter? In other words, why is there ignorance? Why is there an appearance of perceiver and perceived, subject and object? For an answer to these questions I am drawn to Gaudapāda’s Māndūkya Kārikā. This is not to say that all ˙ questions˙ in ˙ the same way. Nonetheless, from this Advaita texts would answer these perspective, the appearance of the observer and that which it observes, the grasper and the grasped, the appearance of duality (dvayābhāsam) arises from the movement of the mind (cittaspanditam). It is the latter that is declared to be avidyā—the imposition of subject and object—self and other—on a reality that is nondual. (This is consistent with Śaṅkara’s BSBh.) As Gaudapāda declared: ˙ Just as the movement of a firebrand gives the appearance of being straight, crooked, etc., so also the movement of the mind (vijñāna) gives the appearance of perceiver and perceived. (MK 4.47) Just as the firebrand without moving is without any appearances and is unborn, so also the mind without moving is without appearances and unborn. (MK 4.48)51 Why the mind moves, or if the mind really moves, returns us to the most fundamental problem: why is there avidyā?52 In the holographic analogy, the movement is part and parcel of the nature of the implicate domain. It is simultaneous and coterminous with the nonmoving, partless implicate domain. From the Advaita perspective, it is only the latter aspect—namely, the implicate-like Brahman—that affords liberation. As such, for the Advaitin, all else is associated with that which obscures liberation— namely, avidyā. Stephen Kaplan 195 Finally, this analysis seems to end up where it began, with the inexplicability of avidyā staring us in the face. However, we must also recognize that in arriving at this point, the movement of the mind does not create the empirical world. It simply allows those things that are the external causes for the appearance of the empirical world to be presented. This analysis may not have resolved why ignorance appears, but it has allowed us to see how the unchanging Brahman can be simultaneous and coterminous with avidyā, and it may have put us in a better position to untangle the complexities surrounding the Advaita view of the empirical world. Notes Abbreviations are used in the text and the Notes as follows: 196 BGBh Śaṅkara. Srı̄mad Bhagavad Gı̄tā Bhāsya of Srı̄ Saṁkarācārya. Translated by ˙ A. G. Krishna Warrier. Madras: Sri Ramakrishna Math, n.d. BrUBh ˙ Śaṅkara. The Brhadāranyaka Upanisad with the Commentary of Śaṅ˙ ˙ ˙ karācārya. Translated by Swāmı̄ Mādhavānanda. Calcutta: Advaita Ashram, 1997. BSBh Śaṅkara. Brahma-Sūtra-Bhāsya of Śrı̄ Śaṅkarācārya. Translated by Swami ˙ Gambhirananda. Calcutta: Advaita Ashrama, 1965. BSBh.s Śaṅkara. Brahmasūtra-Śāṅkarabhāsyam with the Commentaries, Bhāsyarat˙ ˙ naprabhā of Govindānanda, Bhāmatı̄ of Vācaspatimiśra, Nyāyanirnaya of Ānandagiri. Edited by J. L. Shastri. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2000. MK Gaudapāda. The Māndūkyopanisad, Gaudapādiya Kārikā, Śaṅkarabhāsya. ˙˙ ˙ ˙ Gorakhapur: Gita Press, Samvat ˙2026. ˙ NS Sureśvara. The Naiskarmyasiddhi of Sureśvara. Edited and translated by R. ˙ Balasubramanian. Madras: University of Madras, 1988. PD Vidyāranya. Pañcadaśı̄: A Treatise on Advaita Metaphysics. Translated by ˙ Hari Prasad Shastri. London: Shanti Sadan, 1965. RSBh Rāmūnuja. Śrı̄bhāsya of Rāmūnuja. Part 1. Edited by R. D. Karmarkar. Poona: University ˙of Poona, 1959. SS Sarvajñātman. The Saṁksepasārı̄raka of Sarvajñātman. Edited and trans˙ Madras: University of Madras, 1985. lated by N. Veezhinathan. TS Shāntaraksı̄ta. The Tattvasangraha of Shāntaraksı̄ta with the Commentary ˙ ˙ ˙ Ganganatha Jha. Delhi: of Kamalashı̄la. Volumes 1 and 2. Translated by Motilal Banarsidass, 1986. TUBhV The Taittirı̄yopanisad Bhāsya-Vārtika of Sureśvara. Edited and translated by ˙ ˙ R. Balasubramanian. Madras: University of Madras, 1984. US A Thousand Teachings: The Upadeśasāhasrı̄ of Śaṅkara. Translated by Sengaku Mayeda. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992. Philosophy East & West US.s Śaṅkara’s Upadeśasāhasrı̄. Critically Edited with Introduction and Indices by Sengaku Mayeda. Tokyo: Hokuseido Press, 1993. VS Sadānanda. Vedāntasāra or The Essence of Vedānta of Sadānda Yogı̄ndra. Translated by Swami Nikhilananda. Calcutta: Advaita Ashrama, 1974. 1 – US, p. 82. 2 – ‘‘Since the root cause of this transmigratory existence is ignorance, its destruction is desired. Knowledge of Brahman therefore is entered on. Final beatitude results from this knowledge’’ (US 1.1.5, p. 103). 3 – na nirodho na cotpattir na buddho na ca sadhaka/na mumukur na vai mukta ity esa paramārthatā (MK 2.32; see also MK 3.2). 4 – Ātman is always enlightened, according to Śaṅkara. See US 1.1.13, 16, 18, 19. 5 – US 1.16.37–38, p. 153. 6 – We find this expressed by R. Balasubramanian, in the introduction to NS, as: ‘‘It is impossible for us to explain in any intelligible way the relation between Brahman-ātman and avidyā’’ (p. xxxv). 7 – Allen Thrasher, in the context of a discussion of Mandana Miśra’s Brahmasid˙˙ dhi, says ‘‘[I]t is precisely because avidyā is logically contradictory that we call it ‘ignorance’ or ‘illusion’’’ (Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, ed. Karl Potter [Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1981], vol. 3, p. 352). 8 – Advaitins often do not see vidyā and avidyā as being contradictory, just as they do not see Brahman as containing contradictory qualities. Just as Brahman cannot be both motionless and with motion (BGBh 13.2.10; BSBh 2.1.14), partless and with parts (BSBh 2.1.27), so also vidyā is not seen to be contradicted by avidyā. The opposite or contradictory to avidyā is said to be discernment (viveka) (see Andrew O. Fort, ‘‘Reflections on Reflection: Kūtastha, Cidābhāsa and Vrtti in the Pañcadaśı̄,’’ Journal of Indian Philosophy 28˙ (2000): 499; and ˙ PD 6.31–33: atah kūtastha caitanyam avirodhı̄ti tarkyatām). Another way of ˙ phrasing this is to see ˙jñāna and avidyā as opposing each other while cit illuminates them both (J. N. Mohanty, Explorations in Philosophy: Essays by J. N. Mohanty, ed. Bina Gupta [New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001], p. 129). There is no question that cit illuminates each specific state of mind, which is a form of avidyā. Nonetheless, additional perspectives must be noted. First, critics of Advaita assert that the Advaita position is contradictory on exactly this relation between Brahman and avidyā. The Viśistādvaita critique of ˙˙ the Advaita position will be discussed below. For an example of a Buddhist critique of the Advaita position see Śāntiraksita’s text with the commentary of Kamalaśı̄la (TS 7.333, pp. 215–216). There˙ the Advaita position is declared unacceptable because Brahman cannot be pure consciousness while avidyā presents itself. Second, there are places where Śaṅkara and Sureśvara, for example, indicate that the apparent presence of contradictory qualities stemming from ignorance cannot really exist but certainly appears to exist just as the rope Stephen Kaplan 197 is experienced as a snake (NS 2.50, p. 157, and 3.66, p. 290). The latter states: ‘‘This ignorance is without any support. It is opposed to any logic. It cannot endure inquiry in the same way as darkness cannot endure the sun.’’ Although vidyā and avidyā appear to be contradictory, nothing contradictory can exist, and therefore they are declared not to be contradictory. Finally, and I think most significantly, it must be noted that vidyā and avidyā (and their cognates) are often juxtaposed as opposites. For example, Śaṅkara states that only a knowledge of Brahman will remove ignorance (see, e.g., US.s 1.1.6 [vidyaivājñānahanāya] and 2.2.48; BGBh 13.2.3; BrUBh 3.3.1; TUBhV 1.33). ˙ 9 – Potter, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, 3 : 576 (Padmapāda, Pañcapādikā, chap. 31.115–118). 10 – Karl H. Potter, Presuppositions of India’s Philosophies (Westport: Greenwood Press, 1972), p. 163. 11 – For a discussion of the use of this model to illuminate simultaneously three different ultimate realities, see Stephen Kaplan, Different Paths, Different Summits: A Model for Religious Pluralism (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002). 12 – BSBh 1.1, Introduction, p. 2; BSBh.s, p. 13: ucyate, smtirūpah paratra pūrvadrst˙ ˙ ˙˙ vabhāsah/. ˙ 13 – BSBh 1.1, Introduction, pp. 3–4. 14 – BSBh 1.1, Introduction. For a discussion of this passage see Purushottama Bilimoria, ‘‘On Śaṅkara’s Attempted Reconciliation of ‘You’ and ‘I’: Yusmadasmat˙ of Bimal samanvaya,’’ in Relativism, Suffering and Beyond: Essays in Memory K. Matilal, ed. P. Bilimoria and J. N. Mohanty (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1997). 15 – For example, see VS 2.51, p. 37: asyājñānasyāvaranaviksepanāmakamasti śak˙ ˙ two powers to avitidvayam. And see also PD 6.26. This tradition of ascribing dyā is obviously very old, as it appears in a variant form in Gaudapāda, MK 1.14 and 1.16. It is also evident in Mandana Miśra’s Brahmasiddhi˙ (149.16 to ˙ 150.24). For a discussion of the latter and˙ his relation to Gaudapāda, see Allen ˙ Thrasher, The Advaita Vedānta of Brahma-Siddhi (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1993), pp. 72–73. There seems to be some debate as to whether Śaṅkara held the notion that there were two functions of avidyā. For example, Paul Hacker says: ‘‘Even the theory, already current among Ś.’s contemporaries, that avidyā possesses a ‘power of dispersion’ (viksepa-śakti) and a ‘power of concealment’ ˙ (āvarana-śakti) is foreign to the Sbh’’ (Paul Hacker, ‘‘Distinctive Features of the ˙ Doctrine and Terminology of Śaṅkara: Avidyā, Nāmarūpa, Māyā, Īśvara,’’ in Philology and Confrontation, ed. Wilhelm Halbfass [Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995], p. 64). While Hacker references the BSBh, it should be noted that in the MK Śaṅkara distinguishes two functions associated with wrong knowledge of the world—anyathāgrahanam and tattvāpratibodha (see ˙ note 18 below). The authenticity of this work by Śaṅkara is debated. 198 Philosophy East & West 16 – ‘‘Just as a small patch of cloud, by obstructing the vision of the observer, conceals, as it were, the solar disc extending over many miles, similarly ignorance though limited by nature, yet obscuring the intellect of the observer, conceals, as it were, the Self which is unlimited and not subject to transmigration’’ (VS 2.52, p. 38). 17 – ‘‘Just as ignorance regarding a rope, by its inherent power, gives rise to the illusion of a snake etc. in the rope covered by it, so also ignorance, by its own power creates in the Self covered by it, such phenomena as Akasa etc. Such a power is called the power of projection’’ (VS 2.54, p. 39). 18 – Gaudapāda, in MK 1.14, distinguishes some of the characteristics of the four states˙ of consciousness. Śaṅkara comments on this verse by telling us that dreams are the misapprehension of reality (anyathāgrahanam), like seeing the ˙ snake in place of the rope, while dreamless sleep is the non-perception of reality (tattvāpratibodhena), like darkness. In MK 1.16 Gaudapāda states that when ˙ the jı̄va, which has slept because of beginningless māyā, awakens, then it knows the nondual. 19 – SS 2.183, p. 488. Sarvajñātman continues this in verses 2.184–185 telling us that God’s knowledge is nirāvaranam, but that the knowledge of the jı̄va is ˙ sāvaranam. Karl Potter analyzes this issue as follows: ‘‘it is said that God is om˙ niscient, but according to the Samksepaśarı̄raka he is limited by ignorance. ˙ How can this be the proper way of understanding God? The answer is that ‘omniscience’ means ‘lacking the concealing type of ignorance.’ God can be omniscient, in this sense, and still limited by His connection with the projective aspect of māyā’’ (Potter, Presuppositions of India’s Philosophies, p. 180). See also BSBh 2.1.14. 20 – Daniel H. H. Ingalls, ‘‘Śaṅkara on the Question: Whose Is Avidyā,’’ Philosophy East and West 3 (1953): 69. Ingalls sees this situation as presenting Advaita with the horns of a dilemma that should lead either to the end of monism or to the destruction of the doctrine of avidyā. 21 – MK 3.28 and 4.28, with an implied reference to birds. 22 – ‘‘However, ignorance is described as something positive though intangible, which cannot be described either as being or non-being, which is made of three qualities and is antagonistic to Knowledge’’ (VS 2.34, p. 22). 23 – Allen Thrasher, The Advaita Vedānta of Brahma-Siddhi, p. 1 (English), p. 135 (Sanskrit). 24 – R. Balasubramanian, NS, p. 4. 25 – ‘‘Its nature does not consist in anything other than the non-perception of the Self. Only if it is said that the term avidyā is like the term amitra, it is always tenable’’ (TUBhV 2.179, p. 366). 26 – BGBh 13.2.13, p. 415. Stephen Kaplan 199 27 – A cursory overview of the relation between these terms indicates, for example, that Gaudapāda often uses the term māyā, but not avidyā. Yet the former in ˙ usages takes on the characteristics of avidyā, and furthermore, Śaṅsome of its kara in MK 1.16 glosses māyā with avidyā. Also, in BSBh 1.4.3, Śaṅkara links these terms. For a full discussion of this issue within the works of Śaṅkara see Paul Hacker, ‘‘Distinctive Features of the Doctrine and Terminology of Śaṅkara,’’ pp. 75 ff. For a discussion of this in relation to Mandana Miśra, ˙˙ Vidyāranya, and others, see E. A. Solomon, Avidyā: A Problem of Truth and ˙ Reality (Ahmedabad: Gujarat University, 1969). 28 – For example, Daniel Ingalls says: ‘‘What Śaṅkara does is to avoid the difficulty. He concentrates on what he considers the heart of the matter, the teaching that is necessary for the attainment of moksa. This teaching is that avidyā, whatever its modality, is never truly connected with the self. Here, as in other differences that may be noticed between Saṁkara and his disciples, one may say that Saṁkara’s approach to truth is psychological and religious’’ (Ingalls, ‘‘Śaṅkara on the Question,’’ p. 72). Paul Hacker says: ‘‘Ś. in one passage of the Sbh . . . makes it clear that for him theorizing about the āśraya of avidyā is unimportant and contrary to the spirit of the teaching’’ (Hacker, ‘‘Distinctive Features of the Doctrine and Terminology of Śaṅkara,’’ p. 65). 29 – John Grimes, The Seven Great Untenables (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1990), p. 27. 30 – NS 3.1, p. 215 (Sanskrit), pp. 216–217 (English). The objections that Sureśvara raise are presented as follows: nanu ātmano ‘pi jñānasvarūpatvāt, ananytvāt, āśrayaāśrayibhāvasya bhedagarbhatvāt, jñānaprakrtitvāt, asaṅgatvanityamuktatvācca hetubhyo naivājñānam ghatate/. ˙ ˙ 31 – NS 3.1, p. 215 (Sanskrit), p. 217 (English). 32 – Seven objections are presented by Rāmūnuja in his Śrı̄bhāsya, and these objec˙ Śatadūsanı̄. These tions are also elaborated upon by Vedānta Deśika in his ˙ ˙ objections may briefly be summarized as: ‘‘(1) the very nature (svarūpa) of avidyā is riddled with contradictions; (2) its description as inexplicable (anirvacanı̄ya) is untenable; (3) no valid means of knowledge (pramāna) supports such ˙ a theory; (4) the locus (āśraya) of avidyā can be neither Brahman nor jı̄va; (5) it is unintelligible to claim that avidyā can obscure (tirodhāna) the nature of Brahman; (6) its removal by right knowledge (jñāna-nivartya) is untenable; (7) the very conception of the cessation of avidyā (avidyā-nirvrtti) is absurd’’ (John ˙ Grimes, The Seven Great Untenables, p. 22). 33 – RSBh 1.1.1, par. 60, p. 128. 34 – US 1.16.37–38, and BrUBh 4.1.6. ˙ 35 – ‘‘Brahman does exist as an unchanged Entity. There is no violation of the texts about partlessness, since partlessness is accepted on account of its very ‘mention in the Upanisad,’ and the Upanisads are the only authority about It, but not ˙ ˙ 200 Philosophy East & West so are the senses etc. . . . And even these powers can be known not from mere reasoning but from such [śruti] instruction . . .’’ (BSBh 2.1.27, pp. 354–355). 36 – BSBh 2.1.27, p. 356. 37 – There are a number of other examples cited by Śaṅkara dealing with allegedly contradictory qualities. In each case, he asserts that contradictions cannot exist and therefore one of the terms does not really exist. See, for example, his discussion of motion and motionlessness in BGBh 13.2.10. 38 – BSBh 2.1.28, pp. 356–357. 39 – ‘‘Holographic film typically has a resolution of 2,500 to 5,000 lines per millimeter . . . , in contrast to standard photographic film, which has about 200 lines per millimeter. The higher resolution is achieved by using smaller grains of the photosensitive silver in the emulsion. The smaller grains are less sensitive to light and decrease the ‘speed’ of the film substantially’’ (John Iovine, Homemade Holograms: The Complete Guide to Inexpensive, Do-It-Yourself Holography [Blue Ridge Summit, PA: TAB Books, 1990], p. 1). 40 – ‘‘[T]hese reconstructed images have a three-dimensional character because in addition to amplitude information, which is all that an ordinary photographic process stores, phase information also has been stored. This phase information is what provides the three-dimensional characteristics of the image, as it contains within it exact information on the depths and heights of the various contours of the object’’ (‘‘Holography,’’ in Encyclopedia Britannica, CD 1998, p. 2). 41 – Actually, it should be noted that a holographic image can be made to appear using any ‘‘reasonably coherent’’ light source as a reference beam. For example, the light from an ordinary light bulb that is not in phase can be used to present a holographic image, although the clarity of the image is better with a coherent light source. 42 – Parts of this description of holography have appeared previously in Kaplan, Different Paths, Different Summits. My appreciation to the publisher, Rowman and Littlefield. 43 – The use of these terms is indebted to David Bohm, the physicist whose work on quantum theory holds an important place in the field. Bohm, a student of Krishnamurti, also developed a holonomic model for undivided wholeness that reached from physics to philosophy. 44 – David Bohm, Wholeness and the Implicate Order (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980), p. 167. 45 – Mary Hesse, ‘‘Models and Analogy in Science,’’ in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 5, ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan and Free Press, 1967), p. 356. 46 – Bohm, Wholeness and the Implicate Order, p. 167. Stephen Kaplan 201 47 – The phrase ‘‘somewhat akin to Bohm’s proposal’’ is intentional since Bohm’s proposal is distinguished from the Advaita perspective because he see the fundamental nondualism as the holomovement. This holomovement is both static and dynamic, as has been noted earlier in my acknowledgment of the failure of this proposal to exclusively illuminate just the ātmavāda perspective without the anātma perspective. Second, Bohm’s proposal is different from the one developed by this author in Different Paths, Different Summits since Bohm conflates the nondualisms of Advaita and Buddhism, such as Yogācāra, whereas the aforementioned text maintains the differences between these schools. 48 – From a contemporary Advaita perspective, K. C. Bhattacharyya has said: ‘‘The individuality is understood as me, i.e. as the illusory objectivity of the subject and not merely illusory identity with the object taken as real. . . . The individual self means the self feeling itself embodied, the embodiment being only a restrictive adjective of the self; and the illusoriness of the embodiment is the illusoriness of the body itself and not merely of the self’s identity with it. The idea of the object, in fact, as distinct from the subject is derived from the idea of the embodiment, which itself is born in the consciousness of the individual self as false in respect of its individuality’’ (K. C. Bhattacharyya, Studies in Philosophy, ed. Gopinath Bhattacharyya [Calcutta: Progressive Publishers, 1956], vol. 1, p. 114). 49 – ‘‘Since a man without self-identification with the body, mind, senses, etc., cannot become a cognizer, and as such, the means of knowledge cannot function for him; since perception and other activities (of a man) are not possible without accepting the senses etc. (as his own); since the senses cannot function without (the body as) a basis; since nobody engages in any activity with a body that has not the idea of the Self superimposed on it; since the unrelated Self cannot become a cognizer unless there are all these (mutual superimposition of the Self and the body and their attributes on each other); and since the means of knowledge cannot function unless there is a cognizership; therefore it follows that the means of knowledge, such as direct perception as well as the scriptures, must have a man as their locus who is subject to nescience’’ (BSBh 1.1.1, p. 4). 50 – ‘‘Indeed ātman is said to be like ākāśa with the jı̄va being like the space of the pot. And this is an illustration in jāti (origination) by bodies like that from (the space of) a pot’’ (MK 3.3). 51 – rjuvakrādikābhāsamalātaspanditam yathā/ grahanagrāhakābhāsam vijñānas˙ ˙ ˙ ˙ panditam tathā// aspandamānamalātamanābhāsamajam yathā/ aspandamānam ˙ ˙ vijñānamanābhāsamajam tathā// (MK 4.47–48). ˙ 52 – Karl Potter makes the following comment about this analogy: ‘‘Gaudapāda’s use of it does not work very well [sic] it is left unexplained who or what˙ is analogous to the one who waves the stick. It is also not clear whether Gaudapāda ˙ invokes the analogy to help explain the generation of selves or empirical 202 Philosophy East & West objects from God, or of empirical objects by individual selves. His comments seem to suggest the latter, but this appears to conflict with more realistic passages elsewhere in the work’’ (Potter, Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, 3 : 84). The view to which this essay is now leaning suggests a third alternative built upon Potter’s second position. This essay is raising the possibility that for Gaudapāda and the Advaita tradition the individual self does not generate/ ˙ the empirical object, but unfolds for its own knowledge the enfolded nacreate ture of the empirical object. An exposition of this notion requires another essay. Stephen Kaplan 203