A Review of Richard Kearney's Strangers, Gods and Monsters

advertisement
THE HEDGEHOG REVIEW / FALL 03
FEARING THE OTHER—WITHIN AND
BEYOND
Timothy K. Beal
Timothy K. Beal is Harkness Professor of Biblical Literature and Director
of the Baker-Nord Center for the Humanities at Case Western Reserve
University. He is co-editor of the new book series, Afterlives of the Bible,
with the University of Chicago Press, and author, most recently, of Religion
and Its Monsters (2001) and Theory for Religious Studies (2004).
Kearney, Richard. Strangers, Gods and Monsters: Interpreting
Otherness. London: Routledge, 2003.
STRANGERS, GODS, AND MONSTERS ARE THE FORMS WE GIVE
otherness, that which is foreign, “not-us.” These figures appear in our
intellectual and cultural borderlands, calling into question what we
thought we could take for granted about ourselves, our society, and our
world. We encounter them at the edge of knowing, on the verge of
meaninglessness, where we feel our toes curling over the edge of the
abyss. Facing them, we experience a non-rational, vertiginous mixture
of fear and desire, repulsion and fascination. The limit experiences
brought on by such strangers, gods, and monsters may elicit repulsion,
causing us to pull back from the edge at which they appear, but they
may also elicit desire, drawing us over that edge into new and unknown
possibilities. These possibilities include new forms of relationship, community, even grace and redemption, but also paralysis, melancholy,
even self-annihilation. How do we negotiate such limit experiences?
How do we know the gods from the monsters? What is to be done?
108
F E A R I N G T HTEI TOLTEH/E A
R U/ TBHEO
AR
L
It is precisely on this precarious edge of possibility, this liminal noplace between the known and unknown, between fear and desire, that
philosopher Richard Kearney lingers. His ambition is to address the
impossible necessity and necessary impossibility of finding ways to
speak about the unspeakable and think about the unthinkable—in
short, to interpret otherness.
Philosophy’s Abiding Enigma
Kearney explores these figures of otherness as
tokens of fracture within the human psyche. They speak to
us of how we are split between conscious and unconscious,
familiar and unfamiliar, same and other. And they remind
us that we have a choice: (a) to try to understand and
accommodate our experience of strangeness, or (b) repudiate it by projecting it exclusively onto outsiders. (4)
More often than not, we choose the latter, turning others into monstrous scapegoats as a means of purging ourselves of the otherness within. Kearney, on the other hand, chooses the former. Because “if
philosophers are indeed enjoined to know themselves, they do well to
continue concerning themselves with this inaugural and abiding enigma of the monster within” (14).
For the most part, Western philosophy has relegated the task of getting
to know our monsters to art and religion, banishing all such “puzzlements provoked by ‘strangeness’ to the realm of Unreason.” As a result,
“the Other has passed from the horizon of reflective understanding into
the invisible, unspeakable, unthinkable dark” (7). But Kearney is convinced that the project of enlightenment itself “will remain unenlightened until it comes to terms with the strangers, gods and monsters that
it has all too often ostracized or ignored” (5). He brings these ostracized others back into the fold of philosophy. In the process, he brings
philosophy into closer fellowship with art and religion.
109
THE HEDGEHOG REVIEW / FALL 03
Indeed, Kearney does his philosophy in and through works of art,
“exploring the diverse ways in which human ideas, images and narratives have tried to say the unsayable” (229). Each of the book’s ten
chapters draws on visual or literary artistic representations of otherness
in order to raise key philosophical problems and suggest ways of working them through. His brilliant close readings of the mother-monster
in Ridley Scott’s Alien movies and Colonel Kurtz in Francis Ford
Coppola’s Apocalypse Now Redux, for example, reveal “the ways in which
our most feared monsters can serve as uncanny doubles for our all-toohuman selves” (50). His visit to the Terrors and Wonders exhibit at the
DeCordova museum on September 14, 2001 opens a profound space
for thinking about our complex responses to the terrorist attacks of
September 11. And his interpretations of the ghosts of Shakespeare’s
Hamlet and Joyce’s Ulysses lead to reflections on the power of narrative
to recollect traumatic memory in such a way as to transfigure melancholy into mourning.
What Is To Be Done?
Kearney is particularly concerned with what we might call the theological ambiguity of otherness, which raises for him the key question of
ethical discernment. How do we distinguish between different kinds of
otherness? Between
those aliens and strangers that need our care and hospitality, no matter how monstrous they might first appear …
and those others that really do seek to destroy and exterminate? Or to take one of the most ancient examples of ethical discernment, how are we to differentiate between the
voice that bade Abraham kill Isaac and the voice that forbade him do to so? (10)
How, that is, do we discriminate between “enabling and disabling forms
of alterity” (67)?
One of the ways Kearney frames this problem is in relation to my own
book, Religion and Its Monsters (33–5; 42–3; 120–2), which explores
110
F E A R I N G T HTEI TOLTEH/E A
R U/ TBHEO
AR
L
monstrous horror as a kind of religious phenomenon. Monsters, I suggest, raise profound theological questions that are not always so welcome in more traditional, mainstream religious contexts. In the process,
they tend to amplify theological problems over theological solutions.
Consider, for example, some of the questions raised in classic monster
tales such as the Beowulf poem and Bram Stoker’s Dracula. If everything comes from God, is God not the author of evil as well as good,
chaos as well as order? What is evil, anyway, and where does it come
from? Is it, as Professor Van Helsing says in Dracula, rooted deep in all
good? Is immortality always desirable? Is redemption always possible?
Are some, like Count Dracula or Grendel, chosen for curse while others are chosen for blessing?
Perhaps the most radical theological problem raised by the monstrous—
the one Kearney is particularly concerned to address—is the confusion
of gods and monsters in culture and in our imaginations. Frankenstein’s
monster, for example, presses the question: Who is more monstrous, the
Creature or the Creator? Even more radically, films like Nosferatu and
Shadow of the Vampire go so far as to present the monster as a revelation
of dreadful yet fascinating religious otherness, a radically heterodoxical
envoy of the divine. If the Frankenstein stories ask whether God is a
monster, these films ask whether the monster is a god.
That there is a slippery slope between gods and monsters is not a new
idea. As personifications of otherness, the monsters of supernatural
horror are often identified with the divine, especially with its more
dreadful, maleficent aspects. And the experience of fear and horror in
the face of the monstrous is akin in many respects to religious experience: both are often represented as encounters with a mysterious otherness that elicits a vertigo-like combination of dread and fascination.
Indeed, in his classic 1917 essay on religious experience, The Idea of the
Holy, historian of religions Rudolph Otto considered the monstrous
(Leviathan in Job, for example) as an apt expression of the holy in all
its aspects of overwhelming awe, wonder, and dread—what he called
the mysterium tremendum.
Strangers, Gods and Monsters pushes the discussion about the confusion
of gods and monsters to another level by asking the very practical ques-
111
THE HEDGEHOG REVIEW / FALL 03
tion, What is to be done? How do we move beyond the apparent ambiguity and confusion brought on by such encounters with otherness
toward some kind of practical understanding and ethical discernment?
In this regard, Kearney is critical of a certain trend in the thinking of
some contemporary philosophy (e.g., in some work by Slavoj Zizek and
Jean-François Lyotard) that treats otherness as unmediatable, untranslatable, and ultimately sublime. Kearney describes this trend as the “postmodern notion of the monstrous sublime” (83). To this way of thinking,
as Kearney explains it, the human experience of radical otherness is an
encounter with that which is absolutely beyond representation, beyond
ethical discernment, and certainly beyond any ethical notion of the
divine as good. Here there is no distinction between radical evil and
divinity; these are simply terms we employ in order to translate the otherness, which is entirely ineffable, into familiar terms and concepts.
To a point, Kearney sympathizes with the intention behind this notion
of the radically transcendent, ineffable other. Too often philosophy has
erred in the opposite direction, reducing all otherness and difference to
sameness and unity. Nonetheless, he finds reason for ethical concern,
for such a position in relation to otherness leaves us speechless and paralyzed, unable to judge between different encounters with otherness.
(Such is not the case, by the way, for Otto, who was closer to Kant in
seeing moral judgment not as an overcoming or suppression of the
wholly other but as a consummation of it, that is, a “completion and
charging of it with new content.”)
The postmodern “teratology of the sublime,” Kearney argues, leaves no
opening for an ethical response, as if the awesome and awful sublimity
of Hiroshima, the eruption of Mount St. Helens, the collapse of the
World Trade Center, and a Colorado wildfire are indistinguishable in
their radical otherness.
Oneself-as-Another
Kearney proposes a practical alternative to either (a) positing otherness
as radically beyond comprehension and accommodation or (b) conflat-
112
F E A R I N G T HTEI TOLTEH/E A
R U/ TBHEO
AR
L
ing it with the self, thereby reducing it to sameness. “The trick,” he
suggests, is “not to let the foreign become too foreign or the familiar too
familiar.” Borrowing his terms from Paul Ricoeur’s Oneself as Another,
Kearney describes this in-between approach as the “critical hermeneutics of oneself-as-another” (77–81). Between the extremes of homogeneity and heterology, this approach is dialogical, seeking “to make us
more hospitable to strangers, gods and monsters without succumbing
to mystique or madness” (18). To do so involves an interpretive process
of de-alienating otherness by coming to recognize oneself as other and
the other as another self. We need to approach the other with the
understanding that otherness is “both within us and beyond us” (229).
This process of understanding “not only alters the ego into a self-asanother but guarantees that the other, for its part, retains a basic fluidity and equivocity. The other is neither too close nor too far, neither
too familiar nor too foreign, to escape my attention” (81).
Kearney recommends three ways of enacting this critical hermeneutics
of oneself-as-another. Each way effectively takes the allure out of some
postmodern theorizing about radical otherness as it moves into the realm
of praxis. First, there is practical understanding, a kind of judgment-inpractice that is turned toward the future with the aim of acting against
evil, especially the suffering of others. Such an understanding will always
be tentative and provisional, always involving some degree of ambiguity,
but it is necessary if one is to move from reflection to action in order to
prevent or stop unnecessary or unjustifiable suffering in the world.
Second, there is working-through one’s own experience. We each suffer
our own evils. The concern in working-through is to keep such suffering
from destroying oneself, and this, Kearney believes, requires moving
beyond passive lament and melancholy into active complaint, refusing
to be brought down, refusing to be dehumanized (104). Third, there is
pardon, or forgiveness. Even the most atrocious acts are done by human
beings, and we must be able to recognize our own human potential for
atrocity within those very acts. Without pardon, we remain caught up
in endless cycles of revenge that only serve to polarize self and other.
Here Kearney quotes Pascal approvingly: “Comprendre, c’est pardoner.”
To understand is to forgive. Even in the face of the most atrocious, most
monstrously sublime of terrors, borne of the most hateful of human
imaginings, there is no understanding without pardon.
113
THE HEDGEHOG REVIEW / FALL 03
Whoever Fights Monsters
Strangers, Gods and Monsters navigates some extremely difficult intellectual and cultural terrain. Yet no matter how rough the going gets,
Kearney’s writing remains conversational and inviting. He never introduces a philosophical concept or problem without explaining it in lay
terms. Indeed, it is clear throughout that he writes with the heart of a
teacher, and that this book emerges from years of experience in the
classroom exploring these same topics with students. With a combination of philosophical rigor, clear-headedness, and generosity that we
have come to expect from Kearney, Strangers, Gods and Monsters brings
to the table many insights and at least as many questions as he invites
us to get to know our others and, in the process, ourselves in new and
transformative ways.
These days, in the on-going “War on Terror,” we are only too familiar
with the desire in mainstream American culture and political discourse
to make monsters out of enemy others, imbuing them with diabolical
power and construing “our” war against them as a holy war of absolute
good against absolute evil. This war depends on maintaining “terror”
and its agents as monstrously, radically other, uninterpretable, beyond
all human comprehension and practical understanding. Nietzsche
warned that “Whoever fights monsters should see to it that in the
process he does not become a monster.” Indeed. Kearney reminds us
that seeing to this does not mean that we must never fight monsters.
But when we do, we must recognize ourselves in them.
114
Download