Cross-Cutting Cleavages and Government Spending∗ Erik Snowberg Stanford GSB snowberg@stanford.edu www.stanford.edu/∼ esnowber [Secondary Economics Job Market Paper ] Abstract When racial groups differ in terms of their political sensitivity—the propensity of group members to change their vote based on changes in redistribution promised by a candidate—the racial composition of a political jurisdiction affects redistributive policy even when preferences are correlated only with income. Furthermore, the extent to which race and class are cross-cutting is important. Although the concept of crosscutting cleavages is well-known in political science and sociology, its implications have yet to be analyzed formally. This paper formally defines, develops and tests a model of cross-cutting cleavages to better understand the complex relationships between race, class, preferences, political sensitivity and redistributive policy. I show that the effect of cross-cutting cleavages on redistributive policy depends critically on economic parity—the ratio of average black income to average income. The cross-cutting cleavages model makes six predictions that are all supported by data from large U.S. cities between 1942 and 1972. ∗ I thank Keith Krehbiel, David Baron, Gerard Padró-i-Miquel and Romain Wacziarg for their support and insightful comments. This work was supported in part by the SIEPR Dissertation Fellowship through a grant to the Stanford Institute for Economic Policy Research. 1 Introduction How does the racial composition of a jurisdiction affect redistributive policy, such as the taxation and spending decisions of governments? Recent research rationalizes observed correlations between racial composition and redistributive policy by assuming that the preferences of the median voter, and thus policy, change based on the racial composition of a jurisdiction (Alesina, Baqir and Easterly, 1999; Lind, 2007).1 This is in contrast with canonical models of the size of government which assume that preferences for redistribution are correlated only with income (Romer, 1975; Roberts, 1977; Meltzer and Richard, 1981). This paper focuses on how behavior affects the mapping from preferences to redistributive policies when racial and class cleavages are cross-cutting. Similar to canonical models of the size of government, the theory does not assume any differences in preferences for redistribution within a class: the poor like it and the rich dislike it regardless of race. In the cross-cutting cleavages model, changes in racial composition, or the racial cleavage, of a jurisdiction alter redistributive policies due to persistent differences between racial groups in political sensitivity. Political sensitivity is broadly defined to include the propensity of citizens to vote, and if they do vote, their willingness to change their vote based on slight changes in redistribution promised by a candidate. Political sensitivity is similar to an elasticity of votes from a group with respect to changes in redistribution promised by a candidate. The cross-cutting cleavages model is an extension of the redistributive politics framework of Lindbeck and Weibull (1987) and Dixit and Londregan (1996) and is motivated by data on political sensitivity in U.S. cities between 1942 and 1972. In this framework, redistributive policy, specifically the equilibrium tax rate, is determined by the relative sizes and political sensitivities of the rich and the poor. Political sensitivity has not been widely and consistently 1 Austen-Smith and Wallerstein (2006), in the only other formal study of redistribution involving both race and class, study redistribution in the presence of affirmative action policies. Alesina, Baqir and Easterly (1999) intend their model to describe only spending on productive public goods, although it could be applied to more general redistributive policies. Marxists believe that race is used by the capitalist class to create divisions among workers. See Wilson (1978) for a summary. For a formal treatment of this theory see Roemer (1998) and Lee, Roemer and Van der Straeten (2007). 1 measured. To address this measurement limitation and to generate testable predictions, the cross-cutting cleavages model focuses on cities in the United States between 1942 and 1972, years during which within each race the rich were more politically sensitive than the poor and within each class whites were more politically sensitive than blacks. There are two main contributions of the model. The first contribution is to formally define and study the implications of cross-cutting cleavages in redistributive politics. Crosscutting cleavages is an old concept from political science that has not been formalized. A cleavage is simply a trait that divides a society into a number of groups. In the extreme, when two cleavages are reinforcing, both cleavages define the same groups. To the extent that cleavages define different groups—for example if there are both rich and poor whites and blacks—they cross-cut to some extent. The degree of cross-cuttingness thus describes a pattern of groups in a jurisdiction. Specifically, I define the cross-cuttingness of the racial and class cleavage as the correlation between race and income. That is, if knowing a citizen’s race does not increase the accuracy of a prediction of his or her class, then cleavages are said to be perfectly cross-cutting. In contrast, if knowing a citizen’s race allows a perfect prediction of his or her class, then cleavages are perfectly reinforcing. Cross-cuttingness is parameterized here by a new variable, economic parity—the ratio of average black income to average income. If economic parity is less than one, that is, blacks are on average poorer than whites, then a rise in economic parity increases the cross-cuttingness of the racial and class cleavages, holding constant the proportion of the city that is black (the racial cleavage) and average income (the class cleavage). The theory predicts that this change will lead to an increase in tax rates and government spending. This is true even blacks are on average richer than whites, at which point the racial and class cleavage become less cross-cutting with an increase in economic parity. Thus, the relationship between the cross-cuttingness of the racial and class cleavages and redistributive policy is non-monotonic and depends on specific parameters of the model. 2 Despite the fact that the concept of cross-cutting cleavages has not been formally studied, it has been linked to many outcomes of interest. For example, (Lipset, 1960, pp. 88-89) notes “[T]he chances for stable democracy are enhanced to the extent that groups and individuals have a number of crosscutting, politically relevant affiliations.” Lowi (1964, p. 697) summarizes the work of pluralists on cross-cutting cleavages: “Truman (1951), for instance, stresses overlapping membership as a source of conflict ... In contrast, Bauer, Pool and Dexter (1963) found that ... this very overlapping membership was a condition for cohesion.” Underlying these conclusions of a monotonic effect of cross-cutting cleavages on the outcomes of interest is an assertion about how cross-cutting cleavages affect the ability of groups to overcome collective action problems. Here, in contrast, cross-cutting cleavages affect outcomes in a non-monotonic way and have an effect without assertions about collective action problems. The second main contribution of the model is to show that when racial groups differ in terms of their political sensitivity, the racial composition of a jurisdiction affects redistributive policy even when preferences are correlated only with income. Thus, observed correlations between racial composition and redistributive policy can be rationalized without speculative assumptions about preferences. This is advantageous as the components of political sensitivity, especially turnout, are much easier to document than the preferences of large groups of individuals. The model makes six predictions, all of which are supported by data from large U.S. cities between 1942 and 1972. As discussed below, many of these predictions differ from those in the existing literature. Moreover, when politicians can flexibly target spending to different groups the predictions of the cross-cutting cleavages model continue to hold while previous models, such as those of Meltzer and Richard (1981) and Alesina, Baqir and Easterly (1999), which are based on the median voter framework, cannot make predictions. 3 2 The Model This section describes and then formalizes the setup and equilibrium of the cross-cutting cleavages model. It concludes with a subsection that justifies the ordering of political sensitivity between rich and poor blacks and whites. The explanations of the results in Section 3 depend on the lemma and terms defined in this section. The model describes an election in a city in which citizens vote for one of two candidates based on their policy platforms. Platforms are binding and consist of a tax rate and level of government spending. Citizens are characterized by their economic class and their race. These characteristics are associated with different levels of political sensitivity. A citizen’s class also induces a particular tradeoff between preferences for taxes and government spending: the rich have a lower ideal tax rate than the poor as is common in probabilistic voting models. The electoral model is symmetric, and in equilibrium the candidates propose the same platform. That platform maximizes a sum of weighted citizens’ utilities, where the weights are given by the political sensitivity of the citizen’s class-race group. The resulting tax rate lies between the ideal tax rates of the rich and the poor, and an increase in the political sensitivity of one class moves the tax rate closer to that class’s ideal tax rate. More formally, there is a unit measure of infinitesimal citizens. A citizen’s class is either rich or poor i ∈ {R, P }, and her race is either black or white j ∈ {B, W }. The rich here would be more accurately described as middle-class—the label rich is used for congruence with the literature. There are thus four class-race groups indexed by ij ∈ {RW, RB, P W, P B}. The P proportion of a city from each group is given by λij ∈ [0, 1] where ij λij = 1. The proportion of the city from class i is λi = λiB + λiW , i ∈ {R, P }, and the proportion of a city from race j is λj = λRj + λP j , j ∈ {B, W }. Groups also differ in terms of their political sensitivity. The political sensitivity ψ ij ≥ 0 of a class-race group ij is defined to include the propensity of citizens in that group to vote, and if they do vote, their willingness to change their vote based in slight changes in a candidate’s redistributive platform. The demographics of a city are illustrated in Figure 1. 4 Figure 1: A city is composed of rich and poor blacks and whites. Poor citizens have exogenous pre-tax income y P regardless of race, and rich citizens have exogenous income y R > y P regardless of race. The average income of race j is y j = P λRj y R +λP j y P , and the average income of the city is y = ij λij y i . The utility U ij of a citizen λj from class i and race j is specified as U ij (τ, g) = (1 − τ )y i + log(g), (1) where τ is a linear tax on income and g is per capita government spending. A citizen’s ideal tax rate, when spending is constrained to equal tax revenue, depends only on his or her own income, that is, preferences are solely class based as discussed in the introduction. Rich and poor citizens have the same utility tradeoff between consumption (1 − τ )y i and government spending g.2 2 The assumption that government spending is valued as the log of spending allows for a sharp prediction about the effect of an increase in average income on the equilibrium tax rate in Propostion 1. If government spending is valued according to some arbitrary strictly increasing, strictly concave function most results still hold. Blacks may have a greater demand for government spending than whites (i.e. Bergstrom, Rubinfeld and Shapiro (1982)), however, Rubinfield, Shapiro and Roberts (1987) show that this statistical pattern 5 There are two candidates, and each candidate chooses a platform to maximize his or her vote share subject to the constraint that spending is less than tax revenue g ≤ τ y. As candidates do not differ in any substantive way, in equilibrium both candidates propose the same platform, as shown in Appendix A. As preferences in (1) do not depend on race, this platform maximizes a sum of the weighted utilities of the rich and the poor. The weight for i class i is its political prominence ψ λi , the product of the class’s average political sensitivity i ψ = λiB ψ iB +λiW ψ iW λi and size λi . Furthermore, in equilibrium the budget constraint binds and per capita tax revenue τ y equals per capita spending g. These terms will be used synonymously for spending. Intuitively, for a fixed size, groups that are more likely to change their votes based on changes in a candidate’s platform are more likely to swing the results of the election. Candidates target these politically sensitive groups by moving their platform closer to the group’s ideal policy to gain a greater vote share. For a fixed level of political sensitivity larger groups can provide more votes, and hence greater swings in total vote share, which enhances the group’s political prominence. The equilibrium tax rate τ∗ and per capita tax revenue g∗ = τ∗ y are thus a function of the vector of population proportions ~λ = {λRW , λRB , λP B , λP W }, the vector of political ~ = {ψ RW , ψ RB , ψ P B , ψ P W }, and the vector of incomes ~y = {y R , y P }. The results sensitivity ψ ~ and examine demographic changes—that is, changes in ~λ, the in Section 3 fix ~y and ψ proportion of the population in each group. Section 4, which deals with robustness of the theory, examines changes in the underlying income ~y of the rich and poor on the equilibrium. Demographic changes effect the equilibrium tax rate τ∗ and per capita tax revenue g∗ = P τ∗ y through the relative political prominence of the poor ψ λP , R ψ λR the ratio of the political prominence of the poor to the political prominence of the rich. Lemma 1 Changes in the equilibrium tax rate associated with any demographic change are P in the same direction as changes in the relative political prominence of the poor ψ λP R ψ λR asso- arises due to a failure to account for the lower geographic mobility of blacks. 6 ciated with that demographic change. P If the relative political prominence of the poor ψ λP R ψ λR increases, so will the relative weight of the poor in the candidate’s vote share maximization. Politicians respond by moving their proposed tax rate closer to the ideal tax rate of the poor. Thus, the equilibrium tax rate rises. In contrast, consider a purely economic baseline—a social planner who maximizes total social welfare. Since a social planner maximizes the unweighted sum of citizen’s utilities, this is the same as the cross-cutting cleavages model when all class-race groups had the same level of political sensitivity. The tax rate set by the social planner τs∗ = 1 y depends only on average income, whereas in the cross-cutting cleavages model the tax rate depends on the relative political prominence of the poor. This highlights the role of politics in setting a tax rate that differs from the economic baseline in the cross-cutting cleavages model. 2.1 Political Sensitivity The relative political sensitivity of each class-race group ij is central to the predictions of the model. Verba and Nie (1972), and Section 5.4, finds blacks are less likely to vote than whites, and individuals with high socio-economic status are more likely to vote than individuals with low socio-economic status. Verba, Schlozman and Brady (1995) finds similar patterns that extend (often more strongly) to other political behavior such as participating in protests and contributing to campaigns. Wilson (1960) and Dawson (1994) show that blacks are more committed to one party or the other than whites. Wilson (1960) and Banfield and Wilson (1963) find that blacks are more likely to be part of a local political machine, and hence less politically sensitive than whites during the period under study. Pinderhughes (1987, p. 113), in her study of Chicago politics, summarizes the difference in political sensitivity between black and white voters as, “[B]lack voters ... consistently, almost uniformly, commit themselves to the party, faction or individual candidate that is most supportive of racial reform.” 7 As the above references make clear, a larger percentage of high-income than low-income individuals vote, so the rich are more politically sensitive than the poor ψ Rj > ψ P j . Furthermore, a lower proportion of blacks than whites turnout to vote, and blacks are more likely to be committed to one candidate or the other, so blacks are less politically sensitive than ~ where the whites ψ iB < ψ iW . This establishes a partial ordering on political sensitivity ψ, relationship between ψ RB and ψ P W is not determined. This ordering is sufficient to produce the sharp predictions that are derived in the next section.3 3 Results To generate predictions that can be tested with data available for the period under study, the equilibrium tax rate can be re-written in terms of the variables of interest: average income y, the proportion black λB and economic parity yB —the y ratio of average black income to average B income. Thus, the equilibrium tax rate will be written as τ∗ (y, λB , yy ) and the equilibrium B level of per capita tax revenue will be written as g∗ (y, λB , yy ). Taking a partial derivative of the equilibrium tax rate with respect to one of the variables of interest implicitly keeps the other two constant. This leads to straightforward tests of the model since the coefficient on one of the variables of interest from a regression which includes all three variables of interest is the estimated effect of changing that variable keeping the other two constant. The variables of interest were chosen because a changes in these variables map into changes in a particular aspect of the cleavage structure: a change in average income y alters the class cleavage, a change in the proportion black λB alters the racial cleavage, and a change in economic parity yB y alters the cross-cuttingness of the racial and class cleavage, or, given the definition of cross-cuttingness in Section 1, the statistical independence of race 3 The model does not take into account the potential endogeneity of political sensitivity. For example, Washington (2006) finds that having black candidates on the ballot changes turnout patterns. This is not be a particular concern, as in her study both white and black turnout increases at levels that are roughly proportional to the overall turnout level of each group. In addition, Alesina and La Ferrara (2000) find that other forms of engagement respond to the level of diversity in a community. 8 and class.4 The following three subsections examine how the equilibrium tax rate changes with an increase in one of the variables of interest. Each subsection begins by describing the demographic change that increases one of the variables of interest keeping the other two constant. This demographic change combined with Lemma 1 provides the intuition for how the equilibrium tax rate changes with the variable of interest. Each subsection concludes with a brief discussion of the result and any associated corollaries. The final subsection considers spending that may be targeted to different class-race groups and derives a testable prediction about per capita welfare spending. 3.1 Changes in Class Composition Consider a change in class composition, such as increasing the proportion rich and thus average income, holding the other two variables of interest constant. This creates four constraints that specify how the the proportions of the population ~λ change. An increase in average income y, holding constant the proportion black λB and economic parity yB , y changes the underlying proportions of class-race groups as illustrated in Figure 2. Because the proportion black is unchanged, there is no change in the racial cleavage. A greater R proportion of the city is rich, which increases their political prominence ψ λR . Because the rich favor a lower tax rate τ politicians curry favor with this increasingly important group by reducing the tax rate. Proposition 1 An increase in average income, holding constant the proportion black and B economic parity, decreases the equilibrium tax rate: ∂τ∗ (y,λB , yy ) ∂y < 0. 4 Changes in average income, y, and the proportion black, λB , have effects on the statistical independence of the race and class cleavages. However, these effects cannot be signed, whereas a change in economic parity, yB y , has unambiguous effects on the orthoganality of race and class. The definition of cross-cuttingness here differs from Rae and Taylor (1970). Their measure of cross-cuttingness is based on the increase in fractionalization introduced by adding another cleavage. 9 Figure 2: An increase in average income alters the class cleavage. This prediction is in contrast to that of the median voter model of the size of government, such as the two class version of the Meltzer and Richard (1981) model in Persson and Tabellini (2000, Chapter 3.3). The median voter model predicts that an increase in the proportion of the population that is rich generally raises the tax rate. This occurs because the median voter, who is poor, votes for a higher tax rate because there is now more money in the city to appropriate for his or her purposes. Because the median voter model makes predictions about per capita tax revenue g = τ y the prediction that the tax rate will rise holds as long as average income does not increase too much. If average income increases rapidly, the predicted increase in per capita tax revenue may be accompanied by a decrease in the tax rate. The cross-cutting cleavages model considered here has the reverse indeterminacy—when average income increases, the direction of the change in tax rates is well defined, but the diB B rection of the change in per capita tax revenue g∗ (y, λB , yy ) = τ∗ (y, λB , yy )y is indeterminate B because τ∗ (y, λB , yy ) decreases and y increases. 10 Figure 3: An increase in the proportion black alters the racial cleavage. Corollary 1 An increase in average income, holding constant the proportion black and economic parity, has an indeterminate effect on equilibrium per capita tax revenue. 3.2 Changes in Racial Composition A change in the proportion black λB , keeping average income y and economic parity yB y fixed, maintains the proportion of the black population that is rich. Because average income is kept constant, for every increase in the proportion of poor (rich) blacks, there must be a corresponding decrease in the proportion of poor (rich) whites. If average black income is less than average white income, y B < y, as illustrated in Figure 3, this implies that the proportion of the white population that is rich must increase slightly. 11 Proposition 2 An increase in the proportion of the city that is black, holding constant average income and economic parity, depends on the relative difference in political sensitivity between races across classes, ψ P W −ψ P B . ψ RW −ψ RB In particular, the tax rate increases if and only if: ψP W − ψP B <Q ψ RW − ψ RB P where Q = ψ λP λRB . R ψ λR λP B The equilibrium tax rate increases with the proportion black if the difference in political sensitivity between blacks and whites across the poor is smaller than the difference in political sensitivity between blacks and whites across the rich. How much smaller depends on Q. Intuitively, if the difference in political sensitivity is higher across the rich, an increase in the proportion of the city that is black reduces the average political sensitivity of the rich more than it reduces the average political sensitivity of the poor. This increases the relative political prominence of the poor, so by Lemma 1, the equilibrium tax rate increases. Alesina, Baqir and Easterly (1999) predict that if the proportion black is less than onehalf, an increase in the proportion black decreases spending on productive public goods. If the logic of their model is extended to all government spending, then the prediction of the cross-cutting cleavages model stands in contrast, as spending may increase with the proportion black. Interestingly, this is not the result of blacks being on average poorer than whites, as the average income of the population and of blacks are both held constant in the proposition. Rather, the predictions are driven by differences in political sensitivity between races that depend on class. The theory here depends on an inequality, the direction of which is uncertain based on previous research. In the empirical section, the limited data on turnout, a component of political sensitivity, will be examined to see if the statistical patterns in that data match those implied by the statistical patterns in taxation data and Proposition 2. Additionally, the next two subsections derive testable predictions that depend on whether the tax rate 12 Figure 4: The cross-cuttingness of the race and class cleavage increase with economic parity. increases or decreases with an increase in the proportion black. 3.3 The Effects of Cross-Cuttting Cleavages The final variable of interest, economic parity yB , y is unique to this model.5 An increase in economic parity, holding constant average income y and the proportion black λB , corresponds to an increase in the proportion of blacks that are rich, and a corresponding increase in the proportion of whites that are poor, as illustrated in Figure 4. The proportion of the rich that are black and the proportion of the poor that are white both increase with economic parity. This increases the average political sensitivity of the poor and decreases the average political sensitivity of the rich as blacks are less politically sensitive than whites. Because average income y is held constant, the proportion of the city that is rich (or poor) does not change. Thus, the relative political prominence of the poor 5 The ratio of average black income to average white income is used in sociological studies as a measure of economic deprivation of blacks rather than as a parameterization of the cross-cuttingness of racial and class cleavages. See for example Spilerman (1970) and Olzak, Shanahan and McEneaney (1996). 13 P ψ λP R ψ λR rises, leading politicians to increase the tax rate. Proposition 3 An increase in economic parity, holding constant the proportion black and B average income, increases the equilibrium tax rate: ∂τ∗ (y,λB , yy ) B ∂ yy > 0. If average black income is less than average income y B < y as in Figure 4, an increase in economic parity yB y brings the racial and class cleavages closer to statistical independence. That is, the cleavages become more cross-cutting. However, if average black income is greater than average income, then an increase in economic parity will decrease the cross-cuttingness of the racial and class cleavages. Regardless of whether cross-cuttingness increases or deB creases, an increase in economic parity increases the equilibrium tax rate, τ∗ (y, λB , yy ). This shows the difficulty of making general predictions about the effects of cross-cutting cleavages. To understand the effects of increasing or decreasing levels of cross-cuttingness, one must be specific about which cleavages one is examining, and how the groups created by those cleavages relate to one another through political and economic mechanisms. Finally, the previous two propositions lead to a straightforward corollary. Corollary 2 A change in the proportion black or in economic parity, keeping the other two variables of interest fixed, leads to changes in the equilibrium level of per capita tax revenue that are in the same direction as changes in the equilibrium tax rate. A change in either the proportion black λB or economic parity yB y keeps average income y B B fixed. Thus, the change in per capita tax revenue g∗ (y, λB , yy ) = τ∗ (y, λB , yy )y will be in the same direction as, and proportional to, the change in the tax rate. 3.4 Targeted Government Spending The data analyzed in Section 5 provides information on aggregate local government spending in several categories. Only one of these categories, spending on public welfare, can be thought of as targeted to a particular group, in this case the poor. To utilize these data, an additional 14 prediction that depends on whether the equilibrium tax rate increases or decreases with an increase in the proportion black (Proposition 2), is derived in this subsection when politicians can target spending to different groups. There are several reasons why a politician may be able to target spending to some groups while excluding others. For example, there may be intrinsic differences in preferences for different types of spending between groups. Additionally, to the extent that different groups live in different areas of a city, politicians may be able to target spending to certain groups that would be preferred equally by all groups: all citizens might like spending on parks, but only if the park is located in their neighborhood. Preferences are now specified as i j σ σ 1 log + log , U (τ, ~σ ) = (1 − τ )y + i 2 λ λj ij i (2) where σ i is spending directed to class i ∈ {R, P } and σ j is spending directed to race j ∈ {B, W }. As shown in Subsection 4.1, all the previous results continue to hold with this utility function. This utility function captures the intuition that, for example, rich and poor blacks both have some similar preferences (σ j ) and some dissimilar preferences (σ i ) over types of government spending.6 In addition, the value to a citizen of spending targeted to race is independent of a citizen’s class, and each citizen values per capita spending directed to race and class equally.7 6 Wilson (1978) argues that class is more important than race in black political identities. Other scholars, such as Huckfeldt and Kohfeld (1989) disagree. This utility function takes the middle ground on this issue by considering both. 7 The assumption that the rich might like increased government spending because it can be targeted to them differs from the theoretical literature on this subject. However, it is clear that such targeting is feasible. For example, in the period under study, Katzman (1968), Owen (1972) and Sexton (1961) all find that education spending favors the rich in various municipalities. In other types of government expenditure, Martin (1969) and Levy, Meltsner and Wildavsky (1974) both find that library expenditures primarily benefit the rich, and Community Council of Greater New York (1963) finds that the rich benefit more from parks than the poor do. 15 In equilibrium, the level of spending on race or class k ∈ {R, P, B, W }, σ∗k is: k σ∗k ψ λk = , 2γ R P ψ λR y R + ψ λP y P where γ = . y (3) Holding γ constant, total spending on a race or class increases with the political prominence of that group. Groups that are more sensitive and larger, thus more likely to be pivotal in voting, are better provided for by politicians than small and politically insensitive groups. Proposition 4 An increase in the proportion black, holding constant average income and economic parity, will increase per capita spending on the poor if and only if the equilibrium tax rate increases: ∂σ∗P ≥0 ∂λB B ⇐⇒ ∂τ∗ (y, λB , yy ) ∂λB ≥ 0. In Proposition 2, whether tax rates rise or fall with an increase in the proportion black depends on how that change affected the relative political prominence of the rich and poor. When the relative political prominence of the poor increases, so does the tax rate - but as can be seen from (3) this is also the condition that leads to an increase in per capita spending on the poor.8 Changing racial composition has several well specified effects even though preferences do not depend on race. Instead, the cross-cutting cleavages model makes sharp predictions ~ In sumwith only an empirically supported ordering on the vector of political sensitivities ψ. mary, when the proportion black increases, holding constant average income and economic parity, the equilibrium tax rate, per-capita tax revenue and per-capita spending on the poor all increase or all decrease depending on the values of the vector of political sensitivities. Specifically, all three of these variables will rise if and only if the difference in political sensitivity between blacks and whites across the poor is smaller than the difference in political 8 Per-capita spending on the poor may increase or decrease with an increase in average income or economic parity. The intuition above does not apply in those cases because it ignores the effect of increasing the political prominence of the poor on γ. In the case of an increase in the proportion black this omission is inconsequential, but it is important when considering increases in average income or economic parity. 16 sensitivity between blacks and whites across the rich. 4 Robustness of the Theory This section establishes that the above predictions are robust to relaxing two assumptions, and makes no new testable predictions. First, it finds that all the main results hold when politicians can very flexibly target spending to groups. Second, changes in the parameters of interest driven by changes in the income of the rich and poor, rather than changes in the population proportions of different groups, do not alter the main results. 4.1 Targeting Suppose there are K different types of government spending, σ k , k ∈ {1, 2, 3, ..., K}. A citizen in class i and race j then has utility given by: U ij (τ, ~σ ) (1 − τ )y i + = K X k αijk log k=1 s.t. K X k=1 where the condition PK k=1 αijk = 1 , X βk σ ij ij λ 1{αijk >0} ! P (4) λij αijk > 0 , β k ∈ (0, 1] ij αijk = 1 ensures that each class-race group ij has the same utility tradeoff between government spending and consumption. This maintains the earlier assumption that preferences over tax rates depend only on a citizen’s class. Note that some αijk s could be negative, allowing for types of government spending that bring positive P utility to one group and negative utility to another. The assumption that ij λij αijk > 0 ensures that in equilibrium all types of government spending are greater than zero.9 The β k parameters capture how rival a particular form of government spending is. For a type of spending k, β k = 1 means that the type of government spending is perfectly rival, and 9 If some type of government spending were zero then some groups would have infinite utility, and other groups would have negative infinite utility, and equilibrium existence would no longer be guaranteed. 17 as β k → 0 that type of spending moves towards being perfectly nonrival. Finally, dividing P spending by ij λij 1{αijk >0} captures the idea that spending is shared among the groups that gain positive utility from that form of government spending.10 The politicians’ budget P k constraint is now K k=1 σ ≤ τ y. Note that the single type of government spending in (1) and the targeting in the previous section given by (2) are special cases of the utility function in (4). Even when politicians have the ability to flexibly target government spending, the main results do not change. Robustness Result 1 Propositions 1, 2 and 3 hold if citizen utility is given by (4). Alesina, Baqir and Easterly (1999) show that racial diversity may lead to decreases in government spending due to diversity of preferences for different types of spending. In the cross-cutting cleavages model adding preference diversity about spending does not affect the results.11 4.2 Changes in Income Levels All previous results attribute changes in the variables of interest—the proportion black λB , average income y and economic parity yB —to y changes in the population proportions of each group ~λ = {λRW , λRB , λP B , λP W }. Changes in the last two variables of interest, however, may be due to changes in the income of the rich and the poor ~y = {y R , y P }. Even if this is the case, the relevant results still hold. Robustness Result 2 An increase in average income through changes in ~y , holding economic parity constant, leads to a decrease in the equilibrium tax rate. An increase in economic parity through changes in ~y , holding average income constant, leads to an increase in the equilibrium tax rate if and only if average black income is less than average income. 10 Note that I make no distinction between government spending for productive and consumptive purposes. That is, adding preference diversity does not change the level of taxation and spending, or the comparative statics of the model. 11 18 5 Empirical Evidence There are few established facts about the effect of race, class and the cross-cuttingness of racial and class cleavages on tax rates. This section identifies some of these facts and assesses the extent to which the predictions of the cross-cutting cleavages model are observed in data from large U.S. cities between 1942 and 1972. It then examines turnout patterns to determine whether the patterns in this limited data on political sensitivity are consistent with the model. The predictions of the cross-cutting cleavages model are straightforward to test as they isolate the effect of increases in one of the three variables of interest—average income y, the proportion black λB and economic parity yB —holding y the other two constant. Estimating a specification of the form x = α + βy y + βλB λB + β yB y yB + y (5) produces coefficients β that are the correlation of the dependent variable x with one of the variables of interest, holding the other two constant. For example, if the dependent variable is the tax rate τ , then βy is an estimate of the effect of increasing average income on the tax rate holding constant the proportion black and economic parity.12 The predictions of the cross-cutting cleavages model are summarized in Table 1 in terms of the coefficients in (5). When the proportion black increases, holding constant average income and economic parity, the equilibrium tax rate, per-capita tax revenue and per-capita spending on the poor all increase or all decrease depending on the values of the vector of political sensitivities. That is, βy is predicted to be greater than zero or all less than zero for all three dependent variables, depending on the condition in Proposition 2. When these 12 Related studies have measured ethnic diversity using the fractionalization or polarization measures (Easterly and Levine, 1997; Alesina, Baqir and Hoxby, 2004; Montalvo and Reynal-Querol, 2005), but when there are two groups fractionalization= 2λB (1 − λB ) = 21 polarization, making the coefficient on proportion black (λB ) both easier to interpret and theoretically motivated. For more on the measurement of polarization see Esteban and Ray (1994). 19 Table 1: Summary of Theoretical Predictions Dependent Variable Independent Variable Tax Rate (τ ) Per-Capita Spending (g) Per-Capita Spending on the Poor (σ P ) βλB > 0 βλB > 0 βλB > 0 (λB ) βλB < 0 βλB < 0 βλB < 0 Average Income (y) βy > 0 no prediction no prediction Economic Parity B ( yy ) β yB > 0 β yB > 0 no prediction Proportion Black y y three coefficients are greater than zero, the cross-cutting cleavages model predicts that the difference in political sensitivity between races across classes should be larger for the rich than for the poor. The following subsection briefly describes the taxation data; detailed information on the data can be found in Appendix B. The middle subsections examine the data in a panel and cross-sections of cities. The final subsections examine the limited data on political sensitivity to make a final attempt at falsifying the cross-cutting cleavages model. 5.1 Taxation and Spending Data The taxation and spending data are from U.S. cities with a population over 100,000 at approximately five year intervals between 1942 and 1972. The population threshold is chosen to select for cities with active political communities and to ensure data availability.13 The time range is chosen because U.S. cities experienced large changes in ethnic makeup and in the relative income of blacks during this period. The study ends in 1972 to avoid the 13 Banfield and Wilson (1963) find that small cities have distinct forms of political organization—usually involving just a few individuals—from larger cities. 20 unmodeled effects of Asian and Hispanic immigration.14 Moreover, this period predates the passage of Proposition 13 in California in 1978, which significantly altered the dynamics of local taxation. 15 Income data is not easily available before 1940. The main predictions of the theory are in terms of tax rates, however, tax rate data are not available. The data do contain per capita tax revenue g = τ y and average income y for each city. Dividing per capita tax revenue by average income gives a measure of the central tendency of tax rates, τ̂ . Gramlich and Rubinfeld (1982) and others have found that the income elasticity of property-tax payments is one, which supports the modeling assumption that local tax rates can be approximated as a linear tax on income without the distortionary effects of an income tax.16 5.2 Panel Data Analysis Estimates from a cross-section of cities may reflect the selection of citizens into cities based on tax rates rather than the selection of tax rates by politicians based on the demographics of the city (Tiebout, 1956). Thus, a panel specification with city fixed effects is preferred as it isolates the effects of demographic changes within a city over time. The empirical results hold in cross-sectional data as well, as shown in the next subsection. Table 2 estimates the linear, fixed-effects specification xct = α + βλB λB ct + βy y ct + β yB y yB ct + χ(controlsct ) + θt + µc + ct , y ct (6) where t indexes time and c indexes cities, using a panel of U.S. cities between 1942 and 1972. The city level dummy µc removes unobserved heterogeneity between cities, and the 14 It is possible that Hispanic populations may have had an effect before 1972. To control for this possibility Table 7 drops observations from states that share a border with Mexico. 15 The next year where data is available is 1982. When examining expenditure data from the local level it is common to conduct the analysis before Proposition 13 in California and Proposition 2 12 in Massachusetts. For example, see Epple and Sieg (1999) and Epple, Romer and Sieg (2001). 16 Using this estimated tax rate as a proxy for a linear income tax is the same as using income as a proxy for wealth. This specification also treats renters and homeowners similarly, which is common in the public finance literature. For example see Epple, Romer and Sieg (2001). 21 year dummies θt control for any national shocks to the dependent variable.17 The controls are largely the same as those in Alesina, Baqir and Easterly (1999) and attempt to capture other possible determinants of tax rates. Because the predictions of the Meltzer and Richard (1981) model are in terms of the ratio of median to average income, adding this ratio as a control ensures that the cross-cutting cleavages model explains variation in addition to that explained by Meltzer and Richard (1981). The population in school controls for the spending needs of the city, as schools are an important component of local government spending. This also controls for differences in preferences for government spending and taxation that a more and less educated populace might have. The population controls for any scale effects that might be present in larger communities. The number of government employees controls for any propensity for patronage through city jobs a political regime might have. Finally, the percent of the population over 65 controls for the effect of seniors on spending found in Poterba (1997). The results in Table 2 are supportive of the cross-cutting cleavages model. In accordance with Proposition 1 the coefficient on average income y is negative and statistically significant. When per capita tax revenue is the dependent variable the coefficient on average income changes sign when controls are added and is not statistically significant in either column. The coefficient on economic parity is positive and significant in all columns, conforming with the prediction in Proposition 3 and Corollary 2. Finally, the coefficients on the proportion black are positive when the tax rate τ̂ is the dependent variable. Corollary 2 then implies that the coefficients on proportion black should be positive when per-capita tax revenue g is the dependent variable, which is also the case. This has specific implications for the coefficient on the proportion black when per-capita spending on the poor σ P is the dependent variable, and specific implications for the pattern of political sensitivity across all four groups, both of which will be tested. Finally, the standard deviation of the residuals from regressions of tax rates and per capita tax revenue on the time and city fixed effects are 0.3 and 65 respectively. 17 Hausman (1978) tests reject the appropriateness of random-effects specifications in most of the specifications in Table 2. 22 Table 2: Panel Results Dependent Variable: Tax Rate (τ̂ ) Per-capita Tax Revenue (τ y) Proportion Black 1.75∗∗∗ (0.47) 1.66∗∗∗ (0.48) 329∗∗∗ (106) 314∗∗∗ (104) Average Income -0.93∗∗∗ (0.30) -0.55∗ (0.32) -72.8 (65.1) 16.9 (69.1) Economic Parity 0.33∗∗ (0.16) 0.31∗∗ (0.16) 81.4∗∗ (33.2) 61.8∗ (35.1) Median to Average Income Ratio -0.85 (0.56) -240∗∗ (107) Population in School -0.09 (0.07) -12.6 (15.8) -0.09∗∗∗ (0.03) -21.3∗∗∗ (5.63) City Employees 1.44∗∗ (0.58) 408∗∗∗ (135) Senior -5.44∗∗ (2.28) -542∗∗∗ (426) Population Constant R2 n (city × year) 9.08∗∗∗ (2.79) 7.02∗∗ (3.08) 651 (609) 158 (656) 0.897 828 0.910 806 0.853 828 0.882 806 Notes: ∗∗∗ ,∗∗ ,∗ denotes statistical significance at the 1%, 5% and 10% levels, respectively. All columns contain year and city fixed effects. White (1980) heteroskedastictic-consistent standard errors in parenthesis. 23 Thus, the explanatory variables can account for much of the remaining variation. As discussed in Subsection 3.4 the data separates local government expenditures into several categories, only one of which, spending on public welfare, is targeted to a specific group—in this case the poor. Proposition 4 predicts that if tax rates increase with the proportion black, so should per capita spending on the poor. Table 3 estimates (6) with per capita public welfare expenditures as the dependent variable.18 The deficiency of this regression as a test of the proposed theory should be noted. Public welfare spending is only one type of spending that may be preferred by the poor. Thus, increases in public welfare spending may be accompanied by decreases in, for example, police protection for the poor, which the data does not measure. Regardless, per capita public welfare spending increases with the proportion black, in accordance with Proposition 4. 5.3 Cross-Sectional Analysis As a first check on the robustness of the panel results the linear specification τ̂c = α + β1 λB c + β2 y c + β3 yB c + χ(controlsc ) + c yc (7) is estimated in 1960, 1967 and 1972, where c denotes a city. The results are presented in Table 4. These years are chosen because a control for education (the percent of the city with at least four years of college) is available for these years. Analyses of other available cross sections are substantively similar.19 The results of the cross-sectional analysis are once again supportive of the cross-cutting cleavages model. In the cases where the coefficients on the variables of interest are statistically significant, a one-standard deviation in each of the independent variables is associated 18 The reduced sample size is due to the fact that local public welfare spending is not reported by the Census Bureau for all years. 19 That is to say that two of the variables of interest have significant coefficients in the expected direction while the coefficient on the third variable of interest is insignificant. The p-value on the coefficient for average income βy in Column 2 of Table 4 is 0.13. 24 Table 3: Local Public Welfare Spending Dependent Variable: Per-Capita Public Welfare Spending (σ P ) Proportion Black 376∗∗∗ (127) 300∗∗∗ (115) Average Income 58.2 (37.3) 27.5 (34.1) Economic Parity -21.9 (20.4) -25.0 (21.3) Median to Average Income Ratio -95.8 (78.8) Population in School -14.8 (16.7) Population -4.22 (4.35) City Employees 406∗∗∗ (113) Senior 158 (261) Constant -568 (356) -228 (343) R2 n (city × year) 0.601 675 0.720 662 Notes: ∗∗∗ ,∗∗ ,∗ denotes statistical significance at the 1%, 5% and 10% levels, respectively. All columns contain year and city fixed effects. White (1980) heteroskedastictic-consistent standard errors in parenthesis. 25 Table 4: Cross-sectional Results Dependent Variable: Tax Rate (τ̂ ) 1960 1967 1972 Proportion Black 0.64 (0.68) 0.50 (0.71) 2.39∗∗ (0.99) 2.23∗∗ (0.90) 2.21∗∗ (1.01) 1.86∗∗ (0.89) Average Income -1.55∗∗ (0.61) -1.08 (0.70) -0.24 (0.84) 0.47 (0.88) -0.48 (0.87) 0.02 (0.83) Economic Parity 2.50∗∗∗ (0.41) 2.50∗∗∗ (0.51) 3.72∗∗∗ (0.80) 4.13∗∗∗ (1.01) 2.54∗∗∗ (0.81) 2.62∗∗∗ (0.80) Median to Average Income Ratio -1.92 (1.49) -2.22 (1.83) -1.06 (1.93) Population in School -0.57 (0.64) -0.53 (1.08) 0.27 (1.03) College -1.27 (3.22) 0.09 (3.84) 0.47 (2.69) Population 0.06 (0.12) 0.03 (0.25) -0.20 (0.25) City Employees 2.29∗∗ (0.96) 2.47∗∗ (1.21) 5.40∗∗∗ (1.70) Proportion Senior 1.22 (2.44) 0.19 (2.74) 2.87 (3.65) Constant 14.32∗∗∗ (6.02) 11.46∗ (6.35) 0.95 (8.39) -4.29 (8.14) 4.28 (8.75) -0.16 7.82 R2 n (cities) 0.328 122 0.468 122 0.267 131 0.431 131 0.174 141 0.403 141 Notes: ∗∗∗ ,∗∗ ,∗ denotes statistical significance at the 1%, 5% and 10% levels, respectively. White (1980) heteroskedastictic-consistent standard errors in parenthesis. 26 with a one-third to one-half standard deviation change in the tax rate. 5.4 Turnout Patterns across Race and Class The pattern of empirical findings and Proposition 2 imply an additional testable result of the cross-cutting cleavages model. Specifically, tax rates rose with the proportion black, so Propostion 2 predicts (since it is an if and only if statement) that the difference in political sensitivity between races should be larger for the rich than for the poor. Turnout data can thus be used to try to falsify the theory. The two separate analysis of turnout data in this subsection fail to do so. The American National Election Study (ANES) asks approximately 1,000 U.S. citizens every other year whether or not they voted. The ANES also provides data on a respondent’s race and rough data on where a respondent is in the country-wide income distribution. Panel A of Table 5 classifies any respondent with income in the top third of the distribution as rich.20 A respondent’s report of whether or not he or she voted is regressed on an indicator for race, an indicator for whether the respondent was classified as rich, and the product of these indicators. The condition in Propostion 2 requires the coefficient on the product of the indicators, Black × Rich, to have a negative sign. While this is the case across all four columns, in none of the columns is the coefficient statistically significant. The first column of Panel A reports regression results for all urban respondents. Columns 2 and 4 restrict the sample to years with no presidential election. Columns 3 and 4 restrict the sample to respondents in the top third or bottom third of the income distribution. This later sample selection is made to draw a starker contrast between the rich and other respondents. The data presented in the first panel do not falsify the theory, although there are severe data limitations: in the first column only 219 black respondents are classified as rich.21 20 Specifically, the data describes whether the respondent’s income was between the 0-16 percentile, 16-33 percentile, 33-66 percentile, 66-95 percentile or 95-99 percentile of the income distribution. Given the sparse data, there is no flexibility in this cutoff. 21 It is well known that ANES respondents often report that they have voted when in fact they have not. 27 Table 5: Voter Turnout Patterns Match those required by Proposition 2 Panel A: ANES Turnout Data Dependent Variable: Did Respondent Vote? Rich and Very Poor Respondents Only offyear only offyear only Indicator for Black −0.05∗∗ (0.02) −0.09∗∗∗ (0.03) -0.02 (0.03) -0.06 (0.04) Indicator for Rich 0.15∗∗∗ (0.02) 0.14∗∗∗ (0.02) 0.20∗∗∗ (0.02) 0.20∗∗∗ (0.03) Black × Rich -0.02 (0.04) -0.00 (0.06) -0.04 (0.04) -0.02 (0.07) R2 n (respondents) 0.135 6296 0.157 2879 0.195 3862 0.228 1743 Panel B: ROAD Turnout Data Dependent Variable: MCD Group Turnout Non-Homogenous Areas Only offyear only offyear only Proportion Black -0.04 (0.03) -0.06 (0.05) 0.01 (0.04) 0.03 (0.05) Proportion Black × Average Black Income 0.68 (3.14) 1.61 (4.84) 0.22 (2.85) -3.68 (4.15) Proportion White × Average White Income 4.46∗∗∗ (0.26) 3.43∗∗∗ (0.38) 4.60∗∗∗ (0.58) 3.29∗∗∗ (0.87) R2 n (MCD Group × year) 0.439 4257 0.186 2239 0.589 1177 0.357 582 Notes: ∗∗∗ ,∗∗ ,∗ denotes statistical significance at the 1%, 5% and 10% levels, respectively. All regressions include state × year fixed effects. White (1980) heteroskedastictic-consistent standard errors in parenthesis. 28 Panel B of Table 5 presents a second attempt to falsify the theory. Data from the Record of American Democracy (ROAD) (King et al., 1997) is used in ecological regressions to examine the effects of race and income on aggregate turnout in Minor Civil Division groups (MCD Group - a level of data aggregation unique to this dataset) from 1986-1990.22 Turnout πmt is regressed on the proportion black λB the proportion black times average black income λB y B and the proportion white times average white income λW y W . Panel B estimates the specification B B W W π mt = α + β1 λB mt + β2 λmt y mt + β3 λmt y mt + θst + mt , (8) where π is the observed turnout in MCD Group m at time t. θst is a state-year fixed effect, introduced to control for turnout shocks due to particularly competitive statewide elections. The partial derivative of the observed turnout with respect to the proportion of the city B that is black times average black income λB mt y mt is β2 . In the cross-cutting cleavages model, P turnout is given by π = ij λij π ij . The derivative with respect to λB y B , keeping constant λB and λW y W is given by: dπ dλB y B λB , = λW y W π RB − π P B yR − yP thus π RB − π P B β2 = RW P W π −π β3 The point estimates of the coefficient on proportion black times average black income β2 are statistically indistinguishable from zero, so once again the condition in Proposition 2 is satisfied. However, β2 is not statistically different from β3 , the coefficient on the proportion white times average white income. Once again the analysis does not falsify the theory. Sigelman (1982) finds that the tendency to over-report is stronger for blacks than for whites, and Hill and Hurley (1984) finds that wealthier blacks are more likely to over-report than poor blacks or wealthier whites. These patterns would strengthen the results of the analysis in Panel A of Table 5. 22 While it would be preferable to have data from the period under study, this data is the only easily available dataset that is matched with demographic data at a level lower than congressional districts. For a brief description of the data in ROAD see King and Palmquist (1997). It is important to note both that the analysis of ROAD data uses OLS regressions and does not use the ecological inference techniques of King (1997), and that ecological regressions generally suffer from aggregation bias which may bias results either up or down. 29 Columns 3 and 4 of Panel B attempt to produce more precise estimates by eliminating MCD Groups where less than five percent of the population is black or less than five percent of the population is white, but this has little effect.23 Overall, the data are supportive of the cross-cutting cleavages model. The patterns in taxation and spending data are consistent with the theory. Moreover, the taxation data implies a specific prediction about the relative values of political sensitivity for each classrace group. Turnout data does not falsify this prediction. 5.5 Empirical Robustness The large demographic changes in U.S. cities during the period under study were accompanied by large political and social changes, especially in the South. This subsection examines two possible ways in which these changes may bias the results in Table 2. In the cross-cutting cleavages model a decrease in the supression of black turnout increases their political sensitivity, and leads to an increase in the equilibrium tax rate because blacks are on average poorer than whites. If a decrease in the political repression of blacks were correlated with one of the variables of interest, we might be observing the effects of this decrease rather than the effects of demographic changes. For example, it might be easy to suppress black voter turnout if blacks are a small proportion of the population, but impossible when they are a large proportion of the population. This would bias the coefficient on the proportion black upwards.24 Using data from the ANES, Table 6 examines the ratio of the average turnout of blacks to average turnout πB π across states and time. Because there are very few respondents in each state for a given year, ten years worth of data from the ANES are used to estimate a 23 The exception is Column 3 where the p-value on a Wald (1943) test that β2 6= β3 is 0.14. Oberholzer-Gee and Waldfogel (2005), in a study of political behavior in the late 1990s, find that minority turnout increases with the size of the local minority population as the result of changes in media structure. Leighley (2001), using ANES data, finds little evidence of rising black turnout with the proportion of a community that is black. The racial threat hypothesis (Key, 1949) would predict that relative black voter turnout decreases when the proportion black increases. If this hypothesis is correct, it would bias the coefficient on proportion black downwards and hence is not of particular concern. 24 30 single state-decade observation of relative turnout. These estimates are then regressed on demographic data from the decennial census.25 Panel A of Table 6 creates these state-decade observations using all respondents in a state, whereas Panel B uses only urban respondents. Table 6 shows that of the three variables of interest, only economic parity is robustly correlated with relative black turnout. Because rich blacks are more politically sensitive than poor blacks, an increase in economic parity is associated with an increase in the relative political sensitivity of blacks in the cross-cutting cleavages model. Panel B confirms this pattern for urban respondents, although the standard errors are somewhat larger because the Census Bureau and the ANES, which supply the right and left-hand side variables respectively, use different definitions of what constitutes an urban area.26 Even if relative black turnout were correlated with one of the variables of interest, if black political sensitivity were increasing in a relatively uniform way across the country, the effect of this increase would be controlled for by the year fixed effects in (6). However, it is likely that that the relative political sensitivity of blacks increased at different rates in the South as compared with the rest of the country. Year by south fixed effects are added to the specification in (6) in Columns 1 and 4 of Table 2 to control for this possibility. The inclusion of these fixed effects do not affect the results in Table 2. Columns 2 and 5 take this approach one step further by including census division by year fixed effects.27 This reduces the coefficient on economic parity by half as economic parity is highly correlated with the fixed effects, but the other coefficients on the variables of interest are robust. Finally, states that border Mexico have historically had larger Hispanic populations and the different racial dynamics created by this population may affect the local tax rate. To control for this Columns 3 and 6 drop data from the states that border Mexico: California, New Mexico, Arizona and Texas. Dropping these states does not affect the results in 25 The ANES does not identify a respondent’s location until 1956. The sample period is from 1956-1984 to increase the amount of data. Results are very similar if we omit data from 1976-1984. 26 The second panel has fewer observations because the U.S. Census dataset (PUMS) dataset does not identify urban vs. rural respondents in states with less than 250,000 urban or rural residents. 27 There are nine census divisions in the U.S. each containing 4-6 states in close proximity to one another. 31 Table 6: Relative Voter Turnout of Blacks Increases as Relative Black Income Increases Dependent Variable: Ratio of Black Turnout to Overall Turnout all states 1960 and 1970 southern states nonsouthern states all states nonsouthern states Panel A: All Respondents Economic Parity 1.46∗∗∗ (0.48) 1.37∗∗∗ (0.51) 2.24∗ (1.20) 2.29∗∗ (0.97) 2.66∗∗∗ (0.93) 3.51∗∗∗ (1.24) Proportion Black -0.03 (0.31) -0.20 (0.41) -0.91∗ (0.51) 1.56 (1.70) -4.98∗∗∗ (1.64) -4.64 (11.6) Average Income 0.01 (0.08) 0.13 (0.15) 0.00 (0.16) -0.07 (0.12) -1.11 (1.29) -2.22 (2.36) State and Year Fixed Effects No No No No Yes Yes 0.131 93 0.203 93 0.306 45 0.132 48 0.579 93 0.565 48 R2 n (state × decade) Panel B: Urban Respondents Only Economic Parity 1.06∗ (0.62) 1.08 (0.72) 1.99 (1.56) 2.55∗ (1.31) 2.68 (1.91) 4.45∗ (2.27) Black 0.10 (0.34) 0.22 (0.52) -0.54 (0.80) 0.73 (1.42) -4.50∗∗ (1.76) -4.82 (9.66) Average Income 0.01 (0.07) 0.09 (0.20) -0.08 (0.16) -0.11 (0.12) -1.31 (-2.29) 2.65 (3.30) State and Year Fixed Effects No No No No Yes Yes 0.083 71 0.088 49 0.115 34 0.156 37 0.499 71 0.541 37 R2 n (state × decade) Notes: ∗∗∗ ,∗∗ ,∗ denotes statistical significance at the 1%, 5% and 10% levels, respectively. White (1980) heteroskedastictic-consistent standard errors in parenthesis. 32 Table 7: Robustness Checks Dependent Variable: Tax Rate (τ̂ ) Tax Revenue per capita (τ y) Proportion Black 1.62∗∗∗ (0.54) 2.41∗∗∗ (0.62) 1.75∗∗∗ (0.52) 429∗∗∗ (121) 580∗∗∗ (138) 335∗∗∗ (117) Average Income -0.81∗∗∗ (0.29) -0.86∗∗ (0.34) -0.85∗∗∗ (0.35) 57.2 (60.8) 58.5 (75.1) -48.7 (76.0) Economic Parity 0.36∗∗∗ (0.17) 0.15 (0.18) 0.37∗∗ (0.17) 73.9∗∗ (31.7) 41.7 (30.9) 83.5∗∗ (36.6) Constant 6.57∗∗ (2.45) 6.47∗∗ (3.19) 6.80∗∗∗ (3.39) -680 (566) -1010 (701) 156 (731) North / South × Year Fixed Effects Yes No No Yes No No Division × Year Fixed Effects No Yes No No Yes No Year Fixed Effects No No Yes No No Yes Border States Omitted No No Yes No No Yes R2 n (city × year) 0.902 828 0.920 828 0.894 682 0.871 828 0.895 828 0.852 682 Notes: ∗∗∗ ,∗∗ ,∗ denotes statistical significance at the 1%, 5% and 10% levels, respectively. White (1980) heteroskedastictic-consistent standard errors in parenthesis. All columns include city fixed effects. Tabel 2 and shows that any potential bias introduced by the inability to control for Hispanic population due to data limitations in the sample period is small.28 6 Conclusion Canonical political economy models of government taxation and spending focus on the conflict between the rich and the poor over redistribution. This paper adds race to this equation. However, it focuses on the consequences of the empirical fact that blacks and whites exhibit 28 Other robustness checks that do not substantively alter the results include splitting the sample around the median population, dropping any year from the data, changing the units of measurement of many of the control variables and splitting the sample into south/non-south samples. 33 different levels of political sensitivity, rather than the consequences of speculative differences between races in preferences. Considering race and class together allows me to formalize an old concept from political science—that of cross-cutting cleavages—and examine its impact on the taxation and spending decisions of local governments. Specifically, the degree to which race and class cross-cut each other exhibits a non-monotonic relationship with taxation and spending levels. This non-monotonic relationship is mediated by economic parity—the degree to which different races have similar distributions of income. The model produces six predictions in total. All of these predictions are consistent with correlations in the data from large U.S. cities between 1942 and 1972. In sum, adding race and focusing on political sensitivity allows us to understand a richer set of patterns of government taxation and spending decisions. 34 Appendix A Theoretical Derivation and Proofs There are two candidates c ∈ {1, 2} who seek to maximize their own vote share. Candidates propose binding platforms that consist of a tax rate, τ c , and a level of government spending, P g c , subject to a budget balancing constraint: g c ≤ ij λij τ c y i = τ c y. Following the terminology in Grossman and Helpman (2001, Chapter 3), in addition to the positions candidates take on the pliable issue of spending, there are other issues, such as charisma or a reputation for pursuing non-economic race related policies on which candidates have fixed positions. A citizen from class-race group ij turns out to vote with exogenously given probability π ij . Of the citizens who turn out to vote from class-race group ij a proportion 1 − ξ ij is exogenously committed to voting for one candidate or the other based on the fixed positions of the candidates. The remaining citizens that vote and would consider voting for either candidate receive an extra utility for candidate 1 of x, where x is the realization of a random variable drawn independently for each citizen from a cumulative distribution function F (x).29 Each group varies in the relative prominence of fixed versus pliable issues, with ζ ij indexing the prominence a member of class-race group ij puts on pliable issues. A citizen in class-race group ij votes for candidate 1 if and only if x + ζ ij U ij (τ 1 , g 1 ) ≥ ζ ij U ij (τ 2 , g 2 ), that is, if x ≤ ζ ij (U ij (τ 1 , g 1 ) − U ij (τ 2 , g 2 )). The vote share S 1 for candidate 1 is given by S1 = X λij π ij (1 − ξ ij )φij + ξ ij F (ζ ij (U ij (τ 1 , g 1 ) − U ij (τ 2 , g 2 ))) , (A.1) ij where φij is the proportion of exogenously committed voters in class-race group ij who vote for candidate 1. The vote share of candidate 2 is given by an analogous expression so a Nash Equilibrium in pure strategies where both candidates propose the same platform exists. To ensure the existence of a symmetric equilibrium the probability density function, f (x) = F 0 (x), is assumed to be symmetric about zero. For the necessary second-order conditions to hold F (x) cannot change too quickly around zero. I follow the rest of the literature and assume that the second-order conditions hold. For a discussion, see Acemoglu and Robinson (2006, Chapter 12). 29 Appendicies–1 In (A.1) the first term inside the brackets is constant, and in equilibrium candidate 1 takes the platform of candidate 2 as given. Thus the first-order conditions of each candidate’s maximization problem are the same as the first-order conditions of the following problem: max τ,g max τ,g X λij ψ ij U ij (τ, g) s.t. g ≤ τ y ij X i ψ λi U i (τ, g) s.t. g = τ y (A.2) i∈{R,P } i where ψ ij = π ij ξ ij ζ ij > 0 is a class-race group’s political sensitivity, ψ = λiB ψ iB +λiW ψ iW λi , and i ψ λi is a class’s political prominence. Each candidates’ Lagrangian L is given by: L = (1 − τ )ŷ + ψ log(g) − γ (g − τ y) , R P R (A.3) P where ŷ = ψ λR y R + ψ λP y P and ψ = ψ λR + ψ λP . The first order conditions yield dL = −ŷ + γy = 0 dτ and dL ψ = − γ = 0. dg g taken together with the budget constraint, g∗ = τ∗ y, the equilibrium level of government spending, g∗ , and tax rate, τ∗ , are given by: g∗ = ψy ŷ and τ∗ = ψ ŷ (A.4) As noted in Section 2, the equilibrium tax rate and per capita tax revenue is re-written P B in terms of ij λij , y, λB and yy , and partial derivatives are taken with respect to these last ~ and letting ~λ vary. This is equivalent to changing three variables holding constant ~y and ψ P B from the ~λ basis into another basis ~b = { ij λij , y, λB , yy } and taking partial derivatives in this latter basis. Taking derivatives in the ~λ basis in the direction of a particular basis vector in ~b makes the algebra more tractable. For the proofs, the equilibrium tax rate will be written as τ∗ (~λ) and the equilibrium level of per-captia tax revenue will be written as Appendicies–2 g∗ (~λ) = τ∗ (~λ)y to remind the reader that derivatives are being taken in the ~λ basis. Formally, this is accomplished through the use of a directional derivative in the ~λ basis: D~l τ∗ (~λ) = (∇τ∗ (~λ)) · ~l, where ~l is the demographic change—the direction of the derivative in the ~λ basis.30 The function ~q(·) : ~b → R4 maps from the element of the basis b that is changing and the demographic change in ~λ. Lemma 1 For any arbitrary demographic change ~l, changes in the equilibrium tax rate are P in the same direction as changes in the relative political prominence of the poor P D~l τ∗ (~λ) ≥ 0 if and only if D~l ψ λP R ψ λP R ψ λR ! ≥0 ψ λR Proof. Because ~l involves changes only to the proportions of the class-race groups ij: P D~l ψ λP R ! = ψ λR 1 R (ψ λR )2 h R i P P R ψ λR D~l (ψ λP ) − ψ λP D~l (ψ λR ) (A.5) and ψ 1 = 2 ŷD~l ψ − ψD~l ŷ ŷ ŷ i 1 h R R R P P P R P R P R P = 2 (ψ λ y + ψ λ y ) D~l (ψ λR ) + D~l (ψ λP ) − (ψ λR + ψ λP ) D~l (ψ λR )y R + D~l (ψ λP )y P ŷ D~l τ∗ (~λ) = D~l = i yR − yP h R R P P P P R R ψ λ D λ ) − ψ λ D λ ) (ψ (ψ ~l ~l ŷ 2 (A.6) the terms outside the brackets in (A.5) and (A.6) are positive, thus (A.5) is positive if and only if (A.6) is. Proposition 1 An increase in average income, holding constant the proportion black and economic parity, decreases the equilibrium tax rate: Dq~(y) τ∗ (~λ) < 0. 30 Note that, for example, ∂τ∗ (~ λ) ∂λRW = D~l τ∗ (λ) when ~l = {1, 0, 0, 0}. Appendicies–3 yB y Proof. Holding λB and constant while varying y gives four restrictions: Dq~(y) λB = Dq~(y) λRB + Dq~(y) λP B = 0 Dq~(y y = Dq~(y) λRW + Dq~(y) λRB y R + Dq~(y) λP W + Dq~(y) B Dq~(y) yy = 1 y h 1 λB RB R Dq~(y) λ y + Dq~(y) λ PB P y − i B y y PB P λ y =1 =0 Dq~(y) (~1 · ~λ) = Dq~(y) λRW + Dq~(y) λRB + Dq~(y) λP W + Dq~(y) λP B = 0 So ~q(y) = n B B W yW λB y B λW y W , λ y , − y(yλ R −y P ) , − y(y R −y P ) y(y R −y P ) y(y R −y P ) ⇒ λW y W Dq~(y) λRW = y(y R −y P ) B B y Dq~(y) λRB = y(yλR −y P) λW y W Dq~(y) λP W = − y(y R −y P ) B B y PB D = − y(yλR −y P) q ~(y) λ o . Substituting: i 1 h R R W W PW yB P P B B PB W W RW B B RB Dq~(y) τ∗ (y, λ , ) = − 2 ψ λ (λ y ψ + λ y ψ ) + ψ λ (λ y ψ +λ y ψ ) <0 y ŷ y B Corollary 1 An increase in average income, holding constant the proportion black and economic parity, has an indeterminate effect on equilibrium per capita tax revenue. Proof. Defining ∆W = ψ RW − ψ P W and ∆B = ψ RB − ψ P B then Dq~(y) i 1 h R R R RW W P P P RB B PW W PB B g∗ = 2 ψ λ y (λ ∆ + λ ∆ ) − ψ λ y (λ ∆ + λ ∆ ) ŷ Set y R = y P = y ≥ 1 and ∆W = ∆B = ∆ then the expression becomes: i d(τ y) y∆ h R R 2 P P2 = 2 ψ λ −ψ λ dy ŷ (A.7) Now set λRW = 0.15, λRB = 0.05, λP W = 0.6, λP B = 0.2 and ψ RW = 1, ψ RB = ψ P W = 0.8, ψ P B = 0.6. Then the term in brackets is equal to −0.034. Now, if ψ RW = 1, ψ RB = ψ P W = 0.6, ψ P B = 0.2, the term in brackets is equal to 0.02. Because the expression is continuous, the sign of these examples would hold even if y R were slightly larger than y P . Appendicies–4 Proposition 2 An increase in the proportion of the city that is black, holding constant average income and economic parity, depends on the relative difference in political sensitivity between races across classes, ψ P W −ψ P B . ψ RW −ψ RB In particular, the tax rate increases if and only if: ψP W − ψP B <Q ψ RW − ψ RB P where Q = ψ λP λRB . R ψ λR λP B Proof. Holding constant y and B RB Dq~(λB ) λ = Dq~(λB ) λ yB y PB + Dq~(λB ) λ while varying λB gives four restrictions =1 Dq~(λB ) y = Dq~(λB ) λRW + Dq~(λB ) λRB y R + Dq~(λB ) λP W + Dq~(λB ) Dq~(y) yB y = 1 h λB y Dq~(y) λRB − RB λ λB y R + Dq~(y) λP B − PB λ λB λP B y P = 0 i yP = 0 Dq~(λB ) (~1 · ~λ) = Dq~(λB ) λRW + Dq~(λB ) λRB + Dq~(λB ) λP W + Dq~(λB ) λP B = 0 ⇒ RB Dq~(λB ) λRW = − λλB RB D B λRB = λλB q~(λ ) PB Dq~(λB ) λP W = − λλB D B λP B = λP B q ~(λ ) λB n RB RB o λ λ λP B λP B So ~q(λ ) = − λB , λB , − λB , λB . Substituting: B Dq~(λB ) τ∗ (y, λB , i y R − y P h P P RB RW yB R R PB RB PW PB )= ψ λ λ (ψ − ψ ) − ψ λ λ (ψ − ψ ) (A.8) y λB ŷ 2 This derivative is positive if the and only if the term in brackets is positive. This occurs if and only if: P ψP W − ψP B ψ λP λRB < R ψ RW − ψ RB ψ λR λP B Proposition 3 An increase in economic parity, holding constant the proportion black and average income, increases the equilibrium tax rate: Dq~“ yB ” τ∗ (~λ) > 0. y Appendicies–5 Proof. The three conditions Dq~“ yB ” λB = Dq~“ yB ” y = Dq~“ yB ” (~1·~λ) = 0 imply Dq~“ yB ” λRB = y y y y −Dq~“ yB ” λRW = Dq~“ yB ” λP W = −Dq~“ yB ” λP B . Substituting: y y Dq~“ yB ” y y i (y R − y P ) “ ” RB h R R P yB P P R τ∗ (y, λ , ) = Dq~ yB λ ψ λ ∆ +ψ λ ∆ y ŷ 2 y B To sign this expression use the constraint Dq~“ yB ” y Dq~“ yB ” y yB y Dq~“ yB ” λRB y yB y =1 1 RB R PB P “ ” “ ” = Dq~ yB λ y + Dq~ yB λ y =1 yλB y y yλB = R >0 y − yP B so Dq~“ yB ” τ∗ (y, λB , yy ) > 0. y Corollary 2 A change in the proportion black or in economic parity, keeping the other two variables of interest fixed, leads to changes in the equilibrium level of per capita tax revenue that are in the same direction as changes in the equilibrium tax rate. B Proof. The equilibrium level of tax revenue per capita is equal to τ∗ (y, λB , yy )y. For some demographic shift ~l, the change in tax revenue per capita is equal to D~l (τ∗ y) = B B D~l τ∗ (y, λB , yy )y + τ∗ (y, λB , yy )D~l y. If y is constant than the second term is zero, and the change in tax revenue is in the same direction as the change in the tax rate. Since changes in λB and yB y implicitly hold y constant, the change in per capita tax revenue with these variables will be in the same direction as the change in the tax rate. Proposition 4 An increase in the proportion black, holding constant average income and economic parity, will increase per capita spending on the poor if and only if the equilibrium Appendicies–6 tax rate increases: Dq~(λB ) σ∗P ≥ 0 Dq~(λB ) τ∗ (y, λB , ⇐⇒ yB )≥0 y Proof. Taking first order conditions of the candidate’s Lagrangian with citizen utility as given by (2) yields σ∗P = P ψ λP y . ŷ Thus: i yh P P ŷ Dq~(λB ) (ψ λP ) − ψ λP Dq~(λB ) ŷ ŷ i y R y h P P RB RW R R PB RB PW PB = ψ λ λ (ψ − ψ ) − ψ λ λ (ψ − ψ ) λB ŷ 2 Dq~(λB ) σ∗P = The term in brackets is the same as the term in brackets in (A.8), so per capita spending on the poor increases with the proportion black if and only if the tax rate increases as well. Robustness Result 1 Propositions 1, 2 and 3 hold if citizen utility is given by (4). Proof. Setting up and solving the candidate’s maximization problem yields: k σ = from the budget constraint τ∗ y = P k y P ij λij ψ ij αijk ŷ σ k , that is: K 1 X X ij ij ijk 1 X ij ij ψ λ ψ α = λ ψ = τ∗ = ŷ k=1 ij ŷ ij ŷ where the first equality comes from the fact that each group has the same relative tradeoff P ijk between consumption and government spending, K = 1, and other equalities are by k=1 α definition. This is the same expression for the equilibrium tax rate as in (A.4), and thus all previous results continue to hold. Appendicies–7 B For the next robustness result, define ~b0 = {y, yy } and the function q~0 : ~b0 → R2 as the map between a change in the element of ~b0 and the changes in ~y . Since the robustness result examines changes in income levels, denote the equilibrium tax rate here as τ∗ (~y ). Robustness Result 2 An increase in average income through changes in ~y , holding economic parity constant, leads to a decrease in the equilibrium tax rate: Dq~0 (y) τ∗ (~y ) < 0. An increase in economic parity through changes in ~y , holding average income constant, leads to an increase in the equilibrium tax rate if and only if average black income is less than average yB < y ⇐⇒ income: Dq~0 ( yB ) τ∗ (~y ) > 0 y Proof. Start with a ceteris paribus change in y. There are two constraints: R R P P Dq~0 (y) y = λ Dq~0 (y) y + λ Dq~0 (y) y = 1 B Dq~0 (y) yy Since dτ∗ dy = 1 λB y h λRB Dq~0 (y) y R + λP B Dq~0 (y) y P − 1 λB = − ŷψ2 dŷ and dy dŷ dy = ŷy , dτ∗ dy Dq~0 ” B y y R y = λ Dq~0 B Dq~0 “ yB ” yy y Once again “ ” B y y R P y + λ Dq~0 “ y y ” B y y yB . y dτ∗ dy ⇒ D ~0 y P = q (y) yP y There are two constraints: P y =0 1 R P B P RB = λB y λ Dq~0 “ yB ” y + λ Dq~0 “ yB ” y = 1 y =0 yR y = − τy∗ < 0. Next consider a ceteris paribus change in “ i B D ~0 y R = q (y) y ⇒ B P Dq~0 “ yB ” y R = − λR λPyλB −λλ P λRB y Dq~0 “ yB ” y P = y yλB λR λR λP B −λP λRB dŷ = − ŷψ2 dy , and P Dq~0 “ ” B y y R yλR λP λB (ψ − ψ ) ŷ = λR λP B − λP λRB The numerator is negative, and the denominator is positive if and only if y > y B , so if and only if y > y B . dτ∗ dy >0 Appendicies–8 Appendix B Data Tables B.1 and B.2 contain summaries of the data used in this paper. Table B.1: Definitions of Variables Variable Symbol Description Dependent Variables Tax Rate τ̂ Tax rate in percent Public Welfare σ̂ P Public welfare spending per capita (in 1980 dollars) Tax Revenue per capita τy Tax revenue divided by population (in 1980 dollars) Independent Variables Proportion Black λB Average Income y Log of average income of families and unrelated individuals (in 1980 dollars) Economic Parity yB y Ratio of average income of black families and unrelated individuals to city average Proportion of the city that is black Median to Avg. Income Ratio Ratio of median income to average income for families and unrelated individuals Population in School Population in city schools (in 100,000s) College Proportion of city population over 25 with at least four years of college Population City population (in 100,000s) City Employees Number of city employees (in 100,000s) Proportion Senior Proportion of city residents over 65 years old Data for the variables public welfare, tax revenue, black, population in school, college, population, city employees and proportion senior variables are from the 1944, 1949, 1952, 1956, 1962, 1967, 1972, 1977 and 1983 County and City Databook (CCDB) published by the U.S. Census Bureau. These data sources are converted to electronic format by Haines (2005). Tax revenue is used rather than government expenditures because the later includes government transfers that are not determined by local government decisions.31 31 For the early years tax revenue and government expenditures are closely connected, but they begin to Appendicies–9 Table B.2: Summary Statistics of Variables Variable Mean Std. Dev. Min. No. of Max. Obs. Units Dependent Variables Tax Rate 1.42 0.92 0.27 7.28 860 percent Public Welfare 18.3 58.5 0.00 736 763 1980 dollars per capita Tax Revenue 213 160 29 1461 975 1980 dollars per capita Independent Variables Proportion Black 0.15 0.13 0.00 0.72 975 Proportion Average Income 9.62 0.29 8.61 10.4 860 Log 1980 dollars Avg. Black to Avg. Income Ratio 0.67 0.13 0.25 1.08 828 Ratio Median to Average Income Ratio 0.85 0.06 0.59 1.01 860 Ratio Population in School 0.73 1.39 0.12 15.2 945 Hundred-thousands College 0.11 0.05 0.03 0.49 556 Proportion Population 3.94 8.05 1.00 78.9 975 Hundred-thousands City Employees 0.06 0.22 0.00 3.75 1182 Hundred-thousands Percent Senior 0.09 0.03 0.03 0.30 924 Proportion Appendicies–10 Demographic data is obtained for the years 1940, 1950, 1960, 1970 and 1980, while local government data, specifically tax revenue per capita and public welfare spending, is obtained for the years 1942, 1948, 1950, 1955, 1960, 1965, 1967 and 1972. To match these observations, demographic data is linearly interpolated between the decennial years. When the variable of interest is a proportion, such as the proportion of a city over 65, the population and the population over 65 are interpolated separately. Other interpolation schemes, such as interpolating the ratios themselves produced similar results. Income data for 1960, 1970 and 1980 is from the U.S. Census Bureau’s Census of the Population, Volume 2: Characteristics of the Population (COP). The Census Bureau summarizes income data at three levels: for families, families and unrelated individuals and for all individuals over the age of 14. The family level contains all groups of 2 or more people who are related and living together. Thus, single workers who live on their own are not included in statistics at this level. Data at the level of families and unrelated individuals correct for this deficiency; households of one are included in these data. The final category, individuals over the age of 14 is self explanatory. Unfortunately, data at this level treats an unemployed woman who is married to a man making $10,000 dollars a year the same as an unemployed woman married to a man making $1,000 a year. It is likely that the former woman would have a level of political sensitivity commensurate with her status as a member of a rich household, while the later would exhibit similar political behavior to other members of the poor. Thus, all data used in this analysis is for families and unrelated individuals.32 In all cases data is for the city itself rather than the city’s SMSA. Data from the COP were entered by hand, and several checks were performed to ensure accuracy. I entered some data, such as median family income, number of families and population that are available in the CCDB and the COP and checked that the data from both sources matched. When there was a mismatch in a variable for a given city and year, diverge starting in the late 1960s. The results are substantively similar if any given year is left out of the data. 32 Results using data at the family level are substantively similar to those presented below. Appendicies–11 I re-entered all data for that city in that year and checked again. Finally, I entered data for a random 10% of the sample twice. Almost all errors were due to entering the data for the entire city from the city in the column next to it in the census tables. For 1950, the COP contains separate income data for blacks only in southern states. For 1940, the COP does not report income data for cities with populations below 250,000. Income data appears not to have been collected at all by the Census Bureau before 1940. To obtain estimates of income data for 1940 and 1950, I calculated income for these cities using the 1% sample of U.S. households that the Census Bureau makes available through the Public Use Microdata Sample (PUMS). In these data a respondent’s city is reported only if the city has more than 100,000 residents. These data are made available electronically by IPUMS (Ruggles et al., 2004). I also used this data to calculate the proportion of a city that is over 65 in 1940. To ascertain the accuracy of this data, I estimated several variables using PUMS data that are available in the CCDB. The results of regressions of the estimated values on the actual values are reported in Table B.3. The estimated values are statistically different from the actual values only in the case of population in 1940. This indicates that there is some oversampling in cities in 1940, which is not of particular concern since the variables of interest deal with proportions and income, which are estimated with very high accuracy. As another measure of the accuracy of these data, the correlation between predicted and actual values is very high - above 0.8 in all cases, and for 0.89-0.99 in most cases. Unfortunately PUMS data does not identify the city of residence in years after 1950. However, it should be noted that the results remain substantively similar when any year is dropped from the study. One data point calculated from the PUMS data seemed unreasonable—economic parity from Salt Lake City, UT in 1950 was 1.42. I dropped all observations for Salt Lake City before 1960. Additionally, this variable for Gary, IN and Flint, MI in 1960 gave very high values (1.25 and 1.15 respectively) that seemed out of line with the 1970 data. It seemed Appendicies–12 Table B.3: Accuracy and Unbiasedness of PUMS Estimates of Variables Dependent Variable: Estimate form PUMS 1940 1950 1.067∗∗∗ (0.009) 0.998 1.015 (0.014) 0.993 Population coef. s.e. ρ Proportion Senior coef. s.e. ρ Proportion Male coef. s.e. ρ 1.052 (0.094) 0.8011 Proportion Black coef. s.e. ρ coef. s.e. ρ 1.002 (0.011) 0.996 Median Family Income 1.017 (0.084) 0.813 Proportion of coef. Families with s.e. Income <$2000 ρ n 0.994 (0.009) 0.997 1.017 (0.058) 0.894 0.964 (0.058) 0.887 71 77 Notes: Coefficients and standard errors from a regression of actual variables from the CCDB on estimated variables from PUMS. ∗∗∗ denotes statistically different from one at the 1% level. ρ is the first order correlation between the estimated and actual values. Appendicies–13 safest to drop these observations, although including them does not alter the results. All dollar amounts are converted to 1980 dollars using the inflation calculator found online on the U.S. Bureau of Labor Statistics website at: http://www.bls.gov/cpi/. Hawaii is the only state in the sample where a significant proportion of the non-white population is not black. Hawaii is dropped from the sample. To keep the sample within the continental United States, Alaska is dropped as well, although this has almost no impact on the results as this eliminates only a single data point: Anchorage in 1972. Appendicies–14 References Acemoglu, Daron and James A. Robinson. 2006. Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press. Alesina, Alberto, Reza Baqir and Caroline Hoxby. 2004. “Political Jurisdictions in Heterogeneous Communities.” Journal of Political Economy 112(2):348–396. Alesina, Alberto, Reza Baqir and William Easterly. 1999. “Public Goods and Ethnic Divisions.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 114(4):1243–1284. Alesina, Alesina and Eliana La Ferrara. 2000. “Participation in Heterogeneous Communities.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 115(3):847–904. Austen-Smith, David and Michael Wallerstein. 2006. “Redistribution and Affirmative Action.” Journal of Public Economics 90(10):1789 – 1823. Banfield, Edward C. and James Q. Wilson. 1963. City Politics. New York: Vintage Books. Bauer, Raymond A., Ithiel de Sola Pool and Lewis Anthony Dexter. 1963. American Business and Public Policy: The Politics of Foreign Trade. New York: Atherton Press. Bergstrom, Theodore C., Daniel L. Rubinfeld and Perry Shapiro. 1982. “Micro-Based Estimates of Demand Functions for Local School Expenditures.” Econometrica 50(5):1183– 1206. Community Council of Greater New York. 1963. Comparative Recreation Needs and Services in New York Neighborhoods. New York, NY: Community Council of Greater New York. Dawson, Michael C. 1994. Behind the Mule: Race and Class in African-American Politics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Dixit, Avinash and John Londregan. 1996. “The Determinants of Success of Special Interests in Redistributive Politics.” The Journal of Politics 58(4):1132–1155. Easterly, William and Ross Levine. 1997. “Africa’s Growth Tragedy: Policies and Ethnic Divisions.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 112(4):1203–1250. Epple, Dennis and Holger Sieg. 1999. “Estimating Equilibrium Models of Local Jurisdictions.” Journal of Political Economy 107(4):645. Epple, Dennis, Thomas Romer and Holger Sieg. 2001. “Interjurisdictional Sorting and Majority Rule: An Empirical Analysis.” Econometrica 69(6):1437–1465. Esteban, Joan M. and Debraj Ray. 1994. “On the Measurement of Polarization.” Econometrica 62(4):819–851. Gramlich, Edward M. and Daniel L. Rubinfeld. 1982. “Micro Estimates of Public Spending Demand Functions and Tests of the Tiebout and Median-Voter Hypotheses.” The Journal of Political Economy 90(3):536–560. References–1 Grossman, Gene M. and Elhanan Helpman. 2001. Special Interest Politics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Haines, Michael R. 2005. Historical, Demographic, Economic and Social Data: The United States, 1790-2000 [Computer File]. ICPSR02896-v2. Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-university Consortium for Political and Social Research [producer and distributor]. Hausman, Jerry A. 1978. “Specification Tests in Econometrics.” Econometrica 46(6):1251– 1271. Hill, Kim Quaile and Patricia A. Hurley. 1984. “Nonvoters in Voters Clothing: The Impact of Voting Behavior Misreporting on Voting Behavior Research.” Social Science Quarterly 65(1):199–206. Huckfeldt, Robert and Carol Weitzel Kohfeld. 1989. Race and the Decline of Class in American Politics. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Katzman, Martin T. 1968. “Distribution and Production in a Big City Elementary Schools System.” Yale Economic Essays 8:201–256. Key, V.O. 1949. Southern Politics in State and Nation. New York: A.A. Knopf. King, Gary. 1997. A Solution to the Ecological Inference Problem. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. King, Gary and Bradley Palmquist. 1997. “The Record of American Democracy, 1984-1990.” PS: Political Science and Politics 30(4):746–747. King, Gary, Bradley Palmquist, Greg Adams, Micah Altman Altman, Kenneth Benoit, Claudine Gay, Lewis Jeffrey B., Russ Mayer and Eric Reinhardt. 1997. The Record of American Democracy, 1984-1990 [Computer File]. Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-university Consortium for Political and Social Research [distributor]. Lee, Woojin, John E. Roemer and Karine Van der Straeten. 2007. Racism, Xenophobia, and Redistribution: A Study of Multi-Issue Politics in Advanced Democracies. New York and Cambridge, MA: Russell Sage Foundation and Harvard University Press. Leighley, Jan E. 2001. Strength in Numbers?: The Political Mobilization of Racial and Ethnic Minorities. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Levy, Frank, Arnold J. Meltsner and Aaron Wildavsky. 1974. Urban Outcomes: Schools, Streets, and Libraries. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Lind, Jo Thori. 2007. “Fractionalization and the Size of Government.” Journal of Public Economics 91(1):51–76. Lindbeck, Assar and Jörgen W. Weibull. 1987. “Balanced-Budget Redistribution as the Outcome of Political Competition.” Public Choice 52(3):273–297. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1960. Political Man. Garden City, New York: Doubleday. References–2 Lowi, Theodore J. 1964. “American Business, Public Policy, Case-Studies, and Political Theory.” World Politics 16(4):677–693. Martin, Lowell A. 1969. Library Response to Urban Change: A Study of the Chicago Public Library. Chicago, IL: American Library Association. Meltzer, Allan H. and Scott F. Richard. 1981. “A Rational Theory of the Size of Government.” The Journal of Political Economy 89(5):914–927. Montalvo, José G. and Marta Reynal-Querol. 2005. “Ethnic Polarization, Potential Conflict, and Civil Wars.” American Economic Review 95(3):796–816. Oberholzer-Gee, Felix and Joel Waldfogel. 2005. “Strength in Numbers: Group Size and Political Mobilization.” The Journal of Law and Economics 48(1):73–91. Olzak, Susan, Suzzanne Shanahan and Elizabeth H. McEneaney. 1996. “Poverty, Segregation, and Race Riots: 1960 to 1993.” American Sociological Review 61(4):590–613. Owen, John D. 1972. “The Distribution of Educational Resources in Large American Cities.” The Journal of Human Resources 7(1):26–38. Persson, Torsten and Guido Tabellini. 2000. Political Economics: Explaining Economic Policy. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. Pinderhughes, Dianne M. 1987. Race and Ethnicity in Chicago Politics. Urbana, Il: University of Illinois Press. Poterba, James M. 1997. “Demographic Structure and the Political Economy of Public Education.” Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 16(1):48–66. Rae, Douglas W. and Micheal Taylor. 1970. The Analysis of Political Cleavages. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press. Roberts, Kevin S.W. 1977. “Voting over Income Tax Schedules.” Journal of Public Economics 8(3):329–340. Roemer, John E. 1998. “Why the Poor do not Expropriate the Rich: An Old Argument in New Garb.” Journal of Public Economics 70(3):399–424. Romer, Thomas. 1975. “Individual Welfare, Majority Voting, and the Properties of a Linear Income Tax.” Journal of Public Economics 4(2):163–185. Rubinfield, Daniel L., Perry Shapiro and Judith Roberts. 1987. “Tiebout Bias and the Demand for Local Public Schooling.” The Review of Economics and Statistics 69(3):426– 437. Ruggles, Steven, Matthew Sobek, Trent Alexander, Catherine A. Fitch, Ronald Goeken, Patricia Kelly Hall, Miriam King and Chad Ronnander. 2004. Integrated Public Use Microdata Series: Version 3.0 [Machine-readable database]. Minneapolis, MN: Minnesota Population Center [producer and distributor]. References–3 Sexton, Patricia C. 1961. Education and Income: Inequalities of Opportunity in our Public Schools. New York, NY: Viking Press. Sigelman, Lee. 1982. “The Nonvoting Voter in Voting Research.” American Journal of Political Science 26(1):47–56. Spilerman, Seymour. 1970. “The Causes of Racial Disturbances: A Comparison of Alternative Explanations.” American Sociological Review 35(4):627–649. Tiebout, Charles M. 1956. “A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures.” The Journal of Political Economy 64(5):416–424. Truman, David B. 1951. The Governmental Process. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Verba, Sidney, Kay Lehman Schlozman and Henry E. Brady. 1995. Voice and Equality: Civic Voluntarism in American Politics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Verba, Sidney and Norman H. Nie. 1972. Participation in America. New York, NY: Harper & Row. Wald, Abraham. 1943. “Tests of Statistical Hypotheses Concerning Several Parameters When the Number of Observations is Large.” Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 54(3):426–482. Washington, Ebonya. 2006. “How Black Candidates Effect Voter Turnout.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 121(3):973–998. White, Halbert. 1980. “A Heteroskedasticity-Consistent Covariance Matrix Estimator and a Direct Test for Heteroskedasticity.” Econometrica 48(4):817–838. Wilson, James Q. 1960. Negro Politics. Glencoe, Il: The Free Press. Wilson, William J. 1978. The Declining Significance of Race. Chicago, Il: University of Chicago Press. References–4