Debating Comparative Propositions of Policy By Robert Trapp and Christine Hanson* Robert Trapp is a Professor of Rhetoric at Willamette University in Salem, Oregon, U.S.A. Christine Hanson is the Press Assistant for United States Senator Bill Nelson (Democrat of Florida) and is a lecturer at George Washington University They have the resolution . . . and they’re off. All too often, debaters get a resolution and start researching and constructing cases before they think about what they have to do on the affirmative to successfully prove it. Such a process can lead to the construction of cases that, while well-researched, may not meet the logical requirements of the proposition. Much of the frustration of case construction can be avoided easily if debaters identity the kinds of arguments a proposition demands before they crack open a book, scour the web, or write a case. Each debate resolution calls for different types of arguments. For example, a proposition that “Nations of the world should strengthen the International Criminal Court”1 asks the affirmative to propose some plan of action as an alternative to the present system. Likewise, the resolution that “Mandatory national service is justified,” 2 asks the affirmative to evaluate the concept of mandatory national service, but does not necessarily require the affirmative to advocate a specific plan of action. 3 Still another proposition, that “the separation of the public and the private is detrimental to women’s rights” 4 does not ask the affirmative to support a plan of action, nor does it necessarily ask the affirmative to evaluate a particular concept.5 This proposition only asks the affirmative to prove that the existence of a “separation of the public and private” has an inverse cause and effect relationship to “women’s rights.”6 Even though these propositions demand different kinds of arguments, they all can be debated in the Karl Popper format – changing from one kind of proposition to another does not require changing from one debate format to another. Karl Popper debate can be readily adapted to these types of propositions, as well as many others. This essay will explore the kinds of arguments called for by a specific type of policy proposition, which we will label “comparative propositions of policy.” It will contrast these comparative propositions of policy with more standard propositions of policy and will conclude with some observations about how both the affirmative and negative can debate a comparative policy proposition. Before we begin our discussion of the comparative policy proposition, we want to stress that the demand for a particular kind of argument comes from the nature of the proposition, not from any rule of Karl Popper debate. Karl Popper debate does not have specific rules saying what kinds of arguments must or must not be presented – just like there is no rule stating that presumption is with the negative, that the affirmative must present a criterion, or that the negative must present a counterplan. Nonetheless, a savvy debater can and should think through the kinds of arguments that need to be made before they begin the process of constructing a case. International Debate Education Association |29 debatenotes PROPOSITIONS OF POLICY7 Before looking at comparative propositions of policy, a specific type of policy proposition, some readers may want to review propositions of policy in general. Those readers should consult an earlier essay in this magazine, written by Marcin Zaleski, Jurate Motejunate, and Robert Trapp. In this essay, we will emphasize three ideas about a standard proposition of policy: the stance of the affirmative team, the stance of the negative team, and case construction. Stance of the Affirmative When debating a standard proposition of policy, the affirmative is required to take a stance in favor of some plan of action. This requirement does not come from some set of arbitrary rules of debate. It comes from the logic of supporting a proposition that contains the words such as “should” or “ought.”8 For instance, if someone proposes to you that “we + - should go on a vacation,” you might be inclined to accept the proposition, but you would still probably ask some questions like: “Where do you propose we go?” “How do you propose we get there?” “How long do you propose we stay?” “How are we going to pay for it?” Thus, one who says “We should go on vacation” is logically required to provide at least an outline of a plan of action if they want that proposition to be accepted. No rules require the person suggesting the vacation to propose a concrete plan of action. But a reasonable person would not accept it unless an overview of a specific plan is explained.9 Similarly, for the affirmative to successfully argue for a standard proposition of policy such as “The nations of the world should strengthen the International Criminal Court,” the affirmative is required to propose a policy that “strengthens 30| International Debate Education Association the International Criminal Court.” In this standard proposition of policy, the affirmative team is assigned to a position where they must present a plan that is substantially different from the status quo. Thus, the affirmative will typically argue for a new policy, rejecting the present way of doing things. In the example at hand, the International Criminal Court is an existing agency of the present system. One logical requirement of advancing the proposition to “strengthen the International Criminal Court” is to create and support a plan of action that is not only different from the present Court, but is somehow “strengthened.” The affirmative usually defends a change from the status quo because of the wording of the proposition, and not because of the some arbitrary rule. Because propositions are usually (although not always) worded so that they imply a change from the status quo, the affirmative is most often required to defend such a change. In the event that a proposition is worded in such a way that the status quo is advocated, then the affirmative would be obliged to argue in favor of the status quo.10 When arguing for a standard proposition of policy, the affirmative is required to present and defend a plan of action consistent with that policy. Depending on the nature of the proposition and on the strategic choices made by the affirmative team, the plan can be either very specific or fairly general. The main point is that a proposition of policy requires the affirmative to advocate some action. Stance of the Negative Although the affirmative team is ordinarily assigned to defend a policy that differs significantly from the status quo, the negative team has more options. They can choose to defend the present system, make minor repairs to the present system,11 or offer a counterplan that differs both from the status quo and from the affirmative plan.12 When debating a standard proposition of policy, the negative (unlike the affirmative) has more choice regarding the stances they may take. The affirmative is limited to a stance favoring a change to the present system. But the negative has at least three possible stances available to them: defending the present system, offering minor repairs to the present system, or offering a counterplan. Case Construction A number of different ways are available to organize a case for a standard proposition of policy. Two of the most common are called the need-plan-benefits method and the comparative advantages method. As the name implies, an affirmative team using the need-plan-benefits method, will probably offer ideas in those three categories. First, they will present a need for change. In order to prove a need for a change, the affirmative must demonstrate some harm in the present system and show that the present system is to blame for that harm. Second, the affirmative will present their plan. In this section of the argument, the affirmative gives only a brief outline of the plan of action that they intend to follow. At this point, they need only state their plan, not to create arguments for it. Finally, the affirmative will present the benefits of their plan. The benefits should include an explanation of how each of the harms presented in section one will be cured by their plan. This section of their case should address each of the harms individually, showing how they will be reduced by the adoption of the affirmative plan. A second way to structure an affirmative case for a standard proposition of policy is called the comparative advantage method. Logically the comparative advantages method is not substantially different from the need-planbenefits method. The difference lies in the organizational structure of the two cases. A comparative advantage case is presented in two stages. The first stage involves the presentation of the plan. The presentation of the plan in the comparative advantages case follows the same form as in the need-plan-benefit case–just a simple and straight-forward outline of the proposed course of action. The second stage involves presentation of the advantages. Of course the affirmative can choose to present as many or as few advantages as they wish. The primary constraint on the number of advantages presented involves time. As a result, most debaters limit themselves to one, two, or three advantages. As you will see, the logic in presenting an advantage does not differ significantly from the logic used in a need-plan-benefit case. In fact, a comparative advantage case is quite similar to a need-plan-benefit case. The only major difference is the pattern of organization. Each advantage is presented in three parts: First, describe a problem in the present system; Second, show how some aspect of the present system causes that problem; and Third, show how the plan solves the problem. The combined effect of each of these three parts is to demonstrate that the plan has some advantage over the present system. If more than one advantage is presented, then the three steps can simply be repeated. In this section, some basics about arguing for a standard proposition of policy have been discussed. The main ideas in this section include the stance of the affirmative, the stance of the negative, and case construction. Two threads run through each of these points: First, the primary comparison involves a comparison between the present system and the affirmative plan. Second, the affirmative is assigned a stance consistent with change and the negative, at least initially, is assigned a stance consistent with the existing system. These two threads, present in a standard proposition of policy potentially are absent in a comparative proposition of policy. COMPARATIVE PROPOSITIONS OF POLICY An example of a comparative proposition of policy is the one to be debated at the 2004 IDEA Youth Forum in Estonia. That proposition is: “It is better to focus on a harm reduc- International Debate Education Association |31 debatenotes tion strategy than on a law enforcement strategy in dealing with drug abuse.” Before discussing the specifics of this proposition of even the how to debate comparative policy propositions, we will compare standard and comparative policy propositions. A comparative proposition of policy may differ from a standard proposition of policy in two ways. First, whereas in a standard proposition of policy, the affirmative is assigned a certain stance and the negative has more choices regarding their stance, a comparative proposition of policy assigns a certain stance to both teams. In the proposition at hand, the affirmative is assigned to defend a “harm reduction strategy” and the negative is assigned to describe a “law enforcement strategy.” Second, in a standard proposition of policy, the affirmative generally defends the present system and the negative generally defends the status quo (unless, of course, they present a counterplan). But in a comparative proposition of policy, the contrast is not between the status quo and change from the status quo but between a policy stance assigned to the affirmative and a contrasting policy stance assigned to the negative. In fact, in some comparative policy propositions, the concept of “status quo” may not even be meaningful. In this proposition about drugs for instance, the status quo varies from country to country. Some countries use a harm reduction approach while others use a law enforcement approach. Who is to say which is the status quo? The sections that follow will be parallel to the sections about the standard policy proposition: stance of the affirmative team, stance of the negative team and case construction. The first three sections will be brief and more attention will be paid to methods of structuring a case in a comparative manner. Stance of the Affirmative As in the standard policy proposition, the stance of each team is not determined on the basis of arbitrary rules, but on the basis of the logic of the proposition. In the example at hand, the logic of the proposition dictates that the affirmative defend a plan of action consistent with a “harm reduction strategy.” The difference between this and the standard policy proposition is that the affirmative does not necessarily compare the “harm reduction strategy” to the “status quo” but to the negative policy of a “law enforcement strategy.” 32| International Debate Education Association Stance of the Negative In the standard policy proposition, the negative has at least three choices regarding their stance. They could choose to defend the present system, offer minor repairs to the status quo or propose a counterplan. Again, the logic of a comparative policy proposition dictates that the negative defend a policy consistent with the concept assigned to them in the proposition. In the proposition we are discussing, the negative is assigned to defend some plan of action consistent with a “law enforcement strategy.” Because the resolution calls on the negative team to support a policy, they will, in all likelihood, want to present a counterplan. Like the affirmative outlines their plan of action in a case for a standard policy proposition, the negative may want to provide a similar outline of their plan of action. Case Construction We want to emphasize that no rules demand any particular case structure for a comparative policy proposition, or for any other kind of proposition for that matter. The kinds of case structures available for this kind of proposition are limited only by the imagination of the debaters. With just a little thought, most debaters can probably think of ways to adapt the needplan-benefits structure or the comparative advantage structure to this kind of a proposition. Creative debaters can probably envision other ways to structure a case. While many avenues are available to structure a case on a comparative policy proposition, a comparative advantage format may be the most straightforward because the point of the proposition is to compare the advantages of one policy to another. For this reason, this essay will focus on comparative advantage structures teams may take to argue a comparative policy proposition. To make these ideas more concrete, we now turn to a more detailed discus- sion of constructing an actual case for such a proposition. CONSTRUCTING A CASE FOR A COMPARATIVE POLICY PROPOSITION We will begin with an example of a comparative policy proposition: “It is better to focus on a harm reduction strategy than on a law enforcement strategy in dealing with drug abuse.” We will use this example to illustrate how to create a comparative advantage case for a comparative policy proposition. Constructing a case for this, or any other kind of policy proposition, can be conceived of in three phases: conceptualizing the case, creating the plan, and creating the advantages. Conceptualizing the Case Regardless of the kind of case that debaters want to create, they need to begin the process at a rather abstract level. After thinking about the case conceptually, the debaters can then make it more concrete and eventually can develop a persuasive speech that supports their case. Conceptualizing the case means that before the debaters begin to research and write, they must think about the ideas and concepts that will guide its construction. One way to conceptualize the case for comparing two policies is to ask a series of questions that weigh the competing policies. For instance, debaters might ask themselves three questions: 1) What are the central features in both policy options? 2) How do these features interact with one another? 3) How can the some feature of the affirmative plan be used to replace some feature of the negative policy? Consider the topic that suggests that a “harms reduction strategy” is superior to a “law enforcement strategy” for dealing with drug abuse. The first question is “What are the central features of both policy options?” One approach to this question might be to claim that crimi- nalization is central to law enforcement while socialization is central to harms reduction. Because the law enforcement strategy can only work when drug users are identified as criminals who violate laws that police enforce, one can argue that criminalization is inherent to the law enforcement strategy. Alternatively, one can argue that a harms reduction strategy is one that conceives of drug users not as criminals, but as part of society. When we think about drug users as members of society, we then can try to keep that part of society safe from harm rather than put them in prison. The second question is “How do features of these policy options interact with one another?” Arguably the process of criminalization is incompatible to the process of socialization. First, these policies are incompatible with one another because attempts to take people out of society (imprisoning them) through law enforcement strategies is exactly the opposite of considering them as an integral part of society that simply needs protection from the harms of drug addiction. Second, one might argue that criminalizing people by imprisoning them creates a criminal subculture that cannot reintegrate into society even when they are released from prison. When imprisoned, drug users not only are exposed to a culture of criminalized drug users like themselves, but they are exposed to other kinds of criminal lifestyles as well. Why should we be surprised that when they are released into society they are not likely to integrate into the non-criminal elements of society? This kind of thinking helps the affirmative debater see how the features of these two policy options (“harms reduction” and “law enforcement”) interact with one another in nonproductive ways. The third question is “How can some feature of the affirmative plan be used to replace some feature of the negative policy?” Having decided that socialization is central to harms reduction and that criminalization is central to law enforcement, the question now becomes how can socialization be used as a replacement for criminalization? One approach to this question is to think of socialization processes, such as education and rehabilitation, as alternatives to imprisonment. Having thought about the proposition by answering these three questions, the affirmative is now in a position to begin constructing their plan. Constructing the Affirmative Plan Answering the previous three questions (or questions like them) is a mental exercise that allows a debater to think International Debate Education Association |33 debatenotes about what needs to be included in the outline of a plan. By answering these questions, debaters focus on the features of the negative policy that needs to be avoided and features of the affirmative policy that need to be included in the affirmative plan. After identifying these features, debaters are in a better position to decide on the categories of ideas that need to be included in the plan. For instance, the above conceptualization might lead a debater to think that four things are central to an outline of the plan: 1) Features of the negative policy to be excluded from the affirmative plan. 2) An expanded list of categories and subcategories of these policies to be excluded from the affirmative plan. 3) Features of the affirmative to be included in the affirmative plan. 4) An expanded list of categories and subcategories of these policies to be included in the affirmative plan. Having decided on the basic categories of elements that need to be included in the affirmative plan, the debater is now in position to begin actually constructing an outline of the plan. The first things that need to be included in the plan are the essential elements that have come from the central features and their subcategories. Secondary aspects to be included in the plan might be things that prevent possible costs. A third group of things that need to be included in the plan are any necessary administrative and structural elements that the debaters think should be included. So, based on the conceptualizations undertaken, a debater might draft a plan that looks something like this: Affirmative Plan: 1) The affirmative plan explicitly prohibits any and all types of criminalization policies designed to deal with drug abuse. 2) Criminalization policies such as laws making possession and use of drugs illegal will be abolished. 3) The affirmative plan will substitute socialization policies as appropriate methods of dealing with drug abuse. 4) These socialization policies include, but are not limited to, drug education, needle exchange policies, drug maintenance policies and rehabilitation policies. 5) Exceptions to points 1 and 2 will be made only with regard to persons under the age of 18 and to persons engaging in activities such as driving or operating heavy machinery where the use of drugs can seriously endanger other persons. 34| International Debate Education Association 6) The affirmative plan will be administered by . . . 7) The affirmative plan will be funded by . . . In the example above, the first four planks of the plan involve a statement of included and excluded features of “harms reduction” and “law enforcement” strategies. The fifth point in the plan is designed to prevent possible costs – in this case, to prevent people from driving while under the influence of drugs. The sixth and seventh points are illustrative of administrative and structural elements that might be needed to make the plan work. Constructing the advantages Now that the plan is outlined, the debaters think back to the conceptualization stage and begin the process of creating advantages. This involves showing how problems of drug abuse are linked to the negative policy while the affirmative system provides a cure to some of those problems. This process, of outlining the comparative costs and benefits of the affirmative system, is the basis of a comparative advantage case. The next task is to decide on which specific advantages to include in the case. Once this decision is made, the debater then begins to outline each advantage. Based on the earlier conceptualization of the affirmative case, one might outline two advantages to the plan in the following way: I. The affirmative plan is a superior way of reducing the problems associated with drug use. A. Law enforcement strategies define drug users as criminals. Law enforcement strategies define drug users and sellers as criminals. By the very nature of “law enforcement,” drug use must be defined as against the law and drug users must be defined as criminals. B. Defining drug users as criminals is counter productive. Placing drug users in prison with persons who have violated drug laws, as well as with others who may have committed even worse crimes, inculcates them into a criminal subculture. Upon release from prison, drug users frequently cannot find productive employment so they remain a part of the criminal subculture relying on the street skills and contacts they made in prison. C. The affirmative plan replaces criminalization with socialization. Rather than sending drug users to prison, the affirmative plan considers them a part of society needing protection. Thus, the affirmative plan creates other solutions such as education, rehabilitation and, when necessary, maintenance programs. D. Socialization is superior to criminalization. Education, rehabilitation and drug maintenance programs have a much greater chance of success than criminalization. II. The affirmative is a superior way of reducing the problems associated with drug sales. A. Law enforcement strategies allow drug sales to be controlled by dangerous criminal elements. Since the sale of drugs is illegal, drug dealers are criminals. Thus, the only people who can sell drugs are criminals. B. Placing drug sales in the hands of criminals creates drug wars. In their efforts to enforce laws against drug selling, law enforcement agents must engage the drug sellers–sometimes violently. These violent confrontations bring substantial risks not only to the drug sellers, but also to the law enforcement agents. International Debate Education Association |35 debatenotes Criminalization of drug sales is also dangerous to bystanders. Because of the risk of dealing in an illegal trade is so great, the price of drugs and the potential profit is driven up. When criminal elements find themselves in situations where they are able to make great profits on drugs, they start turf battles, which lead to drug wars where innocent bystanders are killed and wounded. C. The affirmative plan takes criminals out of the drug business. Under the affirmative plan, the sale of drugs is no longer illegal. Therefore the sale of drugs will be controlled by the marketplace and regulated by the government, rather than in the hands of criminals. D. Taking criminals out of the drug business reduces the problems associated with drug wars. By making drug sales legal, the dangers to both law enforcement officers and ordinary citizens would be substantially reduced. Just as running a legal liquor store is much less dangerous than being an illegal drug dealer, the violence associated with drug sales would be substantially reduced. Of course the two examples provided above are simply illustrations of how advantages can be described on the basis of an earlier conceptualization of the case. In both of these cases, debaters will have to add more explanation, and even more importantly, they will need to research and add evidence to their presentations. Perceptive readers will notice a pattern in the two examples presented above. The pattern is not the only workable one, but it is one pattern that will work most of the time when describing comparative advantages. Stripped of the drug content, the pattern in the examples above is as follows: A. Describe a condition associated with the negative policy. This point requires returning to the conceptualization of the case and describing an inherent feature of the policy that has been assigned to the negative team. B. Relate that condition to some effect. By drawing a cause and effect relationship between the negative policy and some unwanted effect, the affirmative case proves that 36| International Debate Education Association the negative policy is undesirable. C. Describe an opposing condition associated with th affirmative policy. The debater now describes some condition of the plan that is logically opposed to the condition of the negative policy. D. Relate that condition to some effect. By drawing a causal relationship between the affirmative policy and some positive effect, the affirmative case proves that the affirmative policy is comparatively advantageous to the negative policy. In the end, it is important for debaters to identify what arguments a resolution demands – not because an arbitrary rule exists, but because the nature of the proposition logically calls for it. When arguing comparative policy propositions, the affirmative and negative teams are assigned policy positions by the wording of the resolution. In the case of the 2004 IDEA Youth Forum in Estonia, the affirmative must take a “harm reduction strategy” and the negative must take a “law enforcement strategy” to address the problem of drug abuse. Teams should conceptualize their affirmative case by asking questions that critically compare “harm reduction” and “law enforcement” policies. They should identify an aspect of the “law enforcement” strategy that causes negative effects and show an opposing condition of their “harm reduction” policy that relates to some positive outcome. This process of conceptualizing the case before constructing it and its advantages ensures that debaters prepare cases that can prove a resolution true. Once this preliminary step occurs, it’s off to crack open books, scour the web and write a well-researched and logical case that’ll be tough to beat. + - = NOTES: 1. This proposition was debated at the 2002 IDEA Youth Forum in Podbanske, Slovakia. 2. This proposition was debated as the 1996 IDEA Youth Forum in Celakovice, Czech Republic. 3. Depending on how one interprets this proposition, it can be considered either a proposition of value or a proposition of policy. 4. This proposition was debated at the 2003 IDEA Youth forum in Ljubljana, Slovenia. 5. According to this reading, this proposition presents a purely theoretical question as to whether the idea of “separating public and private” decreases “women’s rights.” This reading does not ask whether a decrease in women’s rights is good or bad. An alternative reading of this proposition would be that the term “detrimental” is an evaluative term and that by implication the affirmative should have to prove that the decrease in women’s rights is harmful. 6. Robert Trapp and Tehmeena Luqman. “Debating Values Using Cause and Effect Argument,” Idebate 3:4 (June, 2003): pp. 28 – 37. 7. This section is not intended to be a fullfledged discussion of standard propositions of policy. Anyone wanting more information about debating policy propositions in general should consult other sources. One such source is Marcin Zaleski, Jurate Motejunate, and Robert Trapp, “Debating about Policies,” Idebate 3:4 (June, 2003): pp. 16 – 27. 8. Merely by convention, some teachers and writers have insisted that the word “should” is a necessary and a sufficient indicator of a policy proposition. This convention, however, is arbitrary and does not mirror ordinary language usage. The term “should” is one of many terms that can signal a logical requirement for a plan of action. 9. Of course one can debate the general idea of going on vacation (or any other action for that matter) without getting into a debate on specifics. Without presenting a specific proposal, one could make a case for going on vacation by saying “Since we’ve been working too hard, have saved a lot of money, and since work is slow, we should go on vacation.” Certainly a general debate could proceed on those kinds of arguments, but before the action is taken the arguers will have to settle on a specific plan. In scholastic debates, the negative will not usually allow the affirmative to be so general. They will want to ask specific questions and absent answers to those questions they might make an argument like “Without a specific plan that includes when and where we will go, we should not agree to go on vacation. If we did we might find ourselves in Minsk in January rather than in Hawaii.” 10. For example, “France should continue its opposition to the U.S. war in Iraq” is phrased in such a way that that the affirmative would be obliged to support France’s current actions. 11. Some writers distinguish minor repairs from a counter plan by saying minor repairs continue the structural and philosophical actions of the status quo arguing only for small changes such as additional funding, more enforcement of current policies, etc. 12. Ordinarily the counterplan must not only be different from the affirmative plan, it should also be inconsistent with the actions envisioned by the proposition. So in our example, the counterplan must not simply be a different way of strengthening the International Criminal Court, it must be a plan that somehow stands in opposition to the very concept of a stronger Court. For example, the counterplan might propose weakening the Court or abolishing the Court altogether. Some debate instructors teach that the counterplan must only differ from the affirmative plan and not from the proposition. A consideration of the arguments for and against this practice is beyond the scope of this essay. International Debate Education Association |37