Cubism and the Early American Modernist Author(s): Abraham A. Davidson Source: Art Journal, Vol. 26, No. 2, (Winter, 1966-1967), pp. 122-165 Published by: College Art Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/775035 Accessed: 29/05/2008 12:20 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=caa. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org 1 movement, and with Benton in particular, with so little qualification. His most popular paintings reflect an attitude of mind quite remote from that of Benton's, and though both were from the mid-west, they did not always respond to it with the same spirit. This is particularly the case during the early 1930's when, in a handful of canvases, Wood was one of our most probing critics. MATTHEW BAIGELL, who received the Ph.D. degree from the University of Pennsylvania, is an assistant professor of art history at The Ohio State University. He co-authored "Happening in the Classroom: A New Way of Teaching Art" which appeared in last summer's issue. Abraham A. Davidson Cubism and the Early American Modernist I In an article entitled "Toward a Re-interpretation of Cubism," Winthrop Judkins singled out a number of formal characteristics common to the still lifes of Picasso, Braque and Gris done between 1912 and 1916: planes which are at once transparent and opaque; tones of objects which "bleed" out and become background tones so that the object is part of, and at the same time in front of, the background; outlines which coincide with other outlines so that the continuity may be read around either or across both; surfaces which recede behind other surfaces and project over them simultaneously; shadows, mutually excluded by each other's light sources, standing side by side; etc. He concluded that "clearly that which all these things have in common, that of which they are an unending variety of manifestations, is this: A deliberate oscillation of appearances, a studied multiplicity of readings, a conscious compounding of identities, an iridescence of form."1 Robert Rosenblum, in his recent Cubism and Twentieth-Century Art,2 interprets the Cubist movement in a broader scope which includes, in part at least, the work of such painters as Chagall, Miro, Klee, Marin, Demuth, and many others. Basically, though, Rosenblum treats Picasso, Braque and Gris as the main figures. It is to them that the other Cubists are compared, and to some extent judged. In the first third of this century, several American Modernists produced paintings which seem to stem from the work of the classical Cubists. Charles Demuth, Marsden Hartley, Alfred Maurer, John Marin, and Max Winthrop O. Judkins, "Toward a Reinterpretation of Cubism," Art Bulletin, 30 (December 1948), 270-278. 2Robert Rosenblum, Cubism and Twentieth-Century Art (New York, 1961). Weber were surely acquainted with the canvases of the Cubists. All of them had been in Paris at one time or another between 1908 and 1912, and presumably saw the early exhibitions of Cubism.3 Subsequently, they could 3 The years these painters spent in Europe are recorded in the principal monographs. Maurer was the first to reach Paris: he arrived in 1897 and, except for some very brief visits to New York, remained in France until 1914. Marin was in Paris in the summer of 1905, and participated in the Salons d'Automne of 1908 and 1910 and in the Salon des Independants of 1909. He returned to America permanently in May, 1911. Demuth spent a year in Paris in 1907, and returned for a two-year stay in 1912. Weber arrived in Paris in 1905 and stayed until December, 1908; he participated in the Salon d'Automne of 1908. Hartley did not reach Paris until late spring, 1912; and saw his first samples of Cubism at Stieglitz's 291 in 1911. (See especially the following: Elizabeth McCausland, A. H. Maurer (New York, 1951); MacKinley Helm, John Marin (Boston, 1948); Andrew C. Ritchie, Charles Demuth (New York, 1950); Whitney Museum of American Art, Max Weber Retrospective Exhibition, New York, 1949; and Elizabeth McCausland, Marsden Hartley (Minneapolis, 1952). In Europe, the proto-Cubist work of Braque could have been seen at Kahnweiler's Gallery from November 9 through 20, 1908, and that of Picasso at the Ambrose Vollard Gallery in 1909. Braque exhibited his early Cubist paintings at the Salon des Independants of 1908 and 1909 and at the Salon d'Automne of 1908. The main Cubist painters exhibited as a group at the Salon des Independants of 1910. For the early Cubist exhibitions, see John Golding, Cubism: A History and Analysis (London, 1959), pp. 19-46. ART JOURNALXXVI 2 122 have seen examples in New York at Stieglitz's Gallery 291 and at the Armory Show.4 Illustrations of Cubist paintings were to be found on the pages of Camera Work5 and Arthur J. Eddy's Cubists and Post Impressionism.6 Yet the American so-called Cubists merely made overtures to this new manner; they adopted some of its devices, but missed the underlying logic of the European movement. Andrew Dasburg remarked in 1923: "Almost everyone [in America] that can be called 'modern' [and among his 'moderns' Dasburg included Demuth, Hartley, Marin, and Weber] has at some time or other shown the influence of Cubism in his work [yet] . .. one cannot write of 'actual Cubism' in America, but only of the effort."7 What was the basis of Dasburg's deprecation? From the standpoint of Judkins' criterion of a purposeful ambiguity, the American painters may be judged as lacking in courage or perhaps as incompetent in their attempt to achieve "actual Cubism." If we analyze the Cubist paintings of the Americans, we see that the corruscating web of planes marking the classical Cubist aesthetic is, in fact, not to be found. The closely cohering surfaces which in Paris made for a diaphanous interrelationship of zones and a curious interchangeability between mass and void are absent; instead we find in most of the American Cubists a clearer demarcation between forms and a less ambiguous proliferation of spatial areas. Hence in Hartley's Landscape No. 32 of 1911 (Fig. which was inspired by Picasso's charcoal drawing of a 1), woman shown at Stieglitz's 291,8 the subtle Cubist network has been transformed into a clear definition of hill formations and tubular roads. Hartley's Portrait of a German Officer, painted in 1914 or early 1915 (Fig. 2), can be called Cubist only with a good deal of reservation, as each object is rendered with a meticulous clarity. Yet Hartley seems to have considered his portraits a new form of Cubism, distinct from the work not only of Picasso but also of Kandinsky, whose colorful abstractions 4In 1911, Stieglitz gave Picasso his first one-man show anywhere. Lists of Stieglitz's Exhibitions can be found in TValdoFrank, Lewis Mumford, Dorothy Norman, Paul Rosenfeld, and Harold Rugg, America and Alfred Stieglitz, (New York, 1934), pp. 313-316. For a list of the works shown in the Armory Show, see Milton W. Brown, The Story of the Armory Show (Greenwich, Conn., 1963). 'An account of Picasso's Show at 291 can be found in Camera Work, 36 (October 1911). 6Arthur J. Eddy, Cubists and Post-Impressionism (Chicago, 1914), Chs. 5 and 6. 7Andrew Dasburg, "Cubism-Its Rise and Influence," 279. Arts, 4 (November s This is illustrated1923), in Camera Work, 36 (October 1911), 71. 123 Davidson: Cubism and the Early American Modernist Fig. 1. Marsden Hartley, LANDSCAPENo. 32, 1911, Coll. of lone and Hudson Walker. had influenced him when he saw them in Munich. Hartley claimed that his painting was the result of "spiritual illumination." In December 1912, he wrote a long letter to Stieglitz in which he dwelt enthusiastically on his projected German series: I am rapidly gaining ground in this variety of expression and I find it to be closest to my own temperament and ideals. It is not like anything here. It is not like Picasso-it is not like Kandinsky, not like any "cubism." It is what I call for want of a better name subliminal or cosmic cubism. It will suprise you. I did these things before I went to London as a result of spiritual illumination and I am convinced that it is my real and true utterance. It combines a varied sense of form with my own sense of color which I believe has never needed stimulation.9 Hartley's style was changing rapidly in the second decade of the century, but the juxtaposition of flattened areas 9Letter from Marsden Hartley to Alfred Stieglitz, December 20, 1912. Stieglitz Collection, Collection of American Literature, Yale University Library. Fig. 2. Marsden Hartley, PORTRAIT OF A GERMAN OFFICER, 1914, Coll. of lone and Hudson Walker. Fig. 3. Marsden Hartley, MOVEMENTNO. 9, 1916, Coll. of lone and Hudson Walker. remained. In 1916, he painted Movement No. 9 (Fig. 3), which again shows no attempt at an intersection of spatial zones. This is a totally non-objective work, featuring simply broad, unmodulated, flattened planes, a painting which might be taken today as a somewhat unsuccessful effort of Poliakoff. Maurer's efforts in the Cubist manner are later in date. In his still lifes of the thirties, transparent areas are juxtaposed with objects whose shapes have been simplified, but which nonetheless seem to function normally. The Cubist areas in Still Life with Pears of c. 1931-32 (Fig. 4), center around a solid cardboard container, against which two pears lean on the right-hand side of the canvas and upon which, on a flattened portion, pears are placed at the left. A portion of the container, located a little to the left of center in the upper half of the canvas, functions, however, in a curious way. It seems to have taken on the properties of frozen jello, into which half of a bowl of pears has been imbedded. Maurer seems to hesitate in his ventures with Cubism: the intricate intersection of planes marking the classical Cubist canvas in its totality is avoided for a more timid use of an occasional diaphanous zone. In one place the property of cardboard is violated as it intersects the fruit; while in another place, the cardboard container, treated realistically, retains the properties of a solid. Novel and highly imaginative is the enclosure device in the water colors of John Marin, traceable perhaps to Whistler in some of the Venetian etchings, but never found in any of the works of classical Cubism. The enclosure assumes the shape of the visual image and can act to resolve the conflict when the shape of the image is not in accord with the shape of the canvas. Moreover, it helps to resolve the picture plane, not by juxtaposing areas of two-dimensional objects as in Synthetic Cubism, but through blunting the force of geometric perspective through the removal of the foreground plane. This device, functioning as a window through which the observer may view a scene, as in certain Cubist paintings by Braque, represents a plane superimposed upon another plane. Maine Islands of 1922 (Fig. 5), night have led to a total intersection of diaphanous zones, but significantly it ART JOURNALXXVI 2 124 Fig. 4. Alfred Maurer, STILL LIFE WITH PEARS, 1931-32, Addison Gallery of American Art. did not. Through the Cubist-like enclosure Marin rendered the islands sketchily but conventionally. He used the enclosure not as a means to achieve an "oscillation of images," but as a device to bind and contain, as he explains in the following: To get to my picture or to come back I must for myself insist that when finished that is when all the parts are in place and are working that now it has become an object and will therefore have its boundaries as definite as-that the prow the stern the sides and bottom bound a boat.10 Occasionally, Marin's expressionistic paintings contain small unexpected Cubist areas, which provide subtle variations beside the looser calligraphy of the rest of the canvas. The term "areas" is not completely appropriate, for Marin's Cubist passages are not segregated from other parts of the work, but either seem to be superimposed upon them, as in Phippsburg, Maine,11 or are scattered about among the more irregular forms. Here they sometimes serve as decorative adjuncts functioning as "fill in" for the empty spaces, as in Sunset of 1922,12where they occupy the space between the large elements of the painting, the sun and the fields. Still more astonishing is Marin's Impression of 1930,13a work which reveals the use of the Cubist passage as an autonomous, apparently mobile spatial structure, something like a transparent container, by means of which the bathers shown have been conveyed to a hitherto uninhabited seashore. Or perhaps the Cubist structure here functions something like 0 John Marin, "John Marin by Himself," Creative Art, 31 (October 1928), xxxvii. Illustrated in Art News, 45 (November 1946), 16. 'Illustrated in Art in America, 47, No. 2 (1959), 26. 3 Illustrated in Formes, 21 (January 1932), 196. 125 Davidson: Cubism and the Early American Modernist Fig. 5. John Marin, MAINE ISLANDS, 1922, Duncan Phillips Coll. Washington, D.C. the medieval mandorla, appearing inseparable from the figure it surrounds. The rectangular outlines about Marin's figures convey the anomalous impression of picture postcards cemented upon a painting of a rather conventional seascape, thereby simulating in paint the technique of collage. Often these American "Cubists" introduce non-Cubist elements such as futurist repetition of forms or expressionist emphasis. In Hartley's Landscape No. 32, wedge-shaped elements have been used to suggest a stifling force pitted against a lonely cottage. One thinks of Hartley's romanticism, his love of Maine, where he has broodingly recalled "factories that were once gigantic in the vision of a child, monstrous, terrifying, prison-like. .. ."14 In Maurer's George Washington of 1932 (Fig. 6), the clear definition and simplification of the features, the precise geometry of the head and the nearly ninety-degree angles that describe its corners, and the rectangular overlapping strips that comprise the background may be called Cubist. And yet this interplay of overlapping shapes is secondary to the expression of a powerful starkness. The face of Washington is as rigidly and fearsomely inflexible as that of a primitive idol. The great rectangular, almost square head with firm jaw and staring, unseeing eyes that occupies about a third of the picture area and rests upon an equally powerful rectangular neck present a terrifyingly hieratic image of the Father of our Country. Demuth's End of the Parade (Fig. 7), with its geometrized factory blocks and billows of smoke, is composed 14Quoted in Gorham Munson, "Homage to Marsden Hartley: the Painter from Maine," Arts, 35 (February 1961),33 Fig. 7. Charles Demuth, END OF THE PARADE, 1920, Coll. of the late Dr. William Carlos Williams. Fig. 6. Alfred Maurer, GEORGE WASHINGTON, 1932, Coll. of Mr. and Mrs. Jan de Graaf. with converging lines describing triangular wedges which resemble morphologically the lines of force in many of the Futurist paintings. But Demuth's converging lines function as transparent and semi-transparent planes which leave intact the geometrical format within the industrial landscape. Russolo used similar triangular wedges in The Revolt to convey the advance of a seething mob. But with Demuth these lines are merely decorative overtones without a sense of dynamic action.15 Futurist devices were for Demuth another form of Cubism.16 Futurist borrowing occurs also in Weber's wellknown Chinese Restaurant (Fig. 8). Near the center of the canvas is the fragmented image of a diner, resembling in its successive positionings the forms in Balla's Dog on a Leash. The cacophonous presence of this figure makes for a jarring effect rarely encountered in the quieter canvases of the classical Cubists. The forms move precipi- tously toward the center of Weber's composition, where fragmented parts of heads with repeated contours and bits of pictures, architectural moldings, and table tops are discernible, perhaps as one would perceive them through the window of a speeding automobile. Weber was well aware of the new ideas of time and dynamic action in art, for in 1910, five years before the Chinese Restaurant, in an essay entitled "The Fourth Dimension from a Plastic Point of View," he observed: In plastic art there is a fourth dimension which may be described as the consciousness of a great and overwhelming sense of space-magnitude in all directions at one time, and is brought into existence through the three known measurements.' "Milton Brown has cleverly suggested the analogy between Demuth's triangular wedges and beams of light. See Milton W. Brown, "Cubist Realism: An American Style," Marsyas, 3 (1943-1945) 139-160. 6 For a vivid summary of the type of political iconoclasm urged by the Futurists, see Rosa T. Clough's Futurism: The Story of a Modern Art Movement (New York, 1961), pp. 11-37. " Max Weber, "The Fourth Dimension from a Plastic Point of View," Camera Work, 31 (July 1910), 25. ART JOURNALXXVI 2 126 Fig. 8. Max Weber, CHINESE RESTAURANT, 1915, Whitney Museum of American Art, New York, N.Y. Fig. 9. Pablo Picasso, GLASS, WITH STRAW-BOUND BOTTLEOF RUM, 1914, Private Coll., Paris. But the differences between the American Cubist work and the European is not to be explained simply through the presence or absence of Futurist intrusions. If we look more closely at the Chinese Restaurant and compare it with, say, Picasso's Glass, with Straw-Bound Bottle of Rum of 1914 (Fig. 9), we see basic differences in the choice of colors and in the handling of forms. In the Parisian work, the colors are those of the earth-bistre brown, ocher, sienna, and shades of green. In spite of modifications of tone, Picasso has varied his colors for the most part in value and in intensity, and seldom along the scale of hue. Weber has kept most of his colors at full intensity; and has introduced a mottled array of hues, which more than simply enriching the surface, make for 127 Davidson: Cubism and the Early American Modernist a strident effect. An alizarin crimson patch is found in the upper left corner; a dull yellow checkerboard pattern in the lower left and right corners. Brilliant crimsons, gaudy pinks, deep blues, yellows, blacks, tans, and dull blues occupy the other areas of the canvas and contribute together to the dissonance. The jarring effect of the harsh contrast of colors is brought into still sharper relief by a disparity in the sizes and shapes of the various forms. The two checkerboard patterns in the lower left- and right-hand corners of the Chinese Restaurant occupy about one-fifth of the total area of the painting, while toward the center occur smaller shapes, which are but one-tenth the size of each of the checkerboard shapes. To be sure, in the Picasso are to be found occasional curvilinear elements modifying the austere gridwork of verticals and horizontals: the nearly circular fruit to the right, for example, and the ovoid tray to the left upon which the decanter of wine is placed. But these are but decorative adjuncts within the whole and do not achieve the prominence of the zigzag strip of red at the center of Weber's canvas, or the looping coils of pink near the upper right-hand corner. Picasso's palette, far more limited than Weber's along the scale of hue, makes for closely cohering surfaces which create a diaphanous interrelationship of zones. In the Chinese Restaurant, because greatly varying hues are contrasted one with the other and because these hues, except toward the center of the canvas, do not vary in intensity and in value within each color area, shape is clearly delineated from shape, and the ambiguous proliferation of areas characterizing classical Cubism is thereby avoided. These formal oppositions underlie a totally different mode of perception between Weber and Picasso. For Weber, the fundamental distinction is between the clarity and "un-clarity" of each object. Weber's original conception cannot be recreated, yet analogies with the psychology of vision are suggested. The blurred details in the center of the canvas are captured, as it were, by the periphery of the vision. Picasso, however, casts doubt upon the very reality of the objects he pictures. His is a purposeful ambiguity. He does not progressively blur objects, as does Weber, but affords us now and then, amidst his proliferating shapes, the sudden glimpse of a recognizable detail. For the handling of space and the arrangement of detail are referable, now, not to the workings of the human visual apparatus, but to the resorts of a master manipulator, whose structuring of reality depends upon his unique mode of apperception. The distinction is no longer between the clear and the unclear, but between the object and the non-object. We question not whether we discern, but what it is that we do discern, and in so doing, we the observers, have ceased to become the frame of reference. And it is in this enforced detachment of the observer that the classical essence in Picasso's Cubist structure may be said to reside.l8 II But why need Dasburg's unenthusiastic evaluation be seen as a condemnation? The Cubist efforts of the early American Modernist ought also to be examined in the light of the history of American painting. It really makes more sense than setting Picasso, Braque, and Gris up as their point of departure. The American painter between 1910 and 1930 had no tradition of revolution to fall back upon; he had no Cezanne or Seurat in his immediate background to pave the way for his experiments. It is no wonder, then, that in America there was no polemical approach to Cubism as there was in Europe,19or, to put it still more accurately, no one in America so much as dreamed that there was such a thing as a Cubist style. Dasburg's observation that some Americans show the influence of Cubism in their work was quite unusual; in fact, as far as I have been able to learn, this is the only reference at that time to any kind of Cubist departure in early American Modernism. Picasso is noted for changing styles in rapid succession, and yet he and Braque worked mainly in a Cubist style for about a decade. In America, on the other hand, the Modernists adopted a Cubist idiom sporadically, returning to it only in an occasional canvas. For them Cubism meant not a systematic revolution, not a movement, certainly not an ongoing evolution, but an extended process of discovery and experimentation. And yet, in spite of its lack of continuity, in spite of the variety of its individual expressions, the American Cubist idiom retains something of a quality consistently discernible in earlier American painting. The meticulous clarity of forms in the paintings of the limners was continued in the work of John Singleton Copley. Unlike the limners, Copley rendered the sheen of textures and modeled his figures, but the sitter again seemed to be sharply etched out from the surrounding space. Copley's precisely "I feel that a recent observation of Otto Brendel concerning the implications of classicism is applicable here. Brendel argued that classicism "is recognized as a concept of the mind which art must define, not illustrate, Even when these images deal with facts of natural experience, it remains clear that their native habitat is in art, not nature." Otto J. Brendel, "The Classical Style in Modern Art," in From Sophocles to Picasso, ed. Whitney J. Oates (Bloomington, Ind., 1962), p. 97. 9 Gleizes and Metzinger in their book Cubism, first published in 1913, claimed that Cubism was a "movement which tends toward the integral realization of painting." They argued that "for the partial liberties conquered by Courbet, Manet, Ckzanne, and the Impressionists, Cubism substitutes an indefinite liberty." Albert Gleizes and Jean Metzinger, Cubism (London, 1913), p. 62. carved forms paved the way or at least prognosticated the poetically crystal silences of many of the landscapes of the American Luminists. If a harbor scene of FitzHugh Lane is compared with one of Monet, it will be seen that though the American took care to observe precisely in his painting the prevailing atmospheric conditions, unlike the French Impressionist (and the French Cubist after him), he maintained the integrity of the object, defining precisely the boundaries between land and water and between sand and rock. These clear definitions in the paintings of the Luminists bring to mind the immaculately rendered military paraphernalia in Hartley's Portrait and the highly enameled surfaces of the checkered floors in Weber's Restaurant. The strident contrasts between hues in American Cubist painting, as in Chinese Restaurant, make for a clear definition between adjacent color areas. The color areas in this and in other American Cubist paintings were allowed to maintain their full brilliance; for atmospheric perspective was not rendered, a device which would have produced blurring effects through a diminution of color contrasts as objects receded into space and through a progressive lowering of color intensities. In Demuth's End of the Parade, the distant chimneys are smaller than those of the foreground, according to the law of geometric perspective, but are as firmly drawn and as intensely colored. As opposed to the American Cubist who retained approximately the correct local colors of each object, Picasso and Braque often used throughout their compositions, regardless of the object depicted, the prevailing tonalities of earth colors, thereby enhancing the creation of diaphanous zones and intermerging planes. The American Cubist, moreover, usually applied his paint in thin layers, avoiding the more painterly styles often used by Picasso and Braque to produce textures which in themselves helped obliterate the boundaries between objects. However, Rosenblum's argument that "the very idea of painting a Chinese restaurant in New York speaks for the close commitment to reality that characterized not only most American painting in general but American Cubism in particular"20should not be applied indiscriminately. Can we say that Hartley's Portrait is more realistic than the Cubist portraits of Picasso, where something of the personality of the sitter is usually indicated? Hartley, though calling his painting a "portrait," has shown nothing of the man himself, but has abstracted those objects of military regalia which served to identify his rank as a German officer. Or the architectural landscapes of Demuth may serve as a less strained example. Lane Faison has shown these to be suprisingly accurate, having proved through photographs of the depicted site that Demuth arrived at his art by subtle shifts rather than by 20 Rosenblum, op. cit., p. 222. ART JOURNALXXVI 2 128 wholesale alterations.21Yet should we use the word "realism" for a cityscape in which all life seems to have been suspended? The key to the appreciation of these American Cubist works lies, I think, in what Baur has said of the paintings of FitzHugh Lane: It is difficult to define the almost magical quality which radiates. ... It does not reside in the tech- nique, which is dry, meticulous, sometimes stiffly naive, nor is it in the design, which is only occasionally of more than passing interest. It seems to exist rather in an impersonal quality, as if conscious thought had been suspended to permit the scene to impress itself on the senses and feelings in the purity of immediate perception.22 Demuth's factories appear to be brand new, almost like metallic toys made with an erector set; smoke will never singe their windows, nor will men picket their walls. Each object painted by these artists, whether organic or inorganic, appears incapable of aging, decay, or destruction of any kind. Each of the sixteen fruits in Maurer's Still Life with Pears is firm and ripe-but distant and untouched. The medals in Hartley's Portrait are bright and metallic, the epaulets stiff. The checkered floor in Weber's restaurant is spotless, the architectural moldings immaculate. If Demuth's End of the Parade of 1920 is placed beside L_ger's The City of 1919, the crystalline character of the American Cubist work may be observed in its deeper iconographic implications. Charles Demuth stripped the industrial landscape of its rough edges, of its people, of all signs of activity, in order to evoke an airless world of pristine purity. The smoke of chimneys, filtered of its grime and soot, has become as white as the fleeciest of clouds, and, appearing as iridescent orbs, it is made to contrast with the more massive rectangular rhythms of the factory blocks. Signs and advertisements are as absent as the workers. Perforating Demuth's factories are large windows, yet though these would potentially offer to the observer access to the activities within, here are the darkest areas of the canvas. Hence, on the formal level Demuth did not paint the shimmering play of light which would have dissolved the clarity of his forms and have indicated evanescent atmospheric conditions, and on the iconographical level we are presented with a silent airless industrialism, whose processes are held frozen and motionless. In Leger's canvas, on the other hand, derricks rise and smoke is darkened with soot. Letters of advertisement appear, and robot workers move industriously Samuel Lane Faison, "Fact and Art in Charles Demuth," Magazine of Art, 43 (April 1950), 122-128. 21 22M. C. Karolik, M. and M. Karolik Collection of Ameri- can Paintings, 1815 to 1865 (Cambridge, Foreword by John Baur, p. xli. 129 Mass., 1949), Davidson: Cubism and the Early American Modernist about to a mechanized rhythm. To say that in America one could not write of "actual Cubism" is hardly meaningful, for the American painters never grappled with that purposeful ambiguity of which Judkins wrote. They never really emulated the Europeans, who served only as a distant point of departure. They worked from their own premises, and what was done in Europe cannot rightfully be made to serve as a criterion to judge their canvases. At the turn of the century, Maurer used to insist that a Cezanne portrait owned by Gertrude Stein must have been a finished picture. "Of course you can tell it is a finished picture, he used to explain to the other american [sic] painters who came and looked dubiously," recalled Gertrude Stein. "You can tell because it has a frame, now whoever heard of anybody framing a canvas if the picture isn't finished."23 Unfortunately we do not know Maurer's view toward Cubism itself. Nonetheless, there is revealed here something of the early American Modernists' inability, before the advent of abstract expressionism, to comprehend the validity of a composition still in the state of flux, something of his perplexity before the very process of creation. Gertrude Stein's recollections are not always to be trusted as a reliable source, yet Maurer's alleged inclination to think in terms of the bounded picture is closely paralleled by Weber's preference for the coherent, palpable form. In 1910 Weber ventured that there can be no color without there being a form, in space and in light, with substance and weight to hold the color. I prefer a form, even if it is in black and white, rather than a tache of formless color.24 As late as 1943 Hartley commented that Picasso's later period of the two-eyed profiles gives me the creeps and I don't care for the kind of painting in them-but heaven knows he has done a lot of the very best painting in the Twentieth Century.25 Hartley's charge may well have been directed, not at the horrors of the facial expressions, but at the uneasiness connoted through the possibility of multiple readings. For when he was first confronted by Cubism, Hartley did (Continued on page 165) Gertrude Stein, The Autobiography of Alice B. Toklas (New York, 1933), p. 9. 24 Max Weber, "Chinese Dolls and Modern Colorists," Camera Work, 31 (July 1910), 51. 2 The Museum of Modern Art, New York, Lyonel Feininger-Marsden Hartley, Dorothy C. Miller, ed. (New York, 1944), p. 64. Hartley's opinion of Picasso is taken from a letter of August 16, 1943, to Richard B. Sisson of Corea, Maine. 23 In another letter of June 7, 1913, he confided to Stieglitz: I think that there must be a consuming preference in me for single meanings. They are comfortable and comforting and one knows where one stands with a single purpose thing.27 Fig. 8. St. Mark, Ebo Gospels, School of Reims, before 835. Epernay, Bibliotheque Municipale, Ms. 1. first of the medieval artists rather than the last of the Romans. As such, it was the Carolingians who set the course which European art was to follow for the next five hundred years. RUTH BERENSON, a Harvard Ph.D. and free lance art critic, now lives in New York and is the wife of Norbert I Muhlen. CUBISM AND THE EARLY AMERICAN MODERNIST (Continuedfrom page 129) not realize that the lettering and numbers in Picasso's paintings of 1910 to 1912 had been integrated within the network of intersecting planes. Rather, he saw these as independent structures that had been placed across the network and that had been meant literally as words or as numbers. In a letter to Stieglitz of July 1912, he wrote that just now Picasso is doing things that have [two illegible words follow] and across these network designs names of people and words like "jolie" or "bien" and numbers like "75."26 165 Berenson: The Exhibition of Carolingian Art at Aachen Similarly, the critics and writers around the time of the Armory Show had remarkably little understanding of the Cubist style that was then sweeping through Europe. Like the Modernists themselves, whom they usually ridiculed, they saw nothing of shifting patterns or spatial ambiguities. In reviewing the Armory Show, President Theodore Roosevelt seemed to fear that the cube, like the trust, threatened to become a monopoly. He suggested that there was no real reason for choosing the cube as a symbol, that the Cubists might "just as well have chosen the octagon or have called themselves the Knights of the Isosceles Triangle."28 Frank Jewett Mather insisted glibly that "the single ascertainable notion behind Cubism is that finer effects, particularly of mass, may be obtained by choosing a single and uniform unit of expression, preferably the cube."29 What characterizes Roosevelt's and Mather's insistence that Cubism can be reduced to a single discernible shape is not an antipathy as much as a rigidity of outlook, an optical aberration, as it were, which prevented them from seeing what most of us could see thirty-five years later (after two World Wars and a depression), that the cubes, in fact, could hardly be read. But Mather's aberration is just the point here. If the early American Modernist and his critic never really. knew what "orthodox" European Cubism was about, it hardly makes sense to regard the American Cubist paintas ings as being one-half Cubist or one-third Cubist, or, there Cubist. Rather, Dasburg did, as not being actually is need for more intelligible and meaningful classifications within the Cubist camp. 2Letter from Marsden Hartley to Alfred Stieglitz, July 1912. Stieglitz Collection, Collection of American Literature, Yale University Library. 27Letter from Marsden Hartley to Alfred Stieglitz, June 7, 1913. Stieglitz Collection, Collection of American Literature, Yale University Library. 23 Theodore Roosevelt, "A Layman's View of an Art Exhibition," Outlook, 103 (March 29, 1913), 718-720. 29Frank J. Mather, Jr., "Newest Tendencies in Art," Independent, 74 (March 6, 1913), 504-512. MR. DAVIDSON teaches history of art at Oakland Unitalk versity, Rochester, Michigan. This article based on a at held Art Midwest Conference delivered at the College a 1964. Lawrence, Kansas, Fall,