R. Zaslavsky©2013 Guide to Ancient (Greek) Thought “Study in antiquity differed from that current in modern times: it was nothing less than the thorough education of the natural consciousness. Testing itself against every separate part of its existence, and philosophizing about everything it encountered, it made itself into a generality that was active through and through. In modern times, on the other hand, the individual finds the abstract form ready-made: the exertion of grasping it and appropriating it is rather more the unmediated production of the inward and the cut-off generation of the general than the emergence of the general out of the concrete and the multiplicity of existence.” [G. W. F. Hegel (1770-1831), Phenomenology of the Spirit (1807), Preface, tr. Walter Kaufmann, excerpt] “For I opine Hesiod and Homer to come to be in their prime four hundred years older than I, and not more; and these are the ones having made the theogony for the Greeks, even giving the gods their nicknames and dividing-up their honors and arts and signifying their looks.” [Herodotus II. 53; tr. mine] Homer (fl. c. 750 BC) Iliad (the culture hero) Odyssey (the nature hero) the work of Homer hovers over the entire development of ancient Greek thought Hesiod (fl. c. 8th-7th century BC) Works and Days: the five ages of humanity (golden, silver, bronze, heroic, and iron) strife as fundamental (the two strifes, one negative and one positive: strife as fighting; strife as striving) manual of agriculture: the natural cycle as the best human horizon Theogony: the genealogy of the gods Thales of Miletus (c. 634-c.546 BC) made the first map of the world astronomer: predicted a solar eclipse (585 BC) first person to demonstrate a geometrical proposition (called the theorem of Thales by Euclid) became the stereotype of the philosopher first to ask the question “what is the ruling-beginning (archê) of all things?” [i.e., instead of asking, “who made the world?” he asked “what is the world?”] his answer to that question was “the archê of nature is water” Anaximander of Miletus (611-547 BC) the archê is not water or any other corporeal element: rather, it is what he called the unlimited (apeiron) 1 Anaximenes of Miletus (585-525 BC) the archê is air, which is differentiated through the processes of condensation and rarefaction Pythagoras of Samos (fl. 6th century BC) institutionalized the distinction between esoteric (true inner) and exoteric (adjusted outer/public) teachings formed a community of initiates, thereby welding together the quest for knowledge and the proper mode of living2 the archê of all things is number every number is represented by a figure, a field; therefore, the archê is limited (finite) the basis of this teaching was the ratios that constitute musical harmony therefore, form, or structure, is the basis of all things 1 The Latin equivalent of this is infinitum, literally, “unlimited,” but sometimes translated as “infinite.” Therefore, when one speaks of Pythagoras, one actually means Pythagoreans. According to Diogenes Laertius (VIII. 2. 8), Pythagoras compared life to an athletic competition: of the three types of humans there (the competing athletes, the vendors, and the spectators), the highest were the spectators (i.e., the lookers or contemplators). 2 1 R. Zaslavsky©2013 Xenophanes of Colophon (c. 568-c. 474 BC) there is only one god: the first rational monotheism3 Parmenides of Elea (c. 512-c. 440 BC) for him, the question becomes “what does it mean to be?/what is being?/what is “is”? in his poem, he describes the journey from ignorance to knowledge as a chariot ride to see an unspecified goddess who teaches him the way of being being is characterized by radical homogeneity (one of the two ultimate competing views of the world: see Heracleitus) the oneness of being being is ungenerated, imperishable, whole, complete, unique, and, altogether contiguous; in short, being is one he asks not about the beings but about being qua being what is the beingness of beings/what is the isness of what is? nullifies becoming to intellect and to be are the same Heracleitus of Ephesus4 (fl. 6th-5th century BC) the archê of all things is not a something all things always flow: being is characterized by radical heterogeneity (one of the two ultimate competing views of the world: see Parmenides ) the manyness of being one cannot go into the same river twice 5 “war is the father of all things, and king of all things” (Fragment 53, tr. mine) [i.e., all is constant motion and turmoil] Zeno of Elea (c. 492-c. 430 BC) student of Parmenides Zeno’s paradoxes to demonstrate the impossibility of motion (what Heracleitus calls “flow”): Achilles and the tortoise; the dichotomy; the arrow; the stadium Empedocles of Acragas (c. 490-c. 430 BC) the four corporeal elements (somatika stoicheia) are the building blocks of all things: fire, air, water, earth each element is like beingness in Parmenides attempt (inadequate) to fuse heterogeneity and homogeneity the motive forces (the archai) of the cosmos are friendship and contention (a refinement of Hesiod’s account) 3 Leucippus of Miletus and Democritus of Abdera (fl. early 5th century BC) unalloyed atomism: the archai are atoms, unlimited (apeiron/infinite) in number to restore the intelligibility of motion that the Eleatics (Parmenides and Zeno) denied, they added the presence of the empty (which some translate as “the void”) to their theory of elements “But if oxen and horses or lions had hands, or [if they had it in them] to write with hands and to complete the very deeds/works [erga] which men [do], [then] horses would write the Looks [ideai] of gods similar to horses and oxen similar to oxen and would make the bodies [of their gods] suchlike as each themselves had body-builds.” (Xenophanes, Fragment 15, tr. mine) 4 In Shakespeare’s The Comedy of Errors, as I understand it, altering his source in Plautus by doubling the number of twins and shifting the locale from Herculaneum to Ephesus is meant to indicate that the play is the presentation of what it would be like to live in a Heracleitean world. As such, it is a great epistemological comedy. 5 Cratylus, a disciple of Heracleitus, reformulated this more radically thus: “one cannot go into the same river once.” 2 R. Zaslavsky©2013 Anaxagoras of Clazomenae (c. 500-c. 428 BC) there are two archai: the unlimited (apeiron) [the matter of the cosmos] and intellectual-intuition (nous) [the primal motive force] the sun is a stone, and the moon is earth, i.e., neither is a god Herodotus of Halicarnassus (c. 484-c. 425 BC) Inquiries6 the book is ostensibly an account of the Persian Wars (500/499-449 BC) as he presents that war, he provides a cultural atlas of the known world based both on his own sightseeing (theoria: contemplation/spectating) and on hearsay (akoê) in a sense, he is presenting himself as the new prose Homer, combining in one work both the Iliad and the Odyssey: he is the new Odysseus recounting the new and bigger equivalent of the Trojan War as he says, his goal is to preserve “the big and wondrous deeds, the ones having been shown forth by Hellenes and by barbarians” (I. 1, tr. mine) the tentacles of causation of the Persian Wars are presented as reaching back to the distant past and around the distant present the book could be described as an account of events supplemented by a comprehensive cultural anthropology (in the literal sense of a rational account of humans) Contemporaries of Socrates: Sophists7 Protagoras of Abdera (c. 490-c. 420 BC) the human (anthropos) is the measure of all things, of the things that are, how they are, and of the things that are not, how they are not” (Fragment 1, tr. mine): what seems to a human to be so, is so {so that what Parmenides called the “way of opinion” is for Protagoras, the true way [one could call this political Heracleiteanism] sometimes described as a thoroughgoing relativist “about the gods, I do not have [any basis] to envision either how they are or how they are not” (Fragment 4, tr. mine): agnosticism taught his students how “to make the worse speech (logos) the better (i.e., how to win arguments by hook or by crook) Gorgias of Leontini (c. 486-c. 378 BC) persuasion is omnicompetent and omnipotent truth always will crumble under the power of persuasiveness Hippias of Elis (c. 485-c. 415 BC) virtuoso orator accused (not formally) of atheism Prodicus of Ceos (c. 465-c. 390 BC) Heracles’s choice between the paths of virtue and vice 6 The title of Herodotus’s work is Historiai in Greek. This has been traditionally translated Histories. However, that translation is misleading. The Greek word historiê means “inquiry.” The earliest translators, who rendered it as “history,” were not wrong to do so, since one could then still refer to science as natural history (i.e., a scientific inquiry into nature). It is only since the 19th century that the translation has become problematic because contemporary scholars—those who refer to Herodotus as “the father of history” (pater historiae: Cicero, De legibus, I. 5)—assume that he is a historian in the modern, especially the post-Hegelian, sense. That is a misleading assumption. Those who have adopted Cicero’s phrase have taken it out of the context that shows that it is not history in the modern sense. 7 Sophists were those who took money for teaching, something scorned by the Platonic Socrates. The word sophistês (sophist) in Greek has a range of meaning from “professional wise person” to “wise guy.” The descendants of the sophists are teachers and professors. 3 R. Zaslavsky©2013 Socrates of Athens (469-399 BC) wrote nothing: in that sense, he is the only truly pure philosopher in Western history virtually nothing is known about him in the strictly historical sense: most of what is known about him is inferred from the play The Clouds, by his contemporary Aristophanes, and from the dialogues of his students, Plato and Xenophon8 the teaching of his predecessors culminated in him, and his successors were elaborators of his teaching he was said to have shifted the focus of philosophy from the cosmos (physics/cosmology) to the human things (anthropology, in the literal sense).9 tried by the city of Athens and put to death by poisoning (hemlock): Athens’s first crime against philosophy Contemporaries of Socrates: Non-Sophists Thucydides of Athens (c. 471/460-c. 399 BC) 10 Athenian general, banished for failing to achieve a desired objective his account of the Peloponnesian War (431-404 BC) was left untitled at his death sets himself against both Homer and Herodotus (cf. I. 21) he sets himself the task of demonstrating that the Peloponnesian War was the “biggest motion” (i.e., the war of wars, bigger in importance than either the Trojan War or the Persian Wars: I. 1, tr. mine) he boldly declares to be writing for posterity, saying that what he writes “is set down as a possession unto always” (I. 22, tr. mine) what he writes looks more like the contemporary notion of history, but it is equally a significant work of political philosophy Aristophanes of Athens (c. 447-c. 387 BC) comic playwright politically conservative The Clouds: a satirical critique of a younger Socrates, a Socrates still focused on the study of physics and caricatured as a sophist Critias of Athens (c. 480-c. 403 BC) Plato’s uncle wrote about politics and composed plays “the most beautiful look in males is the female, but in turn the contrary in females [i.e., the most beautiful look in females is the male]” (Fragment 48, tr. mine) 11 Hippocrates of Cos (c. 460-c. 375 BC) practiced what would now be called holistic medicine The Hippocratic Oath 8 Contemporary classics and philosophy teachers tend to denigrate Xenophon and to elevate Plato. That is a mistake. One should keep in mind the words of the consummate classicist, John Milton, who refers to “the divine volumes of Plato and his equal, Xenophon.” [Apology for Smectymnuus, near the end] 9 Cf. Cicero, Tusculan Disputations, V. 10, tr. mine: “However, Socrates first [i.e., is the first one who] has called down philosophy from the heaven and has placed [it] in towns and even has introduced [it] into homes and has activated [it] to search about life and habits and good and bad things.” (Socrates autem primus philosophiam devocavit e caelo et in urbibus conlocavit et in domus etiam introduxit et coegit de vita et moribus rebusque bonis et malis quaerere.) 10 According to scholars in late antiquity, Thucydides was born in 471 BC. Modern scholars have conjectured the later date of 460 BC. No one knows with certainty which it is. 11 This is a little known, but extremely important, principle for understanding visual representation in the history of art. 4 R. Zaslavsky©2013 Students of Socrates: Plato of Athens Xenophon of Athens (c. 428-c. 347 BC) (c. 430-c. 355 BC) wrote 35 dialogues12 and 13 letters13 soldier, chronicler, and philosopher dialogues are plays and should be read as such14 wrote dialogues and accounts of contemporary and in all but two of the dialogues (Laws, Epinomis), near contemporary events Socrates is an interlocutor (major or minor) Socratic dialogues: Recollections (= Memorabilia), tried to fuse Heracleitean sensory (aisthetic) Oikonomikos,17 Symposium, Apology heterogeneity with Parmenidean intellective Non-Socratic dialogue: Hiero or Tyrannikos18 (noetic) homogeneity Representative other works: Anabasis,19 Cyropaedia20 the dramatic character of the dialogues makes it impossible to read off from them in a direct way any so-called Platonic teaching15 exoteric teaching vs. esoteric teaching (cf. Pythagoras) 16 the dialogues are meant to be a prompt: the reader must be a silent interlocutor in a conversation that the conversation in the dialogue inspires. With respect to the dialogues of Plato and Xenophon, it is almost as if the two thinkers came to an agreement that Plato would do the bulk of the work of presenting the fictionalized Socrates, while Xenophon would address the rest. This would have left Xenophon free to write his chronicle, his Cyropaedia (a manual of politics and pedagogy), among other things (e.g., hunting, equestrianism). Student of Plato: Aristotle of Stagirus (384-322 BC) studied with Plato for twenty years his teaching has the form of expositions and lecture notes that are comprehensive in scope: he wrote on ethics, politics, biology, poetics, physics, psychology, logic and language, and rhetoric tutored Alexander the Big (356-323 BC) 21 four causes: material, formal, efficient, final matter and form differences between Aristotle and Plato are only apparent, not genuine fled Athens to prevent, as he said, Athens from committing a second crime against philosophy Student of Aristotle: Alexander the Big of Macedon (326-323 BC) his conquest ends the Greek period and ushers in the Hellenistic period, a period marked by cosmopolitanism and syncretism Euclid of Alexandria (fl. 300 BC): Elements Archimedes of Syracuse (c. 287-c. 212 BC) 12 Nothing is known with historical certainty about when each of the dialogues was written. Therefore, any scholar who orders them chronologically (rather than internally dramatically) is creating an arbitrary framework based on prejudgments and presuppositions for which there is no genuine justification. 13 Of these, the two most important are the second and the seventh. 14 In Aristotle’s Poetics, they are listed as dramatic works. 15 The dialogues must be read as one would read a Shakespearean play. One should no more simply attribute the statements of Socrates (or Timaeus, or Parmenides) to Plato than one would attribute the statements of Macbeth (or Othello) to Shakespeare. 16 There is no way to capsulize the content of the dialogues of either Plato or Xenophon. I simply will say that most of what one finds in standard textbooks, histories of philosophy, and professorial lectures is incomplete or misleading at best, totally erroneous at worst. 17 This means literally “a person skilled in (or knowledgeable about) the law of the household.” It is the source of the word “economics.” 18 Hiero is a name. “Tyrannikos” means literally “a person skilled in (or knowledgeable about) tyranny.” 19 This is Xenophon’s account of his military service in the Persian expedition. 20 This means The Education of Cyrus. 21 His name is ı ÉAl°jandrοw µ°ga˚, which literally means “Alexander the Big.” In Greek and Latin, the adjective “big” (megas [Gk.], magnus, [Lat.]) can mean “big in size,” “big in age,” “big in importance,” etc. I prefer to render it always the same way. 5