The Culture of Risk By Raphaële Chappe*, Edward Nell** and Willi Semmler† New School for Social Research, New York I. Introduction Economists tend to study human interactions and the decision-making process abstracted from culture. For instance, generally speaking microeconomic models of human behavior assume fixed individual preferences and pay little attention to the role played by the cultural environment in shaping those preferences. Yet some economists have not ruled out culture from their scope of analysis, and have taken seriously the role played by culture in economic behavior. Veblen, for instance, highlighted the limitations of the neoclassical modeling of individual preferences, its neglect of social norms and inability to encompass evolutionary processes (Veblen, 1898). Veblen’s critique focused on the static picture promoted by the neoclassical paradigm, with homo economicus a passive calculator of pleasures and pains bearing “neither antecedent nor consequent”, operating in “an isolated definitive human datum, in stable equilibrium except for the buffets of the impinging forces that displace him in one direction or another”. (Veblen, 1898). Instead, Veblen advocated for an approach that would understand human activity as an ongoing process both shaped by and shaping human tendencies and dispositions: He is not simply a bundle of desires that are to be saturated by being placed in the path of the forces of the environment, but rather a coherent structure of propensities and habits which seeks realisation and expression in an unfolding activity. According to this view, human activity, and economic activity among the rest, is not apprehended as something incidental to the process of saturating given desires. The activity is itself the substantial fact of the process, and the desires under whose guidance the action takes place are Economics Department, New School University, New York, and former attorney with Goldman Sachs, chapr057@newschool.edu. * ** Economics Department, New School University, New York, NellE@newschool.edu Economics Department, New School University, New York and Center for Empirical Macroeconomics, Bielefeld University, Germany, semmlerw@newschool.edu † 1 circumstances of temperament which determine the specific direction in which the activity will unfold itself in the given case. (Veblen, 1898). In this paper, in line with Veblen’s argument, we develop a cultural approach to understanding individual interactions on Wall Street. More specifically, we argue that the cultural environment played a critical role in leading to the 2007-2008 financial crisis. The existence of cyclical financial crises is explained by economists in terms of many different factors, including the macroeconomic environment (low interest rates, external imbalances, etc.), deregulated markets, leverage cycles and credit expansion, asymmetric information, “animal spirits”, “irrational exuberance” and other psychological and behavioral explanations. Analyses of the recent financial crisis have focused on the leverage cycle in the housing and mortgage securities, liquidity spirals, the macroeconomic environment of low interest rates and external imbalances, and the unbalanced international financial flows. Yet we believe that the cultural environment on Wall Street is an important factor in predetermining decisions of market participants -- at the meso level of decision-making (rather than from a micro or macro perspective). In a broad sense, the notion of culture in a sociological or anthropological framework describes a set of commonly shared attitudes. Culture can be thought of as a process or as a state (Jackson, 2009). As a process, culture can help explain the evolution and reproduction of social behavior and institutions. As a state (way of life, the arts), it focuses on the final products of cultivation at the social level. When conceived as a process, culture is more significant for economic and other social analysis to the extent it can shed light on the relations between individuals and society (Jackson, 2009: 22). In this paper we put forward the notion of the culture as a process whereby a set of values collectively shared by influential market participants and Wall Street employees (transmitted through the social environment at the firm or market level) have evolved over time from a relatively risk-averse environment (which we refer to as the culture of trust) into a very aggressive environment which has come to encourage speculative and reckless risk-taking (which we refer to as the culture of risk). We argue that the culture of risk is partly responsible for the breakdown in financial markets experienced in the 2007-2008 financial crisis. As such, it has completely betrayed the social role of financial markets, which is to efficiently allocate capital so as to promote rather than stifle economic growth. To understand culture as a process, we should be asking why and how this change came about. We draw from the risk society literature to develop a systematic analysis of the culture of risk. Modernity is characterized by the emergence of new forms of risk. Businesses have looked to financial markets to solve real problems by financial means, which has led to a massive commodification of risk and the development of a whole new range of financial products enabling the pricing and trading of risk. Playing a central role in the design and marketing of such products, financial institutions have emerged as expert systems, with expertise in risk management. Yet the recent financial crisis has been characterized by a widespread failure of the internal risk management models used by many financial institutions. We suggest that this failure is in part attributable to a misguided heavy reliance on calculable, probabilistic views of the future. The culture of risk, in our sense, is characterized by an inability to recognize the existence of radical uncertainty, and the widely shared overconfident view that all forms of risk can be managed. The commodification of risk has in turn led to an increase in risk and uncertainty, with a financial system characterized by increasing complexity. This process is reflexive in nature, with the very reliance 2 on financial experts creating more complexity, more uncertainty, and new forms of global risks, including systemic risk. We first identify the role played by financial engineering in creating complexity and new forms of manufactured risk in financial markets (Section II). We discuss the failure of risk management systems and controls used in the financial industry evidenced in the 2007-2008 crisis, and the role played by the marginalization in mainstream economics of the concept of uncertainty (Section III). We suggest that the scientific promise of risk management was actually a convenient justification for large risk-taking, and that there were in fact incentives to turn a blind eye to the possibility that risk was improperly understood and managed. Wall Street came to view large risk taking as the norm under the pressure of some structural shifts in financial markets -- with the rise of proprietary trading, the end of the partnership culture, and a transition to a compensation structure based on risk-unadjusted measures of firm profit (Section IV). With the dominance of risk analysis operating, at the policy level, to diverge attention from our radical ignorance about the future, policy-makers chose to deregulate markets. Along with deregulated markets came organized irresponsibility and the absence of clear causality leading to individual liability (Section V). Though undesirable cultural features do not lend themselves well to quick fixes, we argue that the dangers posed by the prevalence of the culture of risk cannot be ignored and beg for a collective discussion on what policy measures could restore common sense and accountability to Wall Street. Rather than take the narrow view that the recent financial crisis is the result of yet another bubble, that we must patiently wait for the economy to recover, and that the issues at hand involved technical details of complex financial products to be debated solely amongst experts, we suggest that we take this opportunity to acknowledge the social, legal and economic implications of the shift to the culture of risk. II. The End of the Culture of Trust and the Commodification of Risk The Culture of Trust In the 19th Century and early 20th Century the main image of the banker or financier was that of the ‘trustee’, who was the prudent and scrupulous manager of other people’s money, someone who could be trusted, and who was wise, rather than smart, farsighted and reliable, taking a long view and planning carefully and conservatively for the future. We could expect such a person to be politically conservative, but this would be a traditional conservative in the old-fashioned sense, celebrating the staid and quiet values of community and hierarchy – “a place for everything and everything in its place” – not the disruptive uproar of radical individualism. Of course, there were plenty of speculators then; indeed, con-men and frauds abounded. But, in a sense, they were on the fringes, on the edges of the system. The culture of trust espoused the values of prudence and thrift, along with hard work, careful foresight and good judgment. Going 3 into debt should not be undertaken lightly; debts should be paid on time, promises should be kept, and one’s reputation must be protected and preserved. In the culture of trust, you see your banker as the person to whom you entrust your money, your savings. Banks can be trusted. And this has an important economic consequence: the commercial banking system is able to provide the greater part of the money supply in the form of bank deposits, and/or bank notes, in place of government paper money. The culture of trust was suited to an economy made up of a large number of privately held family firms, operating small-scale technologies; in these conditions the main issue in finance consisted in finding suitable and safe placements for household savings. Investment was financed by lending or by issuing bonds; equity markets were still small. But the economy changed as small family firms grew into or were displaced by large oligopolistic corporations operating mass production systems. The development of family firms into modern corporations was accompanied by higher levels of complexity in financial markets. First, as compared with the family firm of the craft economy, corporations need more sophisticated forms of financing -- commercial paper, credit for working capital, financing for fixed capital, and stocks. Companies tended to retain and reinvest earnings, so that stocks are held for appreciation and capital gain as opposed to dividends (Nell, 1998: 265). Capital funds were in search of the highest return, creating arbitrage with the bond markets. Second, the level of profits were a key determinant of the system behavior, and it is mainly determined by the structure of aggregate investment. Investment takes place now because of the expectation of future investment and profits. Third, bankers were essentially characterized as merchants of debt: “The financial instability hypothesis takes banking seriously as a profit seeking activity. Banks seek profits by financing activity and bankers. Like all entrepreneurs in a capitalist economy, bankers are aware that innovation assures profits.” (Minsky, 1993: 6) The picture that we see emerge is a profit-driven economy that relies heavily on investment, and a need for financing that has generated a financial system characterized by complexity and innovation. Further, with the rise of mass production and a global interconnected economy, success became dependent on the ability to take on new forms of risk. Recent developments in social theory have placed risk at the center of the discussion on modernization and globalization. The change from external, or natural risks to manufactured risks is well described in the work of German social theorist Beck on risk society (Beck, 1992) or Giddens’s work on modernity (1990). The accelerating pace of technological innovation and scientific discoveries has led to an increase in risk and uncertainty. We can identify four new, global, real hedging problems for corporations: 1) hedging foreign exchange risk, 2) hedging inflation risk, 3) hedging risk that new technologies will not work, that new markets and products will not develop as expected, and 4) hedging risk of setting up operations in new political environments. New business opportunities hinged on the willingness to take on these new forms of risks. Successful businesses are successful risk-takers. The response to the emergence of new risks was to try to solve real problems by financial means – buying fire insurance instead of rewiring the house. In each case financial hedging may be useful, but it is easy to see that a real solution would be better, although it might be out of reach as a practical matter in the here and now. The claim that these risks could be managed privately by the market fit very well with free-market ideology, and not coincidentally, offered a whole new field of enterprise for financial firms. Based on this claim, the business of finance developed to provide 4 large corporations hedging products and solutions. This offered a whole new field of enterprise for financial firms, as there was lot of money to be made (… and lost, too, though few in the financial world admitted that at the time) through pricing and selling off risks. The Commodification of Risk: Explosion of Derivative Markets, Financial Innovation and Trading Volume The full-scale commodification of risk began in the 1980s. The 1980s was a decade of financial change and bull markets. High-tech stocks emerged with the appearance of new technologies, such as the personal computer industry, software entrepreneurs, and biotechnologies. Merger activity and leveraged buy-out reached record levels. In addition to derivatives, new financial products were being created, for example high-yield bonds, also known as “junk bonds”, which became widely popular with investors (junk bonds eventually collapsed in the late 1980’s, and charges of insider trading were pressed against top managers). Wall Street firms started to rely more heavily on program trading to handle the large volume of trading and the mathematical complexity of instruments. But the real commodification of risk really started with the explosion of derivative markets. Derivatives can be used to transform the underlying economic risk or exposure of a security, for example by allowing investors to structure different payoffs or cash flow patterns. The term “derivative” indicates that the value of the financial instrument is derived from the value of an underlying instrument (the reference value is referred to as the ‘notional principal amount’). Derivatives are priced in accordance with expectations formed regarding the value of this underlier. This allows for the risk of change in the value of the underlier to be priced and traded. For example, companies can reduce their exposure to currency fluctuations by entering into a currency future, a contract in which parties agree to exchange currencies at a set exchange rate on a given future date. Both parties achieve certainty about the future exchange value of a currency (the certainty of not losing money), at the cost of giving up the chance of a gain if the rate evolved in their favor. Futures can also exist with other underliers, such as commodities. Options differ from futures in that they give the buyer (call option) or seller (put option) the right but not the obligation to enter into the future transaction. In 1973, Fischer Black and Myron Scholes developed a mathematical model to price options. While options had always been traded, the existence of a mathematical model ensured some level of consistency and rigorousness that allowed for a higher degree of precision. Following the development of the Black-Scholes option-pricing model, options became an essential tool in modern portfolio management, and derivatives markets exploded (the fact that many derivatives could be privately negotiated outside of any regulated trading platform further accentuated the growth of the industry). The Black-Scholes pricing model allowed for the development of more complex derivatives. This resulted in the creation of a myriad of new financial instruments to allow for different types of risk (related to different underliers such as equity, currency, interest rates, credit default) to be traded and reallocated to market participants. Credit default swaps (CDSs), for example, played a key role in the recent financial crisis. CDSs are essentially a form of insurance against default risk, whereby the CDS buyer makes premium payments (the CDS “spread”) to the protection seller who agrees, in exchange, to pay the principal amount owed by a reference entity in the event of a default event. 5 Risk can also be outsourced with securitized products, also financial derivatives in that their value is derived from underlying assets. The securitization process allows for the creation of securities backed by a pool of risky mortgages and loans, whereby each security (or “tranche”) entitles investors to a share of the cash flow produced by the underlying assets, mortgages or loans (both interest and principal). The recent housing boom was financed with credit derivatives and securitized products, resulting in a huge issuing of Mortgage Backed Securities (MBSs) and Collateralized Debt Obligations (CDOs) that helped to outsource risk. In short, MBSs derive their values from underlying mortgages assigned to a Special Purpose Vehicle (SPV), an entity designed to hold the pool of mortgages. To the extent that risky mortgages are pooled together, investors are exposed to the risk profile of the total pool rather than individual assets, and the risk of default is diluted. Different tranches carry different priorities of repayment, thus re-assigning the risks into different classes, and are priced accordingly.1 During the housing boom, securitization allowed for fairly illiquid high-risk assets to be packaged together and converted into securities with different risk profiles, including securities that obtained very good ratings (AAA) from the rating agencies. Financial institutions derived fees from the engineering and marketing of such products (the “originate and sell” model), with the possibility of earning low risk profits, rather than retaining the products on their balance sheets and putting their own capital at risk. It is no surprise that this high degree of financial innovation was accompanied by an inexorable increase in trading volume. By the end of the 1990s, over a billion of shares were traded on a daily basis on both the NYSE and the NASDAQ. In contrast, record trading 20 years before would have amounted to a mere 70 million shares per day (Geisst, 2004: 368). Today a large fraction of trading is actually executed by computer algorithms designed to capture trading opportunities that exist only for fractions of seconds. This is known as “high-frequency trading”, and involves moving in and out of positions several times each day, with models placing trades on the basis of live streaming market data. High frequently trading really took off after the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) authorized electronic exchanges in 1998, and accounts today for about two-thirds of U.S. stock-market volume (Wall Street Journal, 2010). The rising use of computers and algorithms to trade stocks is arguably a source of liquidity to markets, but high-frequency trading may also create vulnerability to technical glitches. The “flash crash” on May 6, 2010 is one example of such potential market disruptions. With no warning signs, automated trades caused the Dow Jones Industrial Average to suddenly plunge 9 percent and recover within minutes. The derivatives market has seen explosive growth in the past decades, empowered by sophisticated computers programs allowing for the pricing and trading. The total notional value of Over-The-Counter (OTC) derivatives traded in the G10 countries as of the end of December 2010 is roughly $600 trillion, with the value of the instruments being traded around $21 trillion.2 Generally speaking, market values rather than outstanding notional amounts are a better measure of the riskiness or credit risk exposure The regular interest payments from those mortgages are income to the SPV. Different tranches are assigned to investors with appropriate attachment points. If the number of defaults remains below the lower attachment point, the investors in that level simply collect the pre-arranged premium. However, once the percentage exceeds the lower attachment point, defaults are paid out of the capital posted by the investors of that tranche. Once the upper attachment point is reached, the next tranche takes over since the lower tranche is effectively exhausted. Investors in the MBS will demand compensatory interest commensurate with the assumed default risks and recovery values. These are paid with the interest income from the mortgages. The difference between the two cash flows is profit to the SPV investors. As long as it is profitable to construct these instruments, liquidity in the mortgage market will only be limited by the default probabilities, the recovery values, and the rates obtainable elsewhere. 2 As per the Bank for International Settlement, statistics at end-December 2010. 1 6 associated with OTC derivatives, since notional principal amounts greatly exceed the amounts potentially owed under the instruments. However, derivatives can also have a leveraging effect, whereby they multiply gains and losses and the potential total liabilities in financial markets. For example, investors can buy and sell CDS without owning any debt of the reference entity. These are called “naked credit default swaps” (in essence speculating on the creditworthiness of reference entities) and constitute most of the market in CDS (as much as 80 percent). This explains how the CDS market grew to an astonishing notional value of $62.2 trillion in 2007. CDS do not simply manage the risk of default, they also paradoxically increase the overall credit risk exposure in the system in that a single default event can trigger liabilities between CDS counterparts that are a multiple of the underlying debt of the reference entity. III. The Triumph of ‘Risk’ Over ‘Uncertainty’: The Failure of Risk Management in the Financial Sector As a direct consequence of this rising complexity and interconnectedness, there has been a significant increase of new forms of manufactured risk – financial manufactured risk. This created risk environment is one of the defining characteristics of Beck’s risk society3, and the analysis is directly applicable to the capitalist economy viewed as a complex financial system. Minsky (1993) noted that the modern capitalist world is characterized by: “an increasing complexity of the financial structure, in connection with a greater involvement of governments as refinancing agents for financial institutions as well as ordinary business firms (both of which are marked characteristics of the modern world) [which] may make the system behave differently than in earlier eras”. (Minsky, 1993: 4-5). What Minsky is referring to here is increasing institutionalized financial complexity, resulting from layers of intermediation between investors, the ultimate owners of wealth, and the units that control and operate that wealth (firms). Due to the explosion in trading volume and the high degree of financial innovation, financial markets and products (instruments of financial intermediation) have become increasingly complex. Giddens (1999) gives the example of Barings Bank, which collapsed as a result of the unchecked activities of rogue trader Nick Leeson. Giddens makes the point that such rogue traders “are involved with systems which even they themselves do not understand, so dramatic is the onrush of change in the new electronic global economy.” (Giddens, 1999: 2). Recent social theory dealing with modernity has focused on the increase of new forms of risk, and shared risk as a social challenge. In Giddens’ analysis, a distinctive feature of modernity is the ‘disembedding’ of social systems, a mechanism defined as “the ‘lifting out’ of social relations from The dark dimension of this development, in Beck’s analysis, is the idea that risk may have emerged as a threat to human civilization itself. Ecological risk, for example, threatens the entire planet and in that sense, transcends any conflict between social classes (Beck, 1995). Financial risk of course is not a direct threat to human civilization, but there is a real possibility that it might be a threat the sustainability of capitalism, as financial crises become more and more severe. 3 7 local contexts of interaction and their restructuring across indefinite spans of time-space.”(Giddens, 1990: 21). This mechanism entails a high degree of abstraction by “removing social relations from the immediacies of context” (Giddens, 1990: 28). Giddens distinguishes two types of disembedding mechanisms, the creation of symbolic tokens (such as money), and the establishment of expert systems (systems of technical accomplishment or professional expertise). Modern societies require individuals to place a high degree of ‘trust’ in both institutions. In environments of risk, these institutions are entrusted to manage and reduce risk. Here we would like to argue that financial institutions have emerged as expert systems, with expertise in risk management. Risks were not to be avoided or minimized, they had to be actively managed. Taking risks had now become the route to high rewards. For this purpose, the field of financial engineering was developed to design new financial instruments and strategies through the use of advanced mathematical tools and models. As we discussed, in recent decades the financial sector saw increased productivity and financial innovation at an astonishing pace, and the commodification of risk at a massive scale. Risk management is firmly based on advances in academic work – in business, finance and economics. First, the Efficient Markets Theory tells us that free markets will always price things correctly. Second, Black-Scholes and associated equations provide formulas for pricing risks. Finally, developments in time series econometrics make it possible to apply these insights to real time market activities. All of this is based on the idea that risk is something that can be quantified and priced, that the future can be made predictable with probabilistic calculations. This is the notion of risk as fundamentally different from real uncertainty. In economics the distinction between risk and uncertainty was first explored in Frank Knight’s Risk, Uncertainty and Profits (1921/1940). Knight distinguishes between forms of indeterminacy that are predictable and lend themselves to probabilistic calculation (risk), and forms of indeterminacy that entail an inability assign probabilities to various potential outcomes of a given situation (this could be because it is impossible to identify all possible outcomes, or because although all event alternatives are known, probabilities cannot be computed). We could further distinguish between two kinds of uncertainty, which David Dequech identifies as ambiguity and fundamental uncertainty (Dequech, 2000). Ambiguity refers to situations where uncertainty exists only to the extent existing relevant information is missing. Yet the information exists at the time the decision is made, and if it were known, the situation would be characterized by risk rather than uncertainty. Fundamental uncertainty is altogether different in essence to the extent that the relevant information simply does not exist at the decision time. Under fundamental uncertainty, some essential information about future events does not exist and cannot be inferred from any data set (Dequech, 1999). John Maynard Keynes was the first economist to grasp the full significance of radical uncertainty for economic analysis. Keynes was particularly interested in the behavior of investors, consumers and businessmen. Much of their actions, he argued, were driven by ‘animal spirits’ – ideas and attitudes very much determined by intangible psychological motivations (this has inspired the title of a recent book by George Akerlof and Robert Shiller, Animal Spirits: How Human Psychology Drives the Economy, and Why It Matters for Global Capitalism). Events determined by human decisions are fundamentally different than say the outcomes of a game of roulette, and do not lend themselves to the calculation of probabilities. To the extent such events (such as wars, inventions, investment decisions, or even changes in prices and interest rates) have economic significance and are by their very nature radically uncertain, the reliance on probabilistic calculus to form expectations of the future is tempting yet mistaken and unscientific: 8 “The orthodox theory assumes that we have a knowledge of the future of a kind quite different from that which we actually possess. This false rationalization follows the lines of the Benthamite calculus. The hypothesis of a calculable future leads to a wrong interpretation of the principles of behavior.” (Keynes, 1972: 122). Yet mainstream economists have not embraced the notion of radical uncertainty as being indispensable to understand the world. The notion of calculable risk has permeated the field, and there has been a triumph of risk over uncertainty (Reddy, 1994). In the second edition of Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (1947), J. von Neumann and O. Morgenstern formally incorporated risk into economic theory with the concept of ‘expected utility theory’.4 Expected utility is risk-based in that it assumes a well-defined event space with known probabilities. This gave rise to a whole new range of risk analysis problems, techniques and models, all of which assume risk to be well defined and disregard the practical consequences of the future as being uncertain. The only critics were outsiders to the economics profession, heterodox economists or practitioners. For example, George Soros has repeatedly warned that the general theory that markets tend towards equilibrium is flawed to the extent financial markets do not merely discount the future but also help to shape it by affecting the fundamentals they are supposed to reflect (Soros, 1994). Based on his analysis of this self-reinforcing mechanism in markets, Soros developed his theory of reflexivity. The theory, which deconstructs the notion of objective market fundamentals, is damaging to the claim that the future can be entirely managed with probabilistic computations, and that radical uncertainty can be completely eliminated. Post-Keynesians have developed their own alternative theories of how financial markets operate, to explain the erratic behavior of financial markets, and the amplitude of price swings in boom and bust cycles. Minksy’s financial instability hypothesis (presented as an interpretation of the substance of Keynes’ General Theory) posits that the economy has financing regimes under which it is stable (the efficient market hypothesis would roughly hold), and financing regimes under which it is not.5 There will be a natural tendency for the economy to transition from a stable system into an unstable system, giving rise to boom and bust cycles.6 (Minsky, 1993). This inherent instability of financial markets is also difficult to reconcile with measurable risk and the future consisting of known outcomes and probabilities. Under expected utility theory, a lottery is defined as a list of outcomes with assigned probabilities. The notation (x, p) is used to denote the prospect (x, p; 0, 1-p) that yields x with probability p and 0 with probability 1-p. Expected utility provides that: 4 . The overall utility of a project is the expected utility of its outcomes, thereby applying the expectation operator of probability theory to lotteries. 5 Minsky distinguishes three distinct financing regimes. Hedge finance is a situation where cash flows can fulfill all payment obligations (interest and principal). Typically, hedge finance is associated with reasonable debt to equity ratios. Speculative finance involves situations where income cash flows do not support repayment of principal. Liabilities are typically rolled over – examples of this could include governments with floating debts, or corporations with floating issues of commercial papers. Finally, ponzi finance entails an inability to cover both interest and principal payment obligations with operational cash flow. 6 Over periods of prosperity, speculative and ponzi financing will naturally increase under the pressure of monetary constraint (such as that resulting from the Central Bank’s attempt to keep inflation under control): driven by their own profit-seeking objective, bankers (using the term generically for all intermediaries in finance) will strive to innovate. However, cash flow shortfalls will lead firms to cover their positions by selling assets, eventually leading to a collapse in asset values. 9 The recent financial crisis has been characterized by a widespread failure of the internal risk management models used by many financial institutions. The risk officers of the failing institutions relied heavily on such models, and were for the most part claiming that risk management and stress testing systems in place for thousands of trading positions (of mind-boggling complexity) were well under control. Quoted in Business Week (2006) just before the 2007-2008 crisis, Bear Stearns chief risk officer Michael Alix asserted that “the machine works”, and Lehman’s Chief Administrative Officer David Goldfarb that “we are in the business of risk management 24/7, 365 days a year". Such confidence was obviously misplaced. The failure of Bear Stearns, triggered by the collapse of two internal hedge funds that had heavily invested in CDOs and went bankrupt in Summer 2007, perfectly illustrates how financial institutions took large risks they did not fully understand when investing in complex products, and how enormous risk taking became the norm on Wall Street. Credit Rating Agencies (CRAs) also did not properly assess the risk profile of new products (e.g. structured and securitized products, credit derivatives) and gave favorable ratings to CDOs that turned out to be quite risky. While investments holding AAA ratings traditionally have had a less than 1 percent probability of default, analysts have determined that over 90 percent of AAA ratings assigned to MBS and CDO securities issued in 2006 and 2007 had to be downgraded to junk status shortly thereafter (U.S. Senate, 2011). Why did internal risk management fail so spectacularly? The triumph of the claim that risk can be managed, and the failure to acknowledge that the future is to a large degree uncertain has been one of the contributing factors to this failure. The world is not as straightforward as a game of roulette and does not lend itself to simple probabilistic calculations: “Manufactured risk refers to new risk environments for which history provides us with very little previous experience. We often don’t really know what the risks are, let alone how to calculate them accurately in terms of probability tables.” (Giddens, 1999: 4) For example, in the case of MBSs, complex phenomena such as default correlation (i.e. the possibility that different mortgages might not be independent of each other, whereby one mortgage defaulting increases the chance of another mortgage defaulting) were important drivers in pricing of securitized products, yet they were not properly understood nor modeled. Further complications can be introduced in asset-backed securitized products by mixing different risky assets of different types, taking more complex positions within the tranches, and by investing in multiple products. All of this is usually simulated with computers, which can keep track of the details. However, once mortgage delinquency rates rose, senior tranches of securities were much quicker to lose value than anticipated. Original pricing did not correspond to the true risk profile given default correlation, leading to sudden and unanticipated losses in value. There are also serious limitations to the current theoretical approaches to risk management. Generally speaking, models are based on a historical simulation of past risks and returns, and make simplifying assumptions about the real world, such as normal distribution of returns. This is true of mortgage deficiency simulations for MBSs. This is also true of Value at Risk (VaR), the main tool for banks’ internal risk management, which is designed to estimate the expected maximum amount that could be lost on bank’s portfolio as result in changes in prices of underlying assets essentially how much the portfolio can lose with a given probability (95 percent or 99 percent) over a stated time horizon. There are many conceptual problems with the approach. First, it is 10 backward-looking in nature, based on a historical simulation of past risks and returns, which does not embrace the inherent uncertainty of future returns (there is no guarantee the future will resemble the past…). Second, VaR does not seek to give the magnitude of the amount that will be lost the rest of the time (events with a low probability, e.g. 5 percent or 1 percent). Hence investors get lulled with a false sense of security, ignoring “abnormal” events. One example (given in Business Week, 2006) is the estimate by JPMorgan Chase & Co. in its 2005 annual report that trading portfolios were at risk of losing $88 million on any given day. The amount seems negligible, but a closer look at the annual report would have indicated the possibility that the amount at risk could increase to a staggering $1.4 billion over a four-week period – not so negligible after all. Yet because of its relatively low probability, this risk would stand to be unnoticed. Third, VaR conveniently assumes a normal distribution of returns, despite evidence to the contrary. This assumption has led to the discarding of fat tails, i.e. the possibility that rare events might not be as unlikely as previously thought. For all these reasons, critics of VaR, such as Nassim Taleb, have argued that it is no more than an alibi that bankers give shareholders (and potentially the bailingout taxpayer) to show documented due diligence regarding risk-taking. Thus at a theoretical level, VaR arguably does not adequately capture the risk profile of financial institutions. Other tools of modern finance, such as CAPM, the Efficient Market Hypothesis, and the Black-Scholes model are also based on the assumption that market prices are normally distributed, and as such are equally flawed in their approach. Mathematician Benoit Mandelbrot and others have been working to develop more robust theoretical foundations of market behavior that would abandon the normalcy assumption and allow for the possibility of fat tails.7 While Mandelbrot’s approach (based on fractal geometry) has launched a new field of study in finance and risk management, it has not yet led to a robust workable theory of market behavior. Further, any such theoretical framework would still be subject to the epistemological problem (highlighted by Soros in his theory of reflexivity) that investor reliance on the model could alter forecasted behavior. New investment vehicles (e.g. hedge funds) are also in dire need of some new risk metrics. One issue is that the traditional risk measures of alphas, betas and Sharpe ratios are static in nature (i.e. based on return distributions at a given point in time). Hedge funds may display nonlinearities and non-normal characteristics that are not captured by linear regression models.8 A new set of risk analytics designed to address the unique features of hedge fund investments is being developed9, but the risk literature shows that we are far from fully understanding and quantifying risk for actively managed investments. Another problem is that risk management has become homogenous. Professionals tend to use the same models learned at the same schools. The models are based on the same information (historical data) and methodology, essentially reflecting the same view of the world. In the mid 1990s, CRAs See for example Mandelbrot and Hudson (2006). For example, Brooks and Kat (2002) have found that published hedge fund indexes exhibit high kurtosis, indicating that the distribution has “fat” tails. Examining data from the Tass database from 1995 to 2003 for various hedge fund categories, Malkiel and Saha (2004) have confirmed that hedge fund returns are characterized by high kurtosis and that many hedge fund categories have considerable negative skewness, implying an asymmetric distribution. The shape of the probability distribution of returns affects the Sharpe ratio. For example, Bernardo and Ledoit (2000) show that Sharpe ratios are misleading when the shape of the return distribution is far from normal. 9 Lo (2008a) has proposed new measures of performance that capture both static and dynamic aspects of decision making on the part of the hedge fund manager. 7 8 11 started disclosing their rating models (the application software) to banks. For example, in 1995 Standard & Poor developed its LEVELs model, a statistical-based approach to determining losses expected on a given bond. The version of the model was subsequently made commercially available to investment banks and securities originators.10 This led to further homogenization as financial products could be designed with those specific guidelines in mind (so as to secure targeted ratings) rather than on the basis of an independent risk assessment. What we have established thus far is that the increasing complexity of financial markets in terms of trading volume, interconnectedness and financial innovation has led to the emergence of new forms of risks – financial manufactured risks. While financial institutions have positioned themselves as experts in risk management, the 2007-2008 financial crisis shows that many institutions took very large risks they did not fully understand, and to a large extent, relied on flawed risk models. Risk management tools gave investors and shareholders the illusion of controlled risk taking. One main characteristic of what we label the culture of risk is the excessive reliance on statistical tools that assume probabilizable risk, the failure to acknowledge that the future is to a large degree uncertain. In the Culture of Risk, risk is not properly understood nor managed, in spite of claims otherwise and academic advances in business, economics and finance. Yet there is something more perverse taking place here. The claims to expert knowledge on the part of the financial sector have actually increased risk. In Giddens’ analysis, a key characteristic of modernity, ‘reflexivity’ is characterized by the fact that “social practices are constantly examined and reformed in the light of incoming information about those very practices, thus constitutively altering their character.” (Giddens, 1990: 38). This occurs at the level of social institutions to the extent institutions entrusted to manage social risk are not detached from social relations, and can influence the very events they are analyzing: “The reliance placed by lay actors upon expert systems is not just a matter – as was normally the case in the pre-modern world – of generating a sense of security about an independently given universe of events. It is a matter of the calculation of benefit and risk in circumstances where expert knowledge does not just provide that calculus but actually creates (or reproduces) the universe of events, as a result of the continual reflexive implementation of that very knowledge.” (Giddens, 1990: 84). The reflexivity of social institutions can help understand how financial institutions and markets can themselves become a new source of risk to the extent their claim to manage risk actually increases risk (Reddy, 1996: 243). We see this very mechanism at work in financial markets, as complex securities, which were supposed to outsource and diversify idiosyncratic risk, have actually accelerated the boom and subsequent collapse.11 Those innovations provided the underlying See U.S. Congress (2008a), testimony of Frank Raiter. The recent crisis can be analyzed in the light of the combination of two leverage cycles, both in the housing sector and in the market for these complex securities. Geanakoplos and Farmer (2009) develop models to explain the double leverage cycle, in the housing and securities sectors, and conclude that the introduction of CDS contracts into the mortgage market in late 2005 was an important trigger for the collapse of 2007-2009. Semmler and Bernard (2009) propose a baseline model that replicates financial market boom-bust cycles and demonstrates the magnifying effects arising from the pricing of the new financial market instruments. 10 11 12 financial intermediation mechanism through which the asset price boom and busts were fueled. 12 We find that the explosion of new financial products designed to offer market based solutions to an increasingly complex and global world actually tends to increase the overall risk of the system. In Risk Society, Ulrich Beck highlights that “along with the growing capacity of technical options grows the incalculability of their consequences” (Beck, 1992: 22). Financial engineering increases complexity and radical uncertainty such that managing individual risk, on a widespread scale, increases rather than reduces systemic risk. The term “systemic risk” is used to describe the possibility that the failure of one financial institution can disrupt the financial system as a whole through a series of correlated defaults, if there is enough interconnectedness between financial institutions. The collapse of Bear Stearns’ internal hedge funds in 200713 illustrates that investment activities conducted by hedge funds have the ability to destabilize the economy and increase systemic risk. The first characteristic of the culture of risk, as we have just outlined, is an epistemic fallacy, the widespread claim that risk can be quantified and managed. The flawed assumption of normal distribution of data has made risk models particularly vulnerable to unpredictable and consequential events (which Nassim Taleb has dubbed “black swans”). As noted by Beck, “in the risk society the unknown and unintended consequences come to be a dominant force in history and society” (Beck, 1992: 23), a remark equally applicable to financial markets. Nassim Taleb’s entire book The Black Swan (Taleb, 2007) is devoted to this very point, and advocates for a greater degree of humility on the part of risk experts. In spite of claims to the contrary, in the culture of risk, risk-taking is not controlled nor managed. It is also reflexive in nature, with the very reliance on financial experts creating more complexity, more uncertainty, and new forms of global risks, including systemic risk. IV. Are There Real Incentives To Manage Risk? The critical question remains as to why risk managers and Credit Rating Agencies relied on flawed models. Were they simply not aware of their theoretical limitations, or did they choose to ignore these issues? To some extent, this reliance can be explained by the appeal of the scientific promise of calculable risk. The claim that risk can be quantified and managed is a move "against the gods" (Bernstein, 1998), inherently connected with the aspiration to control fate. Yet we argue that financial institutions also lacked real incentives to properly manage risk. Three simultaneous and related trends explain what incentives led to the gradual shift in attitudes towards risk taking on the part of financial institutions, and the prevailing willingness to take on large risks that were not Liquidity spirals emerged as a result of underlying self-reinforcing feedback mechanisms. The tightening of margins led to lower security prices, which slowed the issuance of new mortgages and adversely impacted homeowners’ ability to refinance. This in turn increased default risk, thereby making downpayment requirements more stringent, reducing demand for housing, making housing prices fall and thereby further increasing security margins, prompting the whole sequence to repeat. 13 The Bear Stearns funds had heavily invested in CDOs and hoped to make big returns from the flourishing housing sector. As mortgage default rates increased, top-tranche mortgage backed securities suddenly declined in marketable value to become “toxic” assets. 12 13 fully understood: first, commercial banks and investment banks coming to rely on proprietary trading to generate a greater and greater fraction of revenue; second, the end of the partnershiptype organizational structure for the major Wall Street firms; and third, the compensation structure rewarding traders for indiscriminate growth in revenue at the expense of the risk profile of the institution. With firms going public and heavily engaging in proprietary trading, top traders were now aggressively investing shareholder’s funds rather than their own, taking on risks that would maximize their own remuneration in the short run rather than firm value in the long run. As described in Section V, the deregulation policies pursued in the past thirty years left these market developments unfettered. Arguably these trends were the product of globalization, market forces and policy decisions rather than of the cultural environment on Wall Street. However, we suggest that they have led to a set of commonly shared attitudes towards risk-taking within the financial sector, and their continued reproduction at the individual and institutional level. This cultural environment has come to regard the compensation paid out to top traders and executives as economically justified without actual evidence that it is the case. We suggest that a portion of Wall Street bonuses might well constitute economic rent (excess return), creating incentives for risk-taking. The Rise of Proprietary Trading The 1990s saw the rise of alternative investment vehicles, such as hedge funds and private equity funds. A hedge fund is any privately organized pooled investment vehicle administered by professional investment managers whose interests are not sold in a registered public offering. Hedge funds are normally structured as limited partnerships, where a general partner manages the fund for a fixed fee (usually a percentage of assets under management) and a percentage of the gross profits from the fund (the “carry” or “carried interest”). The investors are limited partners with no managerial oversight. One of the first significant and sizeable hedge funds was Long Term Capital Management (LTCM), founded in 1994 by John Meriwether and Nobel Prize winners Myron Scholes and Robert C. Merton. The fund failed spectacularly in 199814 and had to be bailed out by a consortium of creditors. Since the Federal Reserve intervened to prevent this near-collapse, the size of the hedge fund industry has exploded. Roughly, the industry has grown approximately by a factor of five in the past ten years, from $387 billion in 1998 to $1.8 trillion in 2008.15 This growth is in part attributable to the fact that the industry has been (until recently) to a large extent unregulated, which has given hedge funds a competitive advantage over more traditional investment vehicles, like mutual funds. For example, hedge funds have no regulatory trading restrictions, which has allowed for very active management. This active management is said to generate return in excess of the required rate of return (as determined by the Capital Asset Pricing Model) for any diversified investment, for example an index fund. This additional return is called the Its trading strategy was to exploit very small pricing differences between government bonds through the use of sophisticated algorithms. In order to make a decent profit on very tiny spreads, LTCM was heavily leveraged, twenty to thirty times of capital or more. 15 By comparison, over the same period U.S. GDP and the mutual fund industry have grown by only 64 percent and 69 percent respectively. 14 14 "alpha". Presumably, it is the ability to deliver high alphas that is responsible for the rise of the hedge fund industry. Hedge funds are involved in virtually every kind of market and invest in every kind of assets, from equity, loans, mortgages, distressed debt, to project finance, derivatives etc., employing a wide variety of trading strategies. In terms of assets under management, attractiveness of returns, and recruitment of top traders, hedge funds became a serious competitive threat to investment banks. Investment banking had traditionally been relationship driven. Starting in the 1980s, as the financial sector became fast-paced, globalized and competitive, with increasing competition from foreign firms, the existence of long-term relationships became less important than the ability to deliver a deal efficiently. Corporate clients became more transaction-driven, shopping around for the best securities firm. In this new competitive environment, margins began to gradually decline. There was also growing competition from commercial banks, which further contributed to driving down underwriting fees. The traditional bank loan business started to decline in the 1980s, as companies turned to securities issuance to raise capital, forcing commercial banks to compete with investment banks in the underwriting business and securities markets. Glass-Steagall was repealed in 1999 under the lobbying pressure of large commercial banks.16 With commercial banks able to directly compete in the underwriting business and rely on their ability to extend significant credit facilities to clients to secure issuance business, underwriting fees were driven down as commercial banks started to run a “volume based” business (Prins, 2004: 45). In this environment, investment banks had to find other sources of profit to stay competitive. They turned to proprietary trading for larger and larger fractions of their revenue. Proprietary trading desks can be thought of as internal hedge funds within the bank. Proprietary trading refers to the use of the firm’s own capital to actively trade financial assets, as opposed to traditional investment banking fee-based activities, such as underwriting and consulting. The rise of proprietary trading within investment banks was accompanied by an increase in the risk profile of financial institutions. First, proprietary trading is more volatile than the traditional investment banking fee-based activities, giving rise to more volatile returns and increased responsiveness to market swings. For example, in 2007 the “Trading and Principal Investments” division of Goldman Sachs accounted for $13.3 billion of the $17.6 billion of the firm’s pre-tax earnings. Yet in 2008, in the midst of the financial crisis, the division generated a loss of $2.75 billion (when the firm generated pre-tax earnings of $2.34 billion). Proprietary trading is also more capital-intensive in nature (as compared with the traditional fee-based underwriting and consulting businesses, or even market-making activities), and requires intense use of the firm’s own capital to fund both liquid and illiquid positions. High leveraging became a well-established business strategy indispensable to remain competitive and finance, allowing investment banks to turn high profits with minimal capital. Lacking a wide deposit base, which provides abundant and cheap funding to commercial banks, investment banks instead turned to other sources of borrowing, such as shortterm secured loans from repo markets.17 Leverage ratios of the major investment banks increased The Federal Reserve first approved Bank of America’s acquisition of Charles Schwab (brokerage operation) in 1983. A 1987 Supreme Court decision allowed some subsidiaries of commercial banks to conduct investment-banking operations, provided the revenues were small enough. Large banks started lobbying for the repeal of Glass-Steagall, arguing that the ability to deliver a full-range of financial services was essential for U.S. banks to be able to compete with foreign firms. 17 A repo is also known as a Repurchase Agreement. The borrower sells a security to a lender, but simultaneously agrees to buy the same security at some future date for a fixed price. The agreement is economically equivalent to a 16 15 to roughly 35-to-1 and even 40-to-1 before the 2007-2008 crisis.18 It is not surprising that this was accompanied by an increase in the amount of firms’ capital put at risk on a single trading day. For example, in March 2006 Goldman Sachs’s VaR jumped to $92 million, an increase of 135 percent as compared with $39 million in 2001 (Business Week, 2006). This business profile was inherently risky in that investment banks continually borrowed with short maturities, but held risky and potentially illiquid positions - its weakness became all too apparent when credit markets (including repo markets) dried up in 2008, and investment banks like Goldman Sachs and Morgan Stanley had to resort to a change in regulatory status (electing to convert to Bank Holding Company status) to access the Federal Reserve emergency lending facilities (lender of last resort).19 The risk/reward profile for most hedge funds and proprietary trading desks is not as well understood as that for traditional investments. The implications of all this for systemic risk became too apparent in the recent crisis, where the failure of major financial institutions had the potential to severely disrupt markets. One significant new provision in the Dodd-Frank Act is the restriction of proprietary operations undertaken by commercial banks (provision known as the Volcker rule). Banks can now place up to 3 percent of their Tier 1 capital in hedge fund and proprietary trading investments. Banks are also prohibited from holding more than 3 percent of the total ownership interest of any private equity investment or hedge fund. This falls short of a complete disallowance of proprietary desks, which had been originally suggested and would have been equivalent to restoring Glass-Steagall. Further, there are some notable exceptions to the ban. There is a list of permitted activities, including investments in U.S. government securities, transactions made in connection with underwriting or market making related activities, transactions on behalf of customers, and “riskmitigating hedging activities” in connection with individual or aggregated holdings of the banking entity. There is no doubt that in the coming years legal work will have to be done to interpret the language in the bill to define which activities fall within the scope of the exceptions to the Volcker provision. There is enough ambiguity to allow banks to get away with a lot, if they can successfully interpret the rules as they see fit.20 While all major banks are scaling down trading operations and investments in hedge funds, it has even been suggested that the big players (such as Goldman Sachs and Morgan Stanley) are not truly abandoning proprietary trading, but instead are shifting it secured borrowing, whereby the borrower uses a financial security as collateral for a loan at a fixed rate of interest (roughly, the difference between the sale and repurchase price). Repo markets have allowed investment banks (and broker dealers) to access cheaper financing, using their inventory of securities as collateral. 18 The SEC loosened its capital requirements in 2004. Under its Consolidated Supervised Entities program, the SEC allowed broker-dealers with capital of at least $5 billion to increase their debt-to-net capital ratios to as high as 40-to-1. 19 The stand-alone large investment bank is now a thing of the past. By the late Fall of 2008, the five major U.S. investment banks (Merrill Lynch, Goldman Sachs, Morgan Stanley, Lehman Brothers and Bear Stearns) had either failed or abandoned their status as independent investment banks. Goldman Sachs and Morgan Stanley decided to convert to Bank Holding Companies, and thus become regulated by the Federal Reserve instead of the SEC. This was in great part motivated by the need to ensure that they would have access to a loan facility from the Federal Reserve, since the Federal Reserve acts as a lender of last resort (but only for banks member of the Federal Reserve System). In the future, these two firms will have to adhere to stricter requirements regarding regulatory capital, which may affect the extent and nature of their proprietary trading desks. The banks might increase the level of deposit taking on their balance sheet, although the extent to which they will engage in retail banking is yet to be determined. We can expect that in line with the repeal of Glass-Steagall, Wall Street might reorganize to form even larger financial institutions offering a complete range of financial services, including commercial banking, broker-dealer services and insurance. 20 Will investments in funds that mostly trade government securities (for example fixed income arbitrage funds) be allowed? Will activities conducted to facilitate customer relationships qualify as activities done “on behalf of customers”? What types of activities will constitute “risk-mitigating hedging activities”? 16 into trading desks that deal directly with customers, so as to qualify as a permitted activity (see Lewis, 2010a and 2010b). The End of the Partnership Culture As the major Wall Street houses started as family firms, loyalty to the firm was first and foremost a family affair. As the firms grew in size, this model gradually developed into a partnership-type organizational structure, where the business model was based on trust, loyalty and confidentiality – characteristics that often made it possible to do deals and perform transactions quickly and efficiently. However, the partnership model itself was not sustainable as Wall Street firms continued to grow in size. Eventually, most of these firms were taken public to remain competitive. The last major firm to do an IPO was Goldman Sachs (in 1999), although the firm kept the title “Partner Managing Director” so as to preserve a sense of the existence of a partnership. However, the new climate of extreme competition between firms and markets, which began in the 1980s, has led to the gradual erosion of this partnership culture. First and foremost, the organization of investment banks as publicly owned corporations introduces issues of moral hazard and conflict of interest between management and shareholders (a principalagent problem absent from the partnership model, where the firm is trading with management’s own funds rather than shareholders’ equity). Traders’ primary motivation became their own remuneration rather than the maximization of firm value. This in turn meant that management had financial incentives to justify large bonuses in current periods (ex. hitting short term quarterly earnings targets) rather than maximize long-term firm value. Michael Lewis in his book Liar’s Poker describes how Salomon’s lack of system for allocating costs became problematic when the firm became public. Instead of focusing on profits, trading managers began to focus on “indiscriminate” revenue growth, as it is often possible to create revenue without necessarily booking profit (Lewis, 1989: 109). In a classic moral hazard problem, banking executives have a lot to gain from risk taking, but little economic penalty. Shareholders, not managers, suffer the major economic loss in the event of bankruptcy. Further, with the rise of large investment firms that were sufficiently large to present a threat to the economy, basking in the dominant view that they were “too big to fail”, these firms found that, when on the brink of bankruptcy, they could rely on state institutions for safety nets - as we saw with the bailout of huge firms such as AIG.21 Further, in a partnership loyalty was structural in nature in that traders were required to reinvest a substantial portion of earnings in the firm and stood much to lose from leaving the partnership. When firms went public, the loyalty started to gradually break down. For example, Goldman partners reportedly sold nearly As Stiglitz points out in a recent book, the effort to rescue the banking system was inherently flawed (Stiglitz, 2010). Firms used the threat of systemic risk to shift all risk to the government, reduced to the role of “garbage disposal” (the expression is Stiglitz’s) for toxic assets created by financial institution. The implementation of the multi-trillion dollar bailout for the banks orchestrated by the Bush and Obama administrations was inconsistent - some institutions were rescued, others not, without clear guidelines underlying the decisions. Goldman Sachs received billions from AIG (funded by the AIG bailout) as settlement of credit default swaps, while other market participants received only 13 cents on the dollar in settlement of credit default swaps. The expectation that banks are entitled to a socialized takeover of losses while privately pocketing gains is obscene. For these reasons, Stiglitz refers to the bailout as the “Great American Robbery”. 21 17 $700 million of stock in the period of adversity that followed Lehman's bankruptcy. This cashing out would have been unthinkable in the 1960s or 1970s.22 In the partnership environment, employees would rise through the ranks and develop professionally within a single organization. Many firms would not even hire top managers externally. But in the new environment, with all major firms public, employee retention – and motivation - became a key issue. Higher employee turnover became the norm. At Salomon in the early 1980s 75 percent of new hires would be gone after three years, in sharp contrast with prior years when 85 percent of hires would remain with the firm (Lewis, 1989: 38). This new generation of traders began to demand higher levels of compensation and “a higher cut” of trading profits. Top traders would seek more lucrative employment opportunities elsewhere if the firm did not quickly comply, an attitude which Lewis describes as “hit and run” (Lewis, 1989: 127-8). With the decline of the partnership model, compensation became the key factor to motivate employees to be loyal to the firm. More recently many investment banks have struggled to keep top employees from pursuing more lucrative opportunities with hedge funds or private equity funds. In the partnership culture, long-term client relationships were key to a firm’s success. Yet as discussed in the fast-pace globalized and competitive environment that emerged in the 1980s, the importance of long-term relationships declined. Hence it should not come as a surprise that with the loss of the partnership culture, big investment banks came to develop an institutionalized sense of entitlement to huge profits, even if such profit levels entailed potential conflicts with client interests. Goldman Sachs pocketed huge profits by marketing securities (CDOs) to investors, while betting against those very products (see New York Times, 2009). In a public response to the New York Times, Goldman Sachs saw no conflict of interest or ethical issue, viewing its own bets as “prudent hedging management” and justifying their marketing of CDOs as a mere response to client demand. The SEC charged Goldman Sachs with fraud related to the structuring and marketing of subprime mortgage CDOs. The accusation was that Goldman Sachs omitted to disclose key facts to the investors, including the role played by a major hedge fund (Paulson & Co.) in the selection of the underlying mortgages, and the fact that the bank had taken short positions against the CDOs. The case was ultimately settled for $550 million on July 15, 2010.23 Risk Transfer and Compensation The Wall Street bonuses are part of the Wall Street mystique, with a large portion of total compensation coming in the form of company stock, or stock option, thus linking compensation to the profitability of the firm (or a division of the firm). Traders’ bonuses are also typically based on During the great depression a significant part of the firm’s partnership capital was used to cover the losses of The Goldman Sachs Trading Corporation, which had collapsed. 23 Even if Goldman Sachs did not break the law, arguably Goldman’s actions were harmful to their clients, and to financial markets as a whole. There were misrepresentations made to investors. In its marketing material, Goldman represented that it had “aligned incentives” with the Hudson Mezzanine (a $2 billion CDO it created in 2006), and that the underlying assets had been “sourced from the street”. While it was technically true that Goldman had made a small investment in the product, failure to disclose the firm’s much larger bet against the securities in essence was clearly misleading. Further the assets came from Goldman’s own balance sheet rather than randomly selected from other broker-dealers. 22 18 their division’s profit and loss. This is not limited to Wall Street, as the use of stock- and optionbased executive compensation for CEOs has increased dramatically in the past few decades. The median exposure of CEO wealth to stock prices tripled between 1980 and 1994 (Hall and Liebman, 1998) and doubled between 1994 and 2000 (Bergstresser and Philippon, 2006). In the standard economic labor market model, firms employ workers to the extent that the marginal product of the worker is greater than or equal to the firm’s marginal cost of employment. Firms hire a given worker at a given wage rate only to the extent it is profitable for the firm given the worker’s contribution to output. Further, the wage rate must be high enough to attract workers (the banking industry frequently claims that high rewards are necessary to attract the best talent). In theory tying employee compensation to the success of the firm is designed to ensure that executives have incentives to deliver their best efforts and maximize firm value. Aligning the interests of executives with those of the firm minimizes the principal-agent issue. Further, stock options increase retention, since employees often do not gain immediate control of those stocks and stock options. 24 Beck’s discussion of the risk society has placed the distribution of risk, rather than wealth, as the central social issue in modernity. There is, arguably, a big difference between risk in the financial markets and other forms of risk, such as ecological risk discussed in Beck (1995). Though specific populations and parts of the world might be more affected by ecological damage, ecological risk does not necessarily respect divisions between poor and rich countries, and potentially transcends class struggles between capital and labor: “In the ecological conflict, where what are at stake are negatives, there is no direct intermeshing of opposing interests.” Beck (1995: 4). In contrast, we find that while the increase of risk in our financial system threatens most investors (through pension funds and 401ks), executives on Wall Street have stood much to gain from this increase. Higher risk levels are associated with higher volatility in returns, and accordingly higher bonuses in record years, with no possibility of retroactive recovery of such bonuses in bad years. What we find is that this compensation structure has not necessarily led to a maximization of shareholder value. Recently, we saw executives of major collapsing financial institutions (AIG, Lehman, etc…) walk away with millions of dollars in compensation, refusing to accept any blame for improper risk management of their institutions. The link of high bonuses to short-term profits gives incentives for excessive risk-taking on the part of CEOs. For executives, there is more to gain from high volatility (allowing executives to cash out at high inflated stock value), than slow but steady appreciation in value with lower underlying risk levels. Studies show that the manager’s appetite for risk is highly correlated with compensation package’s sensitivity to stock return volatility (Knopf, Nam, and Thornton, 2002, Coles, Daniel, and Naveen, 2006). The compensation structure for hedge fund managers, with managers earning a carried interest (up to 20 percent of profit) gives the fund manager a similar incentive for volatility in returns -- as such, it has been described as having option-like features (Cochrane, 2005).25 The asymmetry is that high volatility leads to above average returns and bonuses in good years, yet when the company experiences above average losses, shareholders are unable to retrieve bonuses paid to executives in prior years. This results in a persistent principal-agent issue. In the words of former Goldman Sachs partner and hedge fund manager Leon Cooperman: There can be a waiting period (the “vesting period”, usually 3 to 5 years) during which the employee cannot sell the stock or exercise the option. If the employee leaves the firm before the vesting period is over, he or she can lose all entitlement. 25 The value of an option increases with the volatility of the underlier. 24 19 “We are not an investor in [investment banks]. I determined many years ago that if you want to make money on Wall Street, you work there; you don't invest there. They just pay themselves too well. I would rather look elsewhere for investment opportunities.”26 In the case of AIG, the company (and its executives) grew rich by taking on excessive risk. It transpires that top executives still received high bonuses even when the company lost over $5 billion in the final quarter of 2007 (losses attributable to its Financial Products Division, the division which issued about $527 billion of CDSs). Based on the findings of U.S. Congress (2008c), the compensation committee that met on March 11, 2008 followed management’s recommendation to exclude the unit’s unrealized market valuation losses from the calculation of bonuses. Martin Sullivan received a golden parachute worth $15 million. Joseph Cassano, the executive in charge of the Financial Products Division, was terminated without cause in February 2008 when his division imploded.27 He had received more than $280 million over 8 years. The compensation committee did not seek to recover any of this past compensation. In fact, he was allowed to keep to $34 million in unvested bonuses. In such situations, we find that the standard economic labor market model breaks down. It is hard to argue that bonuses correspond to the marginal product of the worker when the company is on the brink of collapse, and when compensation is not based on a true (risk-adjusted) measure of firm profitability. Since compensation committee members are themselves executives in the industry (there are no or few outsiders on the Boards), they have a vested interest in keeping a high overall compensation level, which may jeopardize their fiduciary duty to the shareholders of the company. Many Wall Street executives operate like a guild system of insiders who have acquired the power to pay themselves (and each other) with no effective input from shareholders. Quite frequently, severance agreements are put in place from the very beginning, so that executives will walk away with millions of dollars regardless of what happens to the company (as was the case with AIG). Boards also often do not go through an outside search for a new chairman (as was also the case with AIG). The board terminated Mr. Sullivan after AIG lost $13 billion in two quarters, but allowed him to retire and receive his bonus. Had he been terminated for cause, he would not have been entitled to the payment. It is very hard to argue that in such instances compensation committees are acting in the best interest of the shareholders. The overall pay level in the industry may thus well include an element of “rent-taking”, meaning that collectively bonuses are not determined by competitive market forces and exceed value created for firms in the financial sector. This is perfectly compatible with the notion that individually firms aggressively compete for the best resources, and that high rewards may be necessary to attract the best talents to a given firm. There are no easy legal recourses available to shareholders to retrieve bonuses paid to executives in prior years. It is difficult to bring legal charges against compensation committees even when the allowance of bonuses shows very poor governance, as is clearly the case with AIG, when the company was on the brink of collapse. It is also very difficult to press charges against executives for improper risk management, to the extent that poor risk management is merely a bad business decision rather than an illegal business practice. Executives do not go to jail for making bad business decisions. Unless there is a failure to comply with securities law, or actual fraud, it is Cited in Dumortier (2009). Mr. Cassano remained on AIG’s payroll earning $1 million a month to unwind the very financial products the division had sold during his leadership. 26 27 20 difficult to recover damages from executives, or recover prior bonuses paid on the basis of profits that did not take into account the increase in the risk profile of the institution. One possible legal ground for action is the charge of misleading investors. In the case of AIG, U.S. Congress (2008c) explored the possibility that misleading financial statements and incorrect information had been communicated to shareholders.28 The SEC conducted an inquiry regarding Cassano possibly misleading investors by understating the sharp decline of asset values on AIG’s balance sheet, but eventually decided not to bring criminal charges. In his testimony to Congress, Congressman Christopher Shays stated that: “Company compensation is a telling indicator of a corporate culture detached from larger market realities and the fundamental fiduciary duty to be frugal stewards of other people’s money” (see testimony of Christopher Shays, U.S. Congress, 2008c). Referring to the compensation of Fannie May executives (from 1998 to 2003, CEO Franklin Raines alone took over $90 million in salary and bonuses), Shays added: “In the context of a $6 trillion mortgage securities portfolio, those paydays may seem like small change, but it’s indicative of a prevalent and noxious rot that threatens the moral underpinning of the entire capitalist business model.” The critical issue here is that corporate culture has allowed compensation to be misaligned with value creation for the shareholder. The compensation structure creates incentives for high volatility and uncontrolled risk-taking. We of course do not mean to suggest that top executives should avoid risk-taking on the part of financial institutions at all cost. We have merely outlined that incentives exist to disregard the proper measure of the true levels of risk being assumed. The high degree of trust placed in the concept of risk as a form of indeterminacy that can be controlled and measured with probabilistic models served as a convenient discourse for legitimizing business decisions. The acknowledgement that forms of indeterminacy are not predictable, for instance that AIG could not properly value its CDS portfolio (and associated liabilities), would not provide the same support for business leadership. Compensation needs to be based on a risk-adjusted measure of firm profit. Regarding corporate governance and executive compensation, the recent Dodd-Frank Act only includes measures to encourage management to shift focus from short-term profits to long-term growth, rather than strict guidelines. The Act provides for strengthened independence of compensation committees.29 Unfortunately, this is unlikely to impact the size of Wall Street bonuses, since compensation committees have a vested interest in keeping a high overall compensation level (being themselves executives in the industry). The Act also requires the disclosure of executive compensation as compared with the company’s stock performance over a five-year period. The disclosure might alert shareholders to the issue of a discrepancy between executive compensation and stock performance, but will not prevent the issue from occurring in the first place. Unless bonuses are reduced, or at least assessed on the basis of long-term profits rather than short-term (yearly) results, incentives for risk taking and stock volatility will still exist, and it will be business as usual. For example on December 5, 2007 investors were told that the company was confident in the reasonableness of valuation methods, in spite of the fact that PWC had stated concerns regarding risk management just days earlier. 29 All directors on compensation committees of publicly traded companies are to be independent from executives whose compensation they are supervising. In addition, the committees will have the authority to hire independent compensation consultants. 28 21 The fact that 2010 was a record year in terms of Wall Street bonuses (the highest in history) while economic recovery in the U.S. is still fragile, to put it mildly, bears no good sign for the future. V. The Culture of Risk and Regulation The Deregulation of Financial Markets The advent of a risk society presents many policy issues regarding how to manage, at the political level, the emergence of manufactured risk. New politics and new values are needed to rethink collective choices to be made in light of the implications of the new risks being faced. A real tension exists whereby government officials must acknowledge that they are taking specific risks seriously, while maintaining credibility if the risk turns out to be less serious than expected (Giddens, 1999: 5). Risks originating in the financial sector are no exception and must also be politically managed. As we discussed, financial engineering thrived as an industry and created in the process new forms of risks (including risk to the system as a whole with the potential to disrupt markets with great repercussions for the entire economy) that were not, in spite of experts’ claims to the contrary, controlled nor understood. The political decision in the U.S. was to deregulate markets. The first major triumph of deregulation was the repeal of Glass Steagall in November 1999, with the Gramm Leach Bliley Financial Modernization Act. The Act created a new regulatory status, the Financial Holding Company banks, which allowed commercial banks, securities firms and insurance companies to affiliate under common ownership. All the main commercial banks (Citigroup, JP Morgan Chase, Bank of America) converted so as to be able to offer a complete range of financial services. Financial Holding Companies were under the regulatory supervision of the Federal Reserve, while the SEC had supervision over securities firms and investment banks. The rise of proprietary desks within both commercial and investment banks, and their increasing contribution to profits relative to market making activities, can be partly explained by the repeal of Glass Steagall. The second major deregulation initiative was the Commodity Futures Modernization Act of 2000 (CFMA), which provided that over-the-counter derivatives (privately-negotiated instruments traded outside of an exchange platform) would continue to be substantially unregulated. The Act was initiated at the request of Treasury Secretary Robert Rubin, Federal Reserve Board Chair Alan Greenspan, and SEC Chair Arthur Levitt.30 The third deregulatory trend was the lack of supervision for hedge funds. Until the recent Dodd-Frank Act, hedge funds were under no obligation to disclose balance sheets and income statements, and typically remained secretive about their positions and strategies, even to their own investors. Review of financials by an independent auditor was also not required.31 Rubin, Greenspan and Levitt had issued a letter asking Congress to prevent the Commodity Futures Trading Commission (“CFTC”), the regulator of commodity exchanges, from bringing swaps and other OTC derivatives within its regulatory oversight. 31 The Investment Company Act of 1940 deals with the regulation of investment companies. Unlike their mutual fund counterparts, most hedge funds fell outside the scope of the Investment Company Act of 1940 by availing themselves of applicable exemptions, such as having one hundred or fewer beneficial owner and not offering its securities in a public offering, or because investors were all "qualified" high net-worth individuals or institutions. This explains why 30 22 Many funds did voluntarily register with the SEC. However, limited resources jeopardized the SEC’s ability to properly monitor the activities of fund managers.32 The rationale for unregulated markets was to preserve the competitiveness of U.S. firms. The repeal of Glass Steagall, of course, was hailed as a major victory in this respect. The free-market ideology was also guided by a modern version of Adam Smith's ‘invisible hand’ -- the notion that privately negotiated transactions maximize economic welfare (neoclassical economics provides theoretical justification for this, with the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics) 33. The overarching theme was that trusting the banks’ internal risk management systems was the regulator’s best bet – after all, financial firms were experts in risk management. This is essentially the approach found in the Basel II framework for determining capital adequacy requirement. Another illustration is the decision to leave derivative markets unregulated. The growth of derivative markets was seemingly generating profits for all (for example all market participants were finding the CDS market attractive, at least in the short-term34), so there was no real incentive on the part of the regulator to ensure transparency and appropriate risk management. Derivatives were just ‘machinery’ allowing managers to take intelligent risks. As such, they would be used wisely. The market alone would decide whether a counterpart to a derivative was appropriately capitalized or posted adequate collaterals. Any regulation could entail the standardization of instruments, which would reduce the economic value of derivatives to the parties. Inherent was the assumption that investors would be in a position to make their own determination of the risk / return profile of financial instruments and financial institutions. Of course, all of this depended upon the characterization of risk as quantifiable and fully manageable – the triumph of risk over uncertainty. First, as was evidenced in the crisis, the reliance of the regulator on the firm’s internal risk management proved to be misguided. The hedge funds have deliberately chosen not to raise capital on public markets. Hedge fund advisers had also been exempt from regulation under the Investment Advisers Act of 1940, in spite of the SEC’s unsuccessful attempt to impose mandatory registration. The Investment Advisers Act is a companion statute to the Investment Company Act, and was primarily designed to introduce record keeping, anti-fraud standards to the investment advisory profession. Under the Act, investment advisers must register with the SEC. Hedge fund managers were typically exempt from registration under the private adviser exemption, whereby is exempt from registration any investment adviser who during the course of twelve months has had (1) fewer than fifteen clients and (2) did not hold himself out generally to the public as an investment adviser. 32 It turns out that Madoff himself had voluntarily registered with the SEC in September 2006. Many hedge fund managers had voluntarily registered with the SEC to give the market a higher level of confidence and potentially minimize the amount of due diligence performed by new investors. In spite of some red flags (for instance, the fund relied on a small unknown auditing firm, and the returns were too high to match proclaimed the low risk trading strategy), the SEC failed to detect irregularities. The SEC did not have the resources to review all funds, and tended to focus funds with high-risk trading strategies. Because he claimed to engage in very low risk “plain vanilla” option trading, Madoff did not attract any specific scrutiny. 33 The first fundamental theorem of welfare economics provides that any competitive equilibrium leads to a Pareto efficient allocation of resources. 34 CDSs were successful with commercial banks because they allowed for the removal of credit risk with respect to given corporate bond portfolios without selling the underlying bonds – hence they are a quick and easy way to free-up regulatory capital. CDSs offered investors a way to bet on a company’s credit risk without actually trading or investing in corporate bonds. Insurance companies such as AIG were sellers of CDSs because they could book the spread (the cost of the credit protection) without fully disclosing or backing the payouts that might have to be made under such instruments. Investment banks, of course, were earning fees to design and engineer the instruments (with many variations), while also taking positions under CDS contracts (sometimes very successfully, as Goldman Sachs managed to do). 23 entities that failed had remained in compliance with the SEC’s Consolidated Supervised Entity regime’s rules at all relevant times (there was no violation of capital requirements). The banks did not fraudulently mislead investors regarding the excessive leverage. Second, investors relying on financial statements found that the reporting did not convey an accurate representation of risk levels of the company. Accounting rules demand that a fair value be assessed for balance sheet purposes. Yet in many instances (e.g. when direct market information cannot be used there, for instance if there is an illiquid market), the assessment of a fair value requires judgment calls from management (e.g. regarding discount rates, fair value estimates for assets that are not regularly traded, reserves associated with accounts receivable). Many accounting rules (FASB standards, etc.) do indeed require such judgment calls to be made. Accountants, who are not trained in risk assessment, do not have the expertise to challenge these estimates. The extent to which financial statements are subject to interpretation, management policies, and judgment calls is not something that can be fully appreciated by investors short of disclosing the nature and rationale of those decisions. Financial statements simply do not go into that level of detail. Hence, it is possible for financial statements to give a false representation of the financial condition of a company, and mislead investors regarding risk, without necessarily involving accounting fraud, or the communication of false material information. For example, a proper assessment of AIG’s exposure to the sub-prime market would have required a different valuation of the CDS positions on AIG’s portfolio. Building a fair value assessment is extremely difficult when there are few market comparables due to the highly customized nature of derivative contracts (Joe Cassano made this very point in a December 2007 presentation to investors).35 The AIG valuation process relied upon models36 ascribing probability of default to underlying securities, attempting to price the value of the degree of correlation of default between the underlying mortgages (there was no observable market comparables for pricing the degree of default correlation). To date, there has not been evidence of AIG fraudulently misleading investors to the extent that no clear legal accounting violations could be established -- AIG’s valuations did not breach any corporate accounting standards for balance sheet reporting. Was any false information conveyed to investors regarding a material issue? The company disclosed its methodology, and represented that its fair value assessments were the product of a very thorough set of procedures. Chief risk officer Bob Lewis asserted that there were portfolio reviews for all businesses that carried exposure to any sort of credit exposure, and specifically to mortgages. Chief credit officer Kevin McGinn asserted that the entire “super senior” tranche of CDSs was inspected by the risk committee. Whether proper risk control procedures were in place is certainly a material issue, factual in nature. However, it is perfectly possible for AIG to have followed those very procedures, while still completely underestimating the real cost of the CDS portfolio and the risks undertaken by the company, and misleading investors in the process. The real question of interest to shareholders and investors, whether the methodology used to evaluate risk and price instruments gave a true risk assessment of the business, is altogether a different issue, which involves the determination of what appropriate methodology should have been used. This is a question for which there are no clear-cut legal standards. In fact, as we discussed in our overview of the shortcoming of VaR and other risk models, it is a question for As per the final transcript of the AIG Investor Meeting held on Dec. 05, 2007. AIG apparently used a valuation model originally developed by Moody’s in 1996, the Binomial Expansion Technique model. 35 36 24 which there are no clear-cut theoretical guidelines. If we are to take seriously the epistemic fallacy of the characterization of risk as fully quantifiable and manageable, there are many instances in which a company’s risk officers could (and should) realize that we simply do not have enough information to make informed risk assessments. In this regard, AIG missed the mark in that it failed to disclose to investors that its auditor has expressed reservations regarding its risk controls, and that appropriate models required to value a significant share of its portfolio might not even exist at all, so that radical uncertainty could not be done away with – in short, that risk management was not under control. Yet as we have already discussed, the acknowledgement that forms of indeterminacy are not predictable would not necessarily have been a good political move for AIG executives. After all, the acknowledgement that ‘we simply do not know’ does not justify lofty salaries and bonuses. Further, since executives do not go to jail for making bad business decisions, there is little incentive to be cautious. Legal and accounting rules provide a framework in which this culture perpetuates itself. Poor judgments in risk analysis do not constitute breaches of legal or accounting standards if they are not made in bad faith. As such, the legal system is not sophisticated enough to allow for the proper disclosure of risk to investors. Hence, we come to another characteristic of the culture of risk, the dominance of risk analysis operating, at the policy level, to diverge attention from our radical ignorance about the future.37 The faith that the market would provide sufficient risk disclosures to investors provided support for efforts to deregulate financial markets. Yet the current legal and accounting standards of financial reporting are insufficient to expose deceptive representations of a company’s true risk profile and financial situation. In the absence of material factual misrepresentations to its stakeholders, or gross negligence, there does not seem to be any legal protection for investors against negligent risk management. Bonuses are safe. Organized Irresponsibility In the recent financial crisis, arguably a combination of multiple factors and agents is responsible for the breakdown of markets. Mortgage brokers were engaging in unsound mortgage issuance practices. Investment banks underwrote securitized products and other securities without doing proper due diligence and risk disclosure (as we have already described they had no financial incentive to do so, being compensated on the basis of how many securitized products they could structure and market rather than on proper risk disclosures and the long-term quality of the products). CRAs did not correctly assess mortgage default rates and gave high credit ratings to many securitized products that failed when, as it turns out, much of the economy was hinged on the performance of these products. 38 In this respect, it could be argued that this dominance was not democratically legitimate (Reddy, 1996). There is an unacceptable conflict of interest in the “issuer pay” business model of the CRAs, as revenue is derived from customers that are looking for favorable rather than accurate ratings, so that the CRAs’ independence is highly compromised. The industry is also highly oligopolistic in nature, with only three large CRAs that have come to dominate the business (Moody’s, Standard & Poor’s, and Fitch), which has deprived financial markets of diversity of risk assessment methodologies and opinions. This is partly the responsibility of the SEC. In 1975, the SEC created a major barrier to entry into the rating business by creating the category of “nationally recognized statistical rating 37 38 25 Business executives sought short-term gains and bonuses by taking on unregulated risk (increasing leverage in order to enhance profitability, trading in complex financial instruments, etc.) with no guarantee that long-term results would remain positive. The regulator is also to blame, as the SEC allowed investment banks to have very dangerous leverage levels, where firms could be wiped out with any minor downward market value adjustment to their assets. The lack of transparency in derivatives markets is the result of the deregulatory trend. What we see emerge is a multiplicity of agents and incentives, and an intricately interconnected web of interactions that together produced a full breakdown of markets. As a result of this complexity, specific individual liability cannot be identified because of unclear joint causality. The greatest financial crisis since the Great Depression has not led to a single criminal prosecution or conviction of any high-profile Wall Street executive. Consider, for example, the issue of who bears responsibility for the collapse of AIG. Martin Sullivan was CEO from March 2005 to June 2008. Robert Willumstad took over as CEO in June 2008. According to their testimony to Congress (U.S. Congress, 2008c), AIG did not fail because of poor risk management. It failed because it was “caught in a vicious cycle and hit by a global financial tsunami”. Mr. Willumstad apparently stated that he did not believe that AIG “could have done anything differently”. Executives refused to accept any blame for what happened to the company. Yet there were clear failures on the part of upper management to address serious concerns regarding risk controls. On November 29, 2007, the company’s auditor, PriceWaterhouseCooopers (PWC) informed Mr. Sullivan that AIG could have material weakness relating to the risk management of the Financial Products Division. PWC also told the board’s audit committee in March 2008 that AIG’s risk control group did not have appropriate access to the Financial Products Division. A former SEC enforcement official, Mr. Joseph St. Denis, hired to address accounting issues, resigned over Mr. Cassano’s disregard of concerns voiced regarding the Division’s valuation of liabilities. Mr. Cassano apparently told him that he was “polluting” the accounting valuation process.39 While the company’s executives held specific accounting rules (mark-to-market, which forced the company to book unrealized losses) as the main culprit for its financial woes, it is apparent that a more fundamental problem was that AIG got away from its core competency of insurance without dedicating proper care to its risk management. The company did not have proper models to value its CDS portfolio. AIG executives failed to address material questions and concerns (some of which voiced by the company’s auditor) relating to the valuation of the CDS portfolio, and ignored internal audits and warnings. There was at the very least some negligence in the area of risk managements, for which executives accepted no blame at all. And as it turns out, as we have already pointed out, executives do not go to jail for making bad business decisions. Consider Goldman’s defense to fraud charges related to the structuring and marketing of subprime mortgage CDOs. Lloyd Blankfein’s position (April 2010 testimony to the Senate) was that Goldman was simply acting as a market-maker in these securities. However, this argument does not hold. Market-makers typically engage in both purchases and sales of a particular security, taking advantage of the price difference between "bid" and "offer" prices, while Goldman never had any interest in buying the CDOs that were being marketed -- in fact it was aggressively trying to sell them. We find that instead of selling something that already existed, Goldman was really creating organization” (NRSRO). The Credit Rating Agency Reform Act of 2006 provided specific barrier-reduction provisions so that there are now ten NRSROs. In spite of this, only three major NRSROs still dominate the market. 39 See Congress, 2008c, Chairman Waxman’s opening statement. 26 new products in the form of synthethic CDOs. As such, Goldman was really behaving as an underwriter rather than market-maker (Eisinger, 2011). The SEC settled the Goldman Sachs investigation for a mere $550 million (barely 14 days worth of earnings). The settlement sent the firm’s shares up 4.4 percent. While it will likely result in new disclosure standards in the mortgage and securitization industry (Goldman Sachs is required to increase training for employees who structure or market mortgage securities), and possibly a more scrutinized internal approval process, it did not provide an opportunity for the firm to reflect upon the appropriateness of the conflict of interest associated with the marketing of the CDOs. In fact, the firm admitted no legal wrongdoing, and merely acknowledged that marketing materials contained “incomplete information”. More recently, Sen. Carl Levin has expressed the desire that Goldman Sachs executives be criminally prosecuted. At the time of writing, it is unclear whether such criminal prosecutions will be pursued. The idea that society is now confronted to risks that are not accountable according to the prevailing rules of causality, guilt and liability has been developed in the sociological literature on risk (see for example Beck, 1992, 1995). There is a fundamental change in the attribution of responsibility. Beck's famous term ‘organized irresponsibility’ describes the fact while some destructive consequences of risk might clearly originate in human or organizational decisions, no individual responsibility can be identified. There is first and foremost a problem of causality. Beck (1995: 7) suggests that the issue of causality as a factual and philosophical matter can be quite complex. Considering the example of factory accidents in the nineteenth century as an example, Beck (1995) highlights different possible causes of an accident: the worker who might have stuck an arm in a machine, the engineer who designed the machine, the entrepreneur who was turning the screw for higher production. Another example is that of farmers contaminating soil with chemicals: are the farmers responsible, or are they merely “the weakest link in the chain of destructive cycles”? (Beck, 1992: 32). What of the responsibility of the fertilizer industry, or government authorities that could have limited the production of these toxic chemicals? In both examples there is not necessarily a clear causal link allowing for a clear allocation of responsibility. This is the result of the increasing complexity of production processes, the “systemic interdependence of the highly specialized agents of modernization”, where causal links are difficult to establish (Beck, 1992: 32). We believe the analysis to be applicable to risks arising in the financial sector, and particularly helpful to understand the lack of accountability in the recent financial crisis. Recent Regulation – Dodd-Frank In Beck’s analysis, the disturbed relationship between risk and responsibility can be restored with social agreements leading to new legal standards: “the causality problem had to be, and even in the social area still has to be, settled by agreement (that is, social agreements) worked out through conflict, and legal standards had to be established.” (Beck, 1995: 7). The Dodd–Frank Act signed into law by President Obama on July 21, 2010 was the U.S. regulatory overhaul designed to address the issues uncovered in the financial crisis. In addition to measures that specifically target the mortgage industry40, there are many key provisions in the Act, all designed to prevent a For example, in order to better align the interests of financial institutions that sell securitized products and the investors that purchase them, institutions will be required to retain at least 5 percent of credit risk. New disclosure 40 27 meltdown of the sort that recently occurred, including monitoring systemic risk, reducing excessive growth and complexity, creating more transparency with respect to hedge funds and derivatives. We have already briefly discussed the Act’s restriction on proprietary trading, and some measures addressing the issue of executive compensation and corporate governance. There are other key provisions regarding the regulation of derivatives and the hedge fund industry. The Act gives the SEC and the Commodity Futures Trading Commission the authority to regulate over-the-counter derivatives, and requires central clearing and exchange trading for derivatives that can be cleared, including credit default swaps.41 There are registration requirements for investment advisers to private funds with assets under management of $150 million or more. Hedge funds will have to register with the SEC and disclose assets under management, use of leverage (including offbalance sheet leverage) and other information regarding trading practices. 42 One prevalent focus is to design preventive measures that allow for a better monitoring of systemic risk. The Act specifically contemplates the creation of a regulatory agency designed to look after the stability of the financial system as a whole, the Financial Stability Oversight Council. The Council would be empowered to require that financial institutions that may pose risks to the financial system be regulated by the Federal Reserve. It would make recommendations to the Federal Reserve regarding capital, leverage, liquidity, and risk management requirements. The Act also provides for an orderly liquidation mechanism whereby Treasury, the FDIC and the Federal Reserve would agree to unwind failing financial institutions that are systemically relevant, at the cost of shareholders and unsecured creditors. For this purpose, there are data-gathering measures designed to allow the regulator to consider the financial system as a whole, and aggregate information across institutions to develop systemic scenario analyses. For instance, the SEC is empowered to collect systemic risk data with respect to the hedge fund industry. There are also data collection and publication requirements for derivatives markets, through clearing houses. The SEC would make all of this information available to the Federal Reserve and the Financial Stability Oversight Council. The enactment of Dodd-Frank should have offered an opportunity to reexamine the dominant paradigm of risk management and the triumph of risk over uncertainty. Yet vesting the Financial Stability Oversight Council with the authority to monitor systemic risk might be, to some degree, symptomatic of a failure to do so. Measures that increase transparency are a welcome development, of course, but how will the regulator use the data? What criteria are to be used by the regulator to determine whether an entity is too big to fail, or too interconnected to fail? Systemic risk is not a concept that is currently well understood at a theoretical level. There are currently some attempts to develop formal measures of systemic risk. For example, Adrian and requirements would also ensure that issuers disclose more information regarding the quality of the underlying assets. There are also measures that specifically target the mortgage industry, such as the prohibition of financial incentives for subprime loans and mortgage pre-payment penalties, and the requirement of additional disclosures on mortgages (and specifically variable rate mortgages). 41 The SEC and the CFTC would pre-approve contracts before clearing. The use of a clearinghouse would guarantee a trade and bring much more transparency to derivatives market. Banks will be able to continue trading derivatives, although in certain circumstances will have to conduct this business in a separately capitalized entity. 42 Other information to be disclosed includes counterparty credit risk exposures, trading practices, valuation policies and practices of the fund, types of assets held, and side arrangements or side letters (whereby certain investors in a fund obtain more favorable rights or entitlements than other investors). Hedge funds would also have to have assets audited by public accountants. 28 Brunnermeier (2009) develop the concept of CoVaR as an indicator capturing the marginal contribution of a particular firm to the whole systemic risk.43 The approach attempts to overcome the shortcomings of the VaR method (such as fat tails) by using historical data over a long period of time, from 1986 to 2008. However, the robustness of this methodology remains to be tested. Further, given the complexity of the global financial system, it is unlikely that one single measure will suffice. And, as pointed out by Andrew Lo in his testimony to Congress (Lo, 2008b), the increased complexity and connectedness of financial markets requires new approaches in risk management -- a fundamental shift in our linear mode of thinking, to better understand chaotic behavior and complex systems. This new paradigm remains to be developed – if it can. If the regulator does not really have clear guidelines for decision-making and monitoring systemic risk, the creation of a Council specifically entrusted with the crucial task of identifying and neutralizing financial institutions that are systemically relevant might give the market the wrong impression that risk has indeed triumphed over uncertainty when nothing could be further from the truth. The current environment presents new forms of increasing systemic risk. For instance, although the hedge fund industry as a whole played no significant role in the 2008 financial crisis (see U.S. Congress, 2008b), there is the potential for hedge fund failures to contribute to destabilize the economy because of the size of the industry. It is unclear whether the Council even has authority to unwind hedge funds or make recommendations regarding their leverage and risk management. VI. Conclusions The rise of the culture of risk is closely connected to the massive commodification of risk in financial markets. There are, in our view, three key characteristics of the culture of risk. First is the prevailing paradigm of the notion of calculable risk and the triumph of risk over uncertainty. We have seen that this paradigm still dominates the fields of finance, economics and risk management, in spite of recent and not-so-recent dissenting voices such as Keynes, Minsky, Soros and Taleb. Its influence is pervasive, and has shaped the views of policy makers, regulators and financial firms alike (there are different facets and manifestations, such as the reliance on internal risk management systems developed by market participants, and the view that markets tend towards equilibrium). All of this has operated to diverge attention from issues of radical ignorance, and the shortcomings of relying on probabilistic calculations of the future. Second, the fact that corporate culture has allowed compensation to be misaligned with value creation for the shareholder. And third is the issue of ‘organized irresponsibility’ and the lack of accountability and clear specific individual liability. In the culture of risk, responsibility is diluted as every agent feels that they are only a small (insignificant) piece in a complex system of production. There is a widespread inability to accept blame on the part of executives in financial markets. The default position is to characterize the financial crisis as an uncontrollable sweeping ‘financial tsunami’ rather than confront poor decisions on the part of individual executives. Thinking of culture as a process, we have identified different trends that have led to this cultural shift, in a general context of deregulation: commercial banks and investment banks coming to rely 43 CoVaR is calculated as the VaR of the whole financial system conditional on individual firm being in distress. 29 on proprietary trading to generate a greater and greater fraction of revenue, the end of the partnership-type organizational structure for the major Wall Street firms, and the bonus style compensation structure. These developments have created insufficient incentives for controlled risk-taking on the part of Wall Street executives and traders. The concept of risk as a form of indeterminacy that could be controlled and measured with probabilistic models was simply convenient, in the short term. There was no incentive to challenge it. It will be a matter of time before we can assess whether the Dodd-Frank Act was a successful effort. There are of course welcome developments, such as the increased transparency and the focus on systemic risk. Yet we suggest that the major shortcoming of this regulatory overhaul is the failure to address the key characteristics of what we have described as the culture of risk: first, the epistemic fallacy of risk management; second the corporate culture of executive compensation tied to short-term profits rather than risk-adjusted long term measures of profit; and third, the absence of clear causality leading to individual liability, especially regarding negligent risk management. More fundamentally, the sheer complexity of the Act itself means that its implementation will lead to a further increase in the complexity of financial markets, potential loopholes, etc. The danger here is the continued emergence of new forms of manufactured risk in the risk society. References Akerlof, G. and R. Shiller (2009), Animal Spirits: How Human Psychology Drives the Economy, and Why It Matters for Global Capitalism, Princeton University Press Adrian, T. and Brunnermeier, M. (2009), CoVaR, FRB of New York Staff Report No. 348, available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1269446 Business Week (2006), Inside Wall Street's Culture Of Risk, June 12, 2006, available at http://www.businessweek.com/magazine/content/06_24/b3988004.htm Beck, U. (1992), Risk Society, Sage: London Beck, U. (1995), Ecological Enlightenment: Essays on the Politics of the Risk Society, Humanities Press International, Inc.: New Jersey Bergstresser, D., and T. Philippon, 2006, CEO incentives and earnings management, Journal of Financial Economics 80, 511-529. Bernardo, A.E. and O. Ledoit (2000) “Gain, Loss, and Asset Pricing.” Journal of Political Economy, Feb 108 (1): 144-172. Bernstein, P. (1998), Against the Gods: The Remarkable Story of Risk, Wiley 30 Brooks, C. and H. Kat (2002). The Statistical Properties of Hedge Fund Index Returns and Their Implications for Investors. Journal of Alternative Investments, 5(3): 26-44. Business Week (2006), Inside Wall Street's Culture Of Risk, available at http://www.businessweek.com/magazine/content/06_24/b3988004.htm Cochrane, J. (2005), “Betas, Options, and Portfolios of Hedge Funds.”, available at http://www.slidefinder.net/B/Betas_Options_Portfolios_Hedge_Funds/2799231 (last accessed September 18, 2009). Coles, J. L., N. D. Daniel, and L. Naveen, 2006, Managerial incentives and risk taking, Journal of Financial Economics 79, 431-468. Dequech, D. (2000). Fundamental Uncertainty and Ambiguity. Eastern Economic Journal 26, 1 (2000), 41-60 Dequech, D. (1999), Expectations and Confidence under Uncertainty. Journal of Post-Keynesian Economics 21, 3 (1999), 415-430 Dumortier, A. (2009), Goldman's Partnership Is Bankrupt, http://www.fool.com/investing/dividendsincome/2009/07/15/goldmans-partnership-is-bankrupt.aspx Eisinger (2011), Misdirection in Goldman Sach’s Housing Short, NY Times DealBook, available at http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/06/15/misdirection-in-goldman-sachss-housing-short/ Geanakopolos, J. and J. Farmer (2009) "The Virtues and Vices of Equilibrium and the Future of Financial Economics." Complexity (Jan/Feb), 14(3): 11-38, [CFDP 1647, CFP 1274] Geisst, C. (2004), Wall Street: A History: From Its Beginnings to the Fall of Enron, Oxford University Press, USA Giddens, A. (1990), The Consequences of Modernity, Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA Giddens, Anthony (1999) Risk and Responsibility, The Modern Law Review, 62/1, 1-10 Hall, B. J., and J. B. Liebman, 1998, Are CEOs really paid like bureaucrats? Quarterly Journal of Economics 113, 653-691. Jackson, W. (2009), Economics, Culture and Social Theory, Elgar: Massachussets USA Keynes, J.M. (1972), The General Theory and After Part II: Defence and Development, Collected Writings (London, 1972) Knight, Frank H. (1921/1940): Risk, Uncertainty and Profit, London: London School of Economics, Series of reprints of scarce tracts in economic and political science 16, 5th impression, Boston: Houghton Mifflin 31 Knopf, J. D., J. Nam, and J. H. Thornton Jr. (2002), The volatility and price sensitivities of managerial stock option portfolios and corporate hedging, Journal of Finance 57, 801-812. Lewis, M. (1989), Liar's Poker: Rising Through the Wreckage on Wall Street, Penguin Books, New York Lewis, M. (2010a), The Mystery of Disappearing Proprietary Traders, Bloomberg, available at http://www.bloomberg.com/news/2010-09-30/mystery-of-disappearing-proprietary-traderscommentary-by-michael-lewis.html Lewis, M. (2010b), Proprietary Trading Goes Under Cover, Bloomberg, available at http://www.bloomberg.com/news/2010-10-27/wall-street-proprietary-trading-under-covercommentary-by-michael-lewis.html Lo, A. (2008a) Where do Alphas Come From? A New Measure of the Value of Active Investment Management. Journal of Investment Management, 6(3): 6-34. Lo, A. (2008b) Hedge Funds, Systemic Risk, and the Financial Crisis of 2007. Written Testimony Prepared for the U.S. House of Representatives, Committee on Oversight and Government Reform, Hearing on Hedge Funds, Washington, D.C. Malkiel, B. and A. Saha (2004), Hedge Funds: Risk and Return. Princeton University Working Paper, Princeton, NJ. Minksy, H. (1992), “The Financial Instability Hypothesis” Working Paper No. 74, May 1992, Prepared for Handbook of Radical Political Economy, Aldershot, 1993 Mandelbrot, B. and R. Hudson (2006), The Misbehavior of Markets: A Fractal View of Financial Turbulence, Basic Books: New York. Nell, E. (1998), The General Theory of Transformational Growth: Keynes after Sraffa. Cambridge University Press: New York New York Times (2011), Misdirection in Goldman Sach’s Housing Short, Jesse Eisinger, June 15, 2011, available at http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/06/15/misdirection-in-goldman-sachsshousing-short/ Prins, N. (2004), Other People’s Money: The Corporate Mugging of America, The New Press, New York Reddy, S. (1996), Claims to Expert Knowledge and The Subversion of Democracy: The Triumph of Risk Over Uncertainty, Economy and Society Volume 25 Number 2 May: 222-254 Semmler, W. and L. Bernard (2009), Banking, Complex Securities, and the Credit Crisis, Economic & Political Weekly, VOL 44, No. 13, March 28 - April 03, 2009 32 Soros, G. (2008), The New Paradigm for Financial Markets: The Credit Crisis of 2008 and What It Means, Public Affairs: New York. Stiglitz (2010), Freefall: America, Free Markets, and the Sinking of the World Economy, W. W. Norton & Company Taleb (2007), The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable, Random House: New York U.S. Congress (2008a), Credit Rating Agencies and the Financial Crisis, Hearing before the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform (Serial 110-155), 110th Cong. U.S. Congress (2008b), Hedge Funds and the Financial Market. Hearing before the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform. (Serial 110-210), 110th Cong. U.S. Congress (2008c), The Causes and Effects of the AIG Bailout. Hearing before the House Committee on Oversight and Government Reform. (Serial 110-208), 110th Cong. U.S. Senate (2011), Wall Street and the Financial Crisis: Anatomy of a Financial Collapse, Permanent Subcommittee on Investigations, Committee on Homeland Security and Governmental Affairs, U.S. Senate, 112th Cong. (S. Rep., April 13, 2011) available at http://hsgac.senate.gov/public/_files/Financial_Crisis/FinancialCrisisReport.pdf Veblen, T.B. (1898), Why is economics not an evolutionary science?, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 12(3), 373–97. Wall Street Journal (2010), Fast Traders Face Off With Big Investors Over ‘Gaming’, Scott Patterson, June 29, 2010, available at http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052748703374104575337270344199734.html 33