106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 1. Congress passes a law eliminating the 1995-1997 U.S. Supreme Court term. How might you argue that this is unconstitutional? 1. Congress does not have the express power in the Constitution to eliminate the term of the Supreme Court. In fact, Art. III, § 2 states that “the judicial power of the United States shall be vested in one Supreme Court.” Combined with the structure of the other enumerated powers of the other branches, this statement indicates that the framers’ intent was that the powers of the three branches of government be separate. Although Congress eliminated the 1801 Supreme Court term, this was before the decision in Marbury v. Madison. In Marbury, Justice Marshall stated that “It is emphatically the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is.” Thus, a law eliminating the Supreme Court term would prevent it from saying “what the law is.” Thus, this is against the separation of powers doctrine because it effectively, though temporarily, reduces the number of branches of government to two. 2. Marshall’s decision in Marbury has been criticized as being based on an assumption that the judicial branch should be the ultimate interpreter of the Constitution. Even though the power of judicial review is not expressly stated in the Constitution, what arguments can be made that judicial review of Congressional legislation is nevertheless required in our system of government? 2. The Constitution is silent on the issue of what branch of government should be the ultimate interpreter of the Constitution. Clearly, any branch of the federal government is free to interpret the Constitution. However, in the event of a conflict, for practical reasons there must be some body who is the ultimate arbiter. In a constitutional government based on limited powers, it does not make sense for the branch who makes the laws to be able to interpret their own acts to determine constitutionality. Presumably, this self-review would not be effective since it would be biased and subject to political pressures leading to inconsistency. Supreme Court judges, since they are appointed for life, are not as influenced by the term-to-term political pressures on the Congress. Thus, they can make more consistent determinations of the law, and better protect the interests and rights of the minority (although some might feel they are not counter-majoritarian enough). Also, they are more trained in the law. Thus, review by the Supreme Court tends to lend legitimacy to the governing process as viewed by the population. 3. Assume that Congress passes legislation that eliminates the appellate jurisdiction of the Supreme Court in reviewing state court applications concerning affirmative action. How might this be unconstitutional? 3. Art. III, § 2 states that the appellate jurisdiction of the Supreme Court is subject to “such exceptions, and under such regulations as the Congress shall make.” A broad reading of Ex Parte McCardle would seem to indicate that this power is very broad. However, there are limits on this power, as are evidenced by Klien and Plaut. Specifically, under Klien, Congress may not alter the appellate jurisdiction of the Supreme Court as a “means to an end” of altering the outcome of a particular case. Also, Plaut seems to say that even if the restriction is to a general class of cases, and not ostensibly to a particular case, it could still be an unconstitutional means to violate the Roger W. Martin 1 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 separation of powers doctrine. Here, the legislation affects a whole class of cases. However, it is a very important class of cases that has far reaching implications for several sections of the constitution, including due process and equal protection. Thus, precluding the Supreme Court’s power to decide these cases significantly affects the power of the Supreme Court to “say what the law is.” Marbury. This would prevent the Supreme Court from ensuring uniformity and supremacy of federal law because the states would then be the only interpreters of the Constitution in these areas. Martin. 4. Congress passes federal legislation that would require that the school year in all states be lengthened to 300 days per year (from a current 220-240 days). Congress rests authority for this legislation on the commerce clause. Specifically, Congress finds that the United States is suffering at home and abroad in economic competitiveness. They find that a substantial cause of this disadvantage is poor educational level of American workers when compared to that of the Japanese, who have a 300 day school year. Congress finds that an increased educational level would lead to greater productivity, export volume and product quality. Furthermore, Congress states that due to a need for national uniformity in this area, all states must comply. Is this legislation a constitutional exercise of the commerce power? 4. The commerce power has been described as a broad, plenary power that is “complete in itself, may be exercised to its utmost extent, and acknowledges no limitations other than are prescribed by the Constitution.” Gibbons. As such, Congress has been able to regulate any activity, even a local one, if it has a “close and substantial” relationship to, or affect on, interstate commerce. Wickard. For purposes of determining what is a “substantial” affect, small local affects may be “aggregated” in order to give effect to a larger regulatory policy that would otherwise be defeated if each of the actions were viewed in a purely “local” sense. Id. Furthermore, Congress can regulate totally local activities in order to effectuate its regulation of interstate commerce (bootstrap argument), so long as the means used are “rationally related” to the legitimate end of protection of interstate commerce. Darby. Here, the activities of individual schools appears to be purely local in character. However, viewed in the aggregate, local school activities become a large force. Thus, if they were found to have a “substantial affect” on interstate commerce, it is likely that they could be regulated as a means of effectuating a valid exercise of the commerce power. Typically, in a commerce power case, the Supreme Court will give deference to Congressional findings of fact, in order to determine whether there is a “substantial affect” on interstate commerce, and whether the means bear a “rational relationship” to the legitimate end of regulation. E.g., Perez, and the civil rights cases. However, with the recent decision in Lopez, ( gun free school zone act unconstitutional because it does not have a “substantial affect” on interstate commerce), it is likely that the 300 day school year provision will be struck down as lacking the required “nexus” to interstate commerce. Specifically, the length of the school year is not, on its face, a commercial activity. Also, Congress’ findings of the relationship between the school year and commerce, like the government arguments in Lopez, rely on a long string of inferences. This cuts against a “rational relationship.” Also, this legislation is an attempt to regulate an area which has traditionally been under the police power of the states, leading to a possible 10th amendment conflict. Specifically, since it requires uniform application, this Roger W. Martin 2 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 legislation is counter to the federalist idea of allowing the states autonomy to experiment as “laboratories.” As was seen in New York, Congress may not simply “commandeer the legislative processes of the States by directly compelling them to enact and enforce a federal regulatory program.” Thus, this legislation appears to be beyond Congress’ power to regulate interstate commerce under the commerce clause. As a side note, perhaps Congress could implement the same policy by offering federal monetary or other economic incentives to encourage states to institute this extended school year without compelling them to do so. 5. Suppose Congress places a 10% tax on the profits of companies that hire illegal aliens as part of their work force. Is this law constitutional under the Taxing Power? 5. Congress has the substantive power to tax and spend (on equal footing with the commerce power), limited by the requirement that it be exercised to “provide for the general welfare.” Butler. However, Congress may not impose a tax on an industry as a means of regulating it, where the purpose of raising revenue is merely a “pretext” for accomplishing an illegitimate end (i.e. regulating a local activity that may not be regulated under the commerce power). Bailey. Nevertheless, a federal excise tax is not invalid merely because it deters the activity taxed, or generates negligible revenue, as long as its regulations are “reasonably related” to collection of the tax for a valid tax need. Kahriger. Thus, the answer to this question turns on whether the Congress would have an independent power, for example under the commerce clause, to regulate the hiring of illegal aliens. Assuming that sufficient nexus (“substantial affect”) with interstate commerce can be found, this tax could be sustained under the “necessary and proper” clause. Alternatively, if it generates sufficient revenue, the Supreme Court may simply refuse to do a “pretext” analysis because there appears to be a “not irrational” relationship between the means of the tax and a valid tax need. However, if Congress did not otherwise have the power to regulate a company’s hiring of illegal aliens, this legislation would appear to be a “penalty” (as in Bailey) rather than a tax. Specifically, the tax imposes a heavy burden (10% of profits is very large tax) for departure from a “moral” standard, imposed without regard to how many illegal aliens were employed, but simply whether they were employed at all. As in Bailey, the Court would frown heavily on an apparent attempt to use the taxing power to accomplish an illegitimate end that could not be reached by the commerce power. 6. Assume that Congress passes a permanent nationwide mandatory gasoline rationing law. Congress bases authority for this law on the War Power. Congress reasons that since most of the Saudi Arabian oil fields were torched during the war, and much of the infrastructure supporting the middle-eastern oil industry was destroyed in the war, the result has been a substantial increase (about 40%) in the price of gasoline. Thus, Congress feels this legislation is necessary to correct the adverse affect that gasoline prices are having on the economy, and ensure that it won’t happen in the future. Is this law constitutional under the War Power? 6. Congress has the power, under the “necessary and proper” clause as applied to the War Power, to “remedy the evils which have arisen from [a war’s] rise and progress,” even if the formal hostilities had already ceased. Woods. Here, the Supreme Court would likely have no Roger W. Martin 3 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 problem finding the rational relationship between the means of rationing gasoline and the legitimate end of correcting the adverse affects of war-caused, high gasoline prices on the economy. However, the war power may be limited by the rest of the constitution, namely the 9th and 10th amendments, in the same way that the commerce power is bounded. Although the Court in Woods did not have an opportunity to pass on this question, because the rent control act was clearly needed, they felt that there were natural limits on the War Power due to political influences on Congress. However, in his concurrence, Justice Jackson implied that a War Power regulation probably can not last as long as the effects and consequences of war last because many of the effects are permanent. Here, the gasoline rationing system probably does not need to be permanent. It is likely that in time the price of oil will fall, or at least remain steady with inflation, because the infrastructure destroyed in the middle-east will be rebuilt, resulting in a more abundant supply. Thus, the Court might find that the “permanence” aspect of the legislation is unconstitutional as not being “rationally related” to a legitimate end. 7. Suppose Congress signs an official treaty with Ireland which guarantees that the U.S. will take all steps necessary and proper to assist Ireland in locating an prosecuting members of the IRA for terrorist acts. Pursuant to this treaty, Congress passes a national law requiring that all local law enforcement agencies round up and confine suspected IRA terrorists in the United States, pending determination of their involvement in international terrorism. What is wrong with this legislation under the Treaty Power? 7. Congress has the authority, pursuant to the necessary and proper clause as applied to the Treaty Power, to enact legislation which regulates local activities as a means of giving effect to a valid treaty. Missouri v. Holland. Here, Congress has signed a valid treaty. Thus, it becomes the “supreme law of the land.” However, the means used to give effect to the valid treaty are subject to the limitations of the constitution itself. Reid v. Covert. Specifically, a treaty can not confer power on the Congress which is repugnant to the constitution. Id. Here, the legislation which requires rounding up of a “suspected” IRA members is clearly a violation of the due process clause of the 5th amendment. Also, it may violate equal protection, although we haven’t studied that yet. Thus, the legislation, but not the treaty, is unconstitutional. 8. Assume that California passes a state statute which allowed private companies to collect recyclable materials, but requires them to use a certain in-state processing companies to convert the recyclables into raw material before taking the material out of the state. Further assume that Congress has been completely silent with respect to state recycling regulation (no pre-emption problems). The state justifies this law under the general police power, stating that the shipment of un-processed recyclables out of the state causes littering of the highways, as well as endangers highway travelers because the loads are generally uncovered and unstable. How might this pose a constitutional problem with respect to the dormant commerce clause? 8. In general, in the absence of Congressional action, the states are free to regulate (under their general police power reserved by the 10th amendment) those aspects of interstate commerce that are of such a local nature as to require different treatment from state to state, but not those which Roger W. Martin 4 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 required uniform national treatment (which only Congress can provide). Cooley. However, the modern courts also look to the extent of the burden that an otherwise valid exercise of police power would put on interstate commerce. Thus, the modern approach is basically to 1) determine if the state law is a substantial burden on interstate commerce; 2) determine the state’s interest in the law; 3) 3. determine the federal interest in preventing the burden and protecting interstate commerce with respect to the activity; and 4) balance the state and federal interests. Here, the recycling law appears to put a burden on interstate commerce, because it requires an extra processing step to be performed in-state, where it may be more efficient to ship the recyclables out of state for processing. This may result in increased cost. The state’s interest in the law is purported to be one of health, safety and welfare. However, since the regulations appear to discriminate against out-of-state processors, this would trigger a less deferential review of the purpose and means of the regulation, similar to that in Southern Pacific v. Arizona and Dean Milk. In both of these cases, the Supreme Court found that the safety improvement brought by the particular local regulation was small at best, meaning that although there may have been a “rational relationship” between the regulation and the legitimate state interest in promoting health and safety, it was shaky. In such a case, the balancing of the state and federal interests must go in favor of the federal interest in protecting interstate commerce, particularly if there are “less burdensome alternatives” available to effectuate the same health and safety ends. Dean Milk. Here, the legitimate state interest in reducing litter may be accomplished by the “less burdensome” means of requiring a particular type of shipping container. Also, in the absence of statistics to the contrary, the safety interest of protecting other drivers on the highway appears to bear no rational relation to recycling. Thus, this statute is likely to be unconstitutional as being an undue burden on interstate commerce. 9. Suppose that California passed legislation banning all private citizens from owning handguns and requiring that all citizens turn their handguns into local law enforcement authorities for destruction. If a private citizen brought an action to the Supreme Court claiming that it was a violation the 2nd amendment right to keep and bear arms, how might the Supreme Court analyze the case? 9. Clearly, the Bill of Rights does not directly apply to the states. Barron. Unless the specific right is incorporated into the 14th amendment under the “due process” clause, it is not made applicable to the states, because the 14th amendment does not create additional rights that were not already “privileges” of citizens of the United States. Slaugherhouse Cases. In order to determine whether a specific guarantee of the bill of rights is incorporated by the 14th amendment, the modern court performs “selective incorporation” of “fundamental” rights. Whether a right is “fundamental” for purposes of procedural due process is based on whether that right is of “the very essence of a scheme of ordered liberty.” Palko. In applying this standard, the court looks to the bill of rights to determine if a particular “fundamental” right is implicated by this case, and if so, it becomes incorporated into the 14th amendment along with all of its relevant federal jurisdiction “baggage.” Duncan. So the issue is whether the right to keep and bear arms, specifically handguns, is “fundamental” in the concept of “ordered liberty.” Historically, the private ownership of handguns has been instrumental in preserving civilized order. Handguns have been a equalizing force between law-abiding citizens and criminals. The Roger W. Martin 5 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 law enforcement system relies in part on the deterrence caused by a criminal knowing that a potential victim might be armed in his own home. Thus, ownership of handguns is at “the very essence of a scheme of ordered liberty.” 10. Suppose the state of Tennessee were to enact legislation prohibiting the manufacture and sale of tobacco. Assume that there are several cigarette manufacturers in Tennessee, as well as tobacco growers. Is there a compensable taking with regard to the tobacco growers? With regard to the cigarette manufacturers? 10. This question implicates the 14th amendment’s due process clause, which has been held to provide for “just compensation” for a governmental taking for public use, although that specific language is absent. There are two ways that this could be implied by the 14th amendment: 1) the 14th amendment incorporates 5th amendment’s “just compensation” clause (procedural due process), or 2) “just compensation” is a “fundamental” right of liberty and thus springs out of the 14th amendment itself. Here, there is not a complete “physical taking” of the tobacco or cigarettes themselves. However, a taking does not have to be a complete “physical” taking; while property may be regulated to a certain extent, if regulation goes too far, it will be recognized as a taking. Pennsylvania Coal. Since the value of a crop of tobacco depends on the ability to sell it for cigarettes, this is a possible reduction in value of the tobacco farms. However, it is not destroy profitable use of the land for other farming purposes. Thus, it is not a denial of “all economically viable use” of the land, which would be a per se taking under Lucas. As for the current stock of cigarettes on hand by the manufacturer, they would be diminished in value slightly because they would have to be shipped out of state. However, this is probably not a substantial enough reduction to make the sale of cigarettes outside of the state “commercially impracticable” under Pennsylvania Coal. Also, the cases tend to indicate that reduction in value of land is protected, but do not mention property (such as cigarettes). Thus, there is probably not a compensable taking with regard to either manufacture or sale. 11. Suppose that a San Diego passes a construction regulation that requires an exaction of all developers who construct new housing in Del Mar. Specifically, the developer must pay $1,500 per house for local schools, and also donate “free” labor and materials to build low-cost housing in East San Diego. The local city council states that the purpose behind the exaction is 1) to provide adequate new schooling for the children who will live in the new housing, in order to prevent the overcrowding of existing schools which results in poor education, and 2) to prevent the deterioration of the communities of East San Diego due to abandonment by a stable population. Will these provisions pass constitutional muster under Dolan? 11. Under Dolan, to obtain an exaction from a private business, a city must show that there is a an “essential nexus” between the exaction and a “legitimate state interest”, and the exaction must bear a “rough proportionality” to the interest. Although Dolan specifically dealt with exactions of land, it is still persuasive in this case where we are dealing with exactions of money. We will assume that the need for schools is a “legitimate state interest” by accepting the findings of the council as to the adverse affects of school overcrowding. Here, there is a nexus between the Roger W. Martin 6 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 construction of new houses and the need for new schools. Also, the amount of the exaction, $1,500/home, appears to bear a rough proportion to the need for schools. With regard to the low-cost housing, we can again assume that there is a “legitimate state interest” by accepting the councils findings regarding the need for a stable population. However, the nexus appears to be very weak here. Specifically, there appears to be no relationship between housing in Del Mar and housing in East San Diego. Thus, the absence of an “essential nexus” precludes this portion of the exaction. 12. Assume that the state of Arizona passes an abortion regulation statute that has three main facets: 1) an requirement that the mother wait 72 hours after initial consultation with a doctor to have a discretionary (non-emergency) abortion performed, 2) that the mother be required to watch a video entitled “Safe Alternatives to Abortion” which contains some graphic scenes of aborted fetuses, and 3) a complete ban on all post-viability abortions that are not “medically necessary.” Are each of the provisions of this statute constitutional? 12. Although the landmark case of Roe v. Wade held that a woman’s right to choose to terminate her pregnancy was “fundamental,” triggering “strict scrutiny” of the regulation of abortion before viability, the Supreme Court has since abandoned the fundamental/strict scrutiny approach of Roe and substituted an “undue burden” standard in it’s place. Casey. The present state of the right to an abortion, as stated in Casey, is that 1) a woman has a constitutional right to seek abortion before viability without undue interference from the state; 2) the state has the power to restrict, and even proscribe non-life threatening abortions after viability; and 3) the state has legitimate interests in the health of the mother and the life of the fetus from conception. According to Casey, an undue burden exists, and therefore a provision of the law is invalid, if its purpose or effect is to place a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion before the fetus attains viability.” This is a fairly high standard, given that a 24 hour waiting period was found to be burdensome, but not unduly burdensome. Implicitly the right to seek an abortion before viability is now something less than “fundamental,” but still requiring special constitutional protection. With regard to the 72 hour waiting period, it is clearly more burdensome than the 24 hour waiting period in Casey. However, the rationale behind Casey’s upholding that provision, namely that the woman would only be required to make two trips to the doctor, seems to apply here. The absolute time between initial consultation and performance of the procedure does not appear to be significant. Thus, it will probably be sustained. With regard to the mandatory viewing of a graphic video, Casey held that an informed consent requirement, which required mothers to be advised of the alternatives to abortion, was constitutional. However, the information provided to the mother in Casey was not as graphic as that required by this statute. As Justice Stevens stated in his concurrence, there may be an undue burden when the state attempts to “wear down” the resistance of the mother in order to further its interest in preserving the life of the child. Thus, this provision is probably not constitutional. As to the complete ban on non-”medically necessary” abortions after viability, even Roe conceded that the state interest was compelling enough to proscribe discretionary abortions after viability. Although the meaning of “medically necessary” is unclear, it is Roger W. Martin 7 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 probably broader than “non-life threatening,” and thus not an undue burden on a woman’s right to seek an abortion. 13. Suppose San Diego passed a law forbidding co-habitation of non-related adults out of marriage. The city states that the purpose behind the regulation is to reduce the number of illegitimate children who are born, thus reducing the heavy burden on the state when the couples break up and can no longer support the child. What issues/problems does this pose and how might the Supreme Court resolve them? 13. In Moore v. East Cleveland, the Supreme Court held that a city can not pass zoning laws forbidding “extended” family members from living together. The Court applied a “more than deferential review,” indicating that the right of distant-related persons to live together was not “fundamental” and so did not trigger “strict scrutiny.” Here, the co-habitating couple is even less related than those in Moore. However, one can analogize to the reasoning in Eisenstadt, which extended the right of contraception to non-married couples. In Eisenstadt, the Court stated that there was no logical distinction between married and non-married couples when it came to birth control. Thus, the same reasoning could apply here - there is no logical distinction between distant-relations and un-married cohabitating couples when it comes to the right choose who to live with. The resulting right would probably not be “fundamental,” (not “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty”) and would probably be even less important than that of Moore. However, it would still probably trigger more than a “rational relationship” review. Here, the city’s reasoning may not even pass the rational relationship review because whether unmarried couples physically reside together or not does not have any logical affect on pregnancy rates. It is well known that people who live apart often become pregnant. Thus, the law is likely to be unconstitutional. 14. Assume that the divorce rate for couples in California is 50%. The state has found that divorces are a heavy burden on the judicial system, as well as the economy because they lead to population instability. In an effort to reduce the divorce rate, California passes a law that requires couples seeking a marriage license to take a 2-hour, written personality compatibility test. The test would rank each person in several different areas of personality (shy vs. outgoing, loud vs. quiet, etc.). The individual results would be provided to the couple, along with a statistical comparison of their answers. The test will be used for informational purposes to the couple only, not to deny a marriage license. The state hopes that this practice will bring incompatibility to the attention of potential married couples, and cause them to reconsider marriage if the test indicates incompatibility. What constitutional issues does this raise, and how might the Supreme Court resolve them? 14. In Zablocki, the Court held that a state may not pass a law which “directly and substantially” interferes with the “fundamental” right to marry in the absence of a “sufficiently important” state interest. Although they found the right to marry was “fundamental,” the Court did not use a “strict scrutiny” review, but rather a “critical examination” review, which is something less than strict scrutiny. “Critical examination” means that the law cannot be upheld Roger W. Martin 8 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 unless it is supported by sufficiently important state interests and is closely tailored to effectuate only those interests. Here the state interest in preventing divorce appears to be legitimate, and sufficiently important. Thus, one key issue is whether the test “directly and substantially” interferes with the right to marry. Since the results of the test are used only for informational purposes of the couple, and not for denial of a marriage certificate, it probably does not substantially interfere with the right to marry. (Similar to the information provided to a woman seeking an abortion in Casey, which was found not to be “unduly burdensome.”) However, the test takes two hours to complete, and so might be seen to deter some people from getting married who might otherwise be compatible and never divorce. If it is found to be a substantial interference, the test requirement must be found to be closely tailored to effectuate only the state’s interest in preventing divorce. If the state had statistics to show the cause-effect relationship between divorce and test results, it would have a good argument that the test was closely tailored. However, it seems intuitive that personality compatibility is only one small factor in the success of a marriage. Thus, the regulation seems to be underinclusive. Also, if the test would deter people from getting married who would otherwise have a successful marriage, it would be overinclusive. Thus, unless the state can show a valid statistical correlation between test results and divorce rate, the means-end fit is probably not close enough to pass the “critical examination” level of review. 15. Hawaii has a statute that bans same sex marriages. The state’s justification is that to allow same sex marriages would have a harmful affect on tourism because families would be deterred from vacationing in a “refuge for homosexuals.” What constitutional problems does this implicate? 15. Although the right to marry was found to be “fundamental” in Zablocki, the Court in Bowers v. Hardwick stated that there is no constitutionally protected fundamental right of homosexual sodomy. The Court in Bowers reasoned that homosexuality has been banned and discouraged for so long that it can not be said to be “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty” (Palko) or “deeply rooted in the Nation’s history and tradition.” (Moore). Bowers marked an explicit reluctance by the court to recognize new “fundamental” rights that are not found in the Const. because of the “slippery slope” which might lead to finding a fundamental right to adultery, incest, etc. Here, the slippery slope argument might lead to bigamy. If the same reasoning is applied, the Court would find that there was not a “fundamental” right to homosexual marriage, and the statute would stand. However, there is a chance that the Court might frame the issue more broadly, as a privacy right to make intimate personal decisions without undue interference from the government (similar to Blackmun’s dissent in Bowers). Phrased in this manner, the right might be found to be fundamental, triggering something close to “strict scrutiny” (like in Zablocki). In that event, the Court would almost certainly strike down the statute as being tailored to broadly. For instance, even if a relationship between tourism and the ban on homosexual marriage can be shown, it is likely that it will actually increase tourism among the gay population. 16. The fire department of a large metropolitan city is considering instituting some new uniform regulations. One of these new regulations is that no firefighter, male or female, Roger W. Martin 9 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 shall be allowed to wear an earring of any kind while on duty. The fire department states that wearing of earrings while on duty interferes with the readiness of the fire department because it prevents rapid donning of fire-fighting headgear. Also, the fire department is considering another regulation that off-duty female firefighters may wear only a “tasteful stud” earring, and that off-duty male firefighters may not wear any earrings whatsoever. The fire department reasons that this latter requirement will promote esprit de corps, as well as promote a professional image to the public. What constitutional issues do these regulations raise? 16. The right of personal appearance by police officers was addressed in Kelley v. Johnson, where the court held that police officers do not have a fundamental right to wear their hair long. The court reasoned that although the government might not have the right to regulate the personal appearance of private citizens, an exception for police officers existed. As such, the regulations of a police officer’s personal appearance need only meet the “mere rationality” standard. A fire fighter is probably indistinguishable from a police officer in this regard. Both professions involve public service, high level of training, danger, and unique public trust. As such, the arguments of Kelley appear to be applicable here. With regard to the wearing of earrings when on-duty, the department’s interest in safety is clearly legitimate. Banning earrings on-duty is a rational way to accomplish safety because of the delay that might ensue if the earring gets stuck on the headgear, or the burn that might occur in a fire if the earring becomes too hot. With regard to the off-duty regulation of earrings, it is harder to justify the rational relationship. For instance, it is unlikely that a fire fighter must keep a certain appearance to be more visible to the public (as was the case in Kelley). Also, it is doubtful that the public image of fire fighters relies much on whether they wear an earring off-duty. However, it the department were to introduce credible evidence to the contrary, it is likely that the Court would simply defer to their findings, and uphold the regulation. 1. A local school enacts a “tracking” policy by which students that test above a certain score on a standardized test, or maintain their GPA above a predetermined level, are allowed to take advanced college prep classes, whereas all other students are required to take remedial level courses. Does this policy pose a procedural due process problem for a student who does not otherwise qualify for the advanced classes, yet still wishes to take them? 1. Education, like welfare benefits in Kelly, is not a mere charity but a means to promote the general welfare. It affects future education, and ultimately the ability to work. Thus, there would be a “liberty” or “property” interest in education. Assuming that the state constitution has been interpreted to provide a “fundamental” right of education, there would be a “legitimate claim of entitlement” to education. Roth. Thus, this interest in education is strong enough to trigger procedural due process under the 14th amendment. However, here the state is not denying education to the non-qualifying children, it is merely denying them an advanced level of education. So there would probably not be a procedural due process problem since there is no real “taking” here. As a side note, there may be an equal protection problem if the program can be shown to discriminate based on a forbidden classification. Roger W. Martin 10 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 2. Andrew is arrested for shoplifting. He is not charged, but instead is released, and his name is put on a police blotter list as being arrested for shoplifting. The list is published in the local newspaper, and Andrew, who is a respected businessman, is greatly embarrased. He maintains that he is innocent. Andrew brings a defamation action against the city for having his name published as being a shoplifter. One of the grounds of the suit is that publishing his name as a shoplifter, without conducting an evidentiary hearing first, violated his procedural due process rights under the 14th amendment. What is his likelihood of success on this count? 2. Negligible. Although the court in Roth indicated that damage to reputation may be a sufficient infringment on a person’s “liberty” interest to trigger procedural due process protection, the court has since stepped away from that view in Paul v. Davis. Thus, the damage to Andrew’s reputation does not give rise to a cause of action for violation of due process. 3. What must the court consider in a procedural due process case when determining what type of hearing is required before the state may “take” a person’s liberty or property? 3. According to the court in Matthews, “due process is flexible and calls for such procedural protections as the particular situation demands.” Thus, a balancing approach is necessary. The court must balance 1) the private interest that will be affected by the official action, 2) the risk of an erroneous deprivation of such interest throught the procedures used, and the probable value, if any, of additional or substitute procedural safeguards, and 3) the government’s interest including the function involved and the fiscal and administrative burdens that the additional or substitute procedural requirements would entail. 4. Hollandia Dairy is a local dairy that is dedicated to the production of local milk in an environmentally safe and friendly manner. The dairy uses only cardboard milk cartons to distribute its milk. The state passes a law requiring all milk manufacturers to package the milk in plastic containers. As a justification for this law, the state claims the purpose is to “promote the safety and integrity of the milk supply,” and “to conserve natural resources.” Hollandia Dairy brings an equal protection action, claiming that the law arbitrarily discriminates against manufacturers who choose to use paper product cartons. What is their likelihood of success? 4. This is a case of equal protection with respect to economic issues. In this arena, the court normally gives wide deference to the purpose and findings of the legislature, subjecting the law to a mere rationality standard. Railway Express. Here, the avowed purposes stated by the state appear to be legitimate. The state, under its general police power, has an interest in maintaining the health of the food products produced there, as well as preserving natural resources. Use of plastic (hermetically sealed) cartons may result in better preservation of the milk. The banning of paper product cartons would tend to preserve trees. Thus, there appears to be a rational relationship between the classification (paper vs. plastic) and the legitimate state interest. As a Roger W. Martin 11 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 side note, there may be a privileges and immunities problem if this discriminates against out of state manufacturers. 5. Suppose the state of California were to pass a law requiring all government employees having greater than 28% body fat (for males) or 32% body fat (for females) enroll in a state-sponsored physical fitness program (at no cost). If the overweight employees did not come down below the maximum body fat percentage in one year, they would be laid off. If they are medically diagnosed as “obese” (a medical condition), then they will be offered limited medical treatment for obesity for a period of one year after being laid off. The state gives as the purpose for this law “preserving the dwindling funds available for medical insurance for state employees.” Comment on the constitutionality of this law with regard to equal protection. 5. This law is one of social/economic welfare. An important threshold issue is whether the overweight people are members of a suspect class, because that will determine the level of scrutiny applied. According to the Carolene Products footnote, a suspect class may be comprised of a “discrete and insular minority” who has a history of past discrimination, is subject to frequent stereotyping, and share an immutable characteristic. Here, the overweight people do have a history of discrimination and are subject to frequent stereotyping. However, they are probably not an under-represented minority that keep to themselves and are politically disenfrancished. Also, the characteristic of being overweight is not strictly immutable. Thus, they are not a suspect class. As such, the standard of scrutiny is mere rationality. The state has a legitimate interest in preserving the medical insurance fund, and is reason to believe that overweight persons are a disproportionate drain on that fund. Thus, the classification is rationally related to the legitimate state interest. Although the cut-off for weight may seem somewhat arbitrary, and that other persons may have serious medical conditions, there is no requirement that all of the evils be regulated or none at all. Railway Express. 6. The selective service act, as it now stands, requires all males between the ages of 18 and 27 to register for the draft in case of national emergency. It does not require females to register. What are the arguments for and against the constitutionality of the Act? 6. Discrimination based on sex has been held to trigger an intermediate level of scrutiny. Hogan. This is true whether the discrimination is against males or females. Id. For intermediate level scrutiny of gender discrimination, the classification must be “substantially related” to the acheivement of an “important governmental interest.” Craig. The first challenge to this law failed because the court held that the important governmental purpose was to prepare the nation for combat, and since females were not allowed in combat roles at the time, the classification was substantially related to the important purpose. Goldberg. However, since 1980, when Goldberg was decided, women’s roles in combat have increased dramatically. Women are now able to fly combat planes, drive combat vehicles, sail on combatant ships, and perform limited ground support roles. Thus, the classification would seem to bear a less substantial relation to the interest in raising combat troops because men and women are more similarly situated with respect to military service today. Roger W. Martin 12 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 7. Suppose New York passed a law allowing the state to prosecute a pregnant woman for smoking cocaine based on the damage to her unborn child. What constitutional issues of equal protection are presented here, and how would the court likely resolve them? 7. The court has held that gender based discrimination is subject to an intermediate level of review where the classification must be “substantially related” to the acheivement of an “important governmental interest.” Craig. However, the court has also stated that a classification that is not based on gender, as such, is subject only to a lesser standard of review. Aiello. In Aiello, the court stated that a classification such as this was not invidious discrimination against females because the classification was between “pregnant females” and “non-pregnant persons.” Here, the classification could be characterized as “pregnant female crack smokers” and “non-crack smokers.” Since the latter category comprises an equal number of men as women, the classification is not one of gender, per se. Thus, a mere rationality standard applies. 8. Assume that the city of San Diego is considering implementing a plan in which black children at certain elementary schools will be paired with black teachers. The program is intended to provide the students with positive role models from their own cultural background, and improve their interest in school. What constitutional problems does this program raise? 8. The court has held in Brown that separation/segregation in state schools is inherently unequal. The court reasoned that separation of races solely because of their race tends to stigmatize them as being inferior or needing special treatment. However, the reasoning of Brown has been criticized as being based on outdated and inaccurate social science data. It is unclear whether a segregation program would have the same effect today. Also, one may attempt to justify it as a remedy for past discrimination if administered properly. In any event, the present court is unlikely to look favorably on such a situation given the long history of unfavorable segregation in the country. 9. Suppose California were to pass a law requiring all public school teachers to become U.S. citizens after teaching for 7 years. The state defines the purpose of the law as “promoting fundamental American democratic values in children.” What constitutional issues does this law raise? 9. This law would raise an issue of equal protection based on the classification of teachers as citizens or non-citizens, and discriminating against the latter. Under Graham, classifications based on alienage normally trigger strict scrutiny. However, Dougall and Foley carve out a limited exception for positions that carry out a “governmental function” or a “political function.” If teachers are classified as carrying out a “governmental function”, as is implied by the state’s avowed purpose for the law, then the law would only receive rational basis review. The state has a strong interest in educating its children in democracy. Requiring teachers to be Roger W. Martin 13 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 citizens (once they have met residence requirements) seems to be rationally related to that end because a citizen teacher is likely to have a basic understanding of the democrating process, and agree with it. However, if law were to have to withstand strict scrutiny, it would certainly fail because it would be too underinclusive, and too overinclusive. That is to say that many citizen teachers are ignorant as to civics, and many foreign teachers are able to teach the subject well. Thus, it would not be narrowly tailored enough, even if the state interest in teaching democracy was found to be compelling. 10. Suppose the federal government wished to enact a statute denying federal welfare benefits (AFDC aid to families with dependent children) to families with illegitimate children. Would this be constitutionally permissible? 10. No. Although the 5th amendment contains no explicit equal protection clause applicable to the federal government, the court has held that there is an implied clause identical to that of the 14th amendment. Also, although the federal government might have more leeway with respect to discriminating against alien children (due to the INS power), it does not have the same power with respect to illegitimate children. The court has held that a standard of intermediate scrunity applies in reviewing equal protection challenges to law discriminating on the basis of legitimacy. Clark. Here, the federal interest may be to preserve the AFDC budget, to promote marriage, to deter teen pregnancy, and to equalize benefits across state borders. None of these purposes seems to rise to the level of “important governmental objective.” Even if they do, the classification is not “substantially related” to the objectives. Parents probably do not take AFDC benefits into account when getting pregnant out of wedlock. Also, divorces are not prevented due to the absence of federal aid. 11. A state welfare benefit calculation law provides that persons receiving federal aid (such as AFDC) are granted less “need” for purposes of determining the amount of their monthly benefit check. The state purpose in this law is to conserve scarce welfare resources at the state level, since the families in question are already receiving federal help. Does this statute pose a constitutional problem if it can be shown that 87% of all AFDC recipients are minorites? 11. For purposes of equal protection analysis, the constitution only provides protection against purposeful discrimination. Washington v. Davis. Furthermore, naked statistics, without more are insufficient to show purposeful discrimination, despite the disparate impact. Id. This law is facially neutral, and there are no facts supporting a claim of inequitable administration. The only claim is disparate impact. However, 87% minority composition of AFDC recipients appears to be too ambiguous an indicator of purposeful discrimination. If there were statements in the legislative history indicating that the law was based on a discriminatory motive, that would suffice to show purposeful discrimination. Arlington Heights. However, a mere knowledge that the statute might have a discriminatory impact as a side effect is not sufficient. Feeney. The equal protection clause “guarantees equal laws, not equal results.” Id. Roger W. Martin 14 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 12. Suppose that the local district court finds that the city of San Diego has redefined school district lines such that almost no white students are included in the school attendance zones for one particular inner city school. What reasoning must the court follow in order to take remedial action? What remedial action would be proper? May the court include suburban schools from the Poway school district (different than San Diego City school district)? When would the remedies end? 12. The court, in order to create remedies, must find that there is de jure discrimination, and then must eliminate it “root and branch”. Swann. The court may find evidence of this de jure (purposeful) discrimination by the way in which the zone lines were gerrymandered to exclude white students, if they concluded that there could be no other explaination for the zoning change, which there probably isn’t. Keyes. Furthermore, if de jure discrimination is found within one particular area of the district, here the one school, the court may presume that it exists elsewhere in the district, and take remedial action district-wide. Id. The court may use busing, pairing of schools, and realigning school attendance zones to even out the student race ratio. Swann. However, the court may not force the state to spend money on a “magnet school” in the inner city in order to attract white students from the suburbs unless there is a finding that the de jure discrimination caused the “white flight” from the area. Jenkins. Also, the court may not force integration and busing of other students from outlying areas in the Poway school district because it is a different school district, and no de jure discrimination has been found. Milliken. The remedies would continue to be court supervised until the San Diego City school district could show that it has complied with the operation of a “unitary” school system for a reasonable time, and provides evidence of a good faith effort to continue in the future. Dowell. Or, the court could withdraw from one area of supervision if it is satisfactory, and continue to supervise in other areas, even if the school district is not “unitary” yet. Freeman. 13. Suppose that the federal government instituted an affirmative action program for admissions to the FBI academy. Under this program, 10% of the students admitted each year were required to be “disadvantaged.” For the purposes of admissions, a white student could prove that he was disadvantaged by providing evidence of his background. However, minority races were presumed (rebuttably) to be disadvantaged. Is this program constitutional? 13. No. The supreme court has held that the proper standard to apply to race based discrimination, regardless of which race it discriminates against, is strict scrutiny. Croson. Furthermore, the court has held that the equal protection clause of the 14th amendment is implied into and coterminous with the 5th amendement. Adarand. Here, the program includes a strict quota of 10%. Such a quota system in education admissions was held to be invalid in Bakke. It has also been held to be unconstitutional in a commercial construction setting in Croson. Furthermore, the federal government would have to prove actual past discrimination by the FBI against minorities by means of specific proof in order to implement any remdial measures. Id. Thus, the program as stated here is clearly unconstitutional. Perhaps the government could consider race as one ingredient of the admission program, in order to promote diversity in the FBI. Bakke. Roger W. Martin 15 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 14. Suppose that the San Diego school board found that its budget was dwindling, and it was unable to keep a high quality level of education in every school, but it was still able to keep a minimum level of education in every school. As a measure intended to subsidize schools, suppose the city plans to institute a plan in which certain schools are “tuition based” schools. It would cost the parents money to send their children to these public schools, which would, as a result, have better facilities, and higher skill level teachers. If the parents are unable or unwilling to pay the tuition, they may still attend their neighborhood school as normal. Comment on the constitutionality of this plan. 14. The court has held that the inequitable distribution of a fundamental right which is either explicit or implicit in the constitution violates equal protection, regardless of which class of persons it burdens. Rodriguez. However, it has also found that education, or at least the right to a better-than-minimal education, is not a constitutionally guaranteed fundamental right. Id. Furthermore, it has found that wealth, and thus poverty, is not a suspect class, and therefore allowed a state to fund school districts with local property taxes. Id. Here, the situation is similar, except that the subsidization comes only from the parents of the students, rather than each homeowner in the school district. Also, since the students whose parents can not (or will not) pay the tuition will still receive at least a basic level of education, there is no total deprivation of education (which may trigger a more rigorous level of scrutiny - Plyler). There is a permissible government objective here - providing a better level of education for its citizens. And the means chosen, i.e. tuition, bear a rational relationship to the accomplishment of that legitimate objective. As such, it should easily pass muster under Rodriguez. 15. In terms of case law, constitutional provisions, and good policy, should education be found to be a “fundamental right” guaranteed by the federal constitution? 15. There are several persuasive arguments in favor of finding a fundamental right to education. First, as was stated in Plyler v. Doe, education is not just a privilege. By depriving a student of education, a law would foreclose any means by which the child may elevate himself into a functioning member of society. Also, there is a fundamental right to educate your children as you see fit - Society of Sisters. So it would not be a great leap to find that education itself is a fundamental right. Furthermore, in constitutional terms, the 1st amendment right to free speech is meaningless if the population is illiterate. Also, an educated populace is better able to exercise the right to vote, and equal access to voting has been found to be a fundamental right. Harper. Moreover, the government itself compels school attendance, which is evidence of its view of the fundamental nature of education. Lastly, most states, and those whose constitutions were drafted by the drafters of the federal constitution, have found their constitutions to provide a fundamental right of education. 16. Suppose California were to pass a law denying free public education to children who come into the state solely for the purpose of education, and who therefore live apart from their parents. However, the child, once he reaches age 18, may apply for Roger W. Martin 16 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 residency status after living in the state 1 year, and then be able to qualify for the free (or at least subsidized) education. Comment on the constitutionality of this law. 16. Again, the supreme court has held that education is not a fundamental right. Rodriguez. These students presumably have access to free education where their parents live, and are moving to California only for the purpose of attending California schools. However, this law also poses a problem with relation to the fundamental right to travel which was found to exist in Shapiro. There, the court found that a state may not condition the reception of welfare benefits on being a state resident for >1 year because it impermissibly burdened the fundamental right of travel. Such a waiting period was deemed to be a “penalty” on the right of travel in Maricopa. However, since education is not as basic a need as welfare or medical benefits, Shapiro and Maricopa can be distinguished on their facts. The loss of free education in a foreign state for a certain period, especially when it is available at home, is not a strong “penalty” which has been defined as a denial of “vital government benefits and privileges.” Maricopa. Also, the state has a strong interest in preventing itself from becoming the unreimbursed supporter of other state’s children. Thus, the right to a free education here is only postponed, and not eliminated so it probably passes constitutional muster, similar to the 1 year waiting period for use of the courts to divorce an out of state resident in Sosna. 17. Suppose that the automobile union threatened to go on strike nationwide to stop production of parts that are used in cars, and coincidentally used in combat vehicles. Given the present situation in Bosnia, and the President’s interest in maintaining a strong military presence abroad, could a seizure of the auto parts manufacturing by the President (without prior consent of Congress) in order to avert the strike be constitutionally permissible? 17. No. There is a separation of powers problem. The president’s domestic powers are limited. Art II, § 1 states, “The executive power shall be vested in a President.” Thus, most of his power is implied, however it must be “executive” (carrying out laws) in nature, rather than “legislative” or “judical.” Here, the action seems to be more than executive in nature, and very legislative - a function which. In the Steel Seizure Case, the supreme court held that the President may not unilaterally order steel industry plants to be seized (without the consent of Congress) and put under gov’t control in order to prevent a strike. As in that case, the present seizure would not be justified under “commander in chief” power because the theater of war connection is too remote. Justice Jackson has stated that where the president is acting in opposition to Congress, his powers are at their narrowest, supported only by his expressly granted constitutional powers, and then still limited by any overlap Congress may have. There is an argument that a long-standing Presidential custom or habit of action over time in the face of Congressional consent leads to a “gloss” on the enumerated or implied powers of the president, unless Congress takes action to demonstrate their disagreement. However, that would be flatly rejected here in the face of the Steel Seizure Case. 18. Suppose that American civilians in Bosnia are suddenly taken hostage by an overrun of the U.S. Embassy. Would the president have the power to send in a covert Roger W. Martin 17 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 rescue force without consultation with even the leaders of Congress? What of the War Powers Resolution? 18. Probably. Although Congress has the exclusive ability to declare war, the President also has brad foreign powers. - Curtiss Wright. The President is in the best position to make decisions on rescue missions since he is the sole embodiment of U.S. foreign power. Id. Historically, the President has acted frequently in this manner in the presence of initial silence by Congress, usually justifying the action on his ability to protect the U.S. from foreign attack. The Prize Cases. Also, the War Powers Resolution has explicitly delegated the President the power to defend against hostile attack on U.S. forces, territories or possessions. It is unclear whether this is such an attack because the embassy is not technically a U.S. territory or possession. Perhaps the presence of U.S. Marines and government officers (Ambassadors) is sufficient. However, the War Powers Resolution requires that the President consult with Congress before committing troops to hostilities, if possible. Here, it would probably be possible to do so, since the attack has already happened. However, there are several constitutional problems with the War Powers Resolution that bring its legitimacy into question. For example, §5(b)(2) requires the president to withdraw troops within 60 days, unless Congress extends that period. This appears to be a legislative veto (no presentment) of the sort shot down in Chadha. Similar problems are presented by §5(c) which allows Congress to jointly pull any troops out of any hostile zone at any time. Thus, it is unclear that if the President committed troops that Congress could take any action to prevent it. In any event, it is unlikely that the War Powers resolution will be successfully challeged because of lack of standing, and political question. 19. President Clinton is being sued for alleged sexual harrassment of an aide while he was Governor of Arkansas. Does the President have a general immunity from civil liability from this charge? What about a general “executive privilege” from being subject to service of a subpeona duces tecum to produce any records concerning this issue? 19. No. Although the Supreme Court has held that the president has an absolute immunity for civil liability arising from within the outer boundaries of his official acts, (Nixon v. Fitzgerald), this only applies to acts during his pendency as President. The source of the immunity is “rooted in the constitutional tradition of separation of powers and supported by our history.” Id. This event happened before he became President. However, even if it did occur during his Presidency, it is arguable that the immunity would not apply because the alleged act would fall clearly outside of the outer boundaries of his official acts. Clearly, a person who sexually harrasses another does not do it pursuant to any official authority. However, there is the counter argument that it would divert his attention away from more pressing national and international matters, and thus should at least wait until he is out of office. Also, civil liability is not necessary to keep the President honest because of other concerns such as impeachment, the press, re-election, and personal reputation. As to the tapes, the court has held that the President has “executive privilege” to refuse to disclose confidential information related to his official duties, but it is outweighed by interest of justice in a criminal proceeding. - Nixon Tapes Case. Although this is only a civil proceeding, the same reasoning seems to apply. Since the requested tapes do not Roger W. Martin 18 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 contain national secrets, there is no reason to allow the privilege here (other than perhaps attorney client privilege if it applies). 20. Suppose that a local Big Bear market has decided that based on the recent level of criminal activity involving black gangs, including several shooting deaths on its premises, it will no longer serve any black males under the age of 30, and will furthermore press charges for trespassing if any black male under 30 enters the store. Is this constitutional? 20. There appears to be blatant racial discrimination here, the kind which would certainly fail constitutional muster if practiced by the state or federal government. However, there must be some state action for the law to apply, because the constitution does not protect against private discrimination. It has been held that a private citizen that performs a traditionally public function is subject to constitutional regulation. Marsh. However, grocery stores are not really public functions, even though they are open to the public. If the grocery store were leasing the land from the government, or taking advantage of any other mutually beneficial government services, then there would be state action under the nexus theory of Burton. However, there are also no such facts related here. The best argument for state action is a broad reading of Shelley in which the court held that using the power of the courts to enforce a discriminatory policy may be viewed as state action. Here, the grocery store wishes to use the courts to enforce trespassing violations. That may be sufficient to constitute state action. If that were the case, this policy would certainly fall under strict scrutiny as being overbroad. 21. Suppose that the Congress passes a statute subsidizing basic prenatal care for pregnant illegal immigrants. Jim, a federal taxpayer, brings an action in federal court challenging this law, claiming that it violates the immigration and naturalization power of Congress. He claims that he has proper standing as a taxpayer because this will result in an increase in his taxes. Is he correct? 21. No. For a taxpayer to have standing on the basis of being a federal taxpayer, he must show that the statute being challenged rests on the taxing and spending power, and that it violates specific constitutional limitations on the taxing and spending power (rather than just a general limitation on the constitutional power). Flast. The policy behind this judicially based (not constitutionally limited) rule is that we don’t want a nation full of private attorneys general clogging up the courts challenging each and every law. Here, the challenge rests on an exercise of the spending power. However, it does not allege violation of a specific constitutional limitation on that power. This case is similar to Frothingham where the court held that an alleged violation of the 10th amendment was too general, too non-individualized, and too remote to satisfy the standing requirements. 22. Suppose California were to provide for a state educational voucher system, whereby the parents are provided with a voucher good for up to $5,000 per year per student. The parent could take this voucher to any school of her choosing, and use it to pay part of the tuition. If the parent chose public school, then the voucher would be unused. The Roger W. Martin 19 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 private school receiving the voucher would exchange it for cash from the state government. Assuming that 95% of the existing private schools in California are parochial schools, does this law present any constitutional problems? 22. Probably not. In developing its establishment clause jurisprudence, the supreme court has held that a convenient measurement of whether a law may violate the establishment clause is: 1. must have a secular legislative purpose; 2. the primary effect must be neither to advance nor inhibit religion; and 3. it must not foster excessive governmental entanglement with religion. Lemon. Using these guidelines, the court has held that a state may provide tax exemptions for school tuition, books and transportation as long as the exemption is available to the parents of public school students as well. Mueller. It would be only a small step to extend that to vouchers. The voucher here is given to parents directly. Even though parochial school parents may receive a greater statistical benefit from the law, it is neutrally applicable because the child may still go to public school for free. Also, it appears to be part of a larger educational scheme. The only counter-argument is that the parochial school would be required to become very involved with the government in the exchanging of the vouchers for cash. This may be viewed as excessive entanglement. However, it is probably not more entanglement than is necessary for the tax administration of a tax-exempt organization. It also does not provide any direct savings to parochial schools, because they are not getting paid any more, the parent is just paying less. 23. A fundamental Muslim sect practices total separation from Western influences. As such, they raise their children inside their tight community. The children are home schooled for their entire education, until they are 16 years old. Suppose the state of California, due to concern about recent poor performance by students on standardized tests, were to pass a law prohibiting home-schooling. The law would allow all parents to send their children either to public or private school, but forbid home schooling. What are the constitutional implications of such a law? 23. Although a particular religious “belief” may not be outlawed, religious “conduct” inspired by that belief is afforded less protection. The traditional test for determining whether a state may burden free exercise of religion is that free exercise may only be burdened when justified by a compelling state interest. Sherbert. For example, a state may not force ahmish children to attend public schools because the state interest in child education, although compelling, would not be significantly prevented by the less restrictive means of granting an exemption for the ahmish children, given that they receive adequate schooling at home. Yoder. Thus, given the holding in Yoder, this law would appear to be an unconstitutional burden on free exercise if an exemption was not granted for adequate religious home schooling. 24. Practitioners of a religion called “Hedonism” believe in the central tenent “Eat, drink, and be merry, for tommorow you may die.” As such, they live each day to the utmost excess, engaging in drunken parties and celebrations. In a small town in Kansas, the local population is generally outraged by their hedonistic behavior, and takes steps to curtail it. First, the city passes a law forbidding public assembly after midnight and before 4 am without a special permit. This law is meant to cut down on the late night Roger W. Martin 20 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 behavior of the hedonites, although it also has the general effect of a curfew. Second, they pass a law forbidding the playing of loud music after 10 pm without a special permit. Comment on the constitutionality of these laws as applied here. 24. Under the modern test for free exercise, if religious practice goes against neutral and generally applicable criminal prohibition, it has no protection - Employment Div. v. Smith. Although Smith was decided in the context of a criminal prohibition, it is likely that it would be applicable to the civil statutes passed here. However, when a city acts for the primary purpose of preventing the exercise of a specific religion, the law will be subjected to the “most rigid scrutiny” because it is by definition neither neutral nor generally applicable - Lukumi. Both of these laws appear to be enacted with the purpose of preventing the exercise of a particular religion. For instance, with respect to the curfew law, it probably has no effect on anyone except the hedonites. Furthermore, it appears to burden the additional constitutional right of assembly, and so would not fall within the allowable criminal prohibitions of Smith. With respect to the loud music law, it may possibly pass constitutional muster, because there would be no less-restrictive means available. That is to say that if an exemption for the hedonites is granted, the law which is otherwise valid (and which is motivated by the compelling interest of maintaining peace) would be almost totally defeated. Thus, even though purposefully enacted, it may survive strict scrutiny. Note that these laws also present an equal protection problem. 25. John is the leader of a militant minority group, with a central tenent of bringing equality through violence. The group has about 100 members locally. They plan a demonstration for the local public park, where John advocates “stockpiling arms” for eventual “armed conflict with the local police to get our rights back.” Several shouting matches erupt. John is whisked away by the police. As he is taken away, Bill, a white supremacist, shouts racial epithets against him. Bill is also arrested. John is charged with violation of a statute that prohibits “advocacy of violence against law enforcement.” John is charged with violation of a statute that prohibits “the use of racial epithets against a minority race for the purpose of arousing anger in the addressee.” Are either of these two ordinances constitutional as applied here? 25. No. Although the early standard for dangerous speech was whether it posed a “clear and present danger” to the government (Schenk), the court has since settled on a more balanced test whereby a state may not proscribe advocacy of violence for political reform unless that speech is advocating imminent lawlessness, and is likely to produce such violence - Brandenburg. With respect to John’s advocacy of violence, it appears to be a mere abstract teaching of the correctness of violence, and is probably not likely to produce armed conflict. Id. This is evidenced by his advocating “stockpiling” of weapons (they don’t already have them). As for the hate speech, historically “fighting words” (likely to cause an average addressee to fight) have been in a category outside of 1st amendment protection. Chaplinski. However, the court has recently provided even more protection for “fighting words” in that they are not subject to “content-based” or “viewpoint based” regulation. R.A.V.. A state may not ban only fighting words that are directed as hate speech against a minority, because this allows one side of the conflict to use hate speech, but not the other. Id. Thus, the ordinance which prohibits “the use of Roger W. Martin 21 106753212 Printed: 3/7/2016 racial epithets against a minority race for the purpose of arousing anger in the addressee” has criminalized hate speech solely for its content. Unless the city can show that this ordinance is part of a broader ban of all fighting words, it is likely to fall under strict scrutiny. The state certainly has a compelling interest in preventing racial violence. However, the less restrictive means available is to ban all fighting words, in order to put all parties on an equal footing. Roger W. Martin 22