INTRODUCTION The separation of powers, the concept that the legislative, judicial, and executive branches of government ought to be separate and distinct, is a central feature of the United States Constitution. Through this separation, each branch works according to its own authority, forming a check or balance against any abuse of power by the remaining two branches.1 James Madison, the Founding Father most often credited with including this feature in the constitution, declares, “no political truth is certainly of greater intrinsic value” (Federalist Papers No. 47). Most consider the French philosopher Charles Louis de Secondat Baron de Montesquieu the author of this system of checks and balances.2 The Founding Fathers repeatedly cite his work Spirit of the Laws as the authority on the issue.3 Madison himself proclaims, “the oracle who is always consulted 1See C. Rossiter, 1787: The Grand Convention (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 64. 2“The 18th-century French philosopher Montesquieu is popularly credited with originating the doctrine, but its roots reach back to ancient times,” George W. Carey, “Government,” in Encyclopedia Americana (1989), 130; see also D. Hutchison, The Foundations of the Constitution (Secaucus, New Jersey: University Books, 1975), 20-21. 3“‘The Fathers’ had for their oracle of political philosophy the treatise of Montesquieu on the ‘Spirit of Laws’,” James Bryce, American Commonwealth, vol. 1 (New York: Macmillan Company, 1911), 29. “The oracles usually consulted were Blackstone and Montesquieu. The ‘Spirit of Laws’ was studied by Washington as part of his preparation for the work of the convention,” Hannis Taylor, The Origin and Growth of the English Constitution, vol. 1 (Boston: Houghton, Mifflin, 1889), 60. “Montesquieu is accepted as the oracle of political theory for that time,” R. A. Ames and H. C. Montgomery, “The Influence of Rome on the American Constitution,” CJ 30 (1935): 27. and cited on this subject is the celebrated Montesquieu” (ibid.). Nevertheless, this paper proposes that--while Montesquieu may have presented the framers of the Constitution with the most modern incarnation of that principle--he borrows too heavily from Polybius and the ancient theory of the mixed constitution (mikth/) to be credited accurately as its originator. The arguments for this position will be presented in three chapters. The first will trace the origins of the theory of mixed constitution to antiquity and especially Polybius’ Histories,4 while underscoring similarities between Polybius’ system and that of the American Constitution. Other sources will include Herodotus, Thucydides, Plato, Aristotle, his pupil Dicaearchus of Messana, Diogenes Laertius, and Cicero. The second chapter will explore the availability of the Histories to the Founding Fathers, addressing whether they were aware of Polybius’ teachings on the separation of powers. In particular, a survey of the works of Jefferson, Madison, Monroe, Otis, Adams, and Hamilton will serve as representative of what was available to the framers of the constitution generally. Note that while Jefferson was not present at the convention himself (he was representing the United States in Paris at the time), he was in correspondence with many who did attend and had presented them with books, material, and ideas from Europe. 4Translations of all ancient texts will be taken from the Loeb Classical Library. 2 The third chapter will focus on Montesquieu himself, exploring the extent to which his own work is based on that of Polybius and the classical tradition of the mixed constitution. Particular attention will be given to the fact that several of his recent predecessors had already touted the efficacy of separation of powers long before the publication of Montesquieu’s works. Key sources for this chapter will include Harrington, King Charles I of England, Locke, Bolingbroke, and Blackstone, as well as the criticism of several modern scholars who call into question the indispensability of Montesquieu in America’s adopting the separation of powers. 3 CHAPTER ONE In order to discuss the concept of the mixed constitution in antiquity,5 it is important first to understand what is meant by a simple constitution. In Book VI of his Histories (6.4.6-11; cf. 6.3.5), the ancient Greek historian Polybius outlines three simple forms of constitution--each categorized according to the number of its ruling body: monarchy (rule by the one), aristocracy (rule by the few), and democracy (rule by the many).6 According to the historian, these three simple constitutions each degenerate, over time, into their respective corrupt forms (tyranny, oligarchy, and mob-rule) by a cycle of gradual decline which he calls anacyclosis or “political revolution” (6.9.10: politeiw=n a)naku/klwsij ; 6.4.7-11; cf. 6.3.9).7 5For more on mixed constitutions, see Kurt von Fritz, The Theory of the Mixed Constitution in Antiquity (New York: Arno Press, 1975); see also Correa Moylan Walsh, The Political Science of John Adams: a Study in the Theory of Mixed Government and the Bicameral System (New York: Putnam, 1915), 32, n. 1; and Neal Wood, “Essentials of the Mixed Constitution,” chap. in Cicero’s Social and Political Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991), 159-175. 6Herodotus is the first to list these three forms of constitution (Persian Wars 3.80-82). Thucydides (8.97) then describes a constitutional fusion of two elements: the few and the many. Also before Polybius, both Plato (Laws 710e, 712c; Menex. 238c-d) and Aristotle (Pol. 1279a) categorize constitutions into three groups, according to the number of the sovereign body (i.e., the one, the few, and the many). For other early works on mixed constitutions, see F. W. Walbank, Polybius (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990), 135-137; and his A Historical Commentary on Polybius (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1957), 640, 643-47. 7Polybius credits the six categories (i.e., the original three forms of simple constitution and their respective perversions or parekba/seij) to “Plato and certain other philosophers” (6.5.1: Pla/twni kai/ tisin e(te/roij tw=n filoso/fwn). Plato (Laws 712c), however, allows for only five of the six forms of constitution because he does not distinguish nominally between democracy and mob-rule. 4 For monarchy, he claims, inevitably degrades into tyranny. Tyranny is then replaced by aristocracy, which in turn degrades into oligarchy. Oligarchy then is overthrown by democracy, which ultimately falls into its own corresponding distortion, mob-rule (or ochlocracy). In Polybius’ analysis, the cycle then starts up again (monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy) since anarchy inevitably creates a void that some new demagogue will fill.8 'Anaku/klwsij , the sliding from one form of constitution into another, is unavoidable because of the inherent weakness of each simple form of constitution.9 The catalyst for the decay in each simple form, Polybius says (6.7.7), is hereditary succession--the automatic handing Aristotle (Pol. 1279b), on the other hand, mentions the full six, claiming that each of the original three (sovereignty of the one, the few, and the many) splits into two sub-categories, based on whether the ruling authority’s motives are selfish or unselfish: Deviations from the constitutions mentioned are tyranny corresponding to kingship, oligarchy to aristocracy, and democracy to constitutional government [or polity]; for tyranny is monarchy ruling in the interest of the monarch, oligarchy government in the interest of the rich, democracy government in the interest of the poor, and none of these forms governs with regard to the profit of the community. parekba/seij de\ tw=n ei)rhme/nwn turanni\j me\n basilei/aj o)ligarxi/a de\ a)ristokrati/aj dhmokrati/a de\ politei/aj: h( me\n ga\r turanni/j e)sti monarxi/a pro\j to\ sumfe/ron to\ tou= monarxou=ntoj, h( d )o)ligarxi/a pro\j to\ tw=n eu)po/rwn, h( de\ dhmokrati/a pro\j to\ sumfe/ron to\ tw=n a)po/rwn, pro\j de\ to\ t%= koin%= lusitelou=n ou)demi/a au)twn. 8 See below, Thornton Anderson’s comment in note 53. 9For more on a)naku/klwsij , see Stephan Podes, “Polybius and His Theory of Anacyclosis: Problems of Not Just Ancient Political Theory,” History of Political Thought 12 (1991): 577-87; see also George Boas, “Cycles,” in Dictionary of the History of Ideas (New York: Scribner’s, 1968); Stow Persons, “The Cyclical Theory of History in Eighteenth-Century America,” American Quarterly 6 (Summer 1954): 147-63; Walbank, “Polybius and the Roman State,” GRBS 5 (1964): 246; H. Ryfell, Metabolh\ politeiw=n: der Wandel der Staatsverfassungen (New York: Arno Press, 1973); and Bernard Bailyn, The Origins of American Politics (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1968), 19-20. 5 down of the privileges of a particular form of government to future generations without their ever having to internalize for themselves the discipline necessary to maintain those privileges. Each of the three simple forms of constitution serves well enough at its inception, since founder kings arise out of their very excellence of character, aristocracies (by definition at least) form from the noblest of society, and democracies too embrace the highest ideals at the outset. The problem lies not with the initial impetus that forms these governments but with the fact that they each suffer entropy, or internal decay. Polybius explains his theory in fuller detail, describing the mechanism by which hereditary succession weakens the state. When the crown is inherited generation upon generation, kings are no longer then chosen by excellence of leadership but by accident of birth. When monarchs are born to privilege, they no longer have any incentive to serve the state (since their privileges are no longer tied to their performance as leaders). They eventually expend their daily energies in merely fulfilling the desires of their own appetites. Having become arrogant and self-serving, the last in the line of tyrants is pushed aside by those who are close enough to the throne to notice his corruption, namely the members of the aristocracy (Polyb. 6.8.1). They, in turn, serve the state well initially. After all, these were the nobles so offended by the king’s excesses that principle drove them to take action against him. 6 Unfortunately, here again, when the grandchildren of these nobles inherit position, they are ill equipped to handle the power of rule (since they were born to privilege and identify less and less with the problems of the common man). The aristocracy then degrades proportionally by each generation into an oligarchy, just as the kings degenerated into tyrants (6.8.5). The oligarchs then are banished or killed by the people, who finally assume the responsibility of ruling themselves. The people also govern well, at first. As long as there are any living who remember the days of oppression, they guard their liberties with a jealous vigor. Nevertheless, as future generations inherit the same privileges of democracy as their ancestors, yet without effort, they cease to cherish those benefits (6.9.5). Eventually individuals arise among them who, seeking pre-eminence, cater to the creature comforts of the masses, thereby hoping to win their favor. People sell cheap those liberties that have cost them nothing personally. Once the masses accept these demagogues, the cycle of tyranny begins again. This is the cycle Polybius calls a)naku/klwsij . Polybius believes that Republican Rome has avoided this endless cycle by establishing a mixed constitution, a single state with elements of all three forms of government at once: monarchy (in the form of its elected executives, the consuls), aristocracy (as represented by the Senate), and democracy (in the form of the popular assemblies, such as the Comitia Centuriata).10 10Polyb. In a mixed constitution, each of the three 6.11.11-13; cf. Cic. Rep. 1.42, 45, 69-70. 7 branches of government checks the strengths and balances the weaknesses of the other two. Since absolute rule rests in no single body but rather is shared among the three, the corrupting influence of unchecked power is abated and stasis is achieved.11 Polybius is not alone in his praise of mixed government. Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, and Cicero all stress the supremacy of a mixed constitution and the need for separation of powers within the government.12 Plato (Laws 693e, cf. 756e) advises that a state balance both its monarchic and democratic elements, for “a State which does not partake of these can never be rightly constituted” (w(j ou)k aÃn pote tou/twn po/lij aÃmoiroj genome/nh politeuqh=nai du/nait' aÄn 11“The Greek historian Polybius admired the mutual automatic balances which created an equilibrium between its legislative, executive and judicial institutions,” Michael Grant, The Founders of the Western World (New York: 1991), 153. 12For Plato’s references to a mixed constitution, see Laws 681d, 693b-e, 712d-e; Rep. 557d; Menex. 238c-d; and Statesman 291a92a, 301a-3b. For Aristotle’s discussion, see Politics 1266a, 1267b, 1269a-73b, 1278b-80a, 1289a, 1293a-96b, 1298a-b, 1302a, 1318b-19a, 1320b. His pupil, Dicaearchus of Messana, even wrote a treatise on mixed constitution called Tripolitiko/n (Cic. Att. 13.32.2; Phot. Bibl. 37.69c; cf. Walbank, Commentary, 640). Diogenes Laertius lists the theory as a doctrine of the early Stoics: “the best form of government they hold to be a mixture of democracy, kingship, and aristocracy” (7.1.131: politei/an d' a)ri/sthn th\n mikth\n eÃk te dhmokrati/aj kai\ basilei/aj kai\ a)ristokrati/aj). Dionysius of Halicarnassus also praises the theory in his reporting of a speech given by Manius Valerius (2.7.7). For Cato the Elder’s opinion that the constitution of Carthage was mixed, see Serv. Aen. 4.682; cf. Polyb. 6.51. In addition to the previous authors, Carl J. Richard (The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome and the American Enlightenment, (Cambridge: 1994), 126) adds, Although Plutarch, Livy, Sallust, and Tacitus never formally endorsed mixed government, their sympathy toward the lost republic and criticism of absolute monarchy, combined with their disquisitions on the volatile nature of untutored mobs, suggest a strong sympathy for it. 8 kalw=j). He also warns (Laws 691c) against placing too much power in the hands of a single body: If one neglects the rule of due measure, and gives things too great in power to things too small—sails to ships, food to bodies, offices of rule to souls—then everything is upset, and they run through excess of insolence, some to bodily disorders, others to that offspring of insolence, injustice. )Ea/n tij mei/zona did%= toi=j e)la/ttosi du/namin parei\j to\ me/trion, ploi/oj te i(sti/a kai\ sw/masi trofh\n kai\ yuxai=j a)rxa/j, a)natre/petai/ pou pa/nta kai\ e)cubri/zonta ta\ me\n ei)j no/souj qei=, ta\ d )ei)j eãkgonon uàbrewj a)diki/an. Citing as example the Spartan constitution, with its two kings, council of elders (gerousi/a), and ephors, Plato (Laws 692) praises not only the blended form of government but those of tripartite construction. Aristotle agrees, “the better the constitution is mixed, the more permanent it is” (Pol. 1297a: oÀs% d )aÄn aÃmeinon h( politei/a mixq$=, tosou/t% monimwte/ra). For him the well-ordered constitution results from the proper ordering of three factors: the deliberative body, the magistracies, and the judiciary. 13 13 Aristotle (Pol. 1297b-98a) attributes the success of a constitution to the organization of the three factors of government when he states: All forms of constitution then have three factors in reference to which the good lawgiver has to consider what is expedient for each constitution; and if these factors are well-ordered the constitution must of necessity be well-ordered, and the superiority of one constitution over another necessarily consists in the superiority of each of these factors. Of these three factors one is, what is to be the body that deliberates about common interests, second the one connected with the magistracies, that is, what they are to be and what matters they are to control, and what is to be the method of their election, and a third is, what is to be the judiciary. eãsti dh\ tri/a mo/ria tw=n politeiw=n pasw=n peri\ wâân dei= qewrei=n to\n spoudai=on nomoqe/thn e(ka/st$ to\ sumfe/ron: wâân e)xo/ntwn kalw=j a)na/gkh th\n politei/an eãxein kalw=j, kai\ ta\j politei/aj a)llh/lwn diafe/rein e)n t%= diafe/rein eàkaston tou/twn. Eãsti de\ tw=n triw=n eán me\n ti/ to\ bouleuo/menon peri\ tw=n koinw=n, deu/teron de\ to\ peri\ ta\j 9 Polybius (6.3.8) also cites Sparta as the first to draw upon this principle. He elsewhere (6.18.1; cf. below, note 49) concludes: Such being the power that each part has of hampering the others or co-operating with them, their union is adequate to all emergencies, so that it is impossible to find a better political system than this. Toiau/thj d )ou)/shj th=j e(ka/stou tw=n merw=n duna/mewj ei)j to\ kai\ bla/ptein kai\ sunergei=n a)llh/loij, pro\j pa/saj sumbai/nei ta\j perista/seij deo/ntwj e)/xein th\n a(rmogh\n au)tw=n, w(/ste mh\ oiÂo/n t )eiÅnai tau/thj eu(rei=n a)mei/nw politei/aj su/stasin. Referring again to the power of the three branches, “if they wish, to counteract or co-operate with the others” (6.15.1: a)ntipra/ttein boulhqe/nta kai\ sunergei=n a)llh/loij ), Polybius (6.18.7-8) elaborates: For when one part having grown out of proportion to the others aims at supremacy and tends to become too predominant, it is evident that, as for the reasons above given none of the three is absolute, but the purpose of the one can be counterworked and thwarted by the others, none of them will excessively outgrow the others or treat them with contempt. All in fact remains in statu quo, on the one hand, because any aggressive impulse is sure to be checked and from the outset each estate stands in dread of being interfered with by the others. e)peida\n ga\r e)coidou=n ti tw=n merw=n filoneik$= kai\ ple/on tou= de/ontoj e)pikrat$=, dh=lon w(j ou)deno\j au)totelou=j oÃntoj kata\ to\n aÃrti lo/gon, a)ntispa=sqai de\ kai\ parapodi/zesqai duname/nhj th=j e(ka/stou proqe/sewj u(p' a)llh/lwn, ou)de\n e)coidei= tw=n merw=n ou)d' u(perfronei=. pa/nta ga\r e)mme/nei toi=j u(pokeime/noij ta\ me\n kwluo/mena th=j o(rmh=j, ta\ d' e)c a)rxh=j dedio/ta th\n e)k tou= pe/laj e)pi/stasin. In short, Polybius insists “it is evident we must regard as the best constitution a combination of all these three a)rxa/j, tou=to d ) e)sti\ ti/naj dei= kai\ ti/nwn eiånai kupi/aj, kai\ poi/an tina\ dei= gi/gnesqai th\n aiàresin au)tw=n, tri/ton de\ ti/ to\ dika/zon. 10 varieties” (6.3.7: dh=lon ga\r w(j a)ri/sthn me\n h(ghte/on politei/an th\n e)k pa/ntwn tw=n proeirhme/nwn i)diwma/twn sunestw=san). Cicero (Rep. 1.69) also attests to the stability of a mixed constitution against the ravages of a)naku/klwsij : For the primary forms already mentioned degenerate easily into the corresponding perverted forms, the king being replaced by a despot, the aristocracy by an oligarchical faction, and the people by a mob and anarchy; but whereas these forms are frequently changed into new ones, this does not usually happen in the case of the mixed and evenly balanced constitution, except through great faults in the governing class. Quod et illa prima facile in contraria vitia convertuntur, ut existat ex rege dominus, ex optimatibus factio, ex populo turba et confusio, quodque ipsa genera generibus saepe conmutantur novis, hoc in hac iuncta moderateque permixta conformatione rei publicae non ferme sine magnis principum vitiis evenit. Cicero too declares the mixed constitution the best form of government (Rep. 2.41), “the most splendid conceivable” (Rep. 2.42: quo nihil possit esse praeclarius). He concludes, “a form of government which is an equal mixture of the three good forms is superior to any of them by itself” (Rep. 2.66: sed id praestare singulis, quod e tribus primis esset modice temperatum).14 The result of Polybius’ analysis of the Roman Constitution, the theory of a system of checks and balances among three branches of the same government, is ostensibly the 14Cicero is known to have regarded Polybius as a dependable source (Att. 13.30; Rep. 2.27), though he was probably just as greatly influenced by Dicaearchus on the subject of mixed constitution (Att. 2.2.1, 13.31.2, 13.32.2; Tusc. 1.77). See above, note 12. Richard (126) claims, “Cicero (Rep. 2.23-30) seized upon Polybius’ theory to thwart the increasing efforts of ambitious Romans to consolidate their own power at the republic’s expense.” 11 same principle as that of the American Constitution with its executive, legislative, and judicial branches. As Paul A. Rahe admits, “the American regime bears a certain resemblance to Polybius’ depiction of Rome, for the American Constitution deploys institutional checks.”15 Aristotle anticipates the American Constitution as well, when he divides the elements of government into three parts (Pol. 1297b), calling them the legislative (to\ bouleuo/menon), the executive (to\ peri\ a)rxa/j), and the judicial (to\ dikastiko/n).16 The lesson was not missed by the Founding Fathers, as R. M. Gummere notes:17 A careful search in law-makers like Nathaniel Ward or in the studies of Wilson and Madison preparatory to the debates on the Constitution indicates a first-hand knowledge, on the part of the twenty-four college-bred delegates, of the Aristotelian arguments for a “mixed” type of government. The Roman Constitution parallels the American Constitution in historical context as well as content.18 The Roman Republic was founded after the expulsion of the Tarquin 15Republics Ancient and Modern North Carolina Press, 1992), 602. the Roman Constitution, see Thomas Political History of Rome (London: (Chapel Hill: The University of For more on Polybian analysis of Taylor, A Constitutional and Methuen and Company, 1899), 212. 16See above, note 13. Literally the deliberative, the one concerning magistracies, and the one dealing with justice. Note that these are the very branches often mistakenly ascribed as the modern innovation of Montesquieu over the so-called “antiquated” branches (monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy)--e.g., P. C. Bartholomey, “Checks and Balances,” art. in Encyclopedia Americana 6 (1989), 353. 17“The Heritage of the Classics in Colonial North America,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 99 (April 1955): 75; See also Gummere, “John Dickenson, the Classical Penman of the Revolution,” CJ 52 (Nov. 1956): 81, 86; and see below, Gummere’s comments on Aristotle page 27, and notes 71 and 73. 18See Ames and Montgomery, 19-27. For America’s identification with Rome in general, see Charles F. Mullet, “Classical Influences on the American Revolution,” CJ (1939): 92. 12 Kings. Like the Americans, the Romans had ridded themselves of a tyrant and were contemplating the best form of constitution. Rome sent a delegation of three men to Greece to study the laws of Solon, Lycurgus, and Greek institutions (Livy 3.32-33). The opinion of the Romans was that laws should be codified and inscribed onto 12 tables that would be publicly displayed.19 Influenced by the Greeks, their government embraced a mixed constitution.20 In like manner the Founding Fathers, having expelled the tyrant George III,21 consulted the history books to find the best that foreign lands had to offer in constitutional theory.22 They found separation of powers within a mixed constitution. 19For other similarities between the American Constitution and the Roman Constitution, see Gilbert Chinard, “Polybius and the American Constitution,” in The American Enlightenment, ed. F. Shuffelton (Rochester, New York: University of Rochester Press, 1993), 217-237; R. M. Gummere, “The Classical Ancestry of the Constitution,” chap. in The American Colonial Mind and the Classical Tradition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1963), 173-90; and also Ames and Montgomery, 19-27. 20For Solon’s Athenian constitution as mixed, see Walbank, Polybius, 135; for Lycurgus’ Spartan constitution as same, see C. O. Brink and Walbank, “The Construction of the Sixth Book of Polybius,” CQ n.s. 3 (1954): 112-13; and Walbank, “Polybius and the Roman State,” GRBS 5 (1964): 250-51. 21The Virgina state motto is, after all, “Thus Always to Tyrants” (Sic Semper Tyrannis). 22 See Marcus Cunliffe, The American Heritage History of the Presidency (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1968), 26. Here he comments on the Executive but his words are just as appropriate for the Founder’s inclusion of separation of powers in the constitution: The men who invented the Presidency in Philadelphia in 1787 were not bound by a long national tradition. Even so, they were deeply affected by the past. Early in the year, John Adams had written in London that the creators of the American state governments had “adopted the method of a wise architect, in erecting a new palace for . . . his sovereign.” Such an architect, said Adams, would read the best writers, examine the most famous buildings to see how well they had survived the passing years, and then choose the ideas that seemed most 13 CHAPTER TWO The fact that Polybius’ theories and the American system share similarities will not suffice to prove, more than circumstantially, that the U.S. Constitution is founded upon ancient theories. The second focus of this paper, therefore, will be to establish whether the Founding Fathers actually knew and read Polybius. Steeped as they were in the classics, “the Founding Fathers,” Saul K. Padover asserts, “were educationally and spiritually the children of the antiquity.”23 Bernard Bailyn too proclaims, “knowledge of classical authors was universal among colonists with any degree of education.”24 Gummere useful to his own structure. Similarly, in devising the national Executive, the writers of the Constitution called not only on their own sentiments and experience, but also on those of lawmakers and philosophers throughout history. 23World of the Founding Fathers (New York: Barnes & Co., 1960), 30; see also Edwin A. Miles, “The Young American Nation and the Classical World,” in The American Enlightenment, 337-52; F. McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: the Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1985); C. J. Richard, “The Classical Conditioning of the Founders,” chap. in The Founders and the Classics, 12-38; Meyer Reinhold, Classica Americana: The Greek and Roman Heritage in the United States (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1984); S. F. Wiltshire, ed., The Usefulness of Classical Learning in the Eighteenth Century, (Washington, D.C.: American Philological Association, 1975); T. L. Simmons, “Greek Ruins,” National Review, 14 Sept. 1998, 42-43; J. W. Eadie, ed., Classical Traditions in Early America (Ann Arbor: Center for the Coordination of Ancient and Modern Studies, 1976); and Charles F. Mullet, “Classical Influences on the American Revolution,” CJ 35 (Nov. 1939): 92-104. Jefferson, for example, “had commissioned Ticknor to send him from Europe the best and most recent editions of Greek and Latin Classics” Gilbert Chinard, “Thomas Jefferson as a Classical Scholar,” American Scholar 1 (April, 1932): 143. 24The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 1972), 23. For the academic credentials of the members of the Convention, see Ames and Montgomery, 20. See 14 adds, “there was seldom an epoch when the leading men were so imbued with the classical tradition.”25 In recognition of this fact, Richard (130) concludes, The founders had access to every level of this western tradition of mixed government theory. Hence it was only natural that, when confronted by unprecedented parliamentary taxation during the 1760s and 1770s, they should turn to the most ancient and revered of political theories to explain this perplexing phenomenon. Patriot leaders such as Richard Henry Lee, Samuel Adams, and John Adams ascribed the new tyranny to a degeneration of the mixture of the English constitution. Clearly the Founding Fathers were familiar with the classics generally, but did they know about Polybius specifically?26 That the text of Polybius’ Histories itself was available to the Founders is of no doubt, as M. N. S. Sellers attests,27 Americans understood the Roman constitution primarily through the writings of Polybius, readily available in four recent printings, and after [January of] 1787 in excerpts from Spelman’s translation, reproduced in John Adam’s Defense of the Constitutions of the United States of America. also Gummere, “The Heritage of the Classics in Colonial North America,” 75. Rossiter (35) adds, The overall performance of the college graduates in the Convention of 1787 speaks forcefully for the proposition that Latin, rhetoric, philosophy, and mathematics can be a healthy fare for political heroes. 25“John Adams Togatus,” Philological Quarterly 13 (April, 1934): 203. 26Mullet (92) found references to Polybius during an “exhaustive examination of American Revolutionary Literature.” Some of the pamphleteers of the period also derived their knowledge of Rome from Polybius (ibid., 96; cf. 97). Richard (53) adds, “the founders encountered their Roman heroes in the works of Polybius, Livy, Sallust, Plutarch, and Tacitus.” 27M. N. S. Sellers, American Republicanism: Roman Ideology in the U.S. Constitution (New York: New York University Press, 1994), 46. 15 Richard (24) also notes, after the Stamp Act of 1765, many [Bachelor’s and Master’s] theses applied the political principles of Aristotle, Cicero, and Polybius to the debates concerning independence and the Constitution. The best way to prove a direct connection between Polybius and the Fathers is to search for references to him in their own writings. Therefore, a brief survey of the papers of Thomas Jefferson, James Madison, James Monroe, Benjamin Franklin, James Otis, John Adams, and Alexander Hamilton will show that many of the Founding Fathers indeed knew Polybius, especially his passages on the Roman Constitution, a)naku/klwsij , and the separation of powers. Thomas Jefferson, a fervent supporter of mixed government,28 had numerous editions of Polybius’ Histories in his personal library.29 Several private letters reveal that he was buying copies of the Histories for himself and his friends.30 Jefferson sent many of these letters from Paris in 1787, the same year as the Federal Convention that drafted the 28See Richard, 131; for Jefferson’s estimation that the separation of powers is “the leading principle of our Constitution” see James J. Kilpatrick’s response to the speech of William F. Buckley, given at Kent State University, 1 April 1998, “U.S. v. Clinton,” National Review, 28 Sep. 1998, 46. 29E. Millicent Sowersby, compiler, Catalogue of the Library of Thomas Jefferson 5 (Washington, D.C.: Library of Congress, 1953), 383. For Polybius in pre-Revolutionary collections, see Richard Beal Davis, Intellectual Life in the Colonial South 1585-1763 (Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press, 1978), 532, 540. For classical studies among the colonists, see Gummere’s articles, “Some Classical Side Lights on Colonial Education,” CJ 55 (Feb. 1960): 223-232; and “Church, State, and Classics,” CJ 54 (Jan. 1959): 175-83. 30“From Paris Jefferson shipped copies of Polybius and sets of ancient authors to Madison, a former graduate student . . . and to George Wythe, a finished Greek and Latin scholar” Gummere, “The Classical Ancestry of the Constitution,” 174. 16 Constitution. In February of that year, he wrote to Philip Mazzei for an Italian translation of Polybius.31 By August Jefferson had sent an edition of the Histories to his friend Peter Carr (Papers, 18). A month later he wrote George Wythe that he had procured for him “a copy of Polybius, the best edition” and was sending it to him in Williamsburg (ibid., 127). In March of the following year, Jefferson sent Vann Damme a letter requesting the 1548 Dutch edition (ibid., 688). Then two months later he wrote John Trumbul asking him to purchase copies of Hampton’s Polybius from “Lackington bookseller Chriswell Street” (ibid. 179). In January of 1789, Jefferson again wrote to Van Damme for another 1584 Polybius (ibid., 490) which the vendor sent him two months later (ibid., 707).32 James Madison also knew Polybius’ work. He cites the historian in The Federalist Papers No. 63 and devotes nearly the entirety of No. 47 to the separation of powers: 33 31Charles T. Cullen, ed., The Papers of Thomas Jefferson (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1962), 159. Note this is a month after the European release of John Adams’ summary of Polybius (see above, note 27; see below, note 43). 32For more on Jefferson’s involvement with the classics, see David M. Mayer, The Constitutional Thought of Thomas Jefferson (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1994); Louis B. Wright, “Thomas Jefferson and the Classics,” Proceedings of the American Philological Society 87 (1944): 223-33; Lance Banning, “Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser., 43 (Jan. 1986): 4; and David W. Carrithers, “Montesquieu, Jefferson and the Fundamentals of 18th-Century Republican Theory,” FAR 6 (Fall 1982): 160-88. 33Cf. Padover’s statement (31): “in James Madison one finds mentions of the outstanding classical writers, such as Plato, Plutarch, Polybius.” See also Gummere, “The Classical Ancestry of the Constitution,” 181; and his comment on Madison, page 12 above. 17 The accumulation of all powers, legislative, executive, and judiciary, in the same hands whether of one, a few or many, and whether hereditary, self appointed, or elective, may justly be pronounced the very definition of tyranny. Here Madison reveals a Greek influence in his use of such terms as one, few, many, and tyranny. On December 25, 1773, William Bradford wrote him: “Scipio used daily to thank the Gods that they had introduced him to the Acquaintance [sic] of Polybius; nor have I less reason to be thankful that I once enjoyed your company and now you[r] correspondence.”34 Madison himself cites Polybius in a letter to Jefferson dated October 24, 1787 (Papers, 10.210). Other Founding Fathers had no less knowledge of Polybius. During the Virginia state convention on ratification of the Federal Constitution, James Monroe “read several passages in Polybius”35 from the floor. In a letter of May 1779, William Jones sent Benjamin Franklin a “translation of a curious fragment of Polybius.”36 Actually, the pretended fragment was simply a device to draw Franklin’s attention to some ideas on conciliation with the British. Nonetheless, the false fragment attests not only to a familiarity with Polybius, but 34W. T. Hutchinson and W. M. E. Rachal, ed., The Papers of James Madison (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962), vol. 1, 103. 35The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution, ed. Jonathan Elliot (Philadelphia: 1861), 210. 36B. B. Oberg, ed., The Papers of Benjamin Franklin (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992), 570. For the actual text of the fragment, see J. Sparks, ed., The Works of Benjamin Franklin (Boston: Hiliard Gray and Company, 1839), 543-546. 18 also to Jones’ estimation that Franklin would consider the historian an authority worth reading.37 James Otis also read Polybius. He praised the constitution of Rome, observing that the city had been most durable when its powers were separate but fell when it failed to maintain a balance among the three branches.38 Citing Otis (Rights, 14), Mullet (100) comments on Polybius’ contribution as one of the philosophic sources for separation of powers: The very few colonists who knew him found his history more useful for illustrative than for philosophic materials. In this respect, however, his description of the Roman constitution at the time of the battle of Cannae aroused some homage and in all likelihood contributed to the high value placed on separation of powers as a basis of stable government. One should note that Mullet’s reference to the relative obscurity of Polybius is in regards to the population generally.39 minority.40 Indeed well educated colonists were in the Nevertheless, those who were educated received a decidedly classical training--the framers of the Constitution disproportionately so (see above, page 14). Polybius’ work was by no means unknown to them nor does Mullet claim so. Note too that the one exception to Mullet dismissal of 37For another possible example of Franklin’s use of Polybius, see Gilbert Chinard “Polybius and the American Constitution,” 223. 38James Otis, The Rights of the British Colonies Asserted and Proved (Boston: 1764), 14; Mullet, 97; cf. C. F. Adams, ed., The Works of John Adams (Boston: Little and Brown, 1851), vol. 4, 440. 39Nonetheless, given Mullet’s earlier admission that Polybius was a common source among the pamphleteers (see above, note 26), his statement “the very few colonists who knew him” is still at least puzzling, if not overstated. Perhaps Mullet means that they did not know Polybius’ text directly—just as one could say today that more know “of” Plato than have actually read his texts. 40 See Rossiter, 34. 19 Polybius as an ideological source for the Founding Fathers is the doctrine of the separation of powers. At the time of the Convention, John Adams was away in London. He was, as Rossiter (83) describes it, “represented in Philadelphia” by his writings nonetheless. Adams’ own library contained several editions of Polybius.41 The subject of the Greek historian also finds its way into Adams’ private correspondence with his wife.42 Gilbert Chinard even credits Adams for many of the classical references cited during debates of the Federal Convention of 1787:43 To a certain extent, their really surprising knowledge of classical analogies and precedents may be explained by the fact that John Adams had published, early in January 1787, his A Defense of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America. The first part of the work, dealing exclusively with ancient governments and writers, had reached America in March, long before the opening of the Federal Convention. It was immediately reprinted in Boston, New York and Philadelphia.44 Adams (Works, 4.328) fully embraces the classical division of simple constitutions into monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy.45 41Chinard, In the introduction to chapter six of his A “Polybius and the American Constitution,” 222. 42Familiar Letters of John Adams and his Wife Abigail, 25. Abigail quotes Polybius in a letter to her husband. 43“Polybius and the American Constitution,” 221.; cf. 236: “Montesquieu was only one of their authorities . . . they did not neglect the original texts available either in full or in the convenient compilation of John Adams.” 44It is perhaps significant that Jefferson did not begin his flurry of letters from Paris regarding Polybius until the month following the European release of Adams’ book. See above, page 17. 45See C. M. Walsh, 23. Richard (132) calls Adams “the most visible and most persistent proponent of mixed government in America.” See also R. M. Gummere, “The Classical Politics of John Adams,” Boston Public Library Quarterly 9 (Oct. 1957): 172. 20 Defense of the Constitutions, Adams (Works, 4.435) clearly links Polybius with his purpose:46 I wish to assemble together the opinions and reasonings of philosophers, politicians, and historians, who have taken the most extensive views of men and societies, whose characters are deservedly revered, and whose writings were in the contemplation of those who framed the American constitutions. It will not be contested that all these characters are united in Polybius. Note that the constitutions Adams refers to in the title A Defense of the Constitutions are the state constitutions already adopted prior to January of 1787, well before the adoption of the Federal Constitution.47 As McDonald (84) notes, many of these state constitutions (six out of the original thirteen) had already adopted some degree of separation of powers.48 In his A Defense of the Constitutions, Adams devotes an entire chapter to Polybius’ doctrine of the mixed constitution, a)naku/klwsij , and the Polybian assessment of the Roman system of checks and balances.49 Adams, like Polybius, 46For more on John Adams, see Dorothy M. Robathan, “John Adams and the Classics,” The New England Quarterly 19 (1946): 91-98; R. M. Gummere, “John Adams Togatus,” 203-10; Gilbert Chinard, Honest John Adams (Gloucester, Mass.: Peter Smith, 1964); M. N. S. Sellers (46); and especially C. M. Walsh. 47Richard (132) notes that Adams was reciting Polybius even in 1763, when he writes, Adams was devoted to mixed government theory throughout his life. As early as 1763 he claimed, in “An Essay on Man’s Lust for Power:” “No simple Form of Government can possibly secure Men against the Violences of Power, Simple Monarchy will soon mould itself into Despotism, Aristocracy will soon commence on Oligarchy, and Democracy will soon degenerate into Anarchy. 48Cf. J. Bryce, 1.29. See below, note 70. 49Adams summarizes a)naku/klwsij (Works, 4.440-41): Polybius thinks it manifest, both from reason and experience, that the best form of government is not simple, but compounded, 21 credits Rome’s greatness to its constitutional separation of powers (Works, 4.439-440):50 The Roman constitution formed the noblest people and the greatest power that has ever existed. But if all the powers of the consuls, senate, and people had centered in a single assembly of the people, collectively or representatively, will any man pretend to believe that they would have been long free, or ever great? In effect, any Federal Convention delegate who read Adams’ A Defense of the Constitutions had indirectly read Polybius.51 The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, edited by Max Farrand (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1911), are filled with classical references too numerous to cover here.52 Nevertheless, both Gummere and Chinard make important observations about the proceedings. Chinard (“Polybius and the American Constitution,” 221) notes: the delegates called upon Montesquieu as an authority in support of their views; but a careful study of the Records because of the tendency of each of the simple forms to degenerate. Adams hopes the state constitutions will prove themselves even superior to that of Rome, stating (ibid. 440): As we advance, we may see cause to differ widely from the judgment of Polybius, ‘that it is impossible to invent a more perfect system of government.’ 50Adams had defended the principle of separation of powers as early as 1776, when he wrote a pamphlet, “Thoughts on Government” (Works, 4.193; cf. Benjamin F. Wright, “The Origins of the Separation of Powers in America,” Economica 13 (May 1933): 178). 51Cf. Gummere’s comment (“The Classical Ancestry of the Constitution,”178): “Polybius was of special interest to the framers of the Constitution. They studied him intently as the leading authority on the Greek city-states.” 52For a brief digest of references to Rome made during the Convention, see Ames and Montgomery, 21-23. For John Dickenson’s quoting Polybius, see E. H. Scott, ed., The Federalist and Other Constitutional Papers (Chicago: 1894), vol. 2, 806. See also Gummere, “John Dickenson, the Classical Penman of the Revolution,” 81-87. 22 and the Federalist would show that more frequently they went back to the ancient sources from which Montesquieu himself had derived his information, and that they had apparently a first-hand acquaintance with ancient historians and ancient history. Gummere (“The Classical Ancestry of the Constitution,” 175) adds: The debates before, during, and after the Convention of 1787 can be better understood if the doctrine of three ancient authorities--Aristotle, Cicero, and Polybius--are first clarified in relation to the establishment of the federal government. Their testimony underlies all the suggested patterns for the new republic. During the Federal Convention, Hamilton expressed the concern that “if we incline too much to democracy, we shall soon shoot into a monarchy” (June 26th, Records, 1.432). His fear is obviously based on his acceptance of Polybius and the inevitability of a)naku/klwsij --namely that democracy in excess paves the way for tyranny.53 Hamilton frequently used Roman names in the publications of The Federalist Papers and confessed knowing more about the Roman Constitution than that of the British.54 53“It looks as if Hamilton must have read Adams’s first volume and have borrowed from it” (C. M. Walsh, 307; cf. Chinard, “Polybius,” 230). Hamilton cites Polybius directly (The Federalist and Other Constitutional Papers, vol. 1,352; cf. Ames and Montgomery, 23). Cf. Richard’s comment (135) that “democracy, [John] Adams concluded in Polybian fashion, was a mere way station on the road to tyranny.” Thornton Anderson, Creating the Constitution: The Convention of 1787 and the First Congress, (University Park, Pennsylvania: 1993), 24 also notes, Many of the delegates, students of classical history, no doubt remembered that the plebeians of Rome had supported Caesar, not Brutus. There were enough examples in the Greek city states of popular demagogues becoming tyrants to enable Polybius (6.1-9) to construct a cycle of types of government in which democracy deteriorated into mob rule and then into despotism. 54See Thomas P. Govan, “Alexander and Julius Caesar: a Note on the Use of Historical Evidence,” William and Mary Quarterly 32 (1975): 475-80; Padover, 32; and Douglas Adair, “A Note on Certain 23 T. L. Simmons (“Greek Ruins,” 43), the author of the forthcoming book Climbing Parnassus: A Defense of Classical Education, regarding the Founding Fathers concludes, It is no accident, then, that so many who gathered at Philadelphia to declare independence and a decade later to draft a constitution were men who had apprenticed themselves to Thucydides, Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, and Cicero, and who could debate at length on the various constitutional forms of the classical world before they chose one for the new American nation. We owe our very existence as a people in great part to classical learning. In fact, so prevalent were the references to antiquity during the Convention that on June 28th, as Chinard relates, “Franklin rose in despair. The Convention threatened to degenerate into a classical meeting.”55 of Hamilton’s Pseudonyms,” William and Mary Quarterly 12 (1955): 282-97. 55“Polybius and the American Constitution,” 227; cf. 225: “There were few occasions when the ancient writers were not called upon to provide precedents and illustration for the different speakers.” 24 CHAPTER THREE The third focus of this paper will deal directly with Montesquieu himself. If he relied heavily on Polybius, then even those who cite Montesquieu as their source for the doctrine of separation of powers are indirectly citing ancient authority. In fact, Montesquieu had not only read Polybius but also produced summaries of his work, as R. Shackleton attests:56 It was his practice to make extracts or synopses of books which he had read, and the accident of mention in the Pensées or elsewhere discloses that he had made extracts from . . . [among others] . . . Polybius. M. Hulliung admits that “more often than not, Montesquieu derived his inspiration from works of Aristotle, Polybius, or some other classical author.”57 Shackleton adds that the doctrine of separation of powers was “a theory of considerable antiquity . . . Montesquieu made an attempt to bring it into line with the advances in the study of science.”58 Chinard is more blunt, charging that Montesquieu “did nothing but generalize and modernize the lessons of ancient history.”59 M. E. G. Duff ultimately wonders, “if Polybius had not led the 56Montesquieu: a Critical Biography (Oxford University Press, 1961), 153; cf. 158, 233-34. 57Montesquieu and the Old Regime (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), 2; cf. Friedrich’s encyclopedia articles “Constitutions and Constitutionalism,” International Encyclopedia of Social Sciences (New York: Macmillan, 1968), 321; and “Separation of Powers,” Brittanica 20 (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1970), 227. 58“Montesquieu, Bolingbroke, and the Separation of Powers,” French Studies 3 (1949): 25. 59“Polybius and the Constitution,” 223. 25 way, . . . [whether] Montesquieu’s study of the greatness and decadence of the Romans would ever have been written.”60 In Chapter 11 of Spirit of the Laws, Montesquieu proposes balance of power between “the legislative, the executive in respect to things dependent on the law of nations, and the executive in regard to matters that depend on civil law”61 (11.6.1: la puissance législative, la puissance exécutrice des choses qui dépendent du droit des gens, et la puissance exécutrice de celles qui dépendent du droit civil). These powers are essentially the same as Aristotle’s three portions of the state: the deliberative, the executive, and the judicial (Pol. 1298a-b);62 however, as Gummere (“Heritage of the Classics,” 75) notes, “the doctrines of Aristotle were well known to the Colonials long before Montesquieu lifted the sixth book of the Politics into his Esprit de Lois.” An important study of the classical foundation of Montesquieu’s work is Lawrence M. Levin’s dissertation, The Political Doctrine of Montesquieu’s Esprit Des Lois: Its Classical Background (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1936; reprint, 1973).63 In his introduction, Levin points out (VIII-IX): 60“Presidential Address,” Transactions of the Royal Historical Society 11 (1897) 1. Montesquieu is more of a “conduit” than a source (Ames and Montgomery, 23; cf. 26). 61English translations of Montesquieu throughout are taken from Thomas Nugent, trans., The Spirit of the Laws (New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1949; reprint 1959). 62See above, note 16. See below, note 71. 63For more on Montesquieu, see P. M. Spurlin, Montesquieu in America: 1760-1801 (New York: Octagon Books, 1969); and A. M. Cohler, Montesquieu, Comparative Politics, and the Spirit of American Constitutionalism (Lawrence: University of Kansas, 1988). 26 Montesquieu cites certain historical instances of the manner in which the balance of powers functioned in antiquity . . . it is hardly likely that he was not aware of any of the ancient texts that stress the idea, and it is unlikely that these ancient texts were not partially instrumental at least in bringing to his attention a fundamental aspect of his theory: the system of checks or balances as a means of promoting the welfare of the state. Of course, one of the ancient texts Montesquieu read was Polybius’ Histories. For, paraphrasing the ancient historian, Montesquieu describes the government of Rome in the time of the kings (Spirit, 11.12; cf. Polybius 6.11.11): the constitution was a mixture of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy; and such was the harmony of power, that there was no instance of jealousy or dispute. la constitution étoit monarchique, aristocratique et populaire; et telle fut l’harmonie du pouvoir, qu’on ne vit ni jalousie, ni dipute. When Montesquieu (Spirit, 11.17) turns to describe the balance of power in Rome during the Republic, he explicitly cites the Histories: so great was the share the senate took in the executive power, that, as Polybius (Book VI) informs us, foreign nations imagined that Rome was an aristocracy. la part que le sénat prenoit à la puissance exécutrice étoit si grande, que Polybe dit que les étrangers pensoient tous que Rome étoit une aristocratie. The passage in question is 6.13.8-9, in which Polybius himself states: So that again to one residing in Rome during the absence of the consuls the constitution appears to be entirely aristocratic; and this is the conviction of many Greek states and many of the kings, as the senate manages all business connected with them. e)c wÂn pa/lin o(po/te tij e)pidhmh/sai mh\ paro/ntoj u(pa/tou, telei/wj a)ristokratikh\ fai/neq ) h( politei/a. oÁ dh\ kai\ polloi\ tw=n E ( llh/nwn, o(moi/wj de\ kai\ 27 tw=n basile/wn, pepeisme/noi tugxa/nousi, dia\ to\ ta\ sfw=n pra/gmata sxedo\n pa/nta th\n su/gklhton kurou=n. Even more significant than Montesquieu’s direct reference to Polybius are the locations of the two passages, both the citing passage and the one cited. Montesquieu’s citing passage falls in the middle of Chapter 11 of Spirit of the Laws, the same chapter which sets forth his principles of separation of powers and the system of checks and balances. The passage cited from Polybius is taken from the middle of his description of the Roman Constitution. of this is twofold. The significance First, that Montesquieu, when composing his theory of checks and balances, turned to the ancient historian. Second, that any careful reader of Montesquieu’s Chapter 11, after coming upon Polybius’ name, would check the reference and in doing so would find Polybius’ entire theory of a)naku/klwsij and the mixed constitution. Was Montesquieu indispensable to the Founding Fathers? B. Wright (171) is inclined to believe that “had Montesquieu never published his treatise, the [state] constitutions . . . would not have been [different].”64 He argues that discussions on the separation of powers had been a long tradition among English political scientists--e.g., 64 Rossiter (74) echoes this sentiment, when he states: Whatever government the Framers might propose to the people, it would certainly have to be . . . divided, checked, and balanced— not because Montesquieu . . . had taught them to celebrate the beauties of such government but because this was the pattern toward which America had been moving from the beginning. Sellers (222) agrees, “the United States Constitution continued the development towards Rome’s Polybian model that had been evident in the English and earlier state constitutions.” 28 Harrington, Locke, and Blackstone--well before Montesquieu.65 Harrington, a friend of King Charles I, had incorporated elements of checks and balances into his utopian work Oceana.66 It was perhaps this association that spurred Charles I (some 50 years before Montesquieu was born) to claim that England enjoyed separation of powers. For, in a proclamation that Corinne C. Weston (23-24) terms “one of the most influential ever made on the nature of the English government,” and Anderson (24) readily identifies as “based on the old Polybian balance of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy,” King Charles (Answer to the XIX Propositions, 1642) declares: The experience and wisdom of your Ancestors hath so moulded this government out of a mixture of these monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, as to give this Kingdom the conveniences of all three, without the inconveniences of any one so long as the balance hangs even between the three Estates, the King, the House of Lords, and the House of Commons, and they run jointly on in their proper channel.67 65Cf. Gummere, “The Heritage of the Classics in Colonial North America,” 75. See also J. G. Pocock, ed., The Political Works of James Harrington (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977). 66B. Bailyn (Origins, 20) notes, “the value of such a balance was commonly endorsed by sixteenth-century writers, and in the early seventeenth century it came to characterize the working of the English constitution.” John Adams, in his A Defense of the Constitutions, also dedicates a chapter to Harrington (Works, 4.427-34). For the history of mixed constitution in England, see Corinne C. Weston, English Constitutional Theory and the House of Lords, 1556-1832 (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1965). 67Charles I, quoted in Melvin Richter, The Political theory of Montesquieu (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 87; cf. McDonald, 48; B. Bailyn, Origins, 20. For the evolution of the three estates in England, see Michael Mendle, Dangerous Positions: Mixed Government, the Estates of the Realm, and the Making of the Answer to the XIX Propositions (Tuscaloosa, Alabama: University of Alabama Press, 1985). 29 If Montesquieu described the English as having a mixed constitution a full generation after Charles I had done so, can Montesquieu be credited as the author of the balance of powers?68 Gummere (“Heritage of the Classics,” 75) admonishes: It should also be remembered that the idea of representation as well as the theory of checks and balances was not only correlated with the current studies of the Colonials, but traced back to the ancient sources. Bailyn specifies a Polybian lineage for the theory, when he states:69 No one set of ideas was more deeply embedded in the British and the British-American mind than the notion, whose genealogy could be traced back to Polybius, that liberty could survive in a world of innately ambitious . . . men only where a balance of the contending forces was so institutionalized that no one contestant could monopolize the power of the state without effective opposition.70 Indeed, the entire Declaration of Independence is predicated upon the notion that the people share equally with the crown the powers of government.71 68On May Day 1660, the English Parliament decreed, “according to the ancient and fundamental laws of this kingdom, the government is, and ought to be by King, Lords, and Commons,” William Cobbett, ed., Parliamentary History of England, vol. 2 (London: 1806) cols. 24-25. 69Faces of the Revolution (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1990), 76. 70J. Bryce (1.29) concurs: No general principle of politics laid such hold on the constitution-makers and statesmen of America as the dogma that the separation of these three functions [executive, legislative, and judicial] is essential to freedom. It had already been made the groundwork of several State constitutions. 71Bailyn (Faces of the Revolution, 76) notes that the American Colonists “presumed that the three main socio-constitutional contestants for power--the monarchy, the nobility, and the people-had an equal right to share in the struggle for power.” See Gummere’s comment above, page 27. 30 Even among the Founding Fathers, there is some ambiguity concerning the role Montesquieu played. This is understandable, since Montesquieu not only was against an elected executive but also was opposed to the power of the legislative to impeach him (Spirit 11.18; cf. B. Wright 170). Reflecting on John Adams’ A Defense of the Constitutions, B. Wright (178) notices, “Montesquieu is quoted, but without comment. Harrington and Polybius he apparently found better suited to his needs.” Concerning the Convention itself, B. Wright (184) adds: Although Montesquieu was referred to seven or eight times during the debates in the Convention, only once was his authority appealed to in support of the separation principle, and then by Madison.72 Even when James Madison does cite Montesquieu as the oracle of the doctrine of separation of powers, he falls short of calling him its originator when he says (Federalist Papers, 47): If he be not the author of this invaluable precept in the science of politics, he has the merit at least of displaying and recommending it most effectually to the attention of mankind. 72The eight references to Montesquieu during the Convention are: Records 1.71, 308, 391, 485, 497, 580; 2.34, 530. 31 CONCLUSION Polybius’ work on the separation of powers antedates Montesquieu’s considerably. His system includes checks and balances, some of which are the same as the American Constitution’s. Many of the Founding Fathers had read Polybius and even quote him on this issue during the Federal Convention of 1787 and the subsequent State Conventions on ratification. 73 Those who did not read him directly in Greek still had available to them translations in French, Italian, Latin, and English.74 Others had available the summaries of Polybius in John Adams’ A Defense of the Constitutions, released in the same year as the Federal Convention. Montesquieu himself borrowed heavily from Polybius and other ancient authorities. Therefore, if Madison’s comment regarding separation of powers is right, that “the oracle who is always consulted and cited on this subject is the celebrated Montesquieu” (Federalist Papers 47), surely then it is only fair to consider Polybius its very god. 73McDonald, 81; cf. Miles, 338: “Framers of the American Constitution, like the earlier republicans, often referred to Polybius’ theory of mixed government.” 74Polybius was one of the Greek authors whom Pope Nicholas V had translated into Latin (c. 1450); see Arnaldo Momigliano’s “Polybius’s Reappearance in Western Europe,” in Essays in Ancient and Modern Historiography (Wesleyan University Press, 1977), 79-98; cf. Boas, 626. Polybius’ balance of powers also influenced Niccolò Machiavelli (Discourses 1.1). Richard (127) first states, “Machiavelli practically copied Polybius’ discussion of the degeneration of the simple forms of government into his Discourses on Livy” and later concludes (128), “like Polybius and Cicero, Machiavelli ascribed Roman greatness to the gradual development of mixed government there.” 32 BIBLIOGRAPHY PRIMARY SOURCES: Adams, John. The Familiar Letters of John Adams and his Wife Abigail Adams. New York: Hurd and Houghton, 1876. ________. The Works of John Adams. Edited by C. F. Adams. Boston: Charles C. Little and James Brown, 1851. Aristotle. Politics. Translation by H. Rackham. The Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1944; reprint, 1990. Diogenes Laertius. Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Translation by R. D. Hicks. The Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1925; revised 1931; reprint, 1995. Dionysius of Halicarnassus. The Roman Antiquities. Translation by E. Cary. The Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1943. Franklin, Benjamin. The Papers of Benjamin Franklin. Edited by B. B. Oberg. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992. ________. The Works of Benjamin Franklin. Edited by Jared Sparks. Boston: Hilliard Gray and Company, 1839. Herodotus. The Persian Wars. Translation by A. D. Godley. The Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1920; reprint, 1990. Harrington, James. The Political Works of James Harrington. Edited with an Introduction by J. G. A. Pocock. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977. Hamilton, Alexander. The Papers of Alexander Hamilton. Edited by H. C. Syrett. New York: Columbia University Press, 1962. ________, James Madison, and John Jay. The Federalist Papers. Edited with an Introduction by Clinton Rossiter. New York: Mentor, 1961. Hunt, G. and J. B. Scott, ed. Index to the Debates in the Federal Convention. New York: 1920. Jefferson, Thomas. The Papers of Thomas Jefferson. Edited by Charles T. Cullen. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983. Madison, James. Notes of Debates in the Federal Convention of 1787. Introduction by Adrienne Kock. New York: W. W. Norton: 1969; reprint, 1987. 33 ________. The Papers of James Madison. Edited by W. T. Hutchinson and W. M. E. Rachal. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1962. Montesquieu, Charles Louis de Secondat Baron de. The Spirit of the Laws. Translated by Thomas Nugent. With an Introduction by Franz Neumann. New York: Hafner Publishing Company, 1949; reprint, 1959. Plato. The Laws. Vol. 1. Translation by R. G. Bury. The Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1926; reprint, 1984. Polybius. The Histories of Polybius. Vol. 3. W. R. Paton. The Loeb Classical Library. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1928. Translation by New York: G. Sowersby, E. Millicent, ed. Catalogue of the Library of Thomas Jefferson. Washington: Library of Congress, 1953. Thucydides. History of the Peloponnesian War. C. F. Smith. The Loeb Classical Library. Harvard University Press, 1935. Translation by Cambridge: United States. Constitutional Convention (1787). The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787. Edited by Max Farrand. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1911; reprint, 1937, 1966. _____. State Conventions. The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution. Compiled by Jonathan Elliot. Philadelphia: 1861. _____. The Federalist and Other Constitutional Papers. Edited by E. H. Scott. Chicago: 1894. SECONDARY SOURCES: Adair, Douglas. “A Note on Certain of Hamilton’s Pseudonyms.” William and Mary Quarterly 12 (1955): 282-97. Anderson, Thornton. Creating the Constitution: The Convention of 1787 and the First Congress. University Park, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993. Ames, R. A. and Henry C. Montgomery. “The Influence of Rome on the American Constitution.” Classical Journal 30 (Oct. 1934): 19-27. Bailyn, Bernard. Faces of Revolution: Personalities and Themes in the Struggle for American Independence. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1990. ________. The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967. 34 ________. The Origins of American Politics. A. Knopf, 1968. New York: Alfred Banning, Lance. “Jeffersonian Ideology Revisited: Liberal and Classical Ideas in the New American Republic.” William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser., 43 (Jan. 1986): 4. Bartholomey, Paul C. “Checks and Balances.” Article in Encyclopedia Americana. Danbury, Connecticut: 1989. Boas, George. “Cycles.” Article in Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1968; reprint, 1973. Brink, C. O. and F. W. Walbank. “The Construction of the Sixth Book of Polybius.” CQ n.s.4 (1954): 97-122. Bryce, James. American Commonwealth. Company, 1911. New York: Macmillan Carey, George W. “Government.” Article in Encyclopedia Americana. Danbury, Connecticut: 1989. Carrithers, David W. “Montesquieu, Jefferson and the Fundamentals of 18th-Century Republican Theory.” French-American Review 6 (Fall 1982): 160-88. The Casper, Gerhard. Separating Power: Essays on the Founding Period. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997. Chinard, Gilbert. Honest John Adams. Gloucester, Mass.: Peter Smith, 1964; reprint, 1976. ________. “Polybius and the American Constitution.” In The American Enlightenment, ed. Frank Shuffelton, 217-37. Library of the History of Ideas. New York: University of Rochester Press, 1993. ________. “Thomas Jefferson as a Classical Scholar.” American Scholar 1 (April, 1932): 133-43. Cobbett, William. 1806. Parliamentary History of England. London: Cohler, Anne M. Montesquieu, Comparative Politics, and the Spirit of American Constitutionalism. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1988. Cunliffe, Marcus. The American Heritage History of the Presidency. Kenneth W. Leish, ed. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1968. Davis, Richard Beale. Intellectual Life in the Colonial South 1585-1763. Knoxville: University of Tennessee, 1978. 35 Duff, Mountstuart E. Grant. “Presidential Address” (1897). Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, New Series, 11 (1897): 1-17. Quoted in “Polybius.” Classical and Medieval Literature Criticism. Detroit: Gale Research, 1988. Eadie, John W., ed. Classical Traditions in Early America. Ann Arbor: Center for the Coordination of Ancient and Modern Studies, 1976. Friedrich, Carl Joachim. “Separation of Powers.” Article in Encyclopaedia Britannica. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1970. ________. “Constitutions and Constitutionalism.” Article in International Encyclopaedia of Social Sciences, ed. David L. Sills. New York: Macmillan Company: 1968. Fritz, Kurt von. The Theory of the Mixed Constitution in Antiquity. Roman History, ed. T. James Luce, Jr. New York: Arno Press, 1975. Grant, Michael. The Founders of the Western World. Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1991. New York: Govan, Thomas P. “Alexander Hamilton and Julius Caesar: A Note on the Use of Historical Evidence.” William and Mary Quarterly 32 (1975): 475-80. Gummere, Richard M. “The Classical Ancestry of the Constitution.” Chap. in The American Colonial Mind and the Classical Tradition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1963. ________. “Church, State and Classics: The Cotton-Williams Debate.” CJ 54 (Jan. 1959): 223-32. ________. “The Classical Politics of John Adams.” Public Library Quarterly 9 (Oct. 1957): 172. Boston ________. “The Heritage of the Classics in Colonial North America: An Essay on the Greco-Roman Tradition.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 99 (April 1955): 68-78. ________. “John Adams, Togatus.” (April 1934): 203-10. Philological Quarterly 19 ________. “John Dickinson, the Classical Penman of the Revolution.” CJ 52 (Nov. 1956): 81-87. ________. “Some Classical Side Lights on Colonial Education.” CJ 55 (Feb. 1960): 223-32. Hulliung, Mark. Montesquieu and the Old Regime. University of California Press, 1976. 36 Berkeley: Hutchison, David. The Foundations of the Constitution. With an Introduction by Ferdinand Lundberg. Secaucus, New Jersey: 1975. Kilpatrick, James J. “U.S. v. Clinton.” Sep. 1998, 46-47. National Review, 28 Levin, Lawrence M. The Political Doctrine of Montesquieu’s Esprit des Lois: Its Classical Background. New York: Publications of the Institute of French Studies, Columbia University, 1936; reprint, 1973. Lutz, Donald S., ed. Colonial Origins of the American Constitution: A Documentary History. Liberty Fund, 1998. Mayer, David N. The Constitutional Thought of Thomas Jefferson. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1994. McDonald, Forrest. Novus Ordo Seclorum: the Intellectual Origins of the Constitution. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1985. Mendle, Michael. Dangerous Positions: Mixed Government, the Estates of the Realm, and the Making of the Answer to the XIX Propositions. Tuscaloosa, Alabama: University of Alabama Press, 1985. Miles, Edwin A. “The Young American Nation and the Classical World.” In The American Enlightenment, ed. Frank Shuffelton, 237-53. Library of the History of Ideas. New York: University of Rochester Press, 1993. Momigliano, Arnaldo. “Polybius’s Reappearance in Western Europe.” Essays in Ancient and Modern Historiography, 79-98. Wesleyan University Press, 1977. Mullet, Charles F. “Classical Influences on the American Revolution.” CJ 35 (Nov. 1939): 92-104. Padover, Saul K., ed. The World of the Founding Fathers: Their Basic Ideas on Freedom and Self-Government. New York: A. S. Barnes and Company, 1960. Persons, Stow. “The Cyclical Theory of History in EighteenthCentury America.” American Quarterly 6 (Summer 1954), 147-63. Podes, Stephan. “Polybius and His Theory of Anacyclosis: Problems of Not Just Ancient Political Theory.” History of Political Thought 12 (1991): 577-87. Rahe, Paul A. Republics, Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1992. 37 Reinhold, Meyer. Classica Americana: The Greek and Roman Heritage in the United States. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1992. Richard, Carl J. The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994. Richter, Melvin. The Political Theory of Montesquieu. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977. Robatham, Dorothy M. “John Adams and the Classics.” England Quarterly 19 (Mar. 1946): 91-98. Rossiter, Clinton. 1787: The Grand Convention. W. Norton, 1987. New New York: W. Ryffel, Heinrich. Metabolh\ politeiw=n: der Wandel der Staatsverfassungen. Bern: 1949; reprint, New York: Arno Press, 1973. Sellers, Mortimer N. S. American Republicanism: Roman Ideology in the United States Constitution. New York: New York University Press, 1995. Shackleton, Robert. Montesquieu: a Critical Biography. London: Oxford University Press, 1961. ________. “Montesquieu, Bolingbroke, and the Separation of Powers.” French Studies: a Quarterly Review 3 (1949): 25-38. Simmons, Tracy Lee. 1998, 42-43. “Greek Ruins.” National Review, 14 Sep. Spurlin, Paul Merrill. Montesquieu in America: 1760-1801. New York: Octagon Books, 1969. Taylor, Hannis. The Origin and Growth of the English Constitution. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin, 1889. Taylor, Thomas Marris. A Constitutional and Political History of Rome: From the Earliest Times to the Reign of Domitian. London: Methuen and Company, 1899. Walbank, F. W. A Historical Commentary on Polybius. Clarendon Press, 1957. Oxford: ________. Polybius. Sather Classical Lectures. Vol. 42. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972; paperback 1990. ________. “Polybius and the Roman State.” 239-60. 38 GRBS 5 (1964): ________. “Polybius on the Roman Constitution.” (1943): 73-89. CQ 37 Walsh, Correa Moylan. The Political Science of John Adams: a Study in the Theory of Mixed Government and the Bicameral System. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1915. Weston, Corinne Comstock. English Constitutional Theory and the House of Lords, 1556-1832. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1965. Wiltshire, Susan Ford, ed. The Usefulness of Classical Learning in the Eighteenth Century. Washington, D.C.: American Philological Association, 1975. Wood, Neal. “Essentials of the Mixed Constitution.” Chap. in Cicero’s Social and Political Thought. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991. Wright, Benjamin F. “The Origins of the Separation of Powers in America.” Economica 13 (May 1933): 169-185. Wright, Louis B. “Thomas Jefferson and the Classics.” Proceedings of the American Philological Society 87 (1944): 223-33. 39 POLYBIUS AND THE FOUNDING FATHERS: THE SEPARATION OF POWERS Marshall Davies Lloyd MALS 590 SEPTEMBER 22, 1998 Diane Hatch Professor of Classics DEDICATION This paper is presented to Dr. Linda J. Piper, my beloved Ancient History Professor, on the occasion of her retirement from the Classics and History departments at the University of Georgia. Five years or so ago, she first introduced our class to the Greek historian Polybius and the wonders of anacyclosis. We bemoaned the fact that Polybius receives too little credit for his contributions to the U.S. Constitution. The class discussion that day was one of the finest experiences I ever had at Georgia. On that day, Dr. Piper expressed a wish that someone would write a paper on Polybius’ influence on the Founding Fathers. Now that Dr. Piper is retiring, all I could think of this semester has been how I would like to present her this paper as a small token of thanks for her enthusiasm both for the classics and her students, for her willingness to serve on my thesis committee, and most especially for her attending my wedding. Dr. Piper, as you retire, I hope you will never forget what you mean to the lives of so many. I despair for Georgia and grieve for the students for whom Roman History now will be a faint shadow of the experience we once had with you at the helm. I wish you the best in the years to come. My father has thoroughly enjoyed his retirement from the Classics. I hope you will too. God bless you. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS DEDICATION ............................................... ii INTRODUCTION .............................................. 1 CHAPTER ONE ............................................... 4 CHAPTER TWO ............................................. 14 CHAPTER THREE ............................................ 25 CONCLUSION ............................................... 32 BIBLIOGRAPHY ............................................. 33 iii