Subjects, Objects, and Market Exchange: The Emergence of Sale of Goods as Law of Consumption Noah Quastel, B.A.(Hon.) M.A, L.L.B. LLM Candidate, University of Victoria, Faculty of Law; Member of the Law Society of British Columbia May 20, 2006 Submitted as paper for RC-24 Sustainable Consumption and Society Draft copy--Please do not cite without author’s permission. A significant number of theorists now construe consumer goods as elements within “commodity networks”, accentuating the ways persons and things are intertwined in extensive and at times global systems. The approach emphasizes that commodities broadly construed as objects for sale (not just their raw ingredients) are what they are because of the way diverse actors use, distribute, design, manufacture, grow, mine or cultivate them.1 By focusing on particular goods such as coffee, running shoes or wooden furniture, researchers who use the approach accentuate the ways in which consumers are enrolled in networks through their purchase decisions, and that networks are constituted by cultural and symbolic aspects. The approach thus places emphasis on agents’ subjectivity. The commodity networks approach helps scholars provide an account of the ways human discourses and self-understanding become translated into practical activities and relationships with distant ecosystems and human communities. Commodity networks are instances of the global capitalist economy and provide a smaller scale reference point for understanding the links between trade, the environment, geo-political power and the enrollment of consumers. 1Commodity network theorists include: Leslie, D., and Reimer, S. (2004). Knowledge, ethics and power in the home furnishings commodity chain. Geographies of Commodity Chains. Alex Hughes and Suzanne Reimer. New York and London, Routledge: 250; Hughes, A. and Reimer, S. (2004). Introduction. Geographies of Commodity Chains. Alex Hughes and Suzanne Reimer. London and New York, Routledge: 1.; Goodman, D. and Goodman, M. (2001) "Sustainable Foods: Organic Consumption and the Socio-Ecological Imaginary." In Exploring Sustainable Consumption: Environmental Policy and the Social Sciences, edited by Maurie Cohen and Joseph Murphy, 97-119: Elsevier Science Ltd. Raynolds, L. (2004) “The Globalization of Organic Agro-Food Networks” World Development Vol. 32, No. 5 p. 725-741) Whatmore, S. and L. Thorne (1997). Nourishing Networks: Alternative Geographies of Food. Globalising Food: Agrarian Questions and Global Restructuring. D. Goodman and M. J. Watts. New York, Routledge 287-304 1 Commodity network analysis provides a unique description of the exchange process whereby goods are traded: “Such webs not only connect firms through vertical commodity exchange relationships, but also bind together additional agents through the multi-directional flows of information and materials that variously support these exchange relationships”.2 Exchange is one of the central components of networks and agents’ subjectivity as part of networks. Exchange in western capitalist countries is mediating by legal constructions. To understand how exchange works in our societies we need to look at the laws of contract and Sale of Goods. These laws remain largely unchanged since the nineteenth century and are central to the enablement of commodity networks. They developed in concert with many of the central commodity networks of the modern world which we owe to English colonialism, such as tea, sugar, coffee and textiles. Through acting on person’s subjectivity and providing a legal picture of the exchange process these laws in part constitute existing commodity networks. Insofar as sustainable consumption concerns the problems with these networks, it must also concern the exchange processes that lie behind them. The network theorist’s understanding of exchange suggests that individual consumer transactions are part of larger networks by which commodities are produced, distributed and come to market. The approach sees exchange as part of a series of relationships that bind persons together and facilitate the flow of goods in commodity networks. The theory is a second order account, on the part of theorists, to explain the exchange phenomena. Actual agents may in fact not share this picture at all. Individual consumers may be totally unaware or unconcerned with the wider relationships to distant workers or ecosystems that are embodied in the simple decision to buy Nike running shoes or Chilean wine. When we look at the history of contract law and Sale of Goods we see that precisely this sort of unreflective understanding of exchange is both worked into and justified by the law. Not all consumption involves the purchase of goods, but when persons do buy consumer goods, they enter into consumer transactions. Understanding consumption requires understanding the way contract law and Sale of Goods works to structure our relationship to consumer transactions, the ways we think of ourselves, and the objects we buy. 2 Hughes and Reimer, 2004 ibid. at p. 5 2 Understanding consumption through consumer transactions requires investigating into the contingent “architectonics” of exchange—the way subjects (persons), objects (consumer goods) and exchange are discursively presented and actually practiced in historical specific contexts, and how these can change. To speak of contingent architectonics is to recognize that there are a multitude of different ways of understanding exchange and practicing exchange relationships. Architectonics is also a way of bringing out how the difference concepts work together and mutually interact. Network theorists have analyzed the ways fair trade goods such as coffee make for different commodity networks.3 If consumers, producers and others engage in networks through calculated profit maximization alone different networks develop (with different effects for workers and ecosystems) then if consumers are to pay a “fair price” to guarantee farmers’ earn sufficient amounts to meet basic human needs. Different modes of exchange make the difference to commodity networks and the people who are involved with them. Investigating the history of Anglo-American contracts and the Sale of Goods that grew out of contract law in the nineteenth century is a way of understanding markets and the ways persons and things are shaped in them: It is a way of uncovering the “historical ontology”4 of consumption and its practices. The laws of contract and Sale of Goods plays a mediating role in bringing categories of subject, object, and exchange into play on a daily level; they are, “constitutive rather than declaratory of the ontology upon which they are based”.5 Semiotic and discourse analysis suggests that textual moves “constitute” the readers of such texts, that is, position them as having particular selfunderstandings and as acting in certain ways.6 Law, like any language, is a way of world-making, one discourse amongst many that potentially influences our selfunderstanding.7 We are not merely pushed and pulled by laws that exert power over us from the "outside". Instead “we come, in uncertain and contingent ways, to see 3 Whatmore, S. and L. Thorne ibid. at p.295 Foucault, M. (1997) “What is Enlightenment?” -- Ethics Subjectivity and Truth. Essential Works of Foucault 1954- 1984 Volume One. ed. P. Rabinow. New York: The New Press. See also Hacking, Ian (2002) Historical Ontology. Harvard University Press. 5 Pottage, A. (2004) “ Introduction: The Fabrication of Persons and Things” Law, Anthropology and the Construction of the Social: Making Persons and Things. Cambridge University Press. Ed. A. Pottage and M. Mundy at p. 9 6 Dugdale, A. (1999) "Materiality: Juggling Sameness and Difference" Actor Network Theory and After, edited by John Law and John Hassard. London: Blackwell at p. 125 7 Goodman, N. (1978) Ways of Worldmaking. Harvester Press. 4 3 ourselves as law sees us”.8 Tracing the historical development of concepts of subjects, objects and exchange in contract law helps make this apparent. Law becomes in Bruno Latour’s phrase a “plug-in” –a vehicle that provides us tools for becoming who we are, and which we can consciously choose or find ourselves already utilizing as we are “made to be an individual/subject”, a “psycho-morph” that “literally lend you the shape of a psyche”.9 In the interlocking concepts of subject, object and exchange found in the Anglo-American tradition of contract and Sale of Goods, understandings of objects become ways of understanding the self. Over time, persons and things have come to be understood as distinct entities rather than as interrelated through processes with other humans and non-humans. By tracing the history of contract we can see how it is that subjects and objects have come to be understood as disentangled from social and ecosystem constraints. This paper provides an overview of the history and the central concepts of classical contract law and concentrates on a close reading of formative cases in the law of Sales. It focuses on England in the nineteenth century because this is when the basic changes in the law occurred which shape practice in the exchange of goods in the AngloAmerican world. This law parallels the American case law which came to be codified in the United States Uniform Commercial Code and also the Untied Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods. The principles of contract developed at this time provided the “natural and organic conditions of the private sphere and the grundnorms for international commercial relations.”10 A comprehensive history of these areas is well beyond the scope of this paper. Rather, the focus is on a historically informed overview of the concepts of subjects, objects and exchange in contract cases concerning the sale of goods in the nineteenth century and key points which illustrate the problematics of exchange for those interested in commodity networks and consumption. 6.2 Early modern markets The story requires us to go back to the development of the common law in England. Taking a historical approach helps to see the shifting terrain on which laws have developed and variously employed different values concerning market place conduct, Sarat “Legal Education in Law Schools” at p. 132 Latour, B. (2005) Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor Network Theory. At p. 213, but see general description of “plug-ins” from 204-213. 10 Cutler, C. (2003) Private Power and Global Authority. Cambridge University Press. at p. 161 8 9 4 the establishment of prices and the concepts and normative basis for the enforcement of agreements. Two early features are important for setting the stage for the development of modern contract law in the eighteenth and nineteenth century. One concerns the rephrasing of the concept of contract in law. The second concerns the regulation of consumer markets and its links to the wider social and economic transformations of England before and during the industrial revolution. At least since the 1540s the Kings’ Bench operated as a commercial court, and one could sue in assumpsit upon the occasion that money was owed for a trade in goods.11 Confusion was well cleaned up by Slade’s Case (1602) which established that an agreement to exchange in the future (an “executory contract”) implied an undertaking or assumpsit to pay what was due under it and so provided for the right to recover debts. The case law also reveals that the law at the time was certainly sufficient to allow for a robust trading economy: Bates’ Case (1606) is a famous pre-Civil War case concerning the rights of the monarchy to tax international trade, and concerns the import of currants from Venice. Basic frameworks in the common law were thus in place for the resolution of commercial disputes for centuries before the industrial revolution. Critical legal scholars and historians in the 1970s made much of the transitions in contract law in the nineteenth century, hoping to link contract law to the development of the industrial revolution and what Karl Polanyi had thirty years earlier referred to as the “great transformation” in England. Horowitz argued that contract was created by capitalism and the need for future planning,12 such as in futures markets on stock exchanges. Similarly, Atiyah argues that the new formulation of contract was tied to economic liberalism and laissez faire values.13 However, if one looks just at the common law cases the picture that emerges, in the movement from assumpsit to contract in the nineteenth century, is one largely of reconceptualization. Many older actions are given new names and new theoretical justifications. However, this reconceptualization of contract was tied to the rise of the new political economy and laissez faire markets and did give rise to changes in the way cases were decided. The nineteenth century features a subtle but important shift in the legal concept of exchange. 11 Baker, J.H. Introduction to English Legal History. Butterworths, 1979. at p. 283. Horowitz, M. J. (1974). "The Historical Foundations of Modern Contract Law." Harvard Law Review 87(5). 13 Atiyah, P.S. (1979) Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract. Clarendon Press. Oxford. 12 5 Plenty of cases in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries demonstrate how one could sue if horses were not delivered, money was owed, or jewels were fakes. The difference under the new law of contract that was reformulated first by Judge Mansfield in the late eighteenth century and then by subsequent judges in the nineteenth, was two fold. First, under assumpsit the idea was that someone had voluntarily agreed to do an act, in exchange for a sufficient consideration (such as money). Having paid or agreed to pay money or some other personal sacrifice, one party then relied upon the other. In the case the agreement fell apart, this was considered as a nonfeasance, a breach of obligations one was relied upon to perform. The party in the wrong had acted deceitfully.14 The relationship between the parties was cast as a series of interdependencies, foremost of which was reliance. These considered the nature of the relationship and practices the parties were involved in. One did not owe money on a transaction because of a mere promise, but because the relationship created a dependency on one person in relationship to the other. In the nineteenth century the concept of exchange would be recast—with considerable effects in the decision of particular cases—as contract in terms of the meeting of wills of two persons, in terms of mutual obligations created by bare promises. When wider social events are factored in, it becomes apparent that the eighteenth century and early nineteenth century were times of a weakened government, a rapidly expanding and globalizing commodity economy, and social pressures brought by industrialization and urbanization.15 Assumpsit was merely one potential avenue of legal redress available that had been available in the early modern period. Just as contract and Sales of Goods are today only a small part of the elaborate framework of regulation of consumer goods, the Middle Ages and early modern periods in England featured a complex arrangement of weights and measures, and controls of markets in the Assize of Bread and Assize of Beer. These provided for detailed regulation of local markets and embodied a variety of social values. A paternalistic model existed not only in law, but in the consciousness of the labouring poor who at times would riot in support of the system that protected them from at times exorbitant prices. There were specific directions for 14 Baker, ibid. at p. 281 Thompson, E. P. (1971) “The Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the Eighteenth Century. Past and Present. 50: 76-136; Hamilton, Walton H. (1931) “The Ancient Maxim Caveat Emptor” Yale Law Journal Vol. XL. No. 8, p. 1133 15 6 different classes of persons. It was specified when farmers could sell their grains (not in the fields, only to dealers in specific situations), to the poorer classes first, in small parcels, with duly-supervised weights and measures in specific markets. Dealers were regulated, with laws against forestalling, regrating and engrossing. They were not allowed, for instance, to buy standing crops, nor might they purchase to sell again (within three months) in the same market at a profit, or in neighboring markets. The Assize of Bread regulated the price of loafs by weight and in relation to the ruling price of wheat. 16 “Law was conceived of as protective, regulative, paternalistic, and above all, a paramount expression of the moral sense of the community.”17 These regulations began to wither by the time of the industrial revolution. The history of markets in England in the modern period is not one of a slow progression towards government regulation of an otherwise natural and preexisting market. Rather, the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries were periods of deregulation as traditional controls in the marketplace were gradually loosened or simply fell apart to meet the new demands of industrialization. The breakdown of the Assize system and the relevant impoverishment of protections for shoppers in the nineteenth century helped turn the new law of contracts into consumer law. The result of this transformation was that consumer transactions came to be seen as only a special case of the larger class of commercial transactions. Shifts in social and economic conditions in the late eighteenth century also contributed to making contract central in the lives of the majority of people. Industrialization and urbanization meant that the majority of the population shifted from peasant farmers to wage labourers. This brought the reconfiguration of person from the status bound position of peasantry to that of free contractors for labour dependent on money transactions and contract concerning employment.18 Corresponding to urbanization was a shift towards purchased food as the basis of subsistence: An open marketplace came 16 Thompson, ibid. at p. 85-7 Atiyah, ibid. at p. 167 citing Horowitz, M.. (1975) “the Rise of Legal Formalism”19 American Journal of Legal History 251 18 Orth, J. V. (1998). Contract and the Common Law. The State and Freedom of Contract. H. N. Scheiber. Stanford, California, Stanford University Press: pp. 44 to 65, at p. 55 ,detailing the relationship between the shifts in labour and contract 17 7 to dominate.19 In short, the masses became consumers and their consumer transactions legally enframed by contract law. The person as a contracting agent would come to serve as a key mode of legal subjectivity. 6.3 Will Theories and Classical Contract In late eighteenth and early nineteenth century England the common law went through a period of systematization. The idea of a separate and systematized “contract law” so named, as opposed to the older actions on the writ of assumpsit, was new to common law. In the European civil law tradition it had a longer history.20 Earlier continental jurists had invoked the concept of will as part of contract making, but this was laden with concepts of “equivalent value” and “just price” which worked to ensure a variety of protections. Natural lawyers such as Grotius and Pufendorf used concepts of “equality in exchange”. In an exchange, parties must receive equivalent because each wishes to exchange and not to enrich the other party at his own expense. They saw it as intrinsic to the contracting process and implying substantive terms, such as that a seller would warrant goods against defects.21 Will theories began to emerge in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, whereby jurists thought of a contract as merely an expression of the will of the parties who were creating the contract. Increasingly legal scholars in England came to discuss contracts as a unique discipline, and do so by reference to the raw agreements of the parties. William Paley’s Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (1785) stands out as one of the first texts to give a central place to contract. Paley argued that “exchange” was the one principle that could ever become universal with regard to the distribution of wealth.22 Consequently a market price was always a fair price.23 Powell’s Essay Upon the Law of Contracts and Agreements (1790) focused on a narrow set of principles for describing all contracts. He argued that the consent of the parties alone fixes the just price of any thing, without 19 Walvin, James (1997). Fruits of Empire: Exotic Produce and British Taste, 1660-1800. New York University Press at p. 111 20 Gordley, J. (1998). Contract, Property, and the Will--The Civil Law and Common Law Tradition. The State and Freedom of Contract. H. N. Scheiber. Stanford, California, Stanford University Press: pp. 66 to 88.at p. 74 21 Grotius de iure bellis ac acis II.xii.9.1; Pufendorf de iurure naturae. V.iii.I-3 cited by Gordley, bidi. at p. 72 22 Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy Book III, part 1. Chapter III cited by Atiyah at p. 403. 23 Book III, Chapter VII, Atiyah, at p. 403 8 reference to the nature of things themselves, or to their intrinsic value.24 Pothier’s Law of Obligations (1806), a French text, was welcomed by English judges and lawyers and gave expression to the notion that a contract is primarily an agreement based on the intention of the parties and it is their will which crates the legal obligation. These will theorists regarded the will as the source of all the terms of the contract. They no longer claimed that these terms rested on the principle of equality or the nature of the parties’ agreement. This is “essentially the theory of contractual liability which passed into English law, and has remained there ever since”.25 By mid-nineteenth century judges commonly referred to contract as based on the intention of the parties. The will theory represented a significant reconfiguration of the exchange process. The older law of assumpsit configured a series of socially constituted or even “objective” evaluative considerations of appropriate action within relationships, but the new classical contract approach now said it was the bare agreement of the parties that provided any substance to their mutual obligations. Once contract was defined in terms of the will of the contracting parties, it was then used as first principle to explain as many legal rules as possible.26 So the change with will theories is that they introduce the will or agreement of parties without any attempt to delimit what could legitimately be willed. They regarded any attempt to interfere with the express terms of the contract in the interest of justice a paternalistic.27 Implicit in the will theory, and even the idea of contract as centered on choice was the “two-party model” of the contract. The contract terms are provided by the meeting of the minds—the mutual promises—of the two persons engaged in the contract. Of course multi-party contracts are possible—allowing for the meeting of many more minds—but the important point was that other potential stakeholders or affected parties were not conceived of as having a role in the contract formation, or in the “law” that the contracting parties ascribed to themselves. The two party model portrays the contract in terms of the subjective position of the parties, ignoring both the effects on other 24 Horowitz, M. J. (1974). "The Historical Foundations of Modern Contract Law." Harvard Law Review 87(5) at p. 918 25 Atiyah, at p. 400 26Gordley, J. (1998) “Contract, Property, and the Will—The Civil Law and the Common Law Tradition” The State and Freedom of Contract H. H .Schieber. Stanford University Press, pp. 66 to 88 at 67 27 Gordley, ibid. at p. 72 9 stakeholders or ways they themselves might think the contract should be arranged. It thus works as a “frame”, focusing the significance of the contract away from further linkages and relationships between the ways the two parties might characterize it. Early nineteenth century commentators such as Verplank “saw that if value is solely determined by the clash of subjective desire, there can be no objective measure of the fairness of a bargain”.28 Because contract only concerned the interests of the parties involved, no other stakeholders could use the judicial system or otherwise interfere in contractual relations. Consumer transactions were made private. Will theory was a jurists theory: it originated in Roman, Christian and natural law theories, and was modified by an Enlightenment led crisis of faith in Aristotelian based concepts of equality in exchange.29 This was a modernist response to the bogeyman of objective value. However, it was rapidly accepted into English law and formed the unifying conceptual basis for “classical contract theory”. Atiyah provides ample evidence of the way the nineteenth century saw a new breed of lawyers and judges comfortable with the free market ideals of David Ricardo and Adam Smith and sought to remold the law of contracts as part of the centerpiece of a legal system structured around contractual relationships. Will theory provided the tool to achieve these goals. Courts could concern themselves only with the formal aspects of the contract such as formation, and compliance with the contract terms. They would not need to enquire into whether the substantive terms were fair or not. The effect of will theory was that it became the natural ally of everyone with philosophical, political and economic theory that stressed freedom of choice. Contract law could enable commercial transactions without interfering in how parties might want to structure their own affairs. Patrick Atiyah notes that the classical law of contract embodied “the model of the market”.30 The idea was to construct a formalized system, based on the ideals of bargaining between free individuals, and the contract reflecting their mutual intentions. The effect of acceptance of the will theory into classical contract law was the effective adoption of a model of exchange transactions which brought new concepts of subjects and exchange. For Atiyah, in such a model no man is his brother’s keeper: The parties 28 Horowitz, ibid. at page 225. Gordley, ibid. at p. 82 30 Aityah, p. 403 29 10 bargain or negotiate and neither party owes any duty to volunteer information to the other, nor is he entitled to rely on the other except within the narrowest possible limits. Each party must study the situation, examine the subject-matter of the contract, and the general market situation, assess the future probabilities, and rely on his own sources of information. The content of the contract--the terms, price and subject matter-- are entirely for the parties to settle. It is assumed that the parties know their own minds, that they are the best judges of their own needs and circumstances that they will calculate the risks and future contingencies that are relevant, and that all these enter into the bargain and finally, this bindingness is, in principle, a matter of pecuniary calculation.31 This provides in crystallized form an expression of the subject of exchange as autonomous and calculating. It provides a picture of the mode of exchange as a one off discrete transaction between autonomous individuals. The classical picture, although self-described as formal, neutral and resting on basic principles, in fact embodies particular concepts of the person and of exchange. Classical contract law sought to embody a complete explanation of law in terms of basic principles of individual freedom to bargain. This formalistic analysis, however, contains within it a misplaced self- understanding: It misses the degree to which it is in practice oriented towards specific concepts of human well-being and flourishing. The mere rigid application of formal principles became biased towards those who would best flourish under them, and this would often be those persons with relative bargaining power and strength, who were capable of excelling in the rough and tumble world of competitive markets. The classical picture was, in effect, more than just another name for a laissez-faire market; it provided the legal ground rules and sanction for such a market. The concept of the person utilized in the theory is that of an “individual”: “Classical contract law represented a world of totally autonomous individuals free to transact on any terms they wished and thereby to control their own destinies”.32 By construing a sharp distinction between the interests of different persons, classical contracts presented a normative world of individual self-reliance, and entitlement to enjoy benefits without an obligation to share or sacrifice them to the interests of others. 31 Atiyah, at p. 413 Feinman, J. (1989). "The Significance of Contract Theory." Cincinnati Law Review 58: 1283 at p. 1310 32 11 In this conception, choice stands at the centre of person. Classical contract law created a world of private ordering where parties created their own laws by agreement. Liability was imposed through consent, and this was grounded in the conception of a social world as composed of independent freedom-seeking individuals. “Freedom of contract is grounded in the concept of choice. People should be free to choose which contracts they will enter into, on what terms, and which contracts they will avoid”. 33 In the case of a contract for employment there is no cause to second judge wage levels or working conditions because these are assumed to have been freely negotiated by free and equal individuals. The will theory and classical contract created the exchange process as we are familiar with it today. Because the bargaining process occurs between autonomous individuals, it takes on a specific form, but also implies a certain conception of the persons involved. Emile Durkheim, for instance, noted that “In the fact of exchange, the various agents remain outside of each other, and when the business has been completed, each one retires and is left entirely on his own”.34 Ian Macneil calls this the “discrete transaction”.35 More recently Michel Callon refers to a system of the “clean break” whereby the parties momentarily meet and then are “quits”.36 In each case, the point is the same: the model transaction involves an isolated one off event, between two relatively equally situated arms-length bargainers, engaged with each other for the sole purpose of the contractual exchange, and expressing their complete contractual obligations in their mutual promises. ”Contract” is defined through the offer and acceptance rubric, where all the parties’ obligations are objectified in the stated agreement. The result is that parties relate to one another as “calculative agencies”.37 While the concept “consumer” would not come into play until the twentieth century, we have the clear outlines here of the basic model of the rational actor as found in micro-economics and which later becomes the consumer. 33 Feinman, J. (1983). "Critical Approaches to Contract Law." UCLA Law Review 30: 829. citing Holmes, O. (1881) The Common Law, W. Story (1844) A Treatise on the Law of Contracts Not Under Seal 34 Quoted in MacNeil, Ian (1980) The New Social Contract. Yale University Press. At p. 95 35 MacNeil, ibid. at p. 2 36 Callon, M. (1998) "Introduction: The Embeddedness of Economic Markets in Economics." In The Laws of the Markets, edited by Michel Callon, 1-57: Basic Blackwell/The Sociological Review, 1998 at p. 17 37 Callon, ibid. p.19 12 The classical contract picture provides concepts of subjects and exchange that embody a concept of commodity networks. The network is implicitly understood as composed of different people who enter into contracts with one another, as free and equal legal subjects, so the consumer engages with the network by way of contract, and is quits with the network after the contract is fulfilled. A particular person need only relate to the network in terms of pecuniary self-interest and need not have a particular idea of other aspects of the network. Self-interest is to be understood in terms of commodity ownership itself—albeit in forms such as money or real or personal property. Because relations are only with the next person over in the chain, there is no need for considerations about effects on further parties or ecologies in the network to be brought to bear on the exchange. Thus far, I have been drawing on a series of works by twentieth century legal realist and critical legal studies scholars that have taken an interest in understanding the law of contracts as a social institution.38 Writer such as Atiyah, Horowitz, and Feinman were concerned with problems of wealth distribution and the role of contracts and the courts in supporting capitalist social relations in the nineteenth and twentieth century. For contemporary readers concerned about consumption and its social and environmental effects, it remains important to understand consumer transactions as one type of capitalist social relation. Consumption related concerns involve issues of how exchange is part of global commodity networks that link consumers to distant other persons and ecosystems. This brings additional concerns about the material flows and resources usages of the economy. Capitalist social relations depend on the transformation of ecosystems and the non-human parts of the planet into commodities. The issue of objects and their role in exchange is central to such an analysis. In the classical contract law approach that developed in the nineteenth century trade relations are structured and understood as part of the will of the parties—that is of individuals—and this comes to bear upon the way objects are understood. The will theory carries with it a sharp distinction between persons (persona) and things (res). 38 Realists who have made these critiques include Roscoe Pound and Karl Lewellyn. The tradition is continued in the 1970s and 1980s by Patrick Atiyah, Morton Horowitz, Jay Feinman, Roberto Unger and Duncan Kennedy among others. 13 Alain Pottage, writing about property law, notes that “the distinction between persons and things is a foundational theme in Western society, and that legal institutions have played an essential role in constituting and maintaining that distinction.”39 The concept of will was historically linked in Roman, Christian and natural law to the persona, as “subjectum juris”, “according to which legal rights… are the legal clothing of natural individuals or a set of quasi-prosthetic forms that realize and articulate a subjective will.”40 While initially a legal fiction the concept of persona hardened into a dead metaphor and became a principle mode of self-understanding. The person/thing distinction both exemplifies and is productive of the modernist ideal whereby objects are understood as dead or inert things, and subjects as exercising control and jurisdiction over them. The will theory, in rendering subjects intentions the sole ground of value, results in a situation were “objects and relations have value only as individuals choose to accord it to them in the marketplace.”41 By configuring objects as subject to the will of their owner as obtained in exchange, the theory works to eviscerate the social lives and prior history of goods. The will theory was an academic theory found in new treatises, and it does not exactly match all of contract practice. English contract law has always included equitable concepts and the idiosyncratic views of particular judges that make it hard to match the theory with actual judicial decision-making. In what follows, the analysis shifts to case law and commentary on it to see how the will theory and commercial practice worked to forge legal concepts of objects and exchange. This is most striking in the decisions concerning the principle of “caveat emptor”. This principle holds that buyers must take precautions in the market place and have no rights to information or to guarantees concerning the goods they buy. The decisions of caveat emptor are one area where the judges were willing to constrain the plurality of judicial practice to ensure a new uniform approach to subjects, objects and exchange. 6.4 Caveat Emptor Pottage, A. (2004) “Introduction: The Fabrication of Persons and Things” Law, Anthropology and the Construction of the Social: Making Persons and things. Cambridge University Press. Alain Pottage and Martha Mundy (eds.) at p. 4. 40 Pottage, A. (2001) “Persons and things: an ethnographic analogy” Economy and Society (30):1 p. 112-18 at p. 119 41 Feinman, (1983) ibid. at p. 839 39 14 Caveat emptor became in the nineteenth century, “the apotheosis of nineteenth century individualism”.42 It was linked to the principles of liberal political economy by writers in the early nineteenth century such as William Paley and J.R. McCulloch. They argued that free competition in the marketplace was the best way to secure quality goods and reasonable prices.43 The linking of caveat emptor to free markets, and the deregulation of the English economy has lead a number of writers to identify caveat emptor with, as Hamilton expresses it in his famous article, “the refusal of public authority, through legislature and judiciary, to accord effective protection to the purchaser”.44 Horowitz notes, citing the early nineteenth century critic Verplank, that caveat emptor represents “the nineteenth century departure from the equitable conception of contract”.45 This interpretation suggests that when the courts shifted away from caveat emptor in the 1850s and 1860s it represented the beginnings of intervention into the market. An alternative view is that caveat emptor and laissez faire are not the same thing at all. As Lewellyn explains: “the level of dealing (for purposes of dealers, and of civil suits), can shift far toward caveat venditor, and has done so, without disturbing business, or disturbing the unregulated character of business competition.”46 For Lewellyn, if the social context changes such that commercial men and consumers come to expect sellers to bear the risks for bad goods, then the courts can adopt these new customs without imposing new forms of control on the market. On this view, when the courts shifted to the view that sellers of goods implied that their wares were safe, this did not represent significant forms of market intervention.47 Both approaches miss over the ways cases concerning caveat emptor embodies more basic issues of nature of persons, things, and exchange that the cases are debating. The predominant debate in nineteenth century cases concerned the issue of how to account for important aspects of goods that could not be found by the buyers’ inspection. The courts were confronted with the difficulty that the market model provided no direct 42 Atiyah, at p.464 Paley, W. (1790) Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy, Book III, part 1 Chapter VII; J.R. McCulloch , The Principles of Political Economy. Cited by Atiyah, at p. 467 44 Hamilton, W. (1931) “The Ancient Maxim Caveat Emptor” Yale Law Journal Vol. XL. No. 8, p. 1133 45 Horowitz, ibid. at p. 946 46 Lewellyn, K. On Warranty of Quality and Society (1936) 36 Columbia Law Review. 699 47 Lewellyn, ibid at p. 718 43 15 means for buyers to know about important background conditions for goods, but at the same time the integrity of the market depended on this. The result was considerable instability and conflict in the law as different judges took different positions. If a person was buying a physical object then personal inspection would be paramount. However, if a person was buying what was agreed between the parties, then the courts could the buyer relied on the words of the seller: Whatever was handed over would need to comply with the way the goods were described in the initial agreement, regardless of the buyers’ inspection. A series of common law cases that underlie the shift from caveat emptor to the Sales of Goods Act encapsulate this debate. Both conceptions squarely construe transactions in the harsh commercial logic of self-interest and mutual promises. A whole range of cases in the early nineteenth century involve the rigorous proclamation of “caveat emptor”. In Parkinson v Lee (1802)48 there was a sale of hops (as in beer) sold by “sample”—that is, the buyer could inspect some of the hops and then order more “of like goodness and quality”. Six months after the initial inspection, the buyer received hops from the seller’s warehouse. Unbeknownst to the seller, the hos came watered, and then rotted. The extent of belief in caveat emptor can be gleaned from the plaintiff buyer’s own argument (or his lawyers). He was willing to acknowledge that caveat emptor applied in the context “where a defect is apparent on the face of a commodity; there it may fairly be presumed that the buyer exercised his own judgment upon it; at least it was his own fault if he did not”.49 The plaintiff’s lawyers were even willing to concede that “Whatever natural defects or infirmities are incidental to the subject matter, the buyer must take the risk of; such as those with which horses are afflicted,” (referring to the common law tradition of caveat emptor in the sale of horses). Given the state of the law, the plaintiff argues the narrow point that the commodity should answer the sample. The plaintiff invoked the earlier fair price doctrine, arguing that as a fair price was paid, the commodity should be in a merchantable condition at the time of the sale. Otherwise the buyer might receive a different thing from that which he stipulated for, and which it was the understanding of both parties that he should have. The defendant argued that every person entering into a contract in the course of trade is presumed to have a competent skill to enable him to judge of the commodity he bargains for. He knows the defects to which it is liable as well from fraud as from natural causes, and he 48 49 2 East 314, 102 E.R. 389 102 E.R. at 391 16 speculates accordingly. The court bought this argument. Judge Gross ruled that: “It is the fault of the buyer that he did not insist on a warranty”.50 Judge Lawrence: “I must suppose that each party was equally well acquainted with the commodity bargained for…. the plaintiff might, if he pleased, have provided against the risk”.51 Parkinson v. Lee was just one of many cases that upheld caveat emptor in cases of inspection. In Shepherd v Pybus (1841)52 a builder sold a new barge from his wharf. Relief was denied to the plaintiff who after taking possession found the barge to be leaky and in bad shape, on the basis that he had had opportunity to inspect the barge on his own. In Emmerton v Mathews (1862) 53 the courts okayed the sale of meat found to be unfit for human food on the basis that the buyer had inspected. As late as Smith v. Hughes (1871) the courts upheld a contract for oats different from what the buyer said he wanted on the basis that he had inspected a sample of what was provided. Lord Blackburn commented that “there is no legal obligation on the vendor to inform the purchaser that he is under a mistake which has not been induced by the act of the vendor.”54 We see in Parkinson v. Lee and these further cases the idea that the objects of exchange begins as things for which a physical inspection could almost completely provide an accurate analysis. The courts emphasize that the buyer can inspect the article and depend on his own judgment. This is the domain of what Llewellyn has coined “primitive-mercantile”—the domain of “on the spot horse trading” and country vegetable markets. We have, then, a reference to the ideal of the physical marketplace, where goods are handled and seen and the rational agent, self-sufficient in making 50 at 2-East-322. At 2 East 323 52 3 Manning and Granger 868, 133 E.R. 1290 53 7 Hurlstone and Norman 586, 158 ER 604 54 At para. 10. see also Burnby v Bollett (1847)16 Meeson and Welsby 644, 153 ER 1348. Farmer buys dead pig from another farmer. Turns out putrid. Caveat emptor when the defendant is not in the business or trade. This same faith in judgment and first hand inspection also explains the “patent exclusion clause” in the Sale of Goods Act (1893). Chalmers, the author of the Act, directly references two cases: Chanter v. Hopkins (1838) 4 M and W. 399 and Olliviant by Bayley (1843). 4 M and W. 399. Chanter involved a patented apparatus for a “smoke-consuming furnace” to help in making beer. “The [seller] had performed his part of the contract by sending that machine; and it is the [buyers] concern whether it answers the purpose for which he wanted to use it, or not.” So the fact that the object is an “ascertained article” means that there is no particular fitness for purpose. This reasoning is extended in Ollivant v. Bailey: because something patented is an “ascertained article” then the issue of fitness of purpose does not arise. 51 17 judgments, and the things traded as mere objects. This reflects the idea we see in Blackstone who talks of property in chattels (personal property such as consumer goods) as over “things which could be detected by the senses”.55 The emphasis on visual inspection works to construe goods in terms of their physical and phenomenal features. The approach sees the objects of consumer transactions as “things”. There is no way that process features could ever form part of consumers’ decision unless these were independently stipulated by the parties. While a buyer can make inquiries, sellers may well not provide answers. The effect of the competitive market may be that sellers are not likely to provide answers and are likely to not have made any inquiries themselves. It could be expected that no answers would be forthcoming. We have here an historical instance of the process product distinction whereby things on the market are understood in terms of their physical features alone and buyers are given no rights to know about origins.56 In the case of latent defects, where inspection would not show the problem, consumers would have to take their chances. Any actual reliance that consumers vested in sellers that was not protected by an express warranty was not legally protected. This was such an obvious hole in the theory that it would have to give way to a different approach that could accommodate latent defects. Caveat emptor helps ensure that goods become “disentangled”. As Michel Callon writes “To construct a market transaction, that is to say to transform something into a commodity, it is necessary to cut the ties between this thing and other objects or human beings one by one. It must be decontextualised, dissociated and detached.”57 The concept of disentanglement helps show how subjects, objects and exchange become assembled together. For Callon, disentanglement follows from the “clean break and 55Blackstone Commentaries 2 at 17. See also See, also, for the thing view of property Vandevelde, G. (1980) “The New Property of the 19th Century: The Development of the Modern Concept of Property” Buffalo L. Rev. 29: 325 56 For contemporary discussion of this distinction see Kysar, D. (2004). “Preferences for Processes: The Process/Product Distinction and the Regulation of Consumer Choice” Harv. L. Rev. Col 118, No. 2 525-640 57 , M. (1998). Introduction: The embeddedness of economic markets in economics. The Laws of the Markets. M. Callon, Basic Blackwell/The Sociological Review: 1-57 at p. 18 see also . Callon, M. (1998). “An Essay on framing and overflowing: economic externalities revisited by sociology”. The Laws of the Markets. M. Callon, Basil Blackwell and The Sociological Review; Callon, M. (1999). Actor-network theory--the market test. Actor Network Theory and after. J. L. a. J. Hassard. London, Blackwell. 18 then quits” idea of the discrete transaction. What makes the transaction discrete is that each party gets a bundled-thing, and does not become enmeshed in further series of social relations. In gift exchanges when one gives another person a gift, the recipient becomes obligated in some ways to return the gift. There is a kind of debt to be repaid: “If the thing remains entangled, the one who receive it is never quits”. The constitution of exchange relationships in terms of the disentangled conception requires removing the various bonds of social relationship and interdependencies which usually accompany human association. In order to allow market relationships to be discrete, the persons must be disentangled and this requires that the things be removed from their background. All this is implicit in the idea of the exchange of property as “free alienation”. One severs the thing from its past and delivers a new object, without legal (or evaluative, moral, emotional, or other) bonds to the buyer: “The alienation of a thing is its dissociation from producers, former users, or prior context”.58 There is a two way relationship between the concept of discrete exchange and the concept of disentangled objects. The fact that things are seen as objects allows for disentanglement, and the fact that discrete contracting requires disentanglement works to turn things into objects.59 Likewise, the autonomous individual is made autonomous through the configuration of exchange relationships as discrete; simultaneously relations are only discrete because individuals are always operating at arm’s length from one another. For persons who 58 Thomas, N. (1991) Entangled Objects. Exchange, Material Culture and Colonialism in the Pacific. Harvard University Press. Citied in Callon, 1998, at p.20 59 The thing theory has more recently been advocated as “in rem theory”. The initial formulation is in Hohfield, W.H. (1913) “Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning ‘ (1913) 26 Yale Law Journal 16, and “Some Fundamental Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning ‘ (1917) 26 Yale Law Journal 710. “Hofeldian In Rem Theory” has been recently developed in Merril, T. and Smith, H. “What Happened to Property in Law and Economics? 111Yale L. J. 357 (2001); Merril, T. and Smith, H. (2001) “the Property-Contract Interface, 101 Colum. L. Rev. 773; Merril, T. and Smith, H. (2000), Optimal Standardization in the Law of Property: the Numerus Clausus Principle 110 Yale L. J. 1 9. Merrill and Smith distinguish property from contract (and feel that law and economics misses this). Contracts involve only a small number of persons who can actually work out the terms of the deal, and for that reason contracts can be quite complicated. And the contract is all over when the immediate participants finish with it. Property, on the other hand, can easily survive its current owners. A given piece of property may be bought and sold over and over, and the more durable the goods, the more times those goods will show up in the market. So property’s legal consequences attach to the thing ( in rem) as opposed to the persons involved. The theory notes that property has to be kept simple, so that new generations of owners have a good idea about what they are getting, and so that current buyers and sellers do not need to search out extensive relationships that might affect their purchase—exactly Callon’s point. 19 already see themselves as autonomous individuals, disentanglement enables the perpetuation of that self-understanding and way of being. The more traditional reading of caveat emptor is that the concern for individualized judgment had to do with the need for an easy resolution to problems of consumer protection in a deregulated market. What the courts were doing was providing a system for private vigilance, alerting potential victims to danger. Caveat emptor, on this reading is a kind of utterance that hails the consumer with its literal meaning—Buyer, Beware!— and so stimulate buyers to take all kinds of precautions against uncommunicative sellers. A sufficiently vigilant public could then ensure that shoddy goods would disappear from the market, without the need for legislation or litigation.60 If buyers knew there was a possibility of a legal remedy to save them, they might become sloppy in inspecting goods. The result would be more frauds than under caveat emptor.61 This reading reinforces rather than undermines the idea of the new contract law as designing an individualized practice of exchange. Here the courts are using their power to emphasize the importance of individual judgment, to insist that consumers become accustomed to act in just the ways that the market ideal insists. The use of this warning presupposes the “thing” idea of the market and the self-interest model of the consumer. Here we have clear commands from the judiciary that the person should take on the market ideal of subjectivity, and become the legal subject of commercial exchange. “Not until the nineteenth century did judges discover that caveat emptor sharpened wits, taught self-reliance, made a man-- an economic man—out of the buyer, and served well its two masters, business and justice”.62 Arjun Appadurai has noted that objects are not always commodities, in the sense that they can pass into different uses at different times: we relate to a purchased product very differently than to something we find in a forest, but the purchase may in fact have 60 Atiyah, at page at p. 465, citing the Second Report of the Mercantile Law Commission (185455). The technique proved to be failure: Reports of the conditions in which most English people lived in the early nineteenth century show remarkable levels of impoverishment and lack of protection in the marketplace. Bread adulterated with chalk was widely prevalent. Marx, Karl (1976) Capital. Volume 1. Penguin. at p. 278, n 14.citing Report of the Select Committee on the Adulteration of Food 1855, and Dr. Hassal’s Adulterations Detected, 2nd ed.. London 1861. also Thompson, ibid. at p. 874. 61 Mentioned in Kennedy, D. (1976) "Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication." Harvard Law Review 89 (1975-1976): 1655 at p.1695 citing Kessler, F. (1964) “The protection of the consumer under Modern sales law, part 1” Yale Law Journal. 74: 262 62 Hamilton, ibid. at p. 1186 20 once have been found by chance and cherished as such. Hence, we should speak of a “commodity situation” in the social life of an object as “the situation in which its exchangeability (past, present, or future) for some other thing is its socially relevant feature”.63 It would follow that the conceptual framework surrounding exchange works to reinscribe the thing as a commodity. Caveat emptor works to perform things as things as shoppers are enjoined by judges to take caution. There is an ideological aspect to this: The “thing” concept reinforces the notion of the autonomous individual by disentangling the consumption of objects from social bonds. It can be understood as part of complex discourses that emerge to help normalize and justify the existing social order and ease the consumers’ soul. In the early nineteenth century most consumers would have had little knowledge of the working conditions in distant tea plantations but they certainly experienced first hand local factory conditions, which included fourteen to sixteen hour days for pre-adolescent children.64 Prominent social movements sought to change those conditions. This included popular agitation for labour legislation such as in the “Ten Hours” or “Factory Movement” which pressed for the labour rights of working children and adults.65 It also included later efforts such as William Morris’ arts and crafts movement, which attempted integrated reform of the design of products as well as humanizing the ways in which they were made.66 There were strong motivations for the consuming classes to deny their daily complicity in such hardship and seeing consumer goods as products rather than processes helps in this regard. Laissez-faire, caveat emptor and disentangled subjects and objects co-existed in an assemblage formation. Legislation Laissez-faire values were prominent in England’s Parliament in the first half of the nineteenth century Nevertheless, Parliament did continue some legislative provisions relating to consumer issues. The new construal of contracts implied a particular Appadurai, A. (2005) “Commodities and the Politics of Value” Rethinking Commodification. Ed. Martha Ertman and Joan Williams. New York University Press. At p. 37 64 Thompson, E.P. (1980) The History of the English Working Class. Penguin. [1963] at p. 373 65 Thompson, ibid. at p. 371-84 66Foster, J. (1994) The Vulnerable Planet: A Short Economic History of the Environment Monthly Review Press. at p. 67, Kimmel, Michael S. “The Arts and Crafts Movement: Handmade Socialism or Elite Consumerism? Contemporary Sociology Vol. 16 No. 3 (May 1987) 388-390. 63 21 understanding of the relationship of exchange to government regulation which continues to have force to the present. The English state was increasingly under pressure to respond to specific problems such as the mistreatment of emigrants (hence the Passenger Acts), cholera epidemics (hence the Nuisance Removal Act (1848)) or food adulteration. In many cases the “legislation was largely dictated by the shear force of events” rather than philosophical principles.” 67 In England and its colonies there was no explicit constitutional right to freedom of contract, and the liberal politics of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill acknowledged a role for government involvement in the economy. Contractual freedoms fell out of the property and contract system, and the absence of laws restricting commerce. There were laws concerning adulteration of food, including those to prevent adulteration of tea (1730, 1777), to prevent burnt vegetable matter from being mixed with coffee beans (statutes of 1718, 1724 and 1803) to prevent the suppression of alum in bread (1758, 1822, and 1836) and for beer (1761, 1816, and 1819). Once techniques of microscopic analysis became available in the 1850s, more aggressive and effective legislation for adulteration of food could be passed.68 Weights and measures legislation was passed from 1795 through to 1859, providing for inspectors to enter shops, examine weights and certify them as accurate, and to create standardization across the country. In possible response to the caveat emptor principles of Parkinson v. Lee Parliament passed the Hop Trade Acts, in 1808, and 1814, designed to identify the names and addresses of hop growers on bags, with the hope of avoiding fraud in the sale of hops. The 1866 Act noted that the previous ones had been ineffectual, and sought to specifically prohibit the mixing of different qualities so that a sample might not truly match the bulk. Parliament was more willing than the courts to acknowledge the deficiencies of caveat emptor. Other legislative provisions impacted more seriously on traditional realms of contract. The mid nineteenth century saw the emergence of laws limiting first the hours of child labourers (The Factories Act 1833) and then restrictions on the hours of work of all workers (Factories Act 1853).69 The first Alkali Act in 1863 paved the way for a modest 67 Atiyah, at p. 555 Atiyah, at p. 546-7 69 Atiyah, p. 539-40 68 22 environmental and administrative system for dealing with industrial pollution. It acted as a template for central state regulation of pollution” that continues to the present.70 We can trace the ways employment laws might change the way commodities are produced, or how food adulteration laws might improve the quality of food, and these do represent changes to commodity networks and the objects of exchange. The limited powers of the administrative state did provide for minor processes of re-entanglement of goods although initially in terms of relationships between producers, vendors and the state, rather than any thickening of ties between persons. The effect of the will theory was that once the bureaucratic state began to introduce legislation in the nineteenth and early twentieth century reformers saw this not as cohering with, but as a justifiable interference with the autonomous and coherent body of private law. 71 When the state came to impose workplace laws—governing maximum hours and minimum pay—these ceased to be conceived of as contract laws, but rather a removal of an arena from the realm of contract into a realm of legislative control. Commercial activity, including consumer transactions, were insulated in a zone of privacy and construed as free from the substantive constraints on contract activity found in public regimes such as employment law. The result was a conceptual separation of economics and politics, of private and public activities.72 Where no public laws interfered, parties were free to engage in contract without concern as to substantive requirements. Critical legal scholars have made much of the ways in which the division of public and private has contributed to a naturalization of modes of economic ordering. This contributes to a refusal of the liberal state or courts to challenge such modes, both in failing to recognize the political dimensions of contract activity, including consumption, and in shifting political discourse away from regulation of the economy.73 However, the administrative state even in the mid nineteenth century did feature regulations, laws, and policies that changed the face of contracting behaviour: The public-private distinction then, as it is now, was more a feature of liberal politics and economic theorizing than a 70 Coyle and Morrow, ibid. p. 136 Gordley, ibid. at p. 85 72 Cutler, C (2003) Private Power and Global Authority. Cambridge University Press at p. 161) 73 Cutler, C. ibid. at p. 1781Petter, A. and Hutchinson, A.(1988) ” Private Rights and Public Wrongs” University of Toronto Law Journal (33) 3; Horwitz, J. (1982) “The History of the Public/Private Distinction” 130 U. Pa. L.R. 1423 a5 1426 71 23 reflection of any sharp rules undergirding actual government practice concerning consumption. The market ideal operated as a guiding force in Parliament, and when it was used, as it often was, it was to leave issues of governance to contract and private ordering. Caveat Emptor and Title The thing theory was never a very good theory, but rather the effect of the judges’ attempts to maintain individualism, faith in individual choice and disentanglement. The theory was unstable because it meant blocking out obvious aspects of goods not discernible by inspection. The case of title to goods has always illustrated the limits to which courts are willing to accept visual inspection alone. Title concerns aspects of the “world behind the product”. It’s a central part of the business of courts to maintain the system of private property, and preserving property potentially comes into conflict with the free circulation of goods. If caveat emptor were truly the rule, individual buyers would have no basis to know whether, when paying for a good, they were also obtaining the right to have the good. In traditional law of personal property the rule in the common law has always been that a seller can only sell as good title as he has, so if a buyer pays for stolen goods he or she risks those goods being reclaimed by the original owners. No amount of inspection can help the buyer in this regard. So if the system is to be designed to protect property rights of both sellers and buyers, some provision is needed beyond simple declarations that buyer beware unless purchasers are to seek out the histories of each thing they buy. The entire framework of markets in England made such an approach impossible, Middle men, shippers and merchants would sell wares on the streets with potentially mysterious originations. Whereas trade wants disentanglement, property seeks reentanglement.74 Concerns about property foreshadow many future concerns about the hidden life of goods such as ecological concerns about process. 74 Holman v. Johnson [1775-1802] ALL E.R. Rep. 98; 1 Cowp. 341; 98 E.R. 1120 represents an extreme case of Judge Mansfield’s attempt to disentangle the tea trade. The British government in the eighteenth century retained large custom tariffs on tea, with the result that most tea in England was smuggled (Fruits of Empire, p. 109). In Holman Mansfield upholds a contract, made in France, in which both parties knew the purpose was to smuggle tea. His reasoning is that there was nothing illegal in the contract. Unfortunately for tea smugglers legality also breeds entanglement, hence the case remains an anomaly. See, Gedge and others v. Royal Exchange Assurance Corporation [1900-03] ALL E.R. Rep. 179; Foster v. Driscoll, Lindsay v. Attfield, Lindsay v. Driscoll, [1928] All E.R. Rep. 130. 24 The tradition in London of market overt represents probably the most pro-market solution available. Market overt was a particular kind of market whereby so long as goods were openly displayed, buyers for fair market value could always take good title. The market overt represents a kind of victory for the forces of free circulation. Buyers are freed of the need to inquire as to the origination of the goods, and sellers need not ask too many questions of their suppliers, nor worry as to what to say to customers. So it created a climate of unconcern over the history of products. The problem is that the system runs roughshod over the property rights of those who have been robbed or defrauded of their goods—they are asked to patrol markets themselves as their only security. Efforts in the twentieth century in England have been to limit the institution.75 In British Columbia which by historical contingency adopted the market overt rules, the courts have ruled that there are no such markets in the province.76 Outside of London, where property rules would still matter to the buyer, buyers could always make a point of asking the seller whether the goods came with good title, and a positive response would then take the form of a warranty concerning the goods that would bind the seller. In Crosse. v. Gardner (1688) the Chief Justice Sir John Holtd acknowledges that the mere affirmation that oxen properly belonged to the seller gave the buyer a right of action. At common law, if the vendor knew that he had no title and concealed that fact, he was held responsible to the purchaser for a fraud or deceit.77 If the vendor was mistaken the risk fell on the buyer rather than on the seller. However, in the title case, silence was tantamount to an affirmation by the seller that she has title. Caveat emptor only applied, then, concerning the possibility that the seller is innocently (or perhaps negligently) mistaken. 75 Attempts at judicial limitation gain speed in the early 20th C: see Clayton v. Le Roy [1911-1913] ALL E.R. Rep. 284, [1911] 2 K.B. 1031—In the court of appeal Moulton notes that market overt is “unique custom and one which does not seem to me to be very much in keeping with modern ideas, and it certainly is not a custom which is likely to receive any further judicial extension” See also Secretary of State for War v. Wynne and others [1904] All ER Rep. 352, [1905] 2 KB 545 (Market overt protection to bona fide purchasers does not apply to Crown Property). 76 British Columbia is the only Canadian province to have rules concerning market overt. Fridman .G.H.L. Sales of Goods in Canada, 4th Edition. Carswell. 1995 at page 146-7. The courts have ruled that there are no market overt in the province. Westcoast Leasing Ltd. v. Westcoast Communications Ltd. (1980) 22 B.C.L.R. 285 (B.C.S.C.) at 291. 77 deceit (See Coke .Ltt. 102, a, ad 3 Co. rep. 22a ; Sprigwell v. Allen (1) Early v. Garet and Wiliamson v. Allison. 25 The courts did at times apply caveat emptor in matters of title.78 The limited application of caveat emptor in title cases can be seen in the case of Morley v. Attenborough (1849).79 In this case there was a a harp that kept changing hands. First a lease, then a lessee that leaves it at a pawnbroker, a pawnbroker who sells it at auction and a new buyer who loses it to the original owner for want of title. The new buyer sues the pawnbroker. The problem is, he never got a warranty of title. Parke, the presiding judge, argues that there is “by the law of England no warranty of title in the actual contract of sale any more than there is of quality. The rule of caveat emptor applies to both.”80 The strange thing about the case is that the judge declares caveat emptor, but only after listing all the cases it does not apply to regarding title. Not where there is an executory contract-- no court or reasonable person would see a purchaser as bound by a contract if he were to discover defects as to title before receipt of the goods, or if, after receipt the goods were recovered from him. Not if bought in a shop: A shopkeeper impliedly warrants good title. Parke insists that caveat emptor applies but in the very narrow case of a sale by auction by a pawnbroker. All that is implied is that there is a pledge and that the pawnbroker is not aware of any defects. Caveat emptor continued to hold great ideological weight, but by the 1860s the common law courts came to adopt the idea already found in Roman and civil law, that the vendor implies a warranty that he has the right to dispose of the objects which he sells.81 From Caveat Emptor to Implied Terms Throughout most of the nineteenth century there is no clear differentiation of Sale of Goods from contract law in general. The appeal of caveat emptor at the Court of Exchequer and King’s Bench may well have been attributable to the desire to maintain a consistent body of contract law through all areas. It was becoming increasingly questioned by political economists such as John Stuart Mill, and later even Herbert Spencer whether consumers should be left entirely to their own devices concerning potentially dangerous goods.82 In effect, this was a crisis in the “thing theory”. The courts 78 Allen v. Hopkins. (1844) 13 M. & W. 94, 153 E.R. 39 [1843-60] All E.R. Rep. 1045 3 Exch. 500, 154 E.R. 942 80 At paragraph 3 81 Eicholz v. Bannister (1864) 17 CBNS 708, 144 ER 284 82 Atiyah, at p. 470 79 26 did change the law on a case by case basis and by 1893 Judge Chalmers was able to codify a distinct realm of common law cases into the Sale of Goods Act. This new area would still rest on contracts law concerning the formation of agreements and issues concerning damages but embody new ideas of exchange and its objects. In the first transformation courts retain an insistence on individual judgment but also allow, in some limited contexts, that contracts come with implied terms. In Gardiner v Gray (1815)83 the defendant sold twelve bags of waste silk which on its arrival was found to be of a quality not saleable “under the denomination of ‘waste silk’”. Lord Ellenborough: "The purchaser has a right to expect a saleable article, answering the description in the contract”. For Ellenborough this follows, not from any explicit reference to concepts of fairness, but from the way he read the terms of the contract. He says “the intention of both parties must be taken to be, that it shall be saleable in the market under the denomination mentioned in the contract between them." So here we have the first introduction of the concept that the description of goods in the contract can help resolve contract disputes. The contract was read to include an implied term. It was implied that the contract in performance should accord with the promises given. A contract made amongst commercial men presupposes that the goods can be further sold down the line. In Jones v Bright (1829)84 there was an “executory” contract in which a written agreement was for a shipper to purchase, directly from the manufacturer, copper sheathing for commercial navigation ships. The buyer received bad goods and sued in court for the money spent. The court held that here the buyer relied on the word of the seller and manufacturer. According to the court, it was impossible that the buyer should be able to ascertain beforehand whether the article will answer the purpose for which it is destined. In Brown v. Edington (1841)85 a manufacturer who sold a special rope for a warehouse was found liable after it proved too weak to lift and move crates. The court held that if the buyer relies on the seller and states the purpose for a good then the transaction implies that the good will be fit and proper for that purpose. In each of these cases the court is careful to insist that ”if a party purchases an article upon his own judgment, he cannot afterward hold the vendor responsible”.86 On the one hand the 83 4 Campb. 144, 5 Bingham 533, 130 ER 1167 85 2 Manning and Granger 279, 133 E.R. 751. 86 133. E.R. at p. 763 84 27 courts are beginning to accept implied terms, but they are also refusing to budge from the idea that individual judgment is paramount. In the second transformation we witness in Sales is towards description. Mody v. Gregson (1868) provides the key transformation. 87 The Plaintiff bought 2500 pieces of grey shirting. When the goods arrived they were no good. He sued, alleging a breach of contract on the basis that the goods were not of merchantable quality. In Mody the plaintiff argued that the contract carried an implied warranty as to merchantability: Because the defect was latent, it could not be ascertained. Mody featured the distance shipping of textiles-- shirting sent to Calcutta and orders taken and communicated at long distances. When the plaintiff received the goods in Calcutta he discovered that the defendant had put clay into the manufacturing process. The agreed upon weight had been met, but only by destroying the shirts. In the earlier line of cases, when a buyer of goods could not make a direct inspection of goods, the courts were ready to acknowledge that a bargain was made on the basis of descriptions of the goods. This still gave primacy to direct inspection. Here we have a reversal: For goods bought under a specified commercial description “it is an implied term, notwithstanding the sample or inspection, that the goods shall reasonably answer the special description in its commercial sense.” (Italics added). The sample no longer serves as the basis for judgment. Rather, it is the “mere expression of the quality of the article, not of its essential character”. The description is first, and the sample is only to help realize that description. What mattered was simply whether the bulk matched the description. “The parties are dealing, not for the mere semblance or shadow of the thing designated, but for the thing itself as commonly understood in commerce, with the essential qualities which make it worth buying, to a person who wants an article of that designation”.88 This was an immense improvement, allowing the courts to consider the role of latent defects. It also led to the new technique of ascription of purposes. In Randall v. Newson (1877)89 the new doctrine was used in a case involving personal injury. A faulty pole 87 19 L.T. 459 (Exch. Chamber), p. 460 89 36 L.T. 162, 2 QBD 102 (C.A.) 88 28 (axle) on a carriage gave rise to legal action in contract. It was “a pole to be purchased for a specific purpose”. The court ruled that the issue was whether the commodity answers the description of it in the contract, and “it does not do so more or less, because the defect in it is patent or latent or discoverable”.90 In that same year the case of Beer v. Walker 91 found an implied warranty as to merchantability on food (specifically rabbit meat). The House of Lords solidified the cause in Drummond v. Van Ingen (1887).92 Cloth manufacturers and merchants, dealing across the North Atlantic from Bradford to New York ran into problems with latent defects in corkscrew twill for coats. Lord Herschel acknowledged “it is true that the purpose for which the goods were required was not… stated in express terms, but was indicated by the very designation of the goods, ‘coatings’” The sample, therefore, could achieve no more than express words. Chalmers then simply included this principle into the 1893 Sale of Goods Act. He took himself to be codifying existing case law, and not making new law. As a codification of pre-existing contract law, the Act includes the developments concerning implied terms, and also restates that the exchange of goods is by contract. The Sale of Goods Act still provided that in the circumstance of an actual inspection, where defects were patent, the fact of inspection would mean that there was no implied term. But this was now a rare exception, a hold over from previous cases. Chalmers included these out of deference to the common law tradition of accepting older cases if not explicitly overruled. 93 In such cases the buyer’s having inspected and then bought the goods could be understood as an acceptance of their condition. After the passage of the Act and its spread through the colonies, the courts become increasingly willing to ascribe a purpose to objects, in cases where this had not been discussed or otherwise made known by the parties. For instance in Frost v. Aylesbury Dairy Co. (1905)94 we have a case of the delivery of bad milk. In ruling that there was an implied warranty because the company issued pamphlets saying their milk was healthy, the Court of Appeal notes that "I do not suppose that anybody in his senses would 90 36 L.T. at p.166 [1874-80] ALL E.R. Rep. 1139, 37 L.T. 278 92 CC 284, 57 L.T. 1 (H.L. 93 To date cases hold that even where goods are seen by the buyer they may be the subject of a contract of sale by description. See e.g. Wren v. Holt [1903] 1 K.B. 610 (C.A.); Morelli v. Fitch [1928] 2 K.B. 636, Grant v. Australian Knitting Mills [1936] A.C. 85 at 100 (P.C.). Daniels & Daniels v. White & Sons Ltd. [1938] 4 All E.R. 258. Other cases hold that even where specific goods are being sold, the sale may be one by description. Verly v. Whipp [1900] Q.B. 513. 94 [1904-07] All E.R. Rep. 132, 92 L.T. 527 (C.A) 91 29 question for a moment that the purpose for which the milk was bought by the family was for consumption as an article of food”. The court now bypasses any reference to the intentions of the parties and infers a purpose to goods from the context alone. The result is that goods are interpreted by courts as coming with purposes. Subsequently, courts rule that Coca-Cola is for drinking,95 and that mobile homes are for travel from place to place.96 While technically the law requires that the seller rely on the buyer as to the quality of the goods, the courts increasingly adopt a liberal interpretation of when reliance can be inferred from the circumstances.97 Objects of exchange are now objects of utility—merchantable or filled with purposes, not because of any inherent attributes, but because they match their description. The courts would freely implying terms, but this depended on the the consumer transaction being conceived as a language based agreement. The conceptual structure of an agreement planned for the future (an executory contract) whereby the buyer trusts that the goods will match the description, became the model for even simultaneous transactions. This parallels the general developments in property in the nineteenth century. Rather than physical stuff, increasingly personal property came to include various more abstract things which had value, such as financial instruments or intellectual property. The result was a process of “dephysicalization”.98 The thing becomes transformed—not as a mere object available for inspection—but as whatever is specified by the parties, meaning, for the most part, the object of a description in an order form or bureaucratic arrangement. The commodity is no longer the thing as it appears for sale in the public square, but “the thing itself as commonly understood in commerce”. The ways in which sophisticated businessmen carried on their work became the model for consumer transactions. Conclusion 95 Yelland v. National Café [1955] 5 DLR 560 (Sask. C.A.) Marshall v.. Ryan ltd. [1922] E.R. 45 97 see, for example, Manchester Liners, Ltd. v. Rea, Ltd.[1922] ALL E.R. Rep. 605*Also reported [1922] 2 A.C. 74 (H.L.) where Lord Sumner explains that “reliance is a matter of reasonable inference to the seller and to the court”. 98 Vandevelde, ibid. 96 30 Nineteenth century contract and Sale of Goods provided a way of thinking about persons, exchange and commodities which helped to facilitate commodity networks. Key to this process was a set of interlocking concepts of subjects, objects, and exchange which the law attempted to stabilize. The circulation of commodities was enabled through concepts of exchange which hid the realities of networks from the persons who participated in and so perpetrated them. In order to achieve this, the courts had to conceive of objects in ways that kept them disentangled from historical and social relations. The result was at first a concept of these objects as things, and then a concept of these objects that was mediated by the concept of description. This maintained a set of exchange relationships structured around autonomous individuals, profit maximization, and lack of concern for the effects of contracting and its links to other persons and ecosystems. The re-ordering of contract effaced the prior history of consumption as embedded in social contexts and moral relations. While a number of cases in Sales of Goods emphasize the role of trust, the adoption of the functional analysis does not represent the re-entanglement of goods. In so far as a person relies on the abilities or word of another, that other begins to be understood as having duties towards those with whom they deal.99 This suggests a reading of Sale of Goods as incorporating an underlying view of exchange relations in terms of social embeddedness, of recognizing the way a range of social values, including trust, underpin exchange relations as social phenomena.100 Atiyah argues that implied terms reinstates an effective acknowledgment that there are elements of reliance in contracts for goods.101 We need to be cautious about overstating the degree to which the functional analysis re-embeds exchange into an ethical context. The whole idea of caveat emptor can be understood as an extreme swing towards one side of a pendulum Drummond v. Van Ingen ibid. per Herschel: “the merchant trusts to the skill of the manufacturer, and is entitled to trust to it…” Hyman .v Nye (1881) [1881-85] All ER. Rep. 183, 44 LT 919. Where a hired carriage breaks, spills and harms the plaintiff , an action in personal injury and negligence is available on the basis that “there is no distinction in this respect between contracts for sale and for the hire of an article for a specific purpose, where trust is reposed in the person who, in the ordinary course of business, sells or lets to hire”. John MacDonald & Co. v. Princess Manufacturing Co. [1925] O.J. No. 148 (C.A.) at para. 37 “ These particular classes are held to give an implied warranty against latent defects, notwithstanding opportunity of inspection of bulk or sample, because the purchaser trusts to their information, skill, and judgment, and is entitled so to trust.” 100 This would then mirror an analogous move in economic sociology see, for instance, Granovetter, M.S (1985) “Economic Action and Social Structure: the Problem of Embeddedness” American Journal of Sociology (81) 3, 481-50— 101 Atiyah, at p. 475 99 31 oscillating between relationally conceived, or alternatively discrete and, individualistic notions of exchange. Caveat emptor represented a reconstitution of exchange relations in terms of a sparsely framed conception: Over time we see the courts and legislatures slowly adding connections one by one. The description account and the functional account thus represent minor re-entanglements, but only as explicitly provided in terms of implied warranties as to purpose and merchantability. Later in the twentieth century we would see relations of duties of care concerning health and safety features of products as between manufacturers and consumers, and a strengthening of health and safety features of products. Here again, the range of trust, reliance or dependency only concerns a limited domain. For contemporary readers concerned with environmental or social justice concerns, the narrow range of trust concerned with the gap between description and the goods received hardly reconstitutes a world of social relations around goods tied to social and ecological ties. Disentangled goods are part of a distinct morality of self-determination, individual responsibility and competitive striving in the marketplace. The addition of concepts of trust for latent defects does not swing the pendulum very far towards the opposite pole. Sale of Goods law clearly fits into the contract law tradition. In terms of the possible ways in which goods can be re-entangled, even twentieth century consumer protection legislation, and negligence law simply represented adding a limited number of new ties, restricted to the axes of health, safety and financial protections for consumers. The limited environmental and workplace regulations which applied to some goods, depended in large part on where they were made, and so increasingly came to apply to only a subset of available goods on the market. Courts and legislators came to see that the myth of formal equality of contracting parties hid problems of bargaining power and imbalances of information. The analysis never extended to the problem of disentangled goods and the wider problems of how consumers are linked through commodities to wider human and non-human relationships. The history of the treatment of objects in contract and Sale of Goods is a story of the conflicts between free alienation of goods and the reality of their social histories. The thing theory allowed for individual judgment and free alienation. The transformation to the “descriptions” theory worked to plug one hole in the thing theory’s emphasis on the phenomenal aspects of goods. Simultaneously it re-instates the process-product 32 distinction where objects of exchange are understood as detached from their background histories and linkages. Terms like “coffee” do not invoke the complexities behind particular products, but rather single out the common physical features of anything that falls under the description. Linguistic terms abstract from the contingent and particular trajectories of goods as elements of commodity networks. The functional analysis that courts developed in the nineteenth century also continues to contribute to the same malaise; understanding objects in terms of end use purposes runs counter to tracing their origins and transformations from natural resource inputs and human labour. Commodity network approaches that stress human subjectivity as helping constitute networks helps show how these legal constructions ultimately shape commodities themselves. Insofar as the law influences our self-understanding, it comes to shape how we think of the world and our place in it. Even legal fictions, developed to serve idiosyncratic needs of the legal system, can become widely used metaphors and even solidified so we miss their metaphoric qualities. Once commodity networks develop with human subjectivity at their core, the concepts of objects from legal doctrine contribute to the shape of those networks. Commodity networks work to provide humans particular goods for particular purposes. Consumer goods are increasingly understood as constituted artifacts for human purposes—devices that matter in terms of utility. The result is the “device paradigm” where objects, and the commodity networks of which they are a part, come to be seen instrumentally, as something for us and our consumption. Increased complexification and technological sophistication work to create a world of products to which consumers can relate only in terms of utility. Someone who grows their own food or bakes their own bread can derive aesthetic and evaluative rewards from the interactions and process behind the goods they use, but the design of a computer works to shield the consumer from (either desirable or undesirable) aspects of its production.102 Ecological economics must then return to remind us of the glaringly obvious: “Products and services are not only economic goods (measured in monetary term) with a social meaning, but physical objects as well, tangible or-like many services—otherwise physically enjoyed. No economic good exists without a physical 102Borgmann, Albert "The Moral Complexion of Consumption." The Journal of Consumer Research 26, no. 4 (2000): 418-22 at p 419. 33 footprint”.103 The functional approach was a measure to reconcile the needs of exchange with the ways objects are also processes, histories and material flows but it cannot control the instability. By construing contract as open to the design of the individual parties, contract law also provides the space for alternative conceptions of exchange. Workers co-operatives, fair trade goods, or the planning of social movements can all make use of contracts as they seek to re-order “society’s metabolic relations with nature via the growth of new producer-consumer networks cemented by shared social values and commitments”.104 This provides hopes for overcoming impersonal market relations and lead to “socially reregulating and re-linking production, trade, and consumption in a manner that bridges the widening global/local divide”.105 Contract theory and doctrine is one discourse amongst many and exists in spaces of contention with other concepts of subjects, objects and exchange. Fair trade goods represent one way in which consumers can begin to think differently about their engagement in exchange transactions. Discourses of sustainable consumption suggest new ways that law is seeking to grasp the interdependencies of economy, society and ecology that imply new concepts of subjects, objects and exchange. 103Spangenberg, J. H. (2004). The society, its products and the environmental role of consumption. The Ecological Economics of Consumption. Lucia a Reisch and Inge Ropke. Northampton, MA, Edward Elgar: 32-59. p. 33 104 Goodman, D. and M. Goodman ibid. at p. 97 105 Raynolds, L.T. and D.L. Murray (1998) “Yes, we have no bananas: Re-regulating global and regional trade” International Journal of Sociology of Agriculture & Food 7: 7-44 34